Você está na página 1de 19

The Behavior Analyst 2006, 29, 13–31 No.

1 (Spring)

Private Stimuli, Covert Responses, and Private Events:


Conceptual Remarks
Emmanuel Zagury Tourinho
Universidade Federal do Pará, Brazil
In this article, I discuss the concepts of private stimuli, covert responses, and private events,
emphasizing three aspects: the conditions under which private stimuli may acquire
discriminative functions to verbal responses, the conditions of unobservability of covert
responses, and the complexity of events or phenomena described as private. I argue that the role
of private stimuli in the control of self-descriptive verbal responses is dependent on a relation
(correlation or equivalence relation) with public stimuli, and that responses vary along
a continuum of observability. These remarks on private stimuli and covert responses are
introductory to an examination of the varying complexity of phenomena described as private. I
argue that private events is a verbal response emitted under the control of phenomena of
different degrees of complexity, and I interpret these phenomena, based on the principle of
selection by consequences. I introduce the notion of inclusiveness to suggest that some
phenomena related to privacy are less or more complex as they include relations of
a phylogenetic, ontogenetic, and cultural origin.
Key words: private events, private stimuli, covert response, inside world, selection by
consequences

Private events have been acknowl- tion’’ (2000, p. 45) may be achieved
edged as a main topic for behavior once we come to a more complete
analysts dealing with complex human understanding of the topic. This
behavior, especially for those inter- paper is intended to contribute to
ested in clinical applications of be- a conceptual discussion of private
havior analysis (cf. Anderson, Haw- events. The goals of the paper are
kins, Freeman, & Scotti, 2000; (a) to present an analysis of private
Anderson, Hawkins, & Scotti, 1997; stimuli and covert responses that
Dougher, 1993b; Dougher & Hack- works out some aspects of inaccessi-
bert, 2000; Friman, Hayes, & Wilson, bility to public observation; and
1998; Moore, 2000; Wilson & Hayes, (b) to argue that many psychological
2000). Conceptual work concerning phenomena treated as private events
private events, nevertheless, is still are complex phenomena, which may
required to improve Skinner’s origi- be approached with the causal mode
nal discussion (Skinner, 1945). As of selection by consequences.
Moore has stated, ‘‘better services for Following Moore’s (1984) discus-
clients and a better overall theoretical sion and Banaco’s (1999) argument, I
understanding of the human condi- will prefer to speak of covert ‘‘re-
sponses’’ rather than covert ‘‘beha-
The writing of this paper was supported by viors,’’ taking the latter to mean
Grants 520062/98-1 and 477298/2001-0 from
the Conselho Nacional de Desenvolvimento relations among responses and stim-
Cientı́fico e Tecnológico, CNPq, Brazil. Parts uli; therefore, they are not necessarily
of the paper were presented at the 10th annual fully covert (e.g., verbal behavior
meeting of the Associação Brasileira de may involve a covert response under
Psicoterapia e Medicina Comportamental,
2001, and the 30th annual convention of the the control of public stimuli; an
Association for Behavior Analysis, 2004. I instance of problem solving may
thank Simone Neno and Maria Amália involve both covert—precurrent—
Andery for their comments. and overt responses). Both covert
Correspondence may be sent to the author at
Rua Aristides Lobo, 884, Apto. 100, Re-
responses and private stimuli may
duto, 66.053-020, Belém, Pará, Brazil (e-mail: be discussed from several stand-
tourinho@amazon.com.br). points.

13
14 EMMANUEL ZAGURY TOURINHO

I will begin with Skinner’s (1953/ paper also emphasizes responses


1965) view according to which ‘‘a (e.g., thinking, imagining) whose un-
private event may be distinguished by observability results not from physi-
its limited accessibility but not, so far cal barriers between the observed and
as we know, by any special structure the observers, but from features that
or nature’’ (p. 257). In accordance include its emission with restricted
with Skinner’s reasoning, inaccessi- participation of the motor apparatus.
bility to public direct observation has My objective with this focus is not to
turned out to be the distinguishing say that these stimuli and responses
feature of private stimuli and covert are events of a different quality or
responses in behavior-analytic litera- that they deserve a special treatment
ture. However, the basis for such in a behavioral science. On the
inaccessibility is not clearly stated contrary, I intend to argue that what
and demands further examination to goes inside an organism cannot count
achieve a more accurate view of as an independent cause of verbal
privacy. behavior because its possible (pri-
Stimuli and responses may be un- vate) stimulus function is dependent
observable for different reasons. For on a relation with public stimuli; and
example, in our culture, thinking or that responses are not simply public
imagining, in contrast with voting, or private but may vary along
typing a password, taking a shower, a continuum of observability.
or praying are responses that may be After examining the inaccessibility
emitted privately, but their privacy of private stimuli and covert re-
comes from different sources. An sponses, I will address the types of
event that has occurred in the past phenomena described as ‘‘private
(e.g., a soccer game) may constitute events.’’ I will suggest that speaking
an unobservable stimulus as well. or writing about private events is
What makes an event unobservable a verbal response under the control
may be seen as a secondary issue to of diverse phenomena, which should
a behavioral science because behav- be specified. When it is said that
ioral relations are its subject matter. ‘‘hunger pangs’’ (e.g., Skinner, 1945),
From a behavioral standpoint, what ‘‘emotions’’ (e.g., Anderson et al.,
matters about the observability of 1997), or ‘‘anxiety’’ (Friman et al.,
events is whether or not they acquire 1998) are instances of private events,
stimulus functions in the behavior of different types of phenomena, and
observers. phenomena that show different de-
This paper, however, emphasizes grees of complexity are under con-
stimuli that are unobservable not sideration. As a verbal response,
because they lie in the past, but ‘‘private events’’ may be emitted
because they are generated by an under the control of any (more or
individual’s body, and observers can- less complex) behavioral relation in
not establish with them the same which private stimuli and covert
contact as the individual him- or responses take part. I hope to make
herself does (i.e., that in principle, this point clear as I suggest that the
there is only one possible observer). causal mode of selection by conse-
Skinner (e.g., 1974/1993) refers to quences helps us to understand the
these stimuli as ‘‘the world within varying complexity of the phenome-
the skin’’ (p. 24). Donahoe and na we tend to treat under the concept
Palmer (1994), in their definition of of private events.
private events, refer to ‘‘the inner This paper is divided into three
world of the individual; i.e., the sections: (a) private stimuli, (b) covert
stimuli originating within the skin, responses, and (c) private events. The
to which each person has unique sections on private stimuli and covert
[italics added] access’’ (p. 361). This responses are introductory to the
PRIVATE EVENTS 15

section on private events. They in- ‘‘the individual’s response to an


clude a review of some behavior- inflamed tooth … is unlike the re-
analytic (especially Skinner’s) inter- sponse which anyone else can make
pretations, while also adding some to that particular tooth, since no one
conceptual remarks on the treatment else can establish the same kind of
of the concepts of private stimuli and contact with it’’ (p. 257).
covert responses. The section on Private stimuli are often (though
private events develops an interpre- not always) located under the skin,
tation of phenomena related to pri- and that has led Skinner to speak of
vacy, based on its variety of com- ‘‘the world within the skin’’ (e.g.,
plexity. Skinner, 1974/1993, p. 24). But pri-
vacy is not a matter of localization,
PRIVATE STIMULI and the skin is not necessarily
A person contacts the world with a boundary. There are circumstances
the mediation of his or her nervous in which an individual responds to
system, which carries stimulation re- some interoceptive stimulations that
ceived through the sense organs are not ‘‘under’’ or ‘‘inside’’ the skin.
For instance, one may respond to
(vision, hearing, touch, smell, and
a lesion in the skin itself, as in-
taste). Part of this world is one’s own
teroceptive stimulation, as when not
body, which can also affect the
looking at it but still sensing its
person as interoceptive or proprio-
effects. On the other hand, one may
ceptive stimulation. The interoceptive
respond to ‘‘inside’’ events (events
and proprioceptive stimulations are
under the skin) as exteroceptive
those generated by the individual’s
stimulation (e.g., when one hears
own body: The interoceptive stimuli
a stomach noise).
include ‘‘stimulation from organs like
the bladder and alimentary tract,
Private Stimuli and Stimulus Functions
from glands and their ducts, and
from blood vessels’’ (Skinner, 1974/ Private stimuli may be physiologi-
1993, pp. 24–25); the proprioceptive cal events that show stimulus func-
stimuli are those generated by one’s tions, including eliciting, discrimina-
motor apparatus, ‘‘the muscles, tive, and reinforcing functions. Each
joints, and tendons of the skeletal of these functions will be briefly
frame and … other organs involved mentioned below, but a more detailed
in the maintenance of posture and the treatment will be given to the circum-
execution of movement’’ (p. 25). Ex- stances in which private stimuli show
teroceptive stimuli generated by an a discriminative function to verbal
individual’s body may be either responses. The emphasis on the role
public or private (e.g., the visual of private stimuli as discriminative
stimulation generated by one’s danc- stimuli to verbal responses is moti-
ing at a party [public] or in a rehearsal vated by the fact that this is the
before a mirror in a closed room circumstance in which privacy is
[private]). Interoceptive and proprio- linked to the issue of psychological
ceptive stimuli are always private, in concepts; it is also consistent with
the sense that others cannot make Skinner’s (e.g., 1945, 1953/1965,
contact with them as such. Whatever 1974/1993) discussions of privacy.
happens inside one’s body may affect This emphasis also regards the great
others as exteroceptive stimulation importance of the matter to clinical
(sometimes with the help of instru- behavior analysis, in the context of
ments or physiological techniques), which privacy has received a more
but will not affect them as proprio- systematic attention.
ceptive or interoceptive stimulation. Private stimuli and unconditioned
In Skinner’s (1953/1965) example, eliciting functions. Some private stim-
16 EMMANUEL ZAGURY TOURINHO

uli are unconditioned eliciting stimu- For example, an interoceptive stimu-


li, as a result of the phylogenetic lation generated by the respiratory
history of the species. For example, system may function as a discrimina-
certain changes in the respiratory tive stimulus for one’s nonverbal
system may function as interoceptive response when opening the window
stimuli that elicit sneezing responses. of the house or for the verbal re-
The individual will respond to those sponse ‘‘I feel breathless.’’
stimuli whether or not he or she has
been exposed to specific ontogenetic Private Stimuli, Unobservability, and
contingencies. In that sense, some Bodily Conditions
unconditioned eliciting stimuli con-
stitute a part of the private universe When an interoceptive or proprio-
that is a natural part of anyone’s ceptive private stimulus shows a dis-
private environment. Note, however, criminative function for a verbal re-
that when the same event exerts sponse, the processes that work to
a discriminative function to other turn parts of the private universe into
responses—verbal responses, for in- an individual’s private environment
stance—additional processes are in- are those verbal processes described
volved that have to be explained. by Skinner (1945) and other verbal
Private stimuli and conditioned processes later investigated by behav-
eliciting functions. A physiological ior analysts (e.g., emergence of equiv-
event may also become a conditioned alence relations; see DeGrandpre,
eliciting private stimulus. One occa- Bickel, & Higgins, 1992). Skinner
sion in which this may happen is has argued that from a psychological
when the individual is exposed to point of view, ‘‘the only problem
preaversive and aversive uncontrolla- which a science of behavior must
ble public stimuli, contingencies that solve in connection with subjectivism
produce what is called anxiety (cf. is in the verbal field. How can we
Skinner, 1974/1973, 1987/1989). Such account for the behavior of talking
contingencies may produce a decrease about mental events?’’ (1945, p. 294).
in the rate of responding, and the Two aspects of Skinner’s answer
preaversive stimulus may acquire should be stressed here. The first is
eliciting functions. A bodily condi- that verbal responses descriptive of
tion that follows the exposure to the private events are acquired under the
preaversive stimulus may itself ac- control of a set of stimuli that include
quire its eliciting functions: ‘the public stimuli (these make the re-
condition felt as anxiety begins to inforcing action of the verbal com-
act as a second conditioned aversive munity possible). Second, the partic-
stimulus’’ (Skinner, 1987/1989, p. 7). ipation of the public event in the
Private stimuli and reinforcing func- control of that response does not end
tions. A private stimulus may show with its acquisition. As Skinner as-
a positive or negative reinforcing serts,
function. For example, the ingestion
The individual acquires language from society,
of a drug may be positively rein- but the reinforcing action of the verbal
forced by the interoceptive stimula- community continues to play an important
tion it produces (as in the ingestion of role in maintaining the specific relations
alcohol) or negatively reinforced by between responses and stimuli which are
the cessation of an interoceptive essential to the proper functioning of verbal
behavior. How language is acquired is, there-
stimulation (as in the administration fore, only part of a much broader problem.
of a drug that ceases a pain). (p. 272)
Private stimuli and discriminative
functions. A private stimulus may Because the reinforcing action of
show a discriminative function for the verbal community is based on
both verbal and nonverbal responses. public (exteroceptive) stimuli, the
PRIVATE EVENTS 17

private stimulus that comes to ac- functions that result from their par-
quire discriminative control over ticipation in equivalence classes of
a verbal response is an interoceptive stimuli (see DeGrandpre et al., 1992).
or proprioceptive stimulation that is When this is the case, we should note
correlated with those public stimuli that the members of the class (e.g.,
and that becomes relevant through interoceptive and exteroceptive stim-
additional verbal contigencies that uli) are equivalent in the sense that
promote self-observation. The impor- they show emergent equivalence rela-
tant point here is that self-observa- tions, but this does not mean that
tion is not all; a private event is they are equally dependent on these
dependent on a correlation with relations to acquire stimulus func-
a public event to acquire and maintain tion. An exteroceptive stimuli (e.g.,
a stimulus function in the control of a visual stimulus) is not dependent on
a verbal response. This is why a pri- being a member of a class of equiv-
vate event may not be taken as alent stimuli to control, for example,
a cause of verbal behavior (beyond descriptive responses. The same may
the problem of its inaccessibility to not be said of interoceptive and
manipulation). Because its function- proprioceptive stimuli. An interocep-
ality is dependent on its correlation tive of proprioceptive stimulus that is
with public stimuli, the reference to a member of an equivalence class
the private event will not suffice as an depends on these equivalence rela-
explanation. One’s verbal responses tions (or on correlations with public
descriptive of the ‘‘inside world’’ will stimuli, as seen above) to acquire the
always be under the control of a set same functions. Again, reference to
of public stimuli (the ones that the interoceptive or proprioceptive
ground the verbal community rein- stimulation will not suffice to explain
forcing action), though probably they the self-descriptive response.
are also under the control of a varying Skinner (1974/1993) notes that the
(inter- and intrasubject) interoceptive nervous system that makes it possible
or proprioceptive stimulation. for someone to contact exteroceptive
Of course, when one has learned stimulation ‘‘also plays an important
self-descriptive responses partially part in observing our own body’’
under the control of an interoceptive (p. 25), although this is not always
or proprioceptive stimulation, the acknowledged. When people describe
response may be emitted in some themselves as excited, for instance,
occasions under the control of the they are largely under the control of
private stimulus. As Skinner (1945) exteroceptive stimulation, either from
noted, however, social contingencies their own bodies or from their rela-
keep working after the acquisition of tions with the outside world. Howev-
a verbal repertoire to maintain verbal er, in modern western cultures, social
responses under the control of proper contingencies do not favor the dis-
stimuli. In the long run, the re- crimination of all sources of control
sponse’s functionality will depend of self-descriptive repertoires. They
on its control by the public stimuli favor more frequently the discrimi-
on which the verbal community bears nation of what goes on in the body
its reinforcing action. than the discrimination of behavioral
Behavior-analytic understanding relations (e.g., those responsible for
of verbal behavior has advanced descriptions of excitement). It is the
since Skinner’s (1945) original discus- exposure to verbal contingencies that
sion of the processes through which gives rise to the private environment
private stimuli may acquire discrim- about which we talk and that makes
inative functions for verbal re- some physiological events acquire
sponses. We now know, for example, a partial discriminative control of
that interoceptive stimuli may show verbal responses. In other words,
18 EMMANUEL ZAGURY TOURINHO

from the point of view offered here, Examples of such contingencies are
a private stimulus will always be those involved in requests to ‘‘think
dependent on a relation (either a cor- silently’’ or ‘‘think out loud’’ (cf.
relation or an equivalence relation) Skinner, 1968, 1974/1993), as well as
with public stimuli. Note, however, punishment contingent on overt re-
that a correlation is not a sufficient sponses. As responses of the organ-
condition to turn a physiological ism as a whole, covert responses are
event into a private stimulus. Verbal considered to have physical dimen-
contigencies that promote self-obser- sions. Following Skinner’s concep-
vation are also required to build tualizations, his references to a ‘‘re-
one’s world of private stimuli. duced scale’’ of covert responses, and
The fact that the discriminative the possibility of making them ‘‘re-
function of a private stimulus in the turn’’ to the public level, this section
control of a verbal response is de- will focus on responses that are
pendent on the relation of such an unobservable not due to physical
event with public stimuli is the reason barriers between observers and ob-
why, from the point of view of all served but as a result of social
psychological concepts, what goes on contingencies that alter the form of
inside the organism is not enough as its emission. As mentioned before,
an explanation. Consideration of the whether or not the use of the concept
role of private stimuli in verbal of covert responses should be re-
responses regarding psychological stricted to such responses has not
concepts is what leads Skinner and been clearly stated and will not be the
other behavior analysts to say that subject of the present discussion.
private discriminative stimuli should In the light of Skinner’s interpre-
not be taken as causes of behavior. tation of covert responses, three
They should not be considered causes questions may be addressed concern-
not simply because they are unob- ing the privacy of covert responses:
servable or cannot be manipulated (a) If a covert response is emitted in
but because their functionality is a ‘‘reduced scale,’’ what does the
dependent on that relation with scale measure? (b) What is the
public stimuli. topography of a covert response?
(c) What makes thinking different
COVERT RESPONSES from the other unobservable re-
sponses (e.g., secret voting or typing
Covert responses are inaccessible a password) emitted in conditions
to public observation. They are under which they are inaccessible to
responses of the organism as a whole public observation?
emitted ‘‘on such a reduced scale that Before answering these questions,
[they] cannot be observed by others— it should be noted that any covert
at least without instrumentation’’ response is only circumstantially co-
(Skinner, 1953/1965, p. 263). One vert, due to social contingencies of
class of variables that control wheth- reinforcement. One cannot argue that
er a response is emitted covertly or a response like thinking is naturally
overtly includes the social contingen- inaccessible to public observation,
cies of reinforcement to which one whereas a response like voting is only
has been exposed (Skinner, 1968). transitorily inaccessible. They are
According to Skinner (1968, 1974/ both responses that may become
1993), a response learned at the overt public at any time, as long as the
level ‘‘may … recede to the covert individual is exposed to proper con-
level’’ (Skinner, 1945, p. 277) and tingencies of reinforcement.
‘‘return to the overt level’’ (Skinner, It is also important to note that
1974/1993, p. 31) as a function of thinking is not the only type of covert
social contingencies of reinforcement. response identified by Skinner. Ac-
PRIVATE EVENTS 19

cording to Skinner (1968), ‘‘the be- Covert speech is not … wholly or perhaps
havior most easily observed at the even primarily a labor-saving practice. As we
have seen, verbal behavior is frequently
covert level is verbal … but non- punished. Audible behavior in the child is
verbal behavior may be covert’’ reinforced and tolerated up to a point; then it
(p. 124). Whether verbal or not, co- becomes annoying, and the child is punished
vert responses tend to have their for speaking. Comparable aversive conse-
quences continue into the adult years. …
topographies defined in negative That avoidance of punishment is a more likely
terms. The reference made to the explanation than convenience is shown by the
topography of thinking usually fact that covert behavior returns to the overt
points to the fact that it is not vocal. level when a punishing audience is no longer
Also, a definition of the topography in control though convenience has not been
altered. Many people who live alone gradually
of covert ‘‘driving’’ (not covertly come to talk to themselves aloud. In the
seeing oneself driving), for example, presence of other people the return to the
would probably refer to a sort of overt level may take time, for the nonpunish-
nonmuscular driving. ing character of an audience cannot be
established in a moment. (pp. 436–437)
There are probably several reasons
why a response is emitted covertly, Punishment contingent on overt
and it may be helpful to review some responses, more than convenience or
of them. Skinner (e.g., 1957/1992) weak stimulus control, explains the
mentions that covert responses may emission of covert responses, for
result from a sort of weak stimulus instance, those related to thinking.
control. Looking at a very old When a covert verbal response is
picture, one may think ‘‘this seems emitted, it cannot be punished be-
to be Maria,’’ but the person will cause it does not affect the potentially
more likely emit the response ‘‘Ma- punishing social environment. It does
ria’’ overtly when really facing Maria. not affect the social environment
A response may also be emitted because one’s vocal musculature is
covertly because it is ‘‘simply the not activated as in the overt form.
easiest or, for any reason, the likeliest This fact led early behaviorists (e.g.,
at the moment’’ (Skinner, 1957/1992, Watson, 1920) to approach thinking
p. 436). For example, it may be easier as subvocal speech. But Watson
to covertly test a move in a chess (1930/1970) also argued that there
game than to do so by moving the are ‘‘stages’’ of activation of the
pieces on a chess board. In such muscular systems in thinking and
circumstances, convert responding established a relation between the
‘‘has the advantage that we can act higher stage of such activation and
without committing ourselves; we can social constraints:
revoke the behavior and try again if
private consequences are not reinfor- The child talks incessantly when alone. At
cing’’ (Skinner, 1974/1993, p. 114). three he even plans the day aloud … Soon the
When the covert response is simply society in the form of nurse and parents steps
the easiest one, what explains it is in. ‘‘Don’t talk aloud—daddy and mother are
always talking to themselves.’’ Soon the overt
one’s ‘‘convenience’’ (Skinner, 1957/ speech dies down to whispered speech and
1992). a good lip reader can still read what the child
There is a third reason why one thinks of the world and of himself. Some
responds covertly, which Skinner individuals never even make this concession to
(1957/1992) assumes to be much more society. When alone, they talk aloud to
themselves. A still larger number never go
important than weak stimulus control beyond even the whispering stage when alone.
or convenience. It is the fact that one … But the great majority of people pass on to
is faced with social contingencies that the third stage under the influence of social
involve punishment contingent on the pressure constantly exerted: ‘‘Quit whispering
to yourself,’’ and ‘‘Can’t you even read
overt form of the response. In a sec- without moving your lips?’’ and the like are
tion on covert verbal behavior Skin- constant mandates. Soon the process is forced
ner points out that to take place behind the lips. (pp. 240–241)
20 EMMANUEL ZAGURY TOURINHO

In Skinner’s view of the matter, one of them is a well-trained behav-


a verbal response may be emitted ioral psychologist, he or she will
with different degrees of participation probably be better at identifying
of the vocal musculature. A verbal certain responses than a person who
response, in that sense, is not simply has never been asked to observe and
vocal or subvocal. describe behavior or received any
instructions concerning this task. At
The range of verbal behavior is roughly this point, the observability of the
suggested, in descending order of energy, by response would be a property of the
shouting, loud talking, quiet talking, whisper-
ing, muttering ‘‘under one’s breath,’’ sub-
relation between the observer and the
audible speech of unclear dimensions, and observed.
perhaps even the ‘‘unconscious thinking’’ The idea of a continuum of ob-
sometimes inferred in instances of problem servability of responses is not origi-
solving. So far as we know, the events at the
covert end have no special properties, observe
nal. Donahoe and Palmer (1994)
no special laws, and can be credited with no have suggested it in the context of
special achievements. (1957/1992, p. 438) a reference to another source of
variability of observability, the tools
Skinner’s reference to a ‘‘descending of the observer:
order of energy’’ of verbal responses
seems to be an important cue to The observability of a response is not de-
unfold the basis of inaccessibility of termined by its intensity or magnitude, but by
certain covert responses. It may be the characteristics or tools of the observer. …
interpreted as a reference to varying We must avoid the temptation to think of
covert behavior as a kind of behavior, with
degrees of observability of responses, properties essentially different from overt
according to the level of participation behavior. Rather, all behavior lies on a con-
of one’s motor apparatus (the vocal tinuum of observability. (p. 275)
musculature, in the case of verbal
responses; the muscular and skeletal A fourth potential source of vari-
systems in the case of driving, etc.). ability in the observability of re-
According to this view, some covert sponses has been suggested in the
responses are responses emitted with literature of interbehavioral psychol-
lower degrees of participation of ogy (cf. L. J. Hayes, 1994; Kantor &
one’s motor apparatus. Covert verbal Smith, 1975; Observer, 1973, 1981):
responses therefore might be inter- the familiarity or intimacy between
preted as verbal responses emitted observer and observed. It is not the
with lower degrees of participation of goal of this paper to examine inter-
one’s vocal musculature. behaviorist principles, but simply to
However, as Skinner (1957/1992) suggest that this reference to famil-
suggests, perhaps we should not iarity may be adopted in a behavior-
simply talk of a boundary that sets analytic interpretation of covert re-
apart overt and covert responses. sponses. Going back to the example
Responses vary along a continuum of a child’s behavior in a classroom,
of observability, and the basis of such certain responses will most probably
a continuum may be discussed. Skin- be observed and registered by one
ner suggests a ‘‘descending order of who has a shared history with the
energy’’ that has been interpreted child than by one who has just been
here as a reference to the degree of introduced to him or her (assuming
participation of one’s motor appara- that both have the same observation-
tus. Other sources of variability in the al skills, tools, etc.). The intimacy
observability of responses may be between observer and observed (be-
suggested. One of them is the obser- yond the degree of participation of
vation training of observers. Suppose the motor apparatus) partially ex-
two people are asked to register the plains why relatives, friends or part-
behavior of a child in a classroom. If ners sometimes know much more
PRIVATE EVENTS 21

about a person’s behavior than happen that the intimacy L. J. Hayes


others do. L. J. Hayes has noted that (1994) mentions when she explains
Kantor’s reference to intimacy differs Kantor’s views is also one that makes
from Skinner’s notion of unobserva- one able to recognize the other’s
bility of private events. According to response, even when it is emitted
Hayes, with restricted participation of the
motor apparatus. For example, in
What Skinner calls ‘‘private events’’ and Skinner’s discussion of the ‘‘descend-
deems unobservable by virtue of the internal ing order of energy of verbal behav-
location of their execution, Kantor calls ior,’’ he refers to a stage in which
‘‘subtle events’’ held to be capable of obser-
vation. Observation in the latter case depends what we have is a ‘‘subaudible speech
minimally on shared histories between obser- of unclear dimensions’’ (Skinner,
vers and the observed as a matter of en- 1957/1992, p. 438). That response
culturation, and maximally on the intimacy of may be a covert response if it is
the observer and the observed as a matter of
shared individual histories. Kantor’s analysis
emitted before an unfamiliar audi-
suggests, in other words, that what appears to ence or a public response if it is
be unobservable is not so in principle, but is emitted before a very intimate part-
instead subtle; and subtlety is not a formal ner. This is the reason why we should
characteristic of the event in question. That is prefer to include the relation between
to say, subtlety is not something about
a particular event apart from an observer’s the observer and the observed in our
insufficient history with respect to it. The analysis of covert responses instead
greater one’s history of interaction with subtle of working with the idea that the
events, the more obvious they therein become covert character of a response is
since, psychologically speaking, observed
events are nothing other than loci of response
simply a property of the response
functions for observers. (p. 160) itself.
In light of these aspects, we may
The two conceptualizations, never- review the questions addressed in the
theless, may be viewed as comple- beginning of this section and the
mentary to each other. Skinner re- possible answers:
jects a difference in nature between 1. If a covert response is emitted in
overt and covert responses and ar- a ‘‘reduced scale,’’ what does the
gues that both are the responses of scale measure? The reduced scale of
the organism as a whole. He also covert responses has to do with the
proposes that the overt or covert low participation of the individual’s
character of a response is a function motor apparatus in the emission of
of social contingencies. Skinner’s in- the response.
terpretation may be complemented 2. What is the topography of a co-
with Kantor’s view, which more vert response? ‘‘Topography’’ often is
clearly says that the basis for un- a specification of the motor compo-
observability of certain responses is nents in the emission of a response;
a low participation of the motor therefore, one can provide limited
apparatus in their emission. This specification of the topography of
feature may be seen as a function of a covert response, due to its distinc-
social contingencies (Skinner), but it tive feature (i.e., its privacy).
will give rise to unobservability de- 3. What makes thinking different
pending on a history of interaction from other responses emitted in
between observer and observed conditions under which they are
(Kantor). inaccessible to public observation
One may argue that when famil- (e.g., secret voting or typing a pass-
iarity explains the degree to which word)? Unobservability is a criterion
a response is public, what is observed to define privacy. However, it may
is not the covert response per se, but result from different sources, like
collateral public responses. In fact, physical barriers between observer
this may be the case. But it may also and observed (as in secret voting)
22 EMMANUEL ZAGURY TOURINHO

and unshared history, observational sidering the limits of the present


training, observational tools, and paper, a thorough analysis of these
structural features (as in thinking). problems remains only a suggestion.
In any case, the idea of a continuum
of observability of responses seems to PRIVATE EVENTS
be a more consistent one than the
Private events is a verbal response
simple covert–overt distinction.
emitted by behavior analysts under
One might argue that there are
the control of very different putative
covert responses with respect to
phenomena such as happiness, think-
which the reference to observational
ing, anxiety, imagination, pains, and
training and tools, familiarity, and
so on. What is found in common to
participation of the motor apparatus
all those events or phenomena is the
is not so relevant. This seems to be
actual or possible participation of
the case when we speak of private
either a private stimulation or a covert
seeing, because seeing is sometimes
response, as previously examined.
interpreted as a response that can
Because very different phenomena
only be emitted covertly. According
fall into this definition, any assertion
to such a perspective, seeing is simply
about private events in general may
a sort of ‘‘making contact’’ with
be challenged, unless it clearly speci-
a visual stimulus. But seeing is
fies to what class of events it refers.
equally emitted with a restricted par-
Sometimes such specification is not
ticipation of the motor apparatus,
enough because the class itself may
and we should ask only whether or
include phenomena of varying de-
not it becomes covert due to social
grees of complexity. Sadness, for
contingencies. At least in most cases
example, is a broad concept or
(when phylogenesis does not explain),
a verbal response emitted under the
seeing is a function of social con-
control of several nonidentical phe-
tingencies. One may see many differ-
nomena. To go beyond controversies
ent things when walking into a li-
concerning private events, some sort
brary, for example, depending on
of further clarification of that di-
a previous educational history. And
versity is still needed. In the next
as we learn to see certain things our
paragraphs, two directions for such
seeing must show public dimensions
clarification are suggested: first,
in order to be shaped by social
a classification of events or phenom-
consequences. These public dimen-
ena under the control of which
sions (or collateral responses) will not
behavior analysts talk of private
remain as the seeing becomes strictly
events; second, a model for analyzing
private. It is clear that conditioned
the varying complexity of private
seeing, hearing, and other responses
events, based on Skinner’s causal
will demand additional conceptual
mode of selection by consequences.
treatment. As much as we considered
here, however, they do not conflict
with the present analysis. A Preliminary Classification of Events
or Phenomena Treated as Private
Much the same might be said
about covert responses (conditioned The use of the concept of private
and unconditioned respondents), events in behavior-analytic literature
with respect to which one might say shows that at least three classes of
that they are not first emitted in the events are relevant: (a) physiological
overt form and then recede to the conditions, (b) stimuli and responses
covert level. Perhaps, in this case we as components of behavioral rela-
should consider first what counts as tions, and (c) behavioral relations.
a response of the organism as a whole According to which class is referred,
and then decide whether or not certain statements about privacy may
a response is covert. However, con- or may not be valid. Conceptual
PRIVATE EVENTS 23

difficulties or disagreements may a collateral product of one’s evolu-


arise from the fact that some asser- tionary and environmental history.
tions are made concerning privacy in But when an individual’s description
general, although they apply to only of a pain is partially under the
one subset of the events mentioned. control of the stimulation generated
For example, private events may be by his stomach, that bodily condition
described as collateral products of is not simply a collateral product of
contingencies of reinforcement (e.g., his or her environmental history. It is
Skinner, 1985) or possible controlling endowed with stimulus functions;
variables of public responses (e.g., thus it is, or has been, part of
Skinner, 1945). Both perspectives are a contingency. On the other hand,
compatible, because in each case physiological events that have no
‘‘private events’’ refers to different stimulus function should not count
events (physiological conditions in as private stimuli; they are simply
the first case; private stimuli in the part of the behaving organism.
second). Overskeid’s (1994) discus- Private stimuli, covert responses,
sion of private events and the circum- and private events. A different use of
stances in which covert responses the concept of private events is one
may acquire stimulus functions that makes reference to private stim-
ignores those possible distinctions uli or covert responses that are
(although he correctly identifies some components or terms of behavioral
inconsistencies in Skinner’s writings). relations. These are events with re-
His conclusion that a private event spect to which unobservability is
‘‘can be as good a cause as anything’’ assumed to be a crucial feature, and
(p. 39) is an example of the limited the conditions for such unobserva-
validity of assertions concerning pri- bility are those described earlier in
vate events in general. this paper. These are not collateral
Anatomo-physiological conditions products of contingencies but are
and private events. Because one’s terms of contingency relations. These
body may acquire stimulus functions terms have been acknowledged as
in the form of interoceptive or pro- relevant in phenomena usually de-
prioceptive stimulation, some state- scribed as ‘‘mental,’’ ‘‘cognitive,’’ or
ments about privacy are made on the ‘‘subjective’’; their possible or actual
basis of organic occurrences, whether participation in a behavioral relation
or not these occurrences have stimu- defines privacy in behavior-analytic
lus functions. In other words, some- literature. As terms of a contingency,
times one’s assertions regarding pri- private stimuli and covert responses
vate events are concerned with are part of behavioral phenomena;
physiological conditions, and these their relation to other stimuli or
physiological conditions are not nec- responses is required to achieve a de-
essarily endowed with stimulus func- scription of behavior. As seen above,
tions. This is especially the case when this may be crucial in the case of
it is said that what one feels is private stimuli that control self-de-
a ‘‘collateral product of the causes scriptions, whose functions are de-
of behavior’’ (Skinner, 1985, p. 296). pendent on their relation with other
Physiological occurrences are collat- stimuli.
eral products of one’s environmental Behavioral relations and private
history, as long as they acquire no events. When private stimuli or covert
stimulus function. They become responses take part in behavioral
‘‘causes of behavior’’ from the mo- relations, the relations themselves
ment they may be said to function as are complex phenomena that may
either private or public stimuli (i.e., be responded to as private events,
from the moment they are ‘‘felt’’). A even though they are not entirely
biochemically modified stomach is unobservable nor are they collateral
24 EMMANUEL ZAGURY TOURINHO

products of contingencies. Problem which a private stimulation or a co-


solving, for example, is a behavioral vert response may take part. These
relation itself, or more usually a set of are not collateral products of con-
behavioral relations, in which a pre- tingencies of reinforcement, entirely
current response may be private, but unobservable phenomena, or simply
the relation as a whole is not un- a matter of a three-term contingen-
observable. Feeling sad, or happy, or cies. Probably, most of the phenom-
scared may also be seen as including ena described as psychological or
relations of this sort, the private treated as less complex for analytical
stimulation being the unobservable reasons will be shown to be more
component. In behavior-analytic complex in practice. Especially in
publications (e.g. Anderson et al., clinical application of behavior anal-
2000) one instance of this type of ysis, what are dealt with as instances
relation—private verbal stimuli func- of private events may be these sorts
tioning as rules—has been empha- of phenomena. I suggest that behav-
sized to contrast cognitive and be- ior-analytic therapists may unfold
havior-analytic interpretations of this complexity by examining these
cognition. There are also examples phenomena in the light of the princi-
of behavioral relations in which ple of selection by consequences pro-
a private stimulus other than that posed by Skinner (e.g., 1981, 1990).
generated by a covert response exerts
control over a public response. This The Complexity of Private Events as
is usually the case of verbal public Behavioral Relations, and Selection
responses concerning feelings that are by Consequences
partially under the control of in- The complexity of behavioral phe-
teroceptive stimulation. One’s re- nomena may be addressed in several
sponse to an inflamed nerve, for ways. Donahoe and Palmer (1994)
example, may be seen as part of the have argued that complexity is the
pain itself. In this case, the pain is not cumulative result of repeated selec-
a collateral product of contingencies, tive processes:
nor is it simply an observable stimu-
lus or response. It is a behavioral Historical science accounts for complexity as
relation of which a term is unobserv- the outcome of the three-step process of
able. variation, selection, and retention. … Repeat-
When relational phenomena in ing cycles of this three-step process are
sufficient to produce organized complexity in
the field of privacy are considered, we the biological world and—we contend—in the
may be dealing with a single relation, behavioral world as well. (p. 18)
or sets of interlocked relations, that
are more or less complex phenomena. For the present purpose of analyz-
Some psychological concepts, usually ing the varying complexity of private
considered as related to privacy, refer events, I suggest that a productive
to more complex phenomena than alternative is to start with Donahoe
single relations. Concepts such as and Palmer’s (1994) interpretation,
‘‘depression’’ and ‘‘anxiety’’ usually and add to it Skinner’s (e.g., 1981)
refer to sets of relations that are in reference to phylogenesis, ontogene-
some way connected; for example, sis, and culture as the three levels of
patterns of social interaction, self- variation and selection of human
observation repertoires, self-descrip- behavior. I propose that the com-
tive repertoires of bodily conditions, plexity of human behavioral phe-
other public responses under the nomena related to privacy may be
control of self-descriptions, and so treated as a function of repeated
on. What links all these phenomena selective processes involving partici-
to the field of privacy is the fact that pation of phylogenetic, ontogenetic,
for each of them there are relations in and cultural variables. I propose that
PRIVATE EVENTS 25

a continuum of complexity may be show derived stimulus functions.


drawn from this perspective. At one When a person emits a verbal re-
end of this continuum, behavioral sponse like ‘‘I am very angry with this
phenomena would be limited by government!,’’ the response, which is
phylogenetic relations, which include part of his or her anger, not only
responses under the control of events describes a bodily condition or the
that acquired stimulus functions in probability of aggressive behavior
human phylogenetic history. Of towards governmental authorities,
course, this is an ideal end point in but may also control a reduced prob-
our continuum, because no actual ability of social responses towards
relation may be interpreted solely as individuals who share political views
a product of phylogenesis. But some with governmental authorities. This
human responses, like the baby’s is a much more complex anger than
sucking on the mother’s breast or simply the one produced by phyloge-
moving in the direction of the netic or ontogenetic nonverbal con-
mother’s voice, are clearly closer to tingencies.
this end of the continuum. At intermediate points of our
At the other end of the continuum, continuum, there are phenomena de-
we have behavioral phenomena con- fined in terms of more or less
stituted of interlocked relations re- complex relations. One’s depression
sulting from phylogenetic, ontogenet- may include responses (e.g., crying)
ic, and cultural variables. The greater elicited by conditioned stimuli. Or it
complexity here results not only from may also include a high rate of
repeated selective processes but also complaints, a reduced probability of
from the types of variables involved responses towards sources of rein-
in the control, especially the partici- forcement, low rates of social re-
pation of verbal contingencies that inforcement, and so on. These are
make new interlocked relations pos- more complex behavioral phenomena
sible. This is the case, for example, than any phylogenetically selected
when one’s anger is defined not only pattern, but they are less complex
by respondent responses of the than a depression that includes self-
glands and smooth muscles but also descriptions and additional responses
by a set of relations that include under the control of self-descriptions
a high rate of aggressive responses (cf. Cavalcante, 1997; Dougher &
towards a controlling agent (cf. Hackbert, 1994).
Skinner, 1953/1965, p. 362), self-ob- Note that according to the present
servation responses, self-descriptive interpretation, complexity means a
responses, and other responses con- type of inclusiveness. A more complex
trolled by self-descriptions, all pre- behavioral phenomenon is one that
sumably established by previous op- includes additional relations, at some
erant contingencies. In this case, point of our continuum, as a result of
a term of a relation (a stimuli or phylogenetic, ontogenetic, and cultur-
a response) may acquire a stimulus al selective variables. Moving a hand
function to other responses. One’s away from the fire is less complex than
aggression response may be a discrim- cooking an apple pie, which is less
inative stimulus to self-descriptive complex than teaching new home
responses, which in turn may control keepers how to cook. The complexity
discriminatively other responses to- here refers not to the selective pro-
wards the controlling agent or related cesses (ontogenesis is not necessarily
stimuli. Contemporary behavior-an- more complex than phylogenesis) but
alytic literature on verbal behavior to the behavioral results of these
(e.g., S. C. Hayes, Barnes-Holmes, & processes. Also, it is not the principles
Roche, 2001) has argued that verbal of selection that are more inclusive in
stimuli (as in self-descriptions) may one or other selective level but the
26 EMMANUEL ZAGURY TOURINHO

resulting set of relations that come to levels. Some emotions are frequently
define an occurrence of a private interpreted as limited to respondent
event. relations of a phylogenetic origin.
Although the continuum is basi- For example, fear is sometimes inter-
cally grounded on the three types of preted as simply a set of respondent
selective variables, its intervals are relations, physiological responses un-
more numerous than the three sec- der the control of unconditioned
tions based on those variables. The eliciting stimuli. It will be argued
intervals of the continuum may be later that fear often is a more com-
interpreted as corresponding to the plex phenomenon. But the reason
repeated selective processes men- why one is inclined, in some circum-
tioned by Donahoe and Palmer stances, to consider fear a less com-
(1994) and to the extent of the action plex phenomenon is the fact that it is
of the selective variables. That is, a type of ‘‘basic’’ emotion (Ekman,
behavioral phenomena found to be at 1999/2004), that is, an emotion that is
the more complex section of the found in lower levels of complexity,
continuum (the one that includes a result of phylogenetic selective
relations produced on the three levels processes (although it may also as-
of variation and selection) may, in sume more complex features). These
turn, show different degrees of com- emotions have also been mentioned
plexity. Playing checkers, as an ex- in behavior-analytic literature as
ample, is less complex than giving ‘‘primary’’ emotions (cf. Banaco,
a class on radical behaviorist episte- 1999; Millenson, 1967/1975). Some
mology, which in turn is less complex other emotions, like sorrow and guilt,
than describing that class and ana- seem to exist only as more complex
lyzing all the variables of which it was phenomena, produced, at least in
a function. part, by social contingencies. Wheth-
The proposal of a continuum of er or not there are purely basic
complexity based on the causal mode emotions and what constitutes the
of selection by consequences may precise biological basis of emotions
give rise to several discussions in the and feelings in general are controver-
field of interpretation of complex sial issues in biology and psychology.
human behavior. Considering the For the purpose of this paper, it
scope of this paper, it will suffice to suffices to note that what we call
consider some of its implications for emotions may be more or less re-
the analysis of private events. A stricted to phylogenetic selective pro-
preliminary consideration concerning cesses, more or less a product of
private events and selection by con- additional ontogenetic and cultural
sequences is that, in general, phylo- selective processes.
genesis provides unconditioned reflex It was mentioned above that when
responses; ontogenesis produces con- behavior analysts discuss private
ditioned respondent relations and events, their verbal behavior is under
operant relations, some of which are the control of phenomena that show
under the control of conditioned different degrees of complexity. Fear,
stimulus that share a function with for example, might be said to be a less
respondent relations (conditioned or complex feeling than sorrow. But
unconditioned); a culture gives rise to each of these concepts, or each of
self-descriptive responses, some of the concepts related to privacy (or, at
them partially under the control of least, to feelings and emotions), itself
bodily conditions and also verbal and encompasses phenomena with differ-
nonverbal responses under discrimi- ent degrees of complexity. A discus-
native control of self-descriptions. sion of one of these, the concept of
A given private event may show fear, will help to illustrate the idea
components of one or more of those that such concepts are themselves
PRIVATE EVENTS 27

verbal responses emitted under the may also be a variable phenomenon,


control of phenomena that might be then it will be clear why some
adequately treated with the previously assertions about private events are
discussed continuum of complexity. quite controversial (e.g., Alford,
‘‘Fear’’ is a verbal response emitted Richards, & Hanych, 1995; Dougher,
under the control of more or less 1993b; Friman et al., 1998). As
complex sets of relations. Take the a representative private event, fear is
example of a child’s fear of his or not merely a bodily condition, an
her teacher. The child’s fear may event, or a by-product of contingen-
be limited to a set of conditioned cies of reinforcement; nor is it simply
physiological responses (e.g., a higher inaccessible to public observation,
rate of heartbeat) elicited by the nor is it sufficiently described as a set
teacher’s presence. As the child is of organism–environment relations.
exposed to aversive operant contin- The more we can understand the
gencies arranged by the teacher (e.g., variability of fears, and private events
criticisms and threats contingent on in general, the better we can concep-
his or her participation in classroom tualize them, and the more we are
activities), he or she may learn to capable to intervene in consistent and
escape or avoid being in the teacher’s effective ways, theoretically and prac-
presence (e.g., ‘‘getting sick’’ on tically.
school days, hurting a classmate to Similar analyses might be devel-
be taken out of the classroom, asking oped for any emotional concept.
the parents to be taken home, etc.). Sorrow, happiness, sadness, excite-
The child may additionally learn ment, and so on might be interpreted
(when exposed to proper social con- as instances of private events, but
tingencies) to observe his or her body each of them is a verbal response
and to describe him- or herself as emitted under the control of phe-
afraid. The child may also learn, nomena with varying degrees of
through verbal processes, that people complexity. Assertions about their
who feel afraid of teachers are un- causal status, their unobservability,
intelligent people and that it is as well as other features will depend
a shame to be unintelligent. In all largely on the specific occurrence of
these circumstances, we see instances the event we come to examine.
of fear, but these instances are The interpretation offered in this
phenomena that clearly differ in article is also compatible with some
complexity. In all circumstances, co- contemporary proposals by clinical
vert responses and private stimuli are behavior analysts who have ad-
involved, and that makes fear an dressed the problem of emotions.
instance of private events. However, Recent behavior-analytic research
the differences in complexity are so has improved Skinner’s original con-
relevant that they recommend equally ceptualizations of verbal behavior
distinctive approaches to practically and has led to the assumption that
dealing with one’s fear. Changing the verbal processes may give rise to
teaching contingencies may be a suf- original sources of control of human
ficient intervention for an instance of nonverbal behavior. This recognition
less complex fear, whereas verbal has led clinical behavior analysts to
therapy may be a necessary interven- a discussion concerning the need for
tion for an instance of fear that and the techniques and scope of
includes the verbal relations men- verbal behavior therapy (cf. Ander-
tioned above. Thus, to be more son et al., 1997; S. C. Hayes, Stro-
precise, fear is not an ‘‘it’’; there are sahl, & Wilson, 1999; Wilson &
several ‘‘fears.’’ Hayes, 2000; Wilson, Hayes, Gregg,
Once we agree that fear falls in the & Zettle, 2001). One central issue
category of private events and that it surrounds the roles that should be
28 EMMANUEL ZAGURY TOURINHO

ascribed to verbal responses usually Friman et al. (1998) argue that


taken as descriptive of emotions and Skinner’s analysis, in terms of direct
feelings. Research on the roles of relations, is consistent only with
these verbal responses has led to an occurrences of anxiety when verbal
assumption that self-descriptive re- components play no central role.
pertoires often exert control over They assert, however, that there are
other forms of behavior: circumstances in which anxiety is
defined by a set of behavioral rela-
When a human interacts verbally with his or tions, ‘‘not fully explained by the
her own behavior, the psychological meaning direct contingencies in the present
of both the verbal symbol and the behavior
itself can change. This bidirectional property
nor by those in the apprehensible
makes human self-awareness useful, but it also past’’ (p. 145). In these occasions,
makes it potentially aversive and destructive. anxiety may include ‘‘a variety of
(S. C. Hayes et al., 1999, p. 44) functional altering verbal compo-
nents … and related bodily states’’
The topic largely explains the greater (p. 145). This seems to be the case in
interest of clinical behavior analysts many circumstances in which behav-
in private events and their effort to ior therapists have to deal with
enhance our understanding of this anxiety: ‘‘Clinically significant anxi-
subject matter. A review of this field ety appears to refer to avoidance
is beyond the goals of the present responses whose initiating conditions
paper and may be found elsewhere are direct but very remote and whose
(Dougher, 1993a, 1994, 2000; Friman perpetuating conditions are mostly
et al., 1998; S. C. Hayes et al., 1999, derived’’ (p. 143). Relational re-
2001; S. C. Hayes & Wilson, 1993). sponding would explain some com-
In the next paragraphs I will briefly ponents of the phenomenon. Some
suggest that the interpretation for the responses would be under the control
complexity of private events provided of indirect contingencies (stimuli
in this paper is compatible with some whose functions derive from indirect
concerns that arise from clinical in- relations with other events—e.g.,
vestigation of private events, illustrat- avoiding contact with unfamiliar
ed by the contrast between Skinner’s people, described as unreliable in
(1974/1993) and Friman et al.’s (1998) a social environment) explained in
discussions of the concept of anxiety. the light of verbal processes. Addres-
Skinner (1974/1993) argues that sing these verbal processes, if they are
anxiety is a condition felt under important, would necessarily affect
aversive contingencies (including a clinical intervention, and that
a preaversive stimulus in the presence makes private events of the verbal
of which avoidance is not possible) sort an important issue for clinical
that cause behavior directly. Analyz- behavior analysts:
ing one’s behavior under those con-
tingencies suggests that anxiety is at A verbal account of emotion underscores the
the most a bodily condition that values (for clinical behavior analysts) of
needs not necessarily to be taken into attention paid to the client’s private events.
account when practically dealing with Those events include potentially maladaptive
the changes in overt behavior that are verbal and nonverbal responses that are the
direct and indirect results of socialization
said to result from anxiety. After all, within a client’s verbal community. (Friman
one’s ‘‘behavior does not change et al., 1998, p. 146)
because he feels anxious; it changes
because of the aversive contingencies The issues raised by Friman et al.
which generate the condition felt as (1998) offer a distinctive view of the
anxiety. The change in feeling and the different degrees of complexity a pri-
change in behavior have a common vate event reaches when it includes
cause’’ (p. 68). verbal components, which are a prod-
PRIVATE EVENTS 29

uct of a cultural level of determina- Perhaps if the principle of selection


tion. That is, whereas Skinner’s by consequences is admitted as an
(1974/1993) approach to anxiety in effective approach to the features of
terms of direct relations corresponds complex private events (most of the
to the analysis of feelings as behav- phenomena described as psychologi-
ioral relations produced by phyloge- cal), it may serve as a strategy for
netic and ontogenetic variables, the developing the operational analysis
type of verbally influenced anxiety Skinner (1945) called for. That is,
mentioned by Friman et al. illustrates perhaps for each psychological con-
more complex feelings, which are also cept related to privacy, we should ask
the product of cultural variables. about the behavioral components or
Based on the ideas presented by relations produced in each level of
Friman et al. (1998), and before variation and selection. It will prob-
a complaint of anxiety that includes ably be noted that the phenomena
verbal responses of the type ‘‘being these concepts describe present dif-
anxious is very destructive and must ferent degrees of complexity, and it is
be avoided at any time,’’ a clinical in this sense that they lack a scientific
behavior analyst will focus on the precision. However, asking about
functions of that verbal response in those behavioral components or rela-
the control of other verbal and non- tions might work both as a conceptual
verbal responses. This perspective strategy, clarifying the classes of
will probably suggest that the thera- events that we may be dealing with,
pist should work to alter the stimulus and an intervention strategy, clarify-
functions of the verbal responses over ing the relations that need to be
other repertoires of the individual. In changed.
addition to that intervention, the
therapist may have to deal with the CONCLUDING REMARKS
direct relations that are part of the
individual’s anxiety. This need results Scientific psychology has been
from the fact that the verbal compo- more productive in empirical matters
nents of an individual’s anxiety are than on conceptual work (see Ma-
an additional component, an inter- chado, Lourenço, & Silva, 2000).
pretation that is in accordance with Behavior analysis is not an exception,
the inclusiveness view of complexity and private events certainly consti-
developed here. The need to deal with tute one of the topics that require
the direct relations of an ontogenetic further conceptual examination (see
origin is recognized by Friman et al., Anderson et al., 2000; Moore, 2000).
when they suggest that traditional The tentative contribution presented
exposure techniques in the treatment in this paper is largely an interpreta-
of anxiety should be employed, with tion of the issues, following Skinner’s
the help of an analysis of the verbal (1945) example. It is intended to be
aspects of one’s anxiety. consistent with basic behavior-ana-
lytic tenets and to help in clarifying
To be fully effective, exposure may frequently important aspects of private phenom-
have to include all, or at least more, of ena. It may be useful to those who
the events that functionally occasion mal- have an interest in complex human
adaptive avoidance. Most anxious persons behavior, especially in clinical set-
seek treatment to master being in the presence
of the feared object or event while not tings. Thus, I believe it helps to
thinking about or feeling fear. This means clarify (a) the conditions of unobser-
that the verbal aspect of fear is part of the vability of private stimuli and covert
feared event. To incorporate more of the responses, (b) the conditions under
phenomenology of fear in treatment, knowl-
edge of the feared events and of the verbal which private stimuli exert a function
behavior occasioned by the events is therefore in self-descriptions, and (c) the dif-
needed. (p. 150) ferent relations that define instances
30 EMMANUEL ZAGURY TOURINHO

of feelings or other psychological a case report using acceptance-based proce-


dures. The Behavior Analyst, 17, 321–334.
phenomena usually interpreted as Dougher, M. J., & Hackbert, L. (2000).
part of human privacy. Establishing operations, cognition, and
The analysis developed suggests emotion. The Behavior Analyst, 23, 11–24.
that privacy will be better understood Ekman, P. (2004). Basic emotions. In T.
once it is distinguished from the Dalgleish & M. Power (Eds.), Handbook of
cognition and emotion. Sussex, UK: Wiley.
physiological conditions that make Retrieved March 12, 2004, from http://
it possible and limit its scope. Once www.paulekman.com/frame.html (Original
this distinction is made clear, and as work published 1999)
long as we consider the different Friman, P. C., Hayes, S. C., & Wilson, K. G.
(1998). Why behavior analysts should study
degrees of complexity that privacy emotion: The example of anxiety. Journal of
relations may achieve, it should be Applied Behavior Analysis, 31, 137–156.
possible to consider statements re- Hayes, L. J. (1994). Thinking. In S. C. Hayes,
garding privacy more adequately. L. J. Hayes, M. Sato, & K. Ono (Eds.),
Behavior analysis of language and cognition
(pp. 149–164). Reno, NV: Context Press.
REFERENCES Hayes, S. C., Barnes-Holmes, D., & Roche, B.
(2001). Relational frame theory: A post-Skin-
Alford, B. A., Richards, C. A., & Hanych, J. nerian account of human language and
M. (1995). The causal status of private cognition. New York: Kluver Academic/
events. The Behavior Therapist, 18(3), Plenum.
57–58. Hayes, S. C., Strosahl, K. D., & Wilson, K. G.
Anderson, C. M., Hawkins, R. P., Freeman, (1999). Acceptance and commitment therapy:
K. A., & Scotti, J. R. (2000). Private events: An experiential approach to behavior change.
Do they belong in a science of human New York: Guilford.
behavior? The Behavior Analyst, 23, 1–10. Hayes, S. C., & Wilson, K. J. (1993). Some
Anderson, C. M., Hawkins, R. P., & Scotti, J. applied implications of a contemporary
R. (1997). Private events in behavior anal- behavior-analytic account of verbal events.
ysis: Conceptual basis and clinical relevance. The Behavior Analyst, 16, 283–301.
Behavior Therapy, 28, 157–179. Kantor, J. R., & Smith, N. W. (1975). The
Banaco, R. A. (1999). O acesso a eventos reaction system. In J. R. Kantor & N. W.
encobertos na prática clı́nica: Um fim ou Smith (Eds.), The science of psychology: An
um meio? [Access to covert events in clinical interbehavioral survey (pp. 47–55). Chicago:
practice: An end or a means?]. Revista Principia.
Brasileira de Terapia Comportamental e Machado, A., Lourenço, O., & Silva, F. J.
Cognitiva, 1, 135–142. (2000). Facts, concepts, and theories: The
shape of psychology’s epistemic triangle.
Cavalcante, S. N. (1997). Notas sobre o
Behavior and Philosophy, 28, 1–40.
fenômeno depressão a partir de uma per-
Millenson, J. R. (1975). Princı́pios de análise
spectiva analı́tico-comportamental [Some
do comportamento [Principles of behavior
remarks concerning depression from a be- analysis]. Brası́lia: Coordenada. (Original
havior-analytic perspective]. Psicologia: work published 1967)
Ciência e Profissão, 17(2), 2–12. Moore, J. (1984). On privacy, causes and
DeGrandpre, R. J., Bickel, W. K., & Higgins, contingencies. The Behavior Analyst, 7,
S. T. (1992). Emergent equivalence relations 3–16.
between interoceptive (drug) and exterocep- Moore, J. (2000). Thinking about thinking
tive (visual) stimuli. Journal of the Experi- and feeling about feeling. The Behavior
mental Analysis of Behavior, 58, 9–18. Analyst, 23, 45–56.
Donahoe, J. W., & Palmer, D. C. (1994). Observer. (1973). Comments and queries:
Learning and complex behavior. Boston: Private data, raw feels, inner experience,
Allyn and Bacon. and all that. The Psychological Record, 23,
Dougher, M. J. (1993a). Clinical behavior 83–85.
analysis. The Behavior Analyst, 16, 269–270. Observer. (1981). Comments and queries:
Dougher, M. J. (1993b). On the advantages Concerning the principle of psychological
and implications of a radical behavioral privacy. The Psychological Record, 31,
treatment of private events. The Behavior 227–232.
Therapist, 16(8), 204–206. Overskeid, G. (1994). Private events and other
Dougher, M. J. (1994). Clinical behavior causes of behavior: Who can tell the
analysis. The Behavior Analyst, 17, 287. difference? The Psychological Record, 44,
Dougher, M. J. (2000). Clinical behavior 35–43.
analysis. Reno, NV: Context Press. Skinner, B. F. (1945). The operational analysis
Dougher, M. J., & Hackbert, L. (1994). A of psychological terms. Psychological Re-
behavior-analytic account of depression and view, 52, 270–277, 291–294.
PRIVATE EVENTS 31

Skinner, B. F. (1965). Science and human Skinner, B. F. (1993). About behaviorism.


behavior. New York: Free Press. (Original London: Penguin. (Original work published
work published 1953) 1974)
Skinner, B. F. (1968). The technology of Watson, J. B. (1920). Is thinking merely the
teaching. New York: Appleton-Century- action of language mechanisms? British
Crofts. Journal of Psychology, 11, 87–104.
Skinner, B. F. (1981). Selection by conse- Watson, J. B. (1970). Behaviorism (2nd ed.).
quences. Science, 213, 501–504. New York: Norton. (Original work pub-
Skinner, B. F. (1985). Cognitive science and lished 1930)
behaviourism. British Journal of Psychology, Wilson, K. G., & Hayes, S. C. (2000). Why it
76, 291–301. is crucial to understand thinking and
Skinner, B. F. (1989). The place of feeling in feeling: An analysis and application to
the analysis of behavior. In B. F. Skinner drug abuse. The Behavior Analyst, 23, 25–
(Ed.), Recent issues in the analysis of behavir 43.
(pp. 3–11). Columbus, OH: Merrill. (Orig- Wilson, K. G., Hayes, S. C., Gregg, J., &
inal work published 1987) Zettle, R. D. (2001). Psychopathology and
Skinner, B. F. (1990). Can psychology be psychotherapy. In S. C. Hayes, D. Barnes-
a science of mind? American Psychologist, Holmes, & B. Roche (Eds.), Relational
45, 1206–1210. frame theory: A post-Skinnerian account of
Skinner, B. F. (1992). Verbal behavior. Acton, human language and cognition (pp. 211–237).
MA: Copley. (Original work published 1957) New York: Kluver Academic/Plenum.

Você também pode gostar