Você está na página 1de 20

Perceptual Experience and Concepts in Classical Indian Philosophy

First published Thu Dec 2, 2010

Classical Indian Philosophy accepts perception (pratyaka), or perceptual experience, as the primary means of knowledge (prama). Perception (pratyaka) is etymologically rooted in the sense-faculty or the sense-organ (aka) and can be translated as sensory awareness, while prama, on the other hand, is derived from knowledge (pram) and, literally means the instrument in the act of knowing. However, the standard interpretation of perception accepted by classical Indian philosophers, barring the Buddhists and the Vedntins, is that it is a cognition arising within the selfthe knowing subjectfrom mental operations following a sense-object contact. It, therefore, is neither an instrument in the act of knowing, nor a mere sensory awareness. Definitions of perception from various classical Indian philosophy schools are given in section 2 below.

1. Introduction 2. Perspectives on Perception o 2.1 Buddhist nominalism o 2.2 Nyya realism o 2.3 Mms realism o 2.4 Skhya definition o 2.5 Advaita Vednta: direct knowledge 3. Nirvikalpaka and Savikalpaka Pratyaka o 3.1 The basis of Buddhist nominalism o 3.2 The development of Hindu realism: the Nyya mission o 3.3 The Mms advance in realism o 3.4 The bdika (Grammarian) nominalism and realist objections o 3.5 The Advaita Vednta: a compromise on Hindu r ealism 4. Perceptual Illusion Bibliography o Texts in English translation o General works Other Internet Resources Related Entries

1. Introduction
The etymology of perception in Sanskrit underlines a major and, perhaps the most controversial, issue in classical Indian epistemology, viz. is the sensory core all there is to the content of a perceptual experience? Put differently, it is asked whether the content of a perceptual experience is restricted to being unconceptualized (nirvikalpaka), or can any part of it be conceptualized (savikalpaka) as well? The Naiyyikas generally take perception to be a two-staged process: first there arises a nonconceptual (nirvikalpaka) perception of the object and then a conceptual (savikalpaka)

perception, both being valid cognitions. For Buddhists, non-conceptual perceptions alone are valid, while Grammarians (bdikas) deny their validity altogether. Skhya and Mms agree with the Nyya position. These two realist schools, Nyya and Mms, contest the Grammarian as well as the Buddhist positions. Advaita Vednta position on perception seems to agree, in spirit, with the Buddhists, but their reasons for supporting non-conceptual perceptions alone as ultimately valid (paramrthika satta) are very different. This debate, on the role of concepts in perception, is discussed in detail in section 3. A very critical question germane to these epistemological issues is raised by the skeptic Vasubandhu (c. 4th century CE): how do we distinguish veridical perceptions from the non-veridical ones? This is taken up in the last section. Before we start out with the definitions, the following observation may be noted. It is true that the classical Indian philosophers were seriously concerned with the notions of enlightenment, the highest good, freedom from the cycle of rebirth and the attainment of ultimate bliss, etc. Therefore, some even question whether they were concerned with any epistemological questions at all, much less the ones raised here? But they were! For Naiyyikas, in particular, this was a major focus: the reason offered in the early Nyya tradition, in Vtsyyana's (c. 450500 CE) commentary on the Nyya-stra, is that without knowledge of objects there is no success in practical response to them. Not very enlightening, perhaps. However, a much sharper justification comes from Gagea (c. 12th century CE), the founder of the Navya-Nyya school, in the introduction to his great work, Jewel Of Reflection On The Truth (Tattvacintmai): In order that discerning persons may have interest in studying the work, Akapda Gautama (c. 2nd century CE) laid down the stra: Attainment of the highest good comes from right knowledge.. It should not then be surprising that one of the most sophisticated classical Indian treatises dealing with perception, Kumrila's (c. 7th century CE) Pratyakapariccheda (a portion of lokavrttika pertaining to the fourth stra of Mms-stra), discusses the nature and validity of perception without any consideration of its role in the ascertainment of religious and moral truth; in fact, the Mms-stra itself characterizes perception as not being a means of knowing righteousness (Dharma). It is true that epistemological debates in classical Indian philosophy arose in the religiophilosophical context; however, there is plenty of evidence on record to show that classical Indian philosophers were haunted by the very same epistemological concerns that have troubled the minds of Western philosophers through the ages. The controversial classical Indian epistemology issuewhether perception is conceptualized or not?continues to be debated in the Western and Indian philosophy journals even today. That said, what makes this historical inquiry significant is that the epistemological issues in classical Indian philosophy are introduced against the backdrop of radically different metaphysical and ethical presuppositions.

2. Perspectives on Perception

Most classical Indian philosophical schools accept perception as the primary means of knowledge, but differ on the nature, kinds and objects of perceptual knowledge. Here we first survey Buddhist and orthodox Hindu schools' definitions of perception (excluding Vaieika and oga schools since they simply take on board Nyya and Skhya ideas, respectively) and note the issues raised by these definitions. As mentioned above, the orthodox schools generally accept both non-conceptualized (indeterminate) and conceptualized (determinate) perceptual states in sharp contrast to the Buddhist view that perception is always non-conceptualized or indeterminate awareness.
2.1 Buddhist nominalism

The oldest preserved definition of perception in the Buddhist tradition is the one by Vasubandhu (c. 4th century CE), Perception is a cognition [that arises] from that object [which is represented therein] (Frauwallner, 1957, p. 120). However, the more influential and much discussed view is that of later Buddhist philosopher Dinga (c. 480540 CE) for whom perception is simply a cognition devoid of conceptual construction (kalpanpodha). Taber (2005, p. 8) notes two important implications of this definition. First, perception is non-conceptual in nature; no seeing is seeing-as, because that necessarily involves intervention of conceptual constructs, which contaminate the pristine given. Perception is mere awareness of bare particulars without any identification or association with words for, according to Dinga, such association always results in falsification of the object. Referents of the words are universals which, for the Buddhist, are not real features of the world. Second, Dinga's definition only indicates a phenomenological feature of perception; it says nothing about its origin and does not imply that it arises from the contact of a sense faculty with the object. Therefore, for the Buddhist idealist, the object that appears in perceptual cognition need not be an external physical object, but a form that arises within consciousness itself. Both these ideas led to vigorous debates in classical Indian philosophy between the Hindus and the Buddhists. The first of these ideas relates to the notion of non-conceptual perception, the second to idealism. Dinga's philosophy is idealist-nominalist in spirit and his epistemological position is in sync with the Buddhist metaphysical doctrines of no-self and evanescence of all that e ists which, e pectedly, evoke strong reaction from the realist Nyya-Vaieika and Mms schools.
2.2 Nyya realism

The most comprehensive, and the most influential, definition of perception in classical Indian philosophy is offered in Gautama'sNyya-stra 1.1.4: Perception is a cognition which arises from the contact of the sense organ and object and is not impregnated by words, is unerring, and well-ascertained. Expectedly, each part of this definition has raised controversy and criticism. If perception is a cognition (and non-erroneous), then it is a state of knowledge, rather than a means to knowing! How does that constitute a primary means of knowledge? Some Naiyyika commentators, Vcaspati Mira (c. 900980 CE) and Jayanta Bhaa (c. 9th

century CE) among them, suggest that the stra is to be understood by adding to it the term from which (yata ), since the preceding stra-s indicates that Gautama's formulation of this stra was intended to define the instrument of a valid perceptual cognition. Another issue has been the interpretation of the word contact. In what sense are the eye and the ear, the sense organs for vision and auditory perception, respectively, in contact with their objects Here a careful look at the term sannikara, generally translated as contact, helps resolve the issue Sannikara literally means drawing near, and can be interpreted as being in close connection with or in the vicinity of. Thus perception is that which arises out of a close connection between the sense organ and its object. More substantial debates on the nature of perception focus on the adjectives in the latter part of the stra, viz., non-verbal (avyapadeyam), non-erroneous or non-deviating (avyabhichri), and well-ascertained or free from doubt (vyavasytmaka). There is some disagreement among the Naiyyika commentators about the interpretations of the adjectives non-verbal and well-ascertained. Vtsyyana, in his commentary on the Nyya-stra, argues that the adjectives non-verbal and well-ascertained are really part of the definition; non-verbal to point out that perceptual knowledge is not associated with words (Bharthari, the famous Grammarian, on the other hand, holds that awareness is necessarily constituted by words and apprehended through them) and well-ascertained to affirm that perceptual knowledge is only of a definite particular and specifically excludes situations in which the perceiver may be in doubt whether a perceived object a is an F or a G. Vcaspati Mira, argues that the adjective well-ascertained need not be used to exclude the so-called perception in the form of doubt, as doubtful knowledge, being invalid, is already excluded by the adjective non-erroneous. Rather, the term vyavasytmakastands for determinate perceptual judgment. Thus understood, the adjectives non-verbal and determinate seem to be complementary; a piece of nonverbal perceptual knowledge cannot be said to be, at the same time, determinate. Vcaspati Mira posits that these two adjectives indicate two different forms of perceptual cognition and are not to be regarded as its defining characteristics. According to him, Gautama included these adjectives to identify two kinds of perceptual knowledge:avyapadeyam indicates non-conceptual or non-verbal perception and vyavasytmaka indicates conceptual or determinate perceptions. He contends that by the term non-verbal, Gautama refutes the Grammarian view and includes nonconceptual perception and, by the term well-ascertained, he refutes the Buddhist view and includes conceptual or judgemental perceptions as valid. Pradyot Mondal (1982) traces the history of this controversy among Naiyyikas. He offers overwhelming scholarly evidence in favor of the view that Naiyyikas mostly regard the adjectives as part of the definition of perception and do not agree with Vcaspati's interpretation. For most Naiyyikas non-verbal is included to deny the causal role of words in origination of perceptual cognition and, therefore, it applies to non-conceptual and conceptual perceptions both, the difference being that the former is inexpressible in language, while the latter is not. Thus Mondal claims that the adjective non-verbal is sufficient on its own to reject the Grammarian and the Buddhist views of perception. Non -verbal has raised a most contentious debate, for over a millennium, between Nyya and Buddhist

philosophers, and it is still alive today. The role of concepts in perception in dispute in this debatewill be discussed in the next section. The Navya-Naiyyika Gagea objects to the notion sensory connection in the classical Nyya definition of perception, arguing that this makes the definition too wide and too narrow at the same time: too wide because it implies that everyawareness is perceptual being produced by virtue of a connection with the inner sense faculty or mind (manas); too narrow because it fails to include divine perception, which involves no sensory connection. Gagea offers a simpler definition of perception as an awareness which has no other awareness as its chief instrumental cause. Being concerned that his definition may be interpreted as ruling out conceptualized or determinate perception that may have non-conceptual or indeterminate perception as one of it causes, he argues that indeterminate perception can never be the chief instrumental cause of determinate perception, although it is a cause, since it supplies the qualifier or the concept for determinate perception.
2.3 Mms realism

The Purva Mms-stra (MS) were originally composed by Jamini around 200 BCE. The fourth MS 1.1.4 says: The arising of a cognition when there is a connection of the sense faculties of a person with an existing (sat) objectthat (tat) is perception; it is not the basis of the knowledge of Dharma, because it is the apprehension of that which is present. (Taber, 2005:44) There is no consensus among Mms commentators on whether this is intended as a definition of perception, even while an initial reading of it suggests that it may be. Kumrila, the noted Mms commentator argues that the first part of the stra isnot intended as a definition because of the context in which it figures; the stra-s preceding it are concerned with an inquiry into righteousness (Dharma). Moreover, the stra construed as a definition of perception, results in too wide, and not too accurate, a definition, because it only says that perception arises from a connection between the sense faculty and an existing object and does not exclude perceptual error or inferential cognition. Taber (2005, 16), on the other hand, suggests that it is possible to construe MS 1.1.4 as a valid definition, and indeed such a construal was proposed by an earlier commentator, the so-calledVttikra quoted at length by bara in his barabhyam. This, the most extensive commentary on the Mms-stra, suggests that the words of the stra (tat = that and sat = e isting) be switched around for a different reading for the first part of the stra, which would then state that, a cognition that results from connection of the sense faculties of a person with that ( tat) [same object that appears in the cognition] is true (sat) perception. This switch rules out perceptual error and inference; both these present objects other than those that are the cause of the perception.
2.4 Skhya definition

In the oldest Skhya tradition, perception is the functioning of a sense organ. This is clearly inadequate, as the ancient skeptic Jayari Bhaa (c. 8th century CE) is quick to point out. Perception in this sense cannot be a means of knowledge ( prama) as it does not distinguish between proper and improper functioning of sense organs and, therefore, between valid and erroneous perceptions. A more sophisticated definition is later devised wherein perception is an ascertainment [of buddhi or intellect] in regard to a sense faculty (Skhyakrik 5 in Yuktdipik). This implies that perception is a modification of the intellect in the form of selective ascertainment of an object, brought about by the activity or functioning of a sense faculty. In some respects, this characterization of perception as an ascertainment of the intellect neatly captures the idea that perception, being an instrument of knowledge, is the primary means of knowledge. Ascertainment residing in the intellect is regarded as the instrument of perception, while residing in the self it is regarded as the result of the process of perception. Furthermore, theSkhyakrik states that the function of the senses with regard to the objects is a mere seeing (Skhyakrik, 28b), and the function of the intellect, referred to as ascertainment, can be thought of as identification of the object as in this is a cow, etc. (Skhyakrik 5ab). This suggests a two-stage process: first the functioning of the sense faculty results in mere seeing of the object (non conceptualized awareness) and, later this mere seeing is acted upon by the intellect or mind and results in a conceptual identification of the object. This two-stage process is very similar to the detailed account of conceptual (savikalpaka) perception offered by the Mmsakas and the Naiyyikas.
2.5 Advaita Vednta: direct knowledge

According to Advaita Vednta the defining characteristic of perception is the directness of knowledge acquired through perception (Bilimoria, 1980:35). In highlighting the directness of the perceptual process, the Advaitin differs from Nyya and Mms proponents for whom the contact of the sense faculty with its object is central to the perceptual process. Vednta Paribh (ed. 1972: 30) cites pleasure and pain as instances of perception that are directly intuited without any sense object contact. For the Advaitin perception is simply the immediacy of consciousness; knowledge not mediated by any instrument (Gupta et. al., 1991, p. 40). It is worth noting that this definition is very close to that accepted by Navya-Naiyyikas. Like the latter, the Advaitins regard the role of the sensory connection as accidental, rather than essential, to the perceptual process. The Neo-Advaitins accept the distinction between conceptual or determinate perception (they refer to it as viayagata pratyaka) and non-conceptual or indeterminate perception (nirvikaplapka pratyaka), but do not think of non-conceptual perception as simply a prior stage of conceptualized perception, as other Hindu schools do.

3. Nirvikalpaka and Savikalpaka Pratyaka


The Sanskrit term kalpan is variously translated as imagination or conceptual construction and is meant to be the source of vikalpa, roughly translated as concepts, but which may stand for anything that the mind adds to the given. The time-honored differentiation of perception into conception-free perception (nir-vikalpa pratyaka) and

conception-loaded perception (sa-vikalpa pratyaka) is made on the basis of concepts (vikalpa) (Matilal, 1986: 313).
3.1 The basis of Buddhist nominalism

The distinction between non-conceptual and conceptual was first drawn by Dinga who contended that all perception is non-conceptual because what constitutes seeing things as they really are must be free from any conceptual construction. The claim is that a verbal report of proper perception is strictly impossible, for such a report requires conceptualization, which is not perceptual in character; the objects of conceptual awareness are spontaneous constructions of our mind and are essentially linguistic in character. On the other hand, what is seen, the given, does not carry a word or a name as its label and neither is such a label grasped along with the object, nor inherent in it, nor even produced by it; objects-as-such, the real particulars (svalakaas), do not, as Quine would say, wear their names on their sleeves. Furthermore, the sense faculty cannot grasp a concept or a name; if I have never smelt garlic before I first encounter it, I cannot smell it as garlic, though I can smell IT; an olfactory awareness can only grasp a smell present in the olfactory field. The Buddhists argue that a perceiver apprehends only the real particulars, arbitrarily imposes concepts/words on them and believes, mistakenly, that these are really there in the objects and integral to them. The conceptual awareness conceals its own imaginative quality and, because it results directly from experience, the perceiver takes it to be a perceptual experience. The perceiver fails to notice that imagination is involved and mistakenly thinks that he really perceives the constructed world. From the Buddhists standpoint, therefore, a perceiver can only perceive real particulars so that any perceptual experience is always and only at the nonconceptual level.
3.2 The development of Hindu realism: the Nyya mission

The Nyya view evolves in response to Buddhist account of perception. They regard perception as a cognitive episode triggered by causal interaction between a sense faculty and an object. This interaction first results in a sensory impression, nothing more than mere physiological change. This preliminary awareness, non-conceptual perception, is a necessary first step in the process of perception and is invariably followed by a structured awareness leading to conceptual perception. A cognition that is independent of preliminary sensory awareness cannot result in a perceptual judgment. The first awareness does not destroy the perceptual character of the second; rather, it facilitates this subsequent awareness. Non-conceptual perception is an indispensable causal factor for generation of conceptual perception, although memory, concepts and collateral information may also be required. It is important to note that the Nyya notion of vikalpa (in their distinction of nir-vikalpa and sa-vikalpa) is different from that of the Buddhists. Unlike the latter, the Naiyyikas do not think of vikalpa-s as mental creations or imaginative constructions but as objectively real properties and features of objects. Vikalpa in this sense indicates the operation of judging and synthesizing rather than imagining or constructing. Thus conceptual perceptions truly represent the structure of reality. Of the five types of concepts (vikalpa-s) recognized by the Buddhists,

viz. nma (word), jti (universal), gua(quality), kriy (action) and dravya (substance), the Naiyyikas, regard all but the first vikalpa as categories of reality (Mondal, 1982, p. 364). Unlike the Grammarians, the Nyya schools do not accept the objective reality of words; words are not inherent to the object presented in perception. Rather, the Naiyyikas hold that the relation between word and object is created by convention in a linguistic community. Although a concept is associated with a word (nma-vikalpa) by means of a convention, it is not merely a fabrication. For example, when someone brings garlic clove near my nose and teaches me by pointing to it that it is called garlic, then subsequently confronted with the garlicky odor and a similar clove, I can see it and smell it as garlic. Thus perceptual awareness includes knowledge of words but, insofar as it is perceptual awareness, it is brought about by sensory contact with the object and, its properties which exists independently of words. The Buddhists reject this argument on the basis tarthakriysmarthya). Only particular real garlic can flavor one's food or ruin it, but the universal garlichood cannot do any of these; in this sense, only the particulars are real for they fulfill the purposes (artha) of humans. The foregoing discussion shows that the epistemological debate between the Buddhists and the Naiyyikas regarding the nature of perception rests on, and brings to the fore, their metaphysical disagreement about the nature of universals. The Naiyyikas are realists about universals; universals are objective features of the world that impress themselves upon minds they are not mere figments of our imagination. The Naiyyikas hold that particulars are qualified propertied wholes and we directly perceive them as they are, without any kind of manipulation or imposition; we do not impose universals on property-less real particulars, rather we find stable, durable, relational wholes in reality that do not require any imposition or manipulation. They argue that there is no evidence of a world of bare particulars, as claimed by the Buddhists. Therefore conceptual or determinate perception does not involve distortion of reality; rather it presents things as they really are. To see a piece of sandalwood as itreally is, we do not need to see the sandalwood as a colorless, odorless pure particular; indeed, since the piece of sandalwood is really brown and really fragrant, to see it as a propertied whole is to see it as it really is. The idea that the world consists of propertied particulars seems to put pressure on the notion of non-conceptual perception. If there are no indeterminate particulars, what is the object of indeterminate perception? Indeed some Navya-Nyya thinkers hold that the raw data of perception (real particulars in the Buddhists sense) is too inchoate and elusive to count as objects of knowledge. Recently, Arindam Chakrabarti (2000), a prominent contemporary Navya-Nyya thinker offered seven reasons for altogether eliminating non-conceptual, or immaculate perceptions as he calls them, from Nyya epistemology in an attempt to understand the deeper relation between direct realism and concept-enriched perception. Chakrabarti's skepticism about non-conceptual perception as a cognitive state stems from the fact that we cannot assign an intentional role to the object of indeterminate perception because the object of non-conceptual perception is incapable of being apperceived or directly intuited in

it [nirvikalpa pratyaka] is posited by the force of the following inference as the first step of a two step argument. The perceptual cognition A cow (for e ample) is generated by a cognition of the qualifier, since it is a cognition of an entity as qualified (by that qualifier appearing) like an inference. The second step takes a person's first perception of an individual (Bessie, let us say) as a cow (i.e., as having some such property) as the perceptual cognition figuring as the inference's subject (paka) such that the cognizer's memory not informed by previous cow experience could not possibly provide the qualifier cowhood. The qualifier has to be available, and the best candidate seems to be its perception in the raw, a qualifier (cowhood), that is to say, not (as some are wont to misinterpret the point) as divorced from itsqualificandum (Bessie) but rather as neither divorced nor joined, and, furthermore, not as qualified by another qualifier (such as being-a-heifer) but rather just the plain, unadorned entity. In the particular example, the entity is the universal, cowhood, or being-a-cow, although, again, it would not be grasped as a universal. Or as anything except itself. The Navya-Nyya notion of non-conceptual perception differs from that of the Buddhists in many respects, two of which are very important. First, according to NavyaNaiyyikas, there is no apperceptive evidence for non-conceptual perception, unlike the Buddhists who contend that conception-free awareness is necessarily self-aware. The Navya-Naiyyikas, as is obvious from the quote above, emphasize that the evidence for a non-conceptual sensory grasp of universals comes in the form of an inference. Second, according to Navya-Nyya, the object of non-conceptual perception is a qualifier (concept), although not given as that in the first instance, but not a bare particular as the Buddhists hypothesize. It is, as the above quote explains, posited by the force of an inference the bare object of non-conceptual perception becomes the qualifier in a resultant determinate perception. While this does not satisfactorily address Chakrabarti's concern that lack of apperceptive evidence implies that the subject cannot assign an intentional role to the object of non-conceptual perception, Chadha (2006) argues that the subject's not being in a position to assign an intentional role to the object of nonconceptual perception is no hindrance to the intentionality of non-conceptual perception itself. Non-conceptual perception is awareness of a non-particular individual (Chakrabarti, 1995) and can be assigned the intentional role of a qualifier in virtue of the recognitional abilities acquired by the subject on the basis of the perceptual episode. The subject sees a non-particular individual but, since there is no apperceptive or conscious awareness, the subject does not see it as an instance of a universal or a qualifier. Chadha e plicates Gagea's insight that a qualifier is given as a non-particular individual, neither divorced from nor joined to the qualificandum and, therefore it is wrong to suggest that lack of apperceptive evidence implies that non-conceptual perception is not an intentional perceptual state.
3.3 The Mms advance in realism

Kumrila argued against the Buddhist position to show that perception is not always devoid of concepts. InPratyakapariccheda, he principally targets Dinga's theory, while simultaneously addressing some of Dharmakrti's ideas and arguments. Kumrila, like Naiyyikas, holds both the two kinds of perception as valid. For him the initial non -

conceptualized perception is borne of the undifferentiated pure object (uddhavastu) and is comparable to the perception of an infant and others who lack a language. The pure object is the substratum for the generic and specific features of the object, but the subject is not distinctly aware of any of these and simply cognizes the object as an indeterminate particular, as this or something. Although Kumrila agrees with the Buddhists that the object of immediate perception is inexpressible in language, he maintains that it is different, in at least one respect, from the real particular (svalakaa) of the Buddhists; the latter being a structure-less unitary whole, whereas the former is non-unitary and grasps both the particular and the universal aspects of the object. Otherwise, Kumrila argues, it could not give rise to conceptual awareness, which e plicitly identifies such features. Dinga's counterpoint to this is that conceptual awareness at second stage cannot be a perception, since it involves application of concepts and words which, in turn, requires memory. If we admit conceptual awareness as perception, we are forced to accept that a sense faculty is capable of remembering (since perception is a cognition brought about by the functioning of the sense faculty) but that cannot be the case because a sense faculty, being a mere instrument of cognition, is in itself unconscious and cannot remember anything. Kumrila admits that conceptual awareness is aided by memory and concepts, but argues that that does not rob it of its perceptual character for the sense faculty is still functioning while in contact with the very same object. He further suggests that we should not expect a perceptual cognition to arise as soon as there is contact between a sense faculty and its object. He uses the analogy of entering a dimly lit room after walking in the blazing sun; even though the contents of the room are directly available to the sense faculties of the subject who has just walked in, he does not immediately apprehend the objects in front of him. However, the subject may become distinctly aware of the objects in the room and their features in the following moments. The perceptual character of the latter awareness is maintained so long as the connection between the sense faculty and the object is intact, even when other conceptual awarenesses or memories intervene between the initial contact with the object and the subsequent awareness. A conceptual awareness can be referred to as a perception even though the mind,qua memory, is involved because the functioning of the sense faculty is the factor responsible for arising of the awareness. Furthermore, he insists that the mind must be involved in all perceptions since it functions as a link between the sense faculty and the self; the sense faculty is turned on or activated by a connection with the self and, the self as the subject of knowledge is involved in all cognitions. He points out that even Buddhists do not deny this, since they hold that selfreflexive awareness accompanies every cognition. He contends that the Buddhists are wrong to insist that only a cognition arising directly from the functioning of a sense faculty is perception; they agree that we perceive inner states, e.g., pleasure and pain, and if the mind is accepted as the operative sense faculty in the self-reflexive awareness of such cognitions, it follows that they should admit that the mind is also the sense faculty that gives rise to conceptualized cognitions. He, however, clarifies that not every cognition that follows a contact between a sense faculty and an object is a perception, for if one were to open one's eyes momentarily (in the above analogy) and construct a judgment such as that was table with eyes closed again, it would not be a perceptual cognition since it solely depends on the memory of a fleeting sensory contact.

Later, Dharmakrti, using a methodology very different (and akin to proof by contradiction) from his predecessor Dinga, raises new problems for the NyyaMms view. Assuming, he says, for the sake of the argument, that universals are real. Then the judgments This is a cow, It is an animal, relate two distinct entities, namely a particular (or object) and a universal (or concept) arguably via a non-relational tie as in being substratum and superstratum, with the proviso that the substratum object has the power to let the universal reside in it. This leads to all the universals (such as cowness, animalhood, etc) then being tied to the object by this simple and single power. In such a scenario, any perceptual judgment involving the universal cowhood as in the case of This is a cow makes subsequent judgments This is an animal, This is a substance, etc., superfluous. For, if one perceives an object along with its power to let any one universal reside in it, one must be able to perceive its power to attract all other universals that reside in it. Thus, there would be no distinction between This is a cow and This is a substance clearly an unacceptable thesis. Matilal (1986, p.326) notes two points in connection with this argument. First, Dharmakrti assumes that an object, or a unique particular, is perceived in its entirety and no part of it is left unperceived. Second, the realist has objectified all the universals including the relation-universal. If, as the realist believes, the object of perceptionthe particularhas the power to accommodate all universals in it, then the onus is on him to show why only a single universal manifests itself in a perceptual judgment. This concern is pertinent, especially against the Nyya philosophers who admit only one single relation-universal: inherence, which supposedly unites all nesting universals with the object. The Naiyyikas readily respond to this argument by pointing out that the redundancy objection rests on Dharmakirti's assumption that an object is grasped in its entirety in perception. This assumption is false; perception is perspectival, we never see all sides of an ordinary three-dimensional object, but we still see it. Furthermore, Dharmakrti's argues that conceptual or judgmental awareness is phenomenologically distinct from non-conceptual awareness. In the latter we are confronted with the object of perception which is vivid and immediate, while in the former no object is present. In the judgment this is a cow, even the subject of the judgment does not refer to the object of perception, since words do not refer to perceived particulars but to universals which e tend across space and time. Dharmakrti admits that the words we apply to things have some objective basis in those things; we call something a cow because it has a certain effect, it gives milk, is gentle, or it calls forth a certain cognition, etc. This effect, in turn, inclines us to associate the word cow with other things that have the same effect and we do that by jointly dissociating them from things that lack that effect. Universals, according to the Buddhists are arbitrarily constructed e clusions (apoha); words serve the purpose of separating things off from other objects. For e ample, the word cow singles out a class of things by e cluding them from things they are not, all things assembled together under the concept cow are distinct from each other and do not share a single nature that the word cow names. A conceptual awareness insofar as it imputes a word to a particular object and, therefore a universal nature it shares with all others of the same universal-kind, essentially falsifies the object. Kumrila objects to the Buddhists theory of universals (apoha) on the grounds that it is counterintuitive and circular. The theory of universals (apoha)

contradicts our intuition that meaning of a positive word is positive; there is nothing negative about the word cow. A negative entity can be the meaning of a word only where something is negated. Moreover, if we accept that understanding x requires eliminating non-x, then in turn we presuppose knowledge of non-x, which entails an understanding of non-non-x, and so on (Drefyus, 1997, p.215). The Mmsakas also take on board the concerns raised by the Naiyyika philosopher Uddyotakara (c. 7th century CE), who questions the theory of exclusions on the specific grounds that it fails to offer an adequate theory of reference and relation between concepts and reality. He argues if the word cow primarily designates a negative entity, either this entity is a cow in disguise or is different from a cow. If it is a cow in disguise then the Buddhist view of universals is no different from the Nyya common sense realism that words are used to single out phenomena in the world. If the negative entity is different from a cow, then the word cow does not refer to real cows, making it difficult to e plain how any word can refer to real objects or classes thereof. This last point begs the question because the Buddhist denies that words refer to the objects in the real world. For him words refer to universals, and that is precisely what the world does not contain. The onus is put back on the realists to show that universals, which serve as meanings of words, are real properties of objects rather than imagined or mentally constructed features. This challenge is taken up by the Naiyyikas and their position against the nominalist stand of both the Buddhists and the Grammarians is presented later below.
3.4 The bdika (Grammarian) nominalism and realist objections

Bharthari, the most notable Grammarian, highlights the intimate relation between language, thought, and knowledge. Two aspects of his theory have important implications for the nature of perceptual experience. First, there is no non-linguistic cognition in the world all knowledge appears permeated by words. Though Bharthari's theory may leave room for extraordinary, or other-worldly, cognitions, there is no scope for pure non-conceptualized perception in this world. The essence of his theory is: words do not designate objects in the external world directly, but through the intervention of universals, which are inherent in words. Thus universals constitute the basis of our knowledge of the external world, since they are intimately connected with language and mind on the one hand, and the world on the other. Given this, the Grammarians question the very possibility of non-conceptual perception? The second aspect is underscored by Kumrila who ascribes the so-called Superimposition Theory to Bharthari (Taber, 2005, p.27), according to which, a word has its own form superimposed upon its meaning. This has implications for determinate conceptual perception, which (for the pluralists and direct realists of Mms and Nyya persuasions) arises purely out of the object itself and involves discrimination and determination of its nature. Bharthari's argument can be thought of as an attack, on the adjective non-verbal (avyapadeyam) in the Nyya definition of perception, aimed at their belief that for cognitive comprehension language is an inessential detail. For him, bare senseimpressions cannot count as awarenesses because they are nor effective enough, nothing is accomplished by them and, they do not result in appreciable mental activity. Bharthari gives an e ample: a man walking along a village path to approach his house

would invariably touch some grass on the road, and in some sense this would be tactile awareness at a pre-linguistic level (Vkyapadya, Ch.1, verse 123). But this would not count as an awareness unless combined with the further ability to sort it out or verbalize it; consciousness cannot reveal an object to us unless we discriminate it, and the process of discrimination requires verbalization. What about a baby's awareness, or that of a mute person, asks Vtsyyana Bharthari points out that a baby's sensations or a mute person's awarenesses may still count as cognitive because they are linguistically potent. A pre-linguistic state of an infant can be cognitive if and only if it has speech potency, which is the cause of verbal language. So also, in the non-conceptual perceptual awareness (in adults and even some animals) speech-potency is latent; it is an essential trait of human consciousness and the defining characteristic of cognitive awareness (Vkyapadya, Ch.1, verse 126). All knowledge of what is to be done in this world depends on speech-potential; even an infant has such knowledge due to residual traces from previous births (Vkyapadya, Ch.1, verse 121). The initial sensory awareness of external objects which does not grasp any special features of them, nonetheless illuminates them in a non-specific manner as mere things by such e pressions as this or that (Bharthari 123 and 124). Thus, insofar as the initial sensation is an awareness, it can be verbalized. The following analogy is offered as an argument for positing the presence of speech-seed (verbal disposition, as some modern philosophers call it) in prelinguistic awareness: think about the experience of trying, but failing, to remember a verse heard before. Bharthari claims that the entire verse e ists in the cognitive faculty as speech-potency but because of lack of other contributory factors there is no verbalization. Similarly, a non-linguistic experience of a mute-person is an awareness because of the presence of verbal disposition or speech-seed even though there is no actualization of speech. There are no non-conceptual perceptions, because ordinary objects are not given to us without a concept (vikalpa) or some mode of presentation; verbalization makes the concept explicit. There are infinite concepts associated with an object, none integral to it. However, we always perceive an object in a concept as an instantiation of a universal; it is a cow, white, bovine, four-legged, etc. The point to note is that concepts or universals (vikalpa-s) are word-generated and superimposed on the objects there are no thing-universals or real universals over and above these. Bharthari's defends linguistic nominalism, according to which, words are the only universals that exist; thing-universals are word-generated illusions. As Matilal remarks, for Bharthari there is not much of a distinction between words and concepts, they are two sides of the same coin (Matilal, 1986, 396). Naiyyikas and Mmsakas, the common sense realists, raise specific objections to the Grammarian view on the grounds that it is not borne by experience. We have separate awarenesses of words and universals. While we may not perceive something as a cow prior to acquiring the word cow, we are surely aware of cowness before we acquire the linguistic expression, just as we are aware of and can discriminate shades of red even before we acquire the names of some of those shades. A non-conceptual awareness of the object is implied by the subsequent occurrence of a conceptual awareness with determinate content. Kumrila also points to other phenomena which indicate that the awareness of the meaning of a word (the object) is independent and distinct from the word itself. Furthermore, awareness of the meaning and that of the word are usually

different kinds of representations; there is no possibility of confusing or conflating these. Kumrila brings to attention linguistic phenomena that reinforce the point that words and meanings must be distinct representations, e.g., homonymy, synonymy, categorizing and recognizing grammatical parts of speech, etc. The ability to distinguish and discriminate types is perhaps enhanced by knowledge of language and concepts, but is not completely dependent on it. Those who are not trained in music can certainly hear the difference between distinct notes, even though they are unable to identify them by name. Vtsyyana also appeals to the ordinary experience of people who are conversant with words. Ordinarily, words are apprehended as names of objects. The knowledge of the word-object association comes after the perceptual knowledge derived through senseobject contact. Such contact results in a perceptual awareness which, in turn, provides the occasion for recalling the appropriate word, if indeed the appropriate word exists in the experiencer's linguistic repertoire. Perceptual knowledge is antecedent to verbal knowledge and cannot owe its existence to words. Vcaspati Mira specifically objects to Bharthari's claim that infants and adults who lack a language perceive objects by memory impressions of their names from previous births. Objects are vividly and clearly given to us in perception, but the memory-impressions of previous births are at best vague and indistinct. Vcaspati Mira asks, How can such a vague and unclear thing be identified with a clear and distinct perception (Nyyavrttikattparyak, p. 127). His other argument against Bharthari is the obvious point that words do not necessarily refer to their objects, for example words in quotation marks do not refer to objects, only to themselves. Moreover, if the word and its denotation were identical, a blind man would grasp red or redness when he grasps the word red and a deaf person would grasp the word red when he grasps a red thing (Nyyavrttikattparyak, p. 129). The Naiyyikas also have a general response to nominalistsBuddhists as well as Grammarians. They posit monadic universals that correspond to natural and metaphysical kinds and one dyadic universal, viz. inherence. The main nominalist objection is that once we accept real universals in our ontology we risk overpopulating the world with entities corresponding to every expression that designates a property. For example, if we accept horsehood and cowhood as universals, we also need to accept universalhood as another universal. The Naiyyikas propose that not every e pression which designates a property generates an objective universal (jti); some propertyexpressions correspond to subjectively constructed categories (updhi), which though useful for analysis, are not ontologically real. Uddyotakara argues that to correspond to a real universal a general term must meet two conditions: (i) a general term should be based on a ground, which accounts for the common awareness of a number of different objects, that makes the application of the term possible, and (ii) that ground should be a simple (non-compound), unitary property or entity that cannot be analyzed or explained away otherwise (Commentary on Nyya-stra, 2.2.65). Universalhood is a bogus universal; it violates the second condition. There is no simple basis or ground for universalhood as opposed to universals such as cowhood and horsehood; the ground of being one-in-many can be analyzed in terms of inherence. The same applies to universals like barefooted, cook, reader etc. the basis for their application is presence of compound features such as bare feet, etc. However, this stratagem forces the Naiyyikas to admit that many general terms designate bogus universals and,

consequently, they start succumbing to the nominalist pressure. Matilal (1986, p. 420 421) notes that there is another way in which it happens to Navya-Nyya: A real universal must partake of the nature of one-in-many. The Navya-Naiyyika, Udayana (c. 10th century CE), lists a third necessary condition for disqualifying a property from being regarded as a real universal. Under this condition, an abstract property that belongs only to one individual is also a bogus universal even though it is simple and unanalyzable; skyness in the sky is bogus because it is only a nominal attribute. However, since both cowhood and skyness are simple properties, they are grasped as such in perception without further qualification. In this sense, Naiyyikas maintain that some real universals are directly perceptible. When we see a cow, we do not necessarily see it as a cow, the cow and the cowness are not given as separate entities in our awareness, rather they appear fused. This leads to the peculiar Nyya view that real universals and basic properties are grasped in our awareness as epistemic firsts or ultimates (Matilal, 1986, p.421). Gagea calls such perception, in which universals are grasped as such, non-conceptual (nirvikalpaka) perception.
3.5 The Advaita Vednta: a compromise on Hindu realism

The Advaita Vednta theory compromises on the realism of earlier classical Hindu philosophy. Their early view on perception is akin to the Buddhists, although arrived at from a different perspective. Maana Mira says: Perception is first, without mental construction, and has for its object the bare thing. The constructive cognitions which follow it plunge into particulars. ( Brahma-Siddhi, 71.1-2) He draws a distinction between perceptual cognition and constructive cognition, but is careful to use vikalpa-buddhi, rather than savikalpaka pratyaka, for the latter cognition. For him perception is always non-conceptual (nirvikalpaka) perception and it is of a universal, indeed of the highest universal, Being (sat). According to early Vedntins, the real is bereft of all character since its nature is non-differentiated consciousness or Brahman. Therefore, perceptual cognition, which presents the real, must be nonconceptual or indeterminate for it is the knowledge of the existence of a thing without any qualifications or predications. Maana Mira also denies the thesis that nonconceptual (nirvikalpaka) perception is non-verbal. This surprising claim is clearly owed to Bharthari's influence, as is evidenced by the e ample used by Maana Mira in the argument. Confronted by an opponent with the claim that verbal knowledge involves duality and relation, and therefore must involve concepts, Maana Mira replies that verbal knowledge is not necessarily relational: a baby's non-verbal knowledge of its mother's breast, grasps it merely as this (of course we do not assume that the baby articulates the word this the word, as in Bharthari's account, has a more subtle form in the baby's mind) and, therefore, the highest knowledge of the Ultimate reality (Brahman) in which there is no duality, no relations, no concepts, may still be verbal. Neo Advaita-Vedntins, however, accept a distinction between non-conceptual (nirvikalpaka) perception and conceptual (nirvikalpaka) perceptions from empirical or practical (vyvahrika) standpoint; from ultimate (paramrthika) standpoint such

distinction is untenable. A brief description of conceptual (viayagata, Advaita-Vednta term for savikalpaka) perception will help put in perspective Applebaum's (1982) reconstruction of their notion of non-conceptual (nirvikalpaka) perception later. Determinate perception is the result of the activity of mind (manas) or anta karaa (literally translated as inner vehicle)the terms are frequently used interchangeably. Advaitins maintain that the mind (anta karaa) goes out through the respective sense organ (the eye, say) and pervades the object of attention. As a result of this contact, the object presents itself as data to the receptive mind (anta karaa) which, in turn, transforms into mental state (vtti) (Bilimoria, 1980, p.38). As soon as the data are presented to inner faculty, there is an identification of consciousness associated with the mental state (anta karaa-vtti) with the consciousness associated with the object. To say that vtti and data are identified is to say that the form of the mental state, if all goes well, corresponds one-to-one with the form of the object; the mental state is a reflection of the object of perception, and as such is non-different from the object. Thus results a determinate judgment (vttijna) of the form this is a jar. Furthermore, according to them, we do not perceive our mental states; we directly perceive the objects themselves. Bilimora explains, The vtti in the form of the object impresses itself as it were in the mode of the subject itself, and thereby comes to be apprehended, but as a predicateand not as the pure subject-content which is the I-notionin the subject's apperception. (Bilimoria, 1980, p.41) The initial mental state subsides and the subject becomes directly aware of the object itself; the cognition is self-evident to the subject, just like the cognition of pleasure and pain. In this reflective stage, the mind (anta karaa) integrates the mental contents corresponding to the object with familiar or recognized percepts. Determinate perception of the totality of the object occurs with the completion of the assimilative process. David Applebaum (1982) notes that Bilimoria's discussion of the Advaitin's notion of perception focuses on the necessary conditions or criteria for valid or veridical perceptions. According to him, this approach while justified in the light of perception's inclusion among the means of knowledge (prama-s) is mistaken because it only focuses on sensation as a species of mental state (vtti). For the Advaitin, sensation is not a mode exhausted by the judgmental content of a mental state (vtti), it has epistemic value independently of its role in judgmental perception. Applebaum quotes from the Upanisadic texts to support this view: Manas is for men a means of bondage or liberation of bondage if it clings to objects of perception (visayasangi), and of liberation if not directed towards these objects (nirviayam). (Applebaum, 1982, p.203) Non-conceptual perception furnishes us with knowledge of pure existence ( sanmtra) rather than with protodata to construct imagined particulars. Therefore, it is not simply a prior stage of conceptual perception and so also not necessarily a mental state produced in cooperation with the object. Applebaum (1982, p.204) suggests that non-conceptual

perception in this sense focuses attention on sensing, in which consciousness turns its attention inwards to the activity of the sense-organs resulting in deepening and broadening their proprioceptive content. Proprioception, he claims, points the way to the soul or self (tman); mind (anta karaa) returns to its presentational activity, its function of monitoring and unfolding the sensory manifold to create conditions for the emergence of self (tman), which according to the Advaitin, is identical with the Ultimate reality (Brahman). In non-conceptual (nirvikalpaka) perception, consciousness is returned to itself and opens up the possibility of manifesting or seeing the Seer (tman) or knowing the Ultimate reality (Brahman).

4. Perceptual Illusion
The skeptics challenge strikes at the claim made by the Naiyyikas that perception should be non-erroneous (avyabhichri) and well-ascertained or free from doubt (vyavasytmaka). They ask: how do we distinguish between veridical perceptions and the non-veridical ones? In case of a perceptual doubt, say, seeing something at a distance which looks like a pole or an old tree-trunk, we are uncertain which it is but are a priori sure it cannot be both. In case of perceptual illusion, I see a snake but I misperceive as there is only a rope in front of me. Illusoriness of the experience (seeing a snake) is exposed with reference to another veridical experience (seeing a rope), but again, we are a priori sure that both cannot be true together. Then, the Buddhist skeptic, Vasubandhu, raises the ante with the question: could they not both be false simultaneously? The skeptical argument is premised on a denial of the realist thesis that experiences refer to a mind-independent reality. Vasubandhu's argument for idealism appears right at the beginning of Vimatik, when he states: This [the external world] is consciousness only, because there is appearance of nonexistent things, just as a person with cataracts sees non-existent hairs, moons et cetera. (Feldman, 2005, p. 529). Vasubandhu offers many other examples of dreams, delusions, hallucinations, etc., where we are aware of non-existent objects that are products of our imagination and not objects external to the mind. If it is possible for awareness to create its own object and then grasp it (as in a dream) then, Vasubandhu argues, everything that we seem to be aware of could be a making of awareness. The standard reply to this view appeals to the intuition that illusory experience is parasitic on veridical e perience. The Naiyyika, Vtsyyana e plains that an erroneous cognition depends on a principal cognition as its basis. This is a man for a tree-trunk, which is not a man, has for its basis a principal cognition of a man. If a man has never been perceived in the past, an erroneous cognition of a man, in what is not a man, can never be produced (Nyya-Stra-Bhya, 4.2.35). A similar argument is put forth by the Advaita-Vedanta founder ankara. He challenges Vasubandhu's view on the ground that it is incoherent when the Buddhists say that which is the content of an internal awareness appears as though e ternal, they are

assuming the e istence of an e ternal thing even while they deny it For they use the phrase as though because they become aware of a cognition appearing e ternally For nobody speaks thus: Vinumitra appears like the son of a barren woman. (BrahmaStra-Bhya, 2.2.28) Feldman (2005, p. 534) argues that this does not suffice to defeat Vasubandhu's idealism. The illusory experience of x, no doubt requires a memory impression which can be produced by a previous cognition, but there is no further requirement that the previous experience be veridical, because such impressions can be produced by illusory experiences. Feldman uses the case of someone who has only experienced snakes in dreams. He can mistake a rope for a snake, because the previous dream experience provides the necessary memory impression. Feldman's argument ignores the gravity of the concern raised by Vtsyyana and ankara, however. They reject Vasubandhu's argument on the grounds that we cannot imagine (dream, hallucinate, etc) an absolutely unreal thing, like a barren woman's son. The Nyya theory of imagination, working in the background here, says that to imagine something is to superimpose or attribute properties belonging to one kind of thing to a thing of different kind, provided that there is some resemblance between the two kinds of objects (Uddyotakara's Nyya-StraBhya, 3.1.1). For example, to imagine a centaur is to attribute a property belonging to the human-kind to a thing of the horse-kind. There is some general resemblance between the two kinds: both are animals and have legs. However, an absolutely unreal thing can have no properties, and hence a fortiori no properties in common with an existing thing. They, therefore, cannot be an object of imagination. Uddyotakara presents an even stronger argument against the skeptics. In his NyyaVrttika he turns Vasubandhu's own argument against him. Uddyotakara asks: how do we know that the object of a dream experience is non-existent? Vasubandhu accepts that the dreamer does not know that he is dreaming; the knowledge that the object is nonexistent occurs only when he awakens and no longer apprehends the object. If nonapprehension of an object in the waking state is required to support the claim that the objects of dream experience do not really exist out there, then apprehension in the waking state must be an indicator of their existence, otherwise there would be no contrast between what is apprehended and what is not (Nyya-Vrttika, 4.2.33). If there is no such contrast, then Vasubandhu's argument fails because there is no support for the claim that objects of dream experiences do not exist in the external world. And, if there is such a contrast between apprehension and non-apprehension, then at least some external objects must exist. Clearly, Vasubandhu's argument for thesis of universal delusion (or idealism) does not succeed completely, nor are the realists totally defeated. We close this article on the note that Stra-s were primarily composed in the seven centuries from 5th BCE to 2nd CE and, thereafter, for the next millennium and more, the philosophical work was carried forward by Stra commentators (tikkr-s) from respective schools. This latter period saw these epistemological debates rage among scholars from these schools. Note also that there is no consensus on the dates given here; most Western scholars accept these, while Indian schools place them further back in antiquity.

Bibliography
Texts in English translation

Aksapada Gautama, Nyya-Stra, with Vatsyayana's Nyayabhasya, Uddyotakara's Nyayavartikka, and Udayana'aParisuddhi, A. Thakur (ed. and trans.), vol. 1, Mithila, 1967. Bhartrhari, Vkyapadya, Abhyankar K.V. and Limaye V.P. (eds.), Poona University, 1965. Gagea, Tattvacintmai, Epistemology Of Perception: Gagea's Tattvacintmai, Jewel Of Reflection On The Truth (About Epistemology): The Perception Chapter (Pratyaka-khaa), Transliterated Text, Translation, And Philosophical Commentary, by Stephen H. Phillips and N.S. Ramanuja Tatacharya. Treasury of the Indic Sciences. New York: American Institute of Buddhist Studies, 2004. Uddyotakara, Nyaya-Vartika, in The Nyya-Stras of Gauama: With the Nyya-straBhya of Vtsyyana and theNyaya-Vartika of Uddyotakara, Gangnha Jh (trans.), Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1984. Uddyotakara, Nyya-Stra-Bhya, Translations from the introductory commentary on Nyya-Stra-Bhya, Arindam Chakrabarti (trans.), published as an appendix to A. Chakrabarti, The Nyya Proofs for the E istence of the Soul,Journal of Indian Philosophy, 10: 211238, (1982). Vcaspati Mira, Nyyavrttikattparyak, Anantlal Thaur (ed.), Indian Council of Philosophical Research, 1996. Vasubandhu, Viatik-Vtti, Triatika, and Tri-Svabhva-Nirdea, Thomas Kochumuttom (trans.), in A Buddhist Doctrine of Experience: A New Translation and Interpretation of the Works of Vasubandhu the Yogcrin, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1982. Kumarila Bhatta, The Determination of Perception Chapter of Slokavarttika , A Hindu Critique of Buddhist Epistemology: The Determination of Perception Chapter of Kumarila Bhatta's Slokavarttika commentary by Taber, J. (trans.), Routledge Curzon Hindu Studies Series, New York: Routledge Curzon, 2005.
General works

Appelbaum, D., 1982, A Note on Pratyaka in Advaita Vednta, Philosophy East and West 32:2, pp. 201205. Bhatt, Govardhan P. 1989, The Basic Ways of Knowing, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. Bilimoria, P., 1980, Perception (Pratyaka) in Advaita Vednta, Philosophy East and West, 30(1): 3544. Chadha, M., 2001, Perceptual Cognition: A Nyya-Kantian Approach, Philosophy East and West, 51(2): 197209 Chadha, M., 2004, Perceiving Particulars-as-Such Is Incoherent: A Reply to Mark Siderits, Philosophy East and West, 54(3): 382389 Chadha, M., 2006, et Another Attempt to Salvage Pristine Perceptions!, Philosophy East and West, 56(2): 333342

Chakrabarti, A., 2000, Against Immaculate Perception: Seven Reasons for Eliminating Nirvikalpaka Perceptions from Nyya,Philosophy East and West, 50(1): 18. Chakrabarti, A., 2001, Reply to Stephen Phillips, Philosophy East and West, 51(1): 114115. Chakrabarti, A., 2004, Seeing Without Recognizing More on Denuding Perceptual Content, Philosophy East and West, 54(3): 365367 Chakrabarti, A., 1995, Non-Particular Individuals, in P. K. Sen and R. R. Verma (eds.), The Philosophy of P. F. Strawson, New Delhi: Indian Council of Philosophical Research, pp. 124144. Dreyfus, G. B. J., 1997, Recognizing reality: Dharmakrti's philosophy and its Tibetan interpretations, New York: State University of New York Press. Feldman, J., 2005, Vasubandhu's Illusion Argument and the Parasitism of Illusion upon Veridical E perience, Philosophy East and West, 55(4): 529541 Gupta, B., Dharmarajadhvarindra, and Anantakrishna Sastri, N. S., 1991, Perceiving in Advaita Vedanta: Ppistemological Analysis and Interpretation , London: Associated University Presses. Matilal, B. K., 1986, Perception: An Essay on Classical Indian Theories of Knowledge, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Mohanty, J.N., 2000, Classical Indian Philosophy, Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield. Mondal, P. K., 1982, Some aspects of perception in old Nyaya, Journal of Indian Philosophy, 10(4): 357376. Phillips, S. H., 2001, There's Nothing Wrong with Raw Perception: A Response to Chakrabarti's Attack on Nyya's Nirvikalpaka Pratyaka, Philosophy East and West, 51(1): 104113 Phillips, S. H., 2004, Perceiving Particulars Blindly: Remarks on a Nyya-Buddhist Controversy, Philosophy East and West, 54(3): 389403 Siderits, M., 2004, Perceiving Particulars: A Buddhist Defense, Philosophy East and West, 54(3): 367382 Thrasher, A. W., 1993, The Advaita Vedanta of Brahma-Siddhi, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidas. Wezler, A. and Motegi, S., 1998, (eds.) Yuktidipika: The Most Significant Commentary on the Samkhyakarika, Volume 1 (Alt und Neu-Indische Studien, No. 41), Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag.

Você também pode gostar