Você está na página 1de 268

Borges, Swedenborg and Mysticism

Hispanic Studies: Culture and Ideas Volume


Edited by

50

Claudio Canaparo

PETER LANG Oxford Bern Berlin Bruxelles Frankfurt am Main New York Wien

William Rowlandson

Borges, Swedenborg and Mysticism

PETER LANG Oxford Bern Berlin Bruxelles Frankfurt am Main New York Wien

Bibliographic information published by Die Deutsche Nationalbibliothek. Die Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliograe; detailed bibliographic data is available on the Internet at http://dnb.d-nb.de. A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data: [to be inserted]

Cover image: Cameron Adams, Lotus 2013. ISSN 1661-4720 ISBN 978-3-0343-0811-3 Peter Lang AG, International Academic Publishers, Bern 2013 Hochfeldstrasse 32, CH-3012 Bern, Switzerland info@peterlang.com, www.peterlang.com, www.peterlang.net All rights reserved. All parts of this publication are protected by copyright. Any utilisation outside the strict limits of the copyright law, without the permission of the publisher, is forbidden and liable to prosecution. This applies in particular to reproductions, translations, microlming, and storage and processing in electronic retrieval systems. Printed in Germany

It seemed only proper that a blind man might be able to be my guide to the world of darkness
michael harner, The Way of the Shaman

Contents

Acknowledgments ix Introduction 1
Chapter One

Fantastic or real? Borges reading of Dante and Swedenborg


Chapter Two

47

Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter?


Chapter Three

79

In the shadow of William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism


Chapter Four

125

Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges


Chapter Five

165

The Influence of Swedenborg on Borges Conclusion Confronting the shadow: the heros journey in El Etngrafo

193

225

Bibliography 243 Index 253

Acknowledgments

When I was sixteen my Spanish teacher at school, Claire McWilliams, lent me a copy of Fictions which still sits on my bookshelf. It is a 1985 John Calder edition, which I have never seen for sale elsewhere, with a cover illustration of zany zigzag arrows dancing through a labyrinth towards two expressionless eyes. I thank and blame Miss McWilliams for pushing me down the rabbit hole into the Borges Wonderland, from which I have never returned. If we should meet again, I will happily and gratefully return her book. Thanks to the University of Kent for granting me study leave of one semester in order to work on this and other projects. Thanks to Claudio Canaparo, series editor of Peter Langs Hispanic Studies: Culture and Ideas. Thanks also to Hannah Godfrey, Mary Critchley and Holly Catling at Peter Lang. My thanks to Jeremy Carrette for his helpful perspectives on William James, Henry James Sr. and the James familys relationship with Swedenborg. Thanks to Sophia Wellbeloved for her investigation into possible BorgesGurdjieff connections. Thanks also to Patricia Novillo Corvaln for many corridor chats and email exchanges about Borges and for lending me books (which I have returned) from her vast library of the Borges scholarship. Many of the ideas set forward in this book were discussed in the former Centre for the Study of Myth at the University of Kent. My thanks to those who tolerated my ramblings and who shared their ideas and insights; in particular Geoffrey Cornelius, Maggie Hyde, Vered Weiss, Matthew Watkins, Lyndsay Radermacher and Cameron Adams. Additional thanks to Cameron for the use of his artwork for the cover image. Thanks in particular to Angela Voss, for the constant interchange of memories, dreams and reflections. Thanks above all to the wonderful and beautiful Eva, Luca and Blanca, to whom this book is dedicated.

Introduction

Every time I read something, that something is changed. And every time I write something, that something is being changed all the time by every reader. Every new experience enriches the book. [] People read my stories and read many things into them that I have not intended, which means that I am a writer of stories. A writer who wrote only the things he intended would be a very poor writer. A writer should write with a certain innocence. He shouldnt think about what he is doing. If not, what he does is not all his own poetry. Borges, Borges at Eighty Im sorry to say that people have written fifty or sixty books about me. I havent read a single one of them, since I know too much of the subject, and Im sick and tired of it. Borges, Borges at Eighty They tell me there are some 300 books that have been written about me. But I think the writers should choose a better subject. Borges: interview with William F. Buckley Todo hombre memorable corre el albur de ser amonedado en ancdotas [Every memorable man runs the risk of being minted in anecdotes] Borges, Atlas

Emanuel Swedenborg writes in the Preface of Heaven and Hell (1758): it has been granted me to be with angels and to talk with them person to person. I have also been enabled to see what is in heaven and in hell, a process that has been going on for thirteen years (1).1 He writes later in

All citations of Swedenborgs Heaven and Hell are from the translation of George F. Dole for the Swedenborg Foundations New Century Edition, 2000. As is customary

2 Introduction

the work: I have been allowed to talk with some people who lived more than two thousand years ago, people whose lives are described in history books and are therefore familiar (480). He repeatedly claims that I can bear witness from all my experiences of what happens in heaven and in hell (482), and begins many paragraphs with statements such as Angels have told me that (184, 222, 302, 310, 480). Swedenborg, it would appear, was fully aware that his accounts would constitute a challenge to his readership, and, indeed, he famously writes in Arcana Clestia: I am well aware that many will say that no one can possibly speak with spirits and angels so long as he lives in the body; and many will say that it is all fancy, others that I relate such things in order to gain credence, and others will make other objections. But by all this I am not deterred, for I have seen, I have heard, I have felt (68). How is the reader to judge this? What hermeneutic tools does the reader employ in order to judge the literary aesthetic of Swedenborgs texts against works of fantasy or voyages of discovery? Borges admired Swedenborg and wrote extensively about him; indeed the strong presence of Swedenborg in Borges work constitutes a curious absence in the scholarship. Following the lead of Ralph Waldo Emerson, Borges delivered lectures on Swedenborg which he later transcribed and published and in which he called Swedenborg un mstico mucho ms complejo que los otros (2005: 202) [a mystic far more complex than the others] (my translation). In the lecture and in other writings Borges paid close attention to the otherworld journeys of Swedenborg, to his communication with angels and demons and with the discarnate souls of the dead. Whilst uncomfortable with the theological dimension of Swedenborgs writings, arguing that his originality and innovation demonstrated a strong degree of heterodoxy, Borges greatly admired the ethical aspect of his works. Furthermore, Borges repeatedly defended Swedenborg against charges of insanity, arguing that the man was remarkably lucid, that his accounts were the product of a profoundly intellectual mind, and that his voyages constituted journeys of discovery akin to Swedenborgs Viking ancestors.

with the Swedenborg scholarship, I will use throughout paragraph marks: , rather than page references.

Introduction

Swedenborg, wrote Borges, es el primer explorador del otro mundo, el explorador que debemos tomar en serio (2005: 202) [Swedenborg is the first explorer of the other world. An explorer we should take seriously] (my translation). Whilst the reader of Swedenborg is presented with challenges to assumptions about life, death, angelic beings and the divine, the reader of Borges texts concerning Swedenborg is presented with an equally challenging set of questions concerning the relationship between fact and fiction, realism and fantasy, voyages of discovery and poetry, orthodoxy and heterodoxy. Expanding this, it becomes clear that all of Borges writings concerning the ill-defined tradition of mysticism are characterized by equally puzzling questions of the nature of the real. I have been reading and encouraging others to read Borges for twenty years, and have taught his works, especially the poetry, at university level for a decade. In a class discussion at the end of a semesters course, one member of the seminar remarked that the word that best sums up Borges was unsettling. We pursued this, enquiring what exactly is unsettling and what exactly is unsettled. Her response was curious: After reading so much Borges nothing is stable any more. Things are unhinged. Another student had suggested that the course is not for the fainthearted. Over the weeks we had followed a more or less chronological assessment of Borges tales, essays and poems, spending proportionally longer on his later works (1960s onwards) than the prolific era of the 1940s and 1950s, culminating in the whimsical tales of El Hacedor [Dreamtigers], El Libro de Arena [The Book of Sand] and La Memoria de Shakespeare [Shakespeares Memory], the meditative lectures of Siete Noches [Seven Nights], the poem and prose pieces ofElogio de la sombra [In Praise of Darkness] and Los Conjurados, and the many interviews. We reflected on the unsettling aspect of Borges. How do things appear unhinged? Why is the course not for the fainthearted? The class unanimously agreed that not only had the texts been puzzling, challenging, and at times infuriating, but that over the course of their reading something had changed within them, that their relationship with reality had been somehow affected by the many questions and conundrums thrown up by the Borges texts. The discussion, with books closed, lasted a full two hours, and following the lead of the first student, more members ofthe group felt empowered

4 Introduction

to discuss their personal reactions to the texts and the manner in which the course had affected them. Some discussed curious dreams of labyrinthine landscapes; others described sleepless nights or late-night discussions with friends puzzling over the metaphysical riddles crafted by Borges. I myself recalled reading The Book of Sand at the age of seventeen, and how I had struggled to conceptualize and accommodate such alluring horrors as the infinite book, the monstrous Preetorius, and the meeting of the young and old Borges on a bench by a river. To this day I still feel the same vertiginous thrill at contemplating the one-sided disc. What could possibly be on the other side? Clearly there is something transformative in the process of close reading of Borges works and spirited group discussion. A word that had surfaced at repeated moments throughout the course, especially when we dwelt on the tales El Aleph and La escritura del dios [The Gods Script] was mysticism. Nothing, it was soon revealed, is straightforward about this troublesome term, firstly because the definitions of the word are strikingly variant and contradictory, and secondly because the terms mysticism, mystical and mystic raise some profound epistemological questions about the nature of reality. Furthermore, in relation to the act of interpretation of, for example, the ecstatic episode of El Aleph, questions emerged in class discussion about how to reconcile the text with the author and with the reader. Is a mystical text necessarily the product of a mystic? Is El Aleph a mystical text? What is a mystical text? Was Borges a mystic? What is a mystic? Can a text itself be mystical, or is it merely the description of a mystical state? Can there be a mystical reading of a non-mystical text, and vice-versa? If, for example, a reader experiences something profoundly mystical in reading El Aleph, what would be the implications of finding out that the text were a parody of mystical texts? Is El Aleph a parody of mystical texts? Borges was profoundly interested in the ill-defined and shape-shifting traditions of mysticism, writing numerous essays and poems about mystical writers in the Christian traditions: Scotus Erigena, Dante, Meister Eckhart, Jakob Bhme (also written Boehme and Behmen), Angelus Silesius, Emanuel Swedenborg, William Blake, Novalis, and Emerson; exploring Sufi mystical poetry, Buddhist and Zen doctrines of spiritual philosophy, the Kabbalah, and various traditions of Neoplatonism and

Introduction

western esotericism. There is, however, an absence in the scholarship concerning Borges close involvement with mysticism and mystical texts, especially as this book explores Swedenborg. Whilst his interest in religious philosophies and practices such as the Kabbalah and Buddhism has been explored in some excellent books and articles, his relationship to specific mystical writers and texts has received far less attention, and for the most part appears only as oblique and generally unexplored references. This is unsurprising for three reasons that I can identify. Firstly, there is no easily delineated school of mystical writers; the traditions are characterized by heterogeneity. Indeed one of the central tasks of the various scholars of mysticism has been to identify precisely what it is that binds historical figures like Erigena, Eckhart, Teresa de vila, Bhme, Swedenborg and Blake. Likewise, the concepts of mystics, mysticism, mystical visions and mystical states are difficult to define and categorize. This is of crucial importance, as whilst Borges may call Plotinus, Silesius, Swedenborg, Blake and his friend Xul Solar msticos, and whilst he may claim that Pascal, Teresa de Jess, Juan de la Cruz and Luis de Len were not mystics, it is surprisingly difficult to arrive at any clear understanding of what the term means, despite over a century of rigorous scholarship. The scholarship of mysticism reveals countless attempts, pioneered by William Inge and William James, to define mysticism according to key characteristics. However, as I explore in Chapter Two, these defining characteristics are generally themselves vague and difficult to define. Furthermore, these terms are often refuted by the proceeding scholars defining characteristics (Underhills list, for example, is strikingly different from Jamess; Staces is very different from Underhills). There is consequently no consensus. Secondly, Borges himself described mystics and mystical texts with a confusing blend of philosophical scepticism, literary awe, metaphysical perplexity and personal fondness. As such, and in tune with the well-known bon mot from Tln, Uqbar, Orbis Tertius that la metafsica es una rama de la literatura fantstica (1974: 436) [metaphysics is a branch of fantastic literature] (1976: 34), it is difficult to distinguish between his affection for the imagined worlds of H.G. Wells, the fantastical adventures of Stevenson, the biblical accounts of the Virgin Birth or the Resurrection, Dantes poetical visions of the circles of Hell, Purgatory and Heaven, and

6 Introduction

Swedenborgs visions of the angelic realms.2 Are all these texts fantasy, or does Borges develop separate textual hermeneutics for fiction, science fiction, mystical, metaphysical and theological texts? In brief, as I explore in Chapter One, does Borges appraise Swedenborgs angels in the same ontological light as the genies of the Thousand and One Nights, or do his repeated claims of Swedenborgs authenticity suggest a different and curious distinction between fantasy and mystical vision? Thirdly, and importantly, it would appear that Borges scholarship, tied as it is to the Academy, treats the shape-shifting and ill-defined landscape of mysticism and mystical texts with reservation. This, as Kripal (2001) argues, relates to a general mistrust of the numinous within a scholarly methodology that seeks robust conclusions to robust hypotheses. Mysticism, and the many cognate aspects of anomalous human experience generally appraised under the titles of parapsychology, paraphenomena or the occult, appear to defy such a methodology. This aspect is explored in detail in Chapter Two. Borges is, of course, ideal fodder for academic discourse. The complex literary structures of the great Ficciones, the meta-textual game-playing, the web of literary and philosophical influences upon his work, his influence upon other writers, the rigorous and meticulous scepticism, the interplay of philosophies, theologies and metaphysics, the dazzling intellect all such attributes of his work provide limitless scope for further levels of interpretation for research papers and rich material for teaching. There is something academically reliable in Borges, as a judicious choice of his fictions can illustrate with sufficient complexity aspects of literary theory, literary movements, the style of the short story, the interplay of literature and philosophy, and so on. His works are studied to illustrate characteristics of modernism and postmodernism, magical realism (however obliquely), Argentine and Latin American literature, and even postcolonialism (see Warnes 2009). However, I feel that something is often lost in the habitual employment of Borges to illustrate such academic concepts, and it was in response to this that I developed a course dedicated exclusively to the works

See Brescia (2008) for an evaluation of how Borges (and Bioy Casares) blurred genre distinctions in their anthologies of the fantastic.

Introduction

of Borges in which close reading of the texts and responsive discussion are encouraged over a teaching of literary schools and movements, genre buzz words or single attributes of Theory. What, though, is lost? Borges regularly urged the students at his lectures, whether in Argentina or the US, to seek the transformative dimension of literature, to seek el encanto that a text can bring: El encanto es, como dijo Stevenson, una de las cualidades esenciales que debe tener el escritor. Sin el encanto, lo dems es intil (1989: 209) [Enchantment, as Stevenson said, is one of the special qualities a writer must have. Without enchantment, the rest is useless] (1984: 9). He likewise discusses the importance of the love of literature: I think that compulsory reading is wrong. You might as well talk of compulsory love or compulsory happiness. One should be reading for the pleasure of the book. I was a teacher of English literature for some twenty years and I always said to my students: if a book bores you, lay it aside. It hasnt been written for you (Barnstone 1982: 113).3 As I have discovered through conversations with occasional disheartened readers of Borges, an over-examination of his most famous tales such as Pierre Menard, autor del Quijote, Tln, Uqbar, Orbis Tertius, La muerte y la brjula, La biblioteca de Babel or El jardn de senderos que se bifurcan can lead to a reception of Borges as cold, scholastic, passionless and claustrophobic, whose texts are mere springboards for further academic displays of erudition. This is a fair reading, especially amongst pressured undergraduates in full lecture theatres; but it is not the only reading, and it saddens me to consider readers who consequently assume that the text hasnt been written for them and who feel dissuaded from exploring further. Reading need not be a purely intellectual exercise. To argue, however, that there is a more numinous aspect to Borges is problematic, owing to the radical scepticism and spiritual agnosticism that characterize his extensive works.

I said to my students [] I cant teach you English literature because I dont know it. But I can teach you the love of English literature. [] They all fell in love with some book or another, and thats the gist, thats the important thing, yes? (Burgin 1998: 209).

8 Introduction

There are striking similarities, for example, between the experience of the Borges narrator on the basement stairs in El Aleph and the dream revelation of Tzinacn in La escritura del dios. These two passages may be read in isolation of their surrounding texts and may with good reason be considered examples of ecstatic mystical writing akin to Eckhart or Teresa de vila; indeed they constitute remarkable examples of visionary art. Giskin (1990), confirming this aspect, appraised in particular El Aleph as embodying the four characteristics of mystical experience as described by William James: Ineffability, Noetic quality, transiency and passivity. He concludes that Borges was consequently a mystic. However, when the tales are read in their entirety, it is apparent that they are carefully constructed fictions, revealing a radically more sceptical, philosophical and literary quality than the brief isolated passages, and may even be considered parodies of mystical texts. Akin to the uselessness of Funes perpetual rapture, the impossible Aleph serves the narrator only as a means of prying into the private correspondence of his former lover and her cousin, and serves Daneri only as material for pretentious poetry. Tzinacns communion with god serves him only to allay the horrors of his peoples destruction and his incarceration. So are these texts, in tune with Giskins assessment, mystical, or are they parodic critiques of mysticism? One means of addressing this question, in addition to an appraisal of the scholarship of mysticism, is to consider the textual traditions of mysticism as another branch of fantastic literature, and thus to evaluate Borges exploration of such traditions and his employment of them for the purposes of crafting fiction. In this respect one must first consider his intricate engagement with various traditions of philosophy, and his repeated claims that he was not a philosopher himself but a mere poet/author whose interest in philosophy was for aesthetic aims. Is there a parallel between his use of philosophy for aesthetic purposes and his use of mysticism?

Introduction

Mysticism for aesthetic purposes


The relationship between Borges and philosophy has been extensively analysed; and the heart of many of these studies is described by Bosteels (2006: 23) as the perennial question from the audience member in the front seat who, with the triumphant smile of an ironist, remark[s] that the Argentine should not be taken so seriously since, after all, he is not a philosopher but a literary writer, that is, someone who merely toys with philosophical ideas for the sake of entertainment and aesthetic pleasure, without implying any systematic philosophy of his own. To put it more simply: was Borges a philosopher? This question has been approached from the perspective that yes, he was a philosopher, if taking the etymological roots of the term as a lover of wisdom; that no, he was instead an antiphilosopher, in that his scepticism of philosophical discourses was itself systematic.4 Other responses to the contrary have been offered, encapsulated in Victor Langes preface to the original English translation of El Hacedor [Dreamtigers]:
The ancestors of this philosophy of detachment and self-doubt seem present at every moment of Borges reflections: the voice of Pascal or Berkeley, of Hume and Kant join to liberate the spirit of man from the confining reality of this world; Heraclitus, Spinoza, Schopenhauer, and Nietzsche testify to the eternal recurrence in which the single act becomes myth and symbol. Yet there is in Borges writings no coherent 4 [] such a rejection of systematic thinking is in itself astonishingly systematic so systematic, in fact, that it ceases to be astonishing at all. Indeed, the objection that Borgess own delightful sense of irony defeats any and all attempts to offer a systematic account of his thinking falls squarely in line with a longstanding argument according to which all philosophers, in their millenarian love of truth, sooner or later become prey to an arrogant illusion of mastery, and that the sheer thrill of happiness, of enjoyment, or of pleasure, though perhaps no less inaccessible to us mere mortals, nonetheless is a worthier object of pursuit than the ever-elusive line of demarcation between opinion and truth that completely seems to absorb the philosopher since at least Plato. The reaction against philosophy as system not only forms a systematic tradition in its own right, but this tradition moreover hides a prestigious genealogy that as a minimum would have to include the likes of Saint Paul, Pascal, Rousseau, Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, and the early Wittgenstein (Bosteels 2006: 24).

10 Introduction
attempt at elaborating his own or others philosophical positions; indeed, his distaste for any supposition of meaning leads him to insist that all systems of thought, all philosophical or theological speculations are merely evidence of that desperate compulsion to reflect upon our own delusions; as such they are instances of fantastic literature. And it is the agony of philosophical perplexity, those moments at which the scruples and wonders of thought appear at their most illusory, that are the matter of Borges art. (Lange, in Borges 1970: xiii)

Borges himself emphasized that his appreciation of philosophers lay principally in his admiration of the aesthetic value: the poetic language, the elegance of the rhetoric and the finery of argumentation. Whilst admiring the aesthetics, he was nevertheless sceptical about the very nature of philosophy and its pretence to eternal truths. And yet, sceptical as he was, he nevertheless delved deeply into philosophy and its histories, exploring with delight the intellectual complexities and conundrums, the claims to truth, the influence of social context and the passing of philosophical fashions. He gently exposed what for him was the beautiful futility of philosophy in its attempt to explain the riddle of the universe: We can go on making guesswork we will call that guesswork philosophy, which is really mere guesswork. We will go on weaving theories, and being very much amused by them, and then unweaving and taking other new ones (Barnstone 1982: 111), and he was keen to address this aesthetic quality of philosophical or theological systems. In the epilogue to Otras Inquisiciones, he argued that Dos tendencias he descubierto [en] este volumen. Una, a estimar las ideas religiosas o filosficas por su valor esttico y aun por lo que encierran de singular y maravilloso. Esto es quizs indicio de un escepticismo esencial (1974: 775) [the first tendency [of this volume] is to evaluate religious or philosophical ideas on the basis of their aesthetic worth and even for what is singular and marvelous about them. Perhaps this is an indication of a basic skepticism] (1964: 201). He declared to Ronald Christ that I am a man of letters who turns his own perplexities and that respected system of perplexities we call philosophy into the forms of literature (Alazraki 1988: 31). To Richard Stern he declared: Im not really a thinker. Im a literary man and I have done my best to use the literary possibilities of philosophy (Burgin 1998: 8). In a 1973 interview with Mara Esther Vzquez, he asserted that:

Introduction

11

No soy filsofo ni metafsico; lo que he hecho es explotar, o explorar es una palabra ms noble , las posibilidades literarias de la filosofa. [] Yo no tengo ninguna teora del mundo. En general, como yo he usado los diversos sistemas metafsicos y teolgicos para fines literarios, los lectores han credo que yo profesaba esos sistemas, cuando realmente lo nico que he hecho ha sido aprovecharlos para esos fines, nada ms. Adems, si yo tuviera que definirme, me definira como un agnstico, es decir, una persona que no cree que el conocimiento sea posible. (Vzquez 1977: 107) [I am neither philosopher nor metaphysician. What I have done is exploit, or explore a more noble word the literary possibilities of philosophy. [] I have no theory of the world. In general, seeing that I have used diverse metaphysical and theological systems for literary objectives, readers have believed that I have professed those systems, when really all that I have done has been employ them for those ends, nothing more. Furthermore, if I had to define myself, it would be agnostic; thats to say, someone who does not believe that knowledge is possible.] (My translation)

Lastly, he declared to Michael Palencia-Roth that his interest in all systems of thought lay in the application of such systems for aesthetic purposes:
MP-R: You say youre not a thinker Borges: No, what I mean to say is that I have no personal system of philosophy. I never attempt to do that. I am merely a man of letters. In the same way, for example that well, of course, I shouldnt perhaps choose this as an example in the same way that Dante used theology for the purpose of poetry, or Milton used theology for the purposes of his poetry, why shouldnt I use philosophy, especially idealistic philosophy philosophy to which I was attracted for the purposes of writing a tale, of writing a story? I suppose that is allowable, no? (Dutton 1977: 339)

From his repeated and emphatic statements, we can suggest that Borges employed a degree of Kantian logic and Schopenhaurian scepticism in order to expose the frailty of philosophical, theological and metaphysical systems and doctrines. This does not derive from a position of intellectual arrogance, but more from a Jamesian location in which such belief systems are shown to be true only insofar as they relate to provisory human affairs. Thus the antiphilosophical stance of Borges, which is indeed systematic, is gloriously inclusive, not selective, and celebrates the intellectual and aesthetical splendour of his treasured artists, philosophers and metaphysicians. It is an agnostic position in its fullest sense.

12 Introduction

Being an agnostic Borges argued, means all things are possible, even God, even the Holy Trinity. This world is so strange that anything may happen, or may not happen. Being an agnostic makes me live in a larger, a more fantastic kind of world, almost uncanny. It makes me more tolerant (Shenker 1971).5 Agnosticism here should be appreciated in its etymological sense not a position of disinterest in matters religious or spiritual, as it is habitually understood to signify, nor as simply not belonging to any particular faith group but, as Borges describes, an acceptance that ultimate knowledge of the mysteries of existence is not forthcoming. There are two immediately recognisable characteristics within Borges fiction, poetry, essays and interviews that demonstrate this agnostic position. Firstly, numerous texts conclude with a bathetic absence of revelation. For example, the narrator of the tale Pedro Salvadores ofElogio de la sombra concludes with Como todas las cosas, el destino de Pedro Salvadores nos parece un smbolo de algo que estamos a punto de comprender (1974: 995) [As with so many things, the fate of Pedro Salvadores strikes us as a symbol of something we are about to understand, but never quite do] (1975a: 65). Most well-known, perhaps, is the conclusion of La Muralla y los Libros [The Wall & the Books] (1950):
La msica, los estados de felicidad, la mitologa, las caras trabajadas por el tiempo, ciertos crepsculos y ciertos lugares, quieren decirnos algo, o algo dijeron que no hubiramos debido perder, o estn por decir algo; esta inminencia de una revelacin, que no se produce, es, quiz, el hecho esttico. (1974: 635) [Music, states of happiness, mythology, faces molded by time, certain twilights and certain places all these are trying to tell us something, or have told us something we should not have missed, or are about to tell us something; that imminence of a revelation that is not yet produced is, perhaps, the aesthetic reality.] (1964: 4)

Ever mercurial, Borges also recognized that agnostic and gnostic are vague and mutable words. He humorously deflects the sombre tone of Barnstones question: Returning to the question of a personal god, are you a gnostic? I am an agnostic. No, a gnostic. Ah yes, I may be. Why not be Gnostics today and agnostics tomorrow? Its all the same thing (Barnstone 1982: 103).

Introduction

13

Secondly, in countless interviews and essays Borges emphasized that this state of agnosticism leads not to despair but to rapt wonder at the mysteries inherent in the universe; indeed there is scarcely an interview in English in which Borges does not express his amazement, bafflement, wonder and puzzlement confronted with these mysteries. He also repeatedly locates the English word maze within amazement, and consequently perceives the motivation for his lifelong employment of the maze or labyrinth in his art. Mazes are to be explained by the fact that I live in a wonderful world. I mean, I am baffled all the time by things. I am astonished at things (Barnstone 1982: 36). These many citations of his late interviews do, of course, reveal a lessening of the claustrophobic nature of the earlier labyrinthine tales, such as La Biblioteca de Babel or La muerte y la brjula, and a greater sense of joy that the mysteries will remain always mysteries:
I think of them [mazes and labyrinths] as essential tokens, as essential symbols. I have not chosen them. They were given me. I stick to them because I find that they are the right symbols for my state of mind. I am always being baffled, perplexed, so a maze is the right symbol. They are not, at least to me, literary devices or tricks. I dont think of them as tricks. They are part of my destiny, of my way of feeling, of living. I havent chosen them. (Barnstone 1982: 37)

There is, consequently, a profound paradox expressed in the agnostic position of Borges. The philosophically-orientated mind seeks to understand a mystery whilst knowing it to be essentially mysterious.
If lifes meaning were explained to us, we probably wouldnt understand it. To think that a man can find it is absurd. We can live without understanding what the world is or who we are. The important things are the ethical instinct and the intellectual instinct, are they not? The intellectual instinct is the one that makes us search while knowing that we are never going to find the answer. (Burgin 1998: 241)

This paradox may lead to a Sartrean despair at the absurdity of existence; indeed, two oft-quoted lines from the period of the great Ficciones may be considered synoptic of this worldview. The first, from the essay El idioma analtico de John Wilkens [The analytical language of John Wilkens] summarizes the conjectural and wholly anti-Platonic nature of categorized

14 Introduction

systems of thought: notoriamente no hay clasificacin del universo que no sea arbitraria y conjetural. La razn es muy simple: no sabemos qu cosa es el universo (1974: 708) [obviously there is no classification of the universe that is not arbitrary and conjectural. The reason is very simple: we do not know what the universe is] (2000: 231). The other is uttered by the pedantic narrator of Pierre Menard: No hay ejercicio intelectual que no sea finalmente intil. Una doctrina es al principio una descripcin verosmil del universo; giran los aos y es un mero captulo cuando no un prrafo o un nombre de la historia de la filosofa (1974: 44950) [There is no exercise of the intellect which is not, in the final analysis, useless. A philosophical doctrine begins as a plausible description of the universe; with the passage of the years it becomes a mere chapter if not a paragraph or a name in the history of philosophy] (1976: 70). This uselessness, however, need not be the cause of despair, but the perpetual epistemological challenge that maintains our intellectual drive. Indeed, the Borges narrator of John Wilkens qualifies his earlier assertion by stressing the necessity of such provisory systems: La imposibilidad de penetrar el esquema divino del universo no puede, sin embargo, disuadirnos de planear esquemas humanos, aunque nos conste que stos son provisorios (1974: 708) [But the impossibility of penetrating the divine scheme of the universe cannot dissuade us from outlining human schemes, even though we are aware that they are provisional] (2000: 213). As such, the deep exploration of philosophical systems inevitably creates a critical distance that allows for conflicting or even contradictory systems not to compete but to combine and enrich the tapestry of epistemologies. In philosophical matters, this critical distance may be seen simply as not advocating any one philosopher or school of thought over another. In religious and theological matters, this of course implies not placing faith in a particular doctrine.

Introduction

15

Undr and Utopa de un hombre que est cansado: the tension of wonder and despair
This critical distance can become a conundrum. Throughout his writing career, Borges displayed a tension between a radical and deep-rooted scepticism and a fascination with and deep respect for religious, spiritual and mystical aspects of human experience. This is present in his essays from the 1920s, such as the 1926 Historia de los ngeles [History of Angels] (from El tamao de mi esperanza), where his examination of angels throughout history provides them with some undetermined ontological status akin to the unconscious archetypes that Jung described, and the 1922 La nadera de la personalidad [The Nothingness of Personality] (from Inquisiciones), in which his deconstruction of the self rigorous, rational and to an extent nihilist has nevertheless been interpreted as a germinating aspect of his fascination with Buddhism (Barili 1998). The tension is illustrated powerfully in El Libro de Arena, in which opposing forces exert their exacting power over two tales: the devastation, emptiness, meaninglessness and utter bleakness of Utopa de un hombre que est cansado [Utopia for a Tired Man], and the rapt, ecstatic, mystical wonder of Undr. Borges presented a Gnostic sensibility, akin to Jungs narrative of Answer to Job, in which man is empowered by his understanding that he is part of the divine that the divine needs man to be whole. He discussed in many interviews his fondness for Shaws perspective that God is in the making (Burgin 1998: 209). In the dystopian landscape of Utopa de un hombre que est cansado man has lost his sense of the divinity, and has consequently lost the sense of wonder at the mystery of life. The old man tells the narrator: Hay quienes piensan que es un rgano de la divinidad para tener conciencia del universo, pero nadie sabe con certidumbre si hay tal divinidad (1989: 54) [Some people think man is an organ of the godhead for universal consciousness, but nobody knows for sure whether such a godhead exists] (1979: 68). Reason, intellect and cynicism have trumped the passion for existence and sense of awe at the mysteries of

16 Introduction

nature. In this Gulliver-esque tale the future is full of old, tired, people, free of earthly trappings but having found no illumination concerning the riddle of existence. The Borges-like narrator and his Borges-like host have abandoned themselves to despondent cynicism, dulled by governments and politics, dulled by nations and peoples, dulled by language and history; indeed the old man sees it as hubris to attempt to gather meaning from existence. Once having lived out their allotted one hundred years, the old folk end their days by voluntarily entering the gas chamber designed by the filntropo Hitler. Knowing Borges reaction to Hitler and the Third Reich, the irony in this is severe. In the epilogue to the volume, Borges says of this tale: [] es, a mi juicio, la pieza ms honesta y melanclica de la serie (1989: 72) [it] is in my judgement the most honest and melancholy piece in the collection] (1979: 93). The opposite polarity is presented in Undr, a tale brimming with movement, energy and desire, with the narrator visiting strange lands with strange kings and strange languages, searching throughout for the Word a single word that combines all the mystery of the poetic craft and as such all the wonder of existence. At end of tale the narrator recounts his travels to Thorkelsson, an old poet, who responds:
A m tambin la vida me dio todo. A todos la vida les da todo, pero los ms lo ignoran. Mi voz est cansada y mis dedos dbiles, pero escchame. Dijo la palabra Undr, que quiere decir maravilla. Me sent arrebatado por el canto del hombre que mora, pero en su canto y en su acorde vi mis; propios trabajos, la esclava que me dio el primer amor, los hombres que mat, las albas de fro, la aurora sobre el agua, los remos. Tom el arpa y cant con una palabra distinta. Est bien, dijo el otro y tuve que acercarme para orlo. Me has entendido. (1989: 51) [Life gave me everything as well. Life gives everything to everyone, but most men are unaware of it. My voice is tired and my fingers weak, but listen to me. He took up his harp and uttered the word undr, which means wonder. The dying mans song held me rapt, but in it and in his chords I recognized my own verses, the slave woman who gave me my first love, the men I had killed, the chill of dawn, daybreak over the water, the oars. I took up the harp and sang to a different word. All right, the other man said, and I had to draw close to hear him. You have understood.] (1979: 63)

Introduction

17

Both tales construct their narrative upon a foundation of ignorance of the divine, yet they portray radically contrasting perspectives of this agnostic position. The narrator and the aged euthanist of Utopa have followed the trail that Borges beat in La nadera de la personalidad of exposing the substancelessness of the fabric of reality. Politics, nations, language and even the human race have been hollowed out and jettisoned as mere ephemera of endless and useless cycles and repetitions; and suicide is the inevitable cessation of this meaningless existence. The narrator ofUndr, on the other hand, has no firmer teleological understanding, but is empowered to kiss the joy as it flies and sing to this glorious meaninglessness. In scrutinising the many interviews that Borges performed throughout the 1960s, 1970s and early 1980s, it is strikingly clear how both visions are present in his philosophical outlook: his exclamations of delighted bafflement and rapt wonder come in equal measure to his anticipation of being blotted out, [of being] sick and tired of myself, [and] greedy for death (Barnstone 1982: 17). Whilst on the one hand this is a polarity of despair and joy, it is a dialectic that can be perceived at many further levels: reason and intuition, intellect and emotion, empiricism and esotericism, the revealed and the occult, fact and fiction, reality and fantasy. These are difficult polarities to reconcile. Borges, for example, maintained the same degree of critical distance vis--vis mysticism as he maintained with philosophy: Many people have thought of me as a thinker, as a philosopher, or even as a mystic. [] People think that Ive committed myself to idealism, to solipsism, or to doctrines of the cabala, because Ive used them in my tales. But really I was only trying to see what could be done with them (Burgin 1998: 79). Whilst we should be cautious of leaping to call Borges a mystic, for the reasons that are explored in Chapter Two, nevertheless we need to appraise the deeper ramifications of this insistence that his interests in all systems of thought were purely aesthetic. My reading of Borges over the last five years has accompanied a close reading with weekly group discussions of the works of Jung. It has become an increasingly motivating enterprise to perceive the close affinities between Jung and Borges, not at the level of personal connections (although Borges did read Jung and commented on his works, and there are intermediary contacts between them, such as Victoria Ocampo and Gershom Scholem),

18 Introduction

but at the level of their shared interests.6 Of most concern for us here is the tension of opposites that is central to both their works.

The case of Jung


Jung underwent a period of psychic crisis in his thirties, yet kept secret the harrowing accounts of his experience with the unconscious entities and the discarnate dead, documenting them in great majesty in the Liber Novus which he never published (it was published in 2009 as The Red Book). He was aware that his experiences constituted a radical discord with the ontological certainties held by himself and the wider public, and he was fully cognizant of the ridicule that he would face amongst friends and peers ifhe claimed that he conversed with Old Testament prophets and the dead. Even as late as 1958, his essay on UFOs concentrates almost entirely in evaluating the psychic cause and psychic effect of the phenomenon, and not the phenomenon itself. Jung was emphatic in the critical distance maintained

There is much to link Borges and Jung at three levels: firstly, as I discuss in Chapter Five, Borges engagement with Jungs psychological works. Secondly, Jungs and Borges debt to William James; their reading of mystics, especially Swedenborg, Dante, Jakob Bhme, Angelus Silesius, Meister Eckhardt, Blake; their admiration of Schopenhauer and Kant; their reading of Gnosticism, hermeticism and alchemy, especially Paracelsus; their interpretation of the Book of Job; their critical reading of Joyce; their critique through a mythological prism of the Third Reich; their interest in the epistemological value of fantasy, imagination, myth, symbols and dreams. Thirdly, biographical parallels: their association with Gershom Scholem; their connection with Victoria Ocampo (she met Jung and sponsored Ramn Gmez de la Serna to translate Psychological Types [Tipos psicolgicos: Buenos Aires 1945], the first Spanish translation). One might object to a comparative appraisal of Borges and Jung based on the idea that Jung was a psychologist and Borges an artist. I would argue, however, that Jung was manifestly an artist (viz The Red Book) and that Borges was fascinated by the complexities of the psyche. In this and other respects their projects have far more in common than has hitherto been acknowledged.

Introduction

19

through scientific objectivity, which permitted him, like Borges, to explore with great enthusiasm all manner of alchemical, gnostic, mystical, hermetic and occult texts without abandoning robust empiricism. Whilst Borges may have stressed that his interest lay in the merely aesthetic, Jung would argue that his interest was in the psychological aspect of these systems of thought. Yet it becomes apparent through a scrutiny of Jungs work that he felt torn between his desire to be a scientist and his inclination towards philosophy, theology and metaphysics as maps not only of the human psyche, but of reality itself. That is to say that his concerns were not merely epistemological but ontological also. This is evident in his strident riposte as footnote in his work on UFOs: It is a common and totally unjustified misunderstanding on the part of scientifically trained people to say that I regard the psychic background as something metaphysical, while on the other hand the theologians accuse me of psychologizing metaphysics. Both are wide of the mark: I am an empiricist, who keeps within the boundaries set for him by the theory of knowledge (1958: 328).7 There is so much to be elucidated from this, especially given the arbitrary nature of the terms employed, such as empiricist and theory of knowledge. Jung was obviously pulled between intuition and education, and even when he did consider the ontological possibility of the UFO (in the final chapter

A number of commentators, not least Jung himself, have observed his vociferous appeal to the reader not to consider him anything other than a rational scientific empiricist. Note a later footnote to the text on UFOs: Here I must beg the reader to eschew the popular misconception that this background is metaphysical. This view is a piece of gross carelessness of which even professional people are guilty. It is far more of a question of instincts which influence not only our outward behaviour but also the psychic structure. The psyche is not an arbitrary fantasy; it is a biological fact subject to the laws of life (1958: 346). It is important to note that this footnote pertains to a paragraph in which he declares: Since the discovery of the empirical unconscious the psyche and what goes on in it have become a natural fact and are no longer an arbitrary opinion (346). Some may suggest that in equating the unconscious to a natural law of physics, he is demonstrating a level of dogmatic faith in his discovery such as he observed in Freuds defence of pleasure and its frustration (348) being the sole roots of psychic illness.

20 Introduction

of his investigation) he concentrated not on the phenomenon itself, but on the psychic response to it, the projection of psychic energy upon it. In a similar fashion, Borges would argue that his interests lay in their aesthetic value, as if that negates any speculation about the actual questions raised in metaphysics, psychology (and parapsychology) and religious and mystical texts. Yet both Borges and Jung were clearly deeply drawn to such liminal, mysterious, levels of human experience, and their safety lines in these dark caves were literature and psychology respectively. The publication of The Red Book has inspired a fresh approach to Jung, an approach hinted at since early publications of Von Franz, Jaff, Hannah, Jacobi and others, but rarely stated outright: that Jung did consider such matters at their ontological level. Off-beat scholars and certain leftfield practitioners have been calling Jung a mystic and a shaman for decades (at least since 1962 when Memories Dreams Reflections was published in English). Aniela Jaffs essay Was C.G. Jung a mystic? (1989) focuses from the opening page on the tension between Jungs mystic sensibilities and his insistence on principles of empiricism, observing that Jung reacted strongly against any claims that he was anything other than a scientific observer. Gary Lachmans recent Jung the mystic (2010), as the title suggests, testifies to the mystical nature of Jung, and he appraises with sensitivity the double nature present in Jung: Jung seemed to have two minds about the supernatural: a public one that wanted to understand it scientifically, and a private one that acknowledged ghosts, visions, and premonitions as part of the essential mystery of life (4). Lachman also cites Anthony Storr, who writes in his book Feet of Clay: A Study of Gurus that Jung was a guru (in Lachman 2010: 6). Jungian analyst Roger Woolger, in his review of Jungs Red Book (Woolgers final publication prior to his death in 2011), declared outright that Jung displayed all the characteristics commonly associated with shamans, calling Jung the Hidden Shaman:
Now that we have the record of Jungs struggles to integrate the polarities of scientistphilosopher versus mystic within his soul we can also see how they urged upon him another mantle that he was very reluctant to wear because so many have been ridiculed and persecuted for wearing it that of shaman-prophet. [] The evidence of the Red Book and of those who knew him intimately us that Jung was very much

Introduction

21

a shaman. [] Perhaps Shamdasani shies away from calling Jung a shaman because shamanism is not politically correct in academic or conservative professional circles in Britain. (2011: 45).

I have no intention of suggesting that Borges was a shaman or guru, terms which have a stricter definition than mystic, though equally problematic. However, the parallel drawn with Jung here is helpful in illustrating a perplexing dialogue between polarities present in Borges. Neither am I assuming that an equivalent Red Book a secret illuminated manuscript of Borges encounters with the dead will be unearthed and published to corroborate such a position. I would argue that such a discovery is not necessary; the published work of Borges poems, tales, essay, reviews and interviews is replete with subtle indications that Borges, like Jung, was fascinated with the more anomalous aspects of human experience at a level beyond the mere aesthetic. In an appraisal of his many writings, it becomes evident that he read extensively and sympathetically in the traditions of mystical, spiritual and esoteric texts. My argument is that there is a limit to the capacity of a reader to explore such texts to the extent that Borges did if, ultimately, one is not predisposed towards them. Borges, like Jung, was a reader of alchemical texts, dramatizing, for example, the aged figure of Paracelsus in one of his final tales La Rosa de Paracelsus. One can also identify his inveterate interest in hermetic philosophy (he discusses Ficino and Giordano Bruno in Libro de los seres imaginarios [Book of Imaginary Beings] with Margarita Guerrero), Neoplatonism (Historia de la eternidad [A History of Eternity]), daimonic beings (Libro de seres imaginarios [Book of Imaginary Beings], Las Ruinas circulares [The Circular Ruins]), esoteric societies (Tln, Los Conjurados, El Congreso), Gnosticism (Una vindicacin del falso Baslides [A Vindication of the False Basilides],8

That Borges work demonstrates certain Gnostic leanings and concepts is welldocumented, but it is generally ignored in deconstructive criticisms haste to erase the logos in the name of its own brand of indeterminacy and deferral. It is much fairer to view Borges Gnosticism, particularly his affinity for the malevolent demiurge who creates an imperfect universe, as his own attempt to work through the concerns

22 Introduction

Tres versiones de Judas [Three Versions of Judas]), anomalies in time (J.W. Dunne, El milagro secreto [The Secret Miracle]), persistence of the soul after death (Dilogo de muertos [Dead mens dialogue]), the many discussions of transmigration of the soul), depth psychology (his many citations of Jung), eschatology (poem Doomsday), and so on. He was likewise a devoted reader of Angelus Silesius, and translated Silesius challenging Cherubinischer Wandersmann with Mara Kodama.9 He was a dedicated reader of Dante, of William Blake and Sufi poets. He was also a reader of Theosophy, describing his surprise at being unable to find the works ofSwedenborg in Theosophical bookshops, a statement which would imply that he frequented them.10 He made many references to William James, Jung, Rudolf Steiner and the later works of Aldous Huxley. I would argue that it is difficult to make meaningful statements about James, Jung, Steiner, or Huxley without entering their challenging works with energy and sympathy. He cites Ouspensky (Historia de la eternidad, Los conjurados), a perplexing writer whose works are difficult to summarize based on only a rudimentary reading.11 Likewise, as I explore in Chapter One,
of theodicy, and his sense of the inadequacy of orthodox religions efforts to do so (Soud 1995: 748). I was translating, with Mara Kodama, Angelus Silesius Cherubinischer Wandersmann and we came to the same statement that if a soul is damned it is forever in hell (Barnstone 1982: 8). Yo s que en la Biblioteca Nacional hay un ejemplar de Del cielo, del infierno y sus maravillas. Pero en algunas libreras teosficas no se encuentran obras de Swedenborg (2005: 202) [I know that in the National Library there is an edition of Heaven and Hell. But you will not find Swedenborgs works in Theosophical bookshops] (my translation). Ouspensky is a name generally associated with Gurdjieff, a particularly curious guru figure of the early twentieth century whose influence was felt upon writers, painters, film directors, philosophers and even politicians on both sides of the Atlantic. The Borges-Gurdjieff-Ouspensky connection is obscure, and whilst I can find no reference to Gurdjieff in Borges writing, it would seem likely that Borges knowledge of Ouspenskys works would guarantee him at least a passing knowledge of Gurdjieff. James Webb (1987: 492) writes that Borges attended a Gurdjieff group in Argentina though provides no evidence. Likewise Gurdjieff scholar Sophia Wellbeloved (2003: xxvii) attests that Borges attended meetings on Gurdjieff s Work in Buenos Aires,

9 10

11

Introduction

23

Borges read Swedenborg with great devotion, and died with the project still unrealized of writing an entire book on Swedenborgs voyages to the heavens and hells. He paid close attention to Swedenborgs otherworld journeys, the angelic and demonic beings Swedenborg encountered there, his communication with the discarnate dead, and his description of the process of death, all the while adamant that Swedenborg was not a madman. In defending Swedenborg against charges of insanity, therefore, Borges would appear to defend the possibility that Swedenborgs adventures were neither fantasy, fiction nor hallucination. This splendidly tolerant attitude, which Borges would correlate with the tolerance inherent in agnosticism, needs to be assessed in light of Borges scepticism even cynicism regarding faith. There is a sensitivity and sensibility to such matters visible in Borges work that demonstrate something more than mere material for story-telling. Borges, as I explore in this book, investigated mysticism in particular with a series of questions and arguments that reveals a level of deep personal investment. This tension of polarities is likewise visible in the Libro del cielo y del infierno, which Borges edited with Bioy Casares, which contains passages

but provides no evidence that Borges even read Gurdjieff : Jorge Luis Borges is said to have attended meetings in Argentina in the 1950s. By then Gurdjieff s influence was widespread in South America. In email communication with Wellbeloved, she explained to me that this notion derived not from Webb, but from her communication with Gurdjieff scholar Martin Wallace who had, she wrote, met Borges and had asked him whether he knew Ouspenskys and by extension Gurdjieff s works. Wellbeloved explained to me: Martin Wallace wrote the introduction to the second edition of my Gurdjieff, Astrology and Beelzeubs Tales. I asked him by email if he thought that Borges had been influenced by Ouspensky, and he sent me an email recounting meeting Borges and asking him the same question, Borges replied by immediately reciting the entire list of cosmoses from memory, an achievement as you can see, you can find them in In Search of the Miraculous (1949), which gives and account of Gurdjieff s teaching in Russia before the revolution. Ouspensky was obsessed with theories of time and also recurrence, this was an aspect of what he taught that was in addition to Gurdjieff s teaching (private email correspondence). The true extent of the influence or co-interests of Borges, Gurdjieff and Ouspensky remains to be fully explored.

24 Introduction

from Swedenborg alongside an extract from Bertrand Russells An Outline of Intellectual Rubbish. The brief passage from Russell that Borges and Bioy included comes from an essay in which Russell systematically lambasts all manner of woolly-brained thinking that he detected in religious, spiritual and superstitious texts and practices throughout the ages and across the cultures. It was published in 1943 and much of Russells venom is directed against the Nazis and their political mythologies. It is noteworthy, therefore, that Borges and Bioy chose to include an extract from this essay, as the essence of the essay would clearly dismiss any notion of heavens, hells or the afterlife as nonsense; indeed the brief extract concerns Russells snide dismissal of F.W.H. Myers claims to have been able to communicate with the dead.12 There is much of Russell in Borges: the disdain for the dogma of faith, the bafflement at the readiness of the faithful to abandon not only reason but also the authority of experience, the prodigious memory, cruel wit and sharp intellect. Their comments on the Nazis and the Third Reich are equally scornful. However, Russell was keen to dismiss matters of theology, esotericism, spiritualism, religion, as nonsense, absurdity, and rubbish. Despite their intellectual kinship, the same cannot be said for Borges, whose tolerance would permit him greater warmth to such matters. The appearance of Russell, therefore, in a book by Borges which claims in its prologue to seek lo esencial, sin descuidar lo vivido, lo onrico y lo paradjico (1983: 7) [the essential, without overlooking the experiential, the oneiric and the paradoxical] (my translation) of matters of the afterlife is therefore particularly arresting, as it demonstrates the presence of radical scepticism and philosophical scrutiny alongside intellectual curiosity, aesthetic appreciation, and metaphysical wonder.

12

It would be fascinating to find further references to Myers in Borges work, as Myers a close friend of William James maintained a strongly scientific methodology, married to a healthy scepticism, in his exploration of the survival of the soul after death.

Introduction

25

Defindeme Dios de mi
Borges writes in Avatares de la Tortuga [Avatars of the Tortoise] of the dream-like nature of reality, and postulates that the anomalies and vagueries that are encountered might suggest our own participation in the construction of reality:
El mayor hechicero (escribe memorablemente Novalis) sera el que se hechizara hasta el punto de tomar sus propias fantasmagoras por apariciones autnomas. No sera se nuestro caso? Yo conjeturo que as es. Nosotros (la indivisa divinidad que opera en nosotros) hemos soado el mundo. Lo hemos soado resistente, misterioso, visible, ubicuo en el espacio y firme en el tiempo; pero hemos consentido en su arquitectura tenues y eternos intersticios de sinrazn para saber que es falso. (1974: 258) [The greatest sorcerer (writes Novalis memorably) would be the one who bewitched himself to the point of taking his own phantasmagorias for autonomous apparitions. Would not this be true of us? I believe that it is. We (the undivided divinity that operates within us) have dreamed the world. We have dreamed it strong, mysterious, visible, ubiquitous in space and secure in time, but we have allowed tenuous, eternal interstices of injustice in its structure so we may know that it is false.] (1964: 120)

This is a powerful statement, and deserves to be appraised as more than a mere philosophical reference to Novalis; indeed the fictional nature of reality forms a deep hermeneutic current throughout Borges work. Importantly, Borges identifies here the intersticios de sinrazn that suggest that not all aspects of reality conform to patterns identifiable with the epistemological tool of reason. Some matters, as Jung argued with regard anomalies of reality, operated acausally. One such anomaly that was of such interest to Jung was the contested phenomenon of meaningful coincidence, which he dubbed synchronicity. It is important to stress that the impact of Jungs theory lies not with the idea that a subject can attribute meaning to a series of random coincidences an idea that bears no ontological inference but that the psyche of the individual and the external events are in some undetermined mutual exchange (Main 2004). This, as a scientific rather than a religious theory, is still notably challenging, as it presupposes a conscious dimension to reality. Borges took this matter

26 Introduction

seriously whilst never abandoning his sceptical scrutiny. In an interview with Burgin he described a possible synchronistic event and suggested an explanatory conclusion that displays sympathy with the deeper ontological implications of Jungs theory, whilst maintaining a sceptical, almost cynical, standpoint. So illustrative is the episode of the curious tension in Borges between scepticism and a predisposition to religious experience that it deserves citation in full:
Borges: [] Im on the lookout for symmetries. Burgin: Youve criticized yourself before for always looking for the symmetries, the mirrors, the labyrinths in life. Do you really feel that way or Borges: No, no, I feel that way. But perhaps coincidences are given to us that would involve the idea of a secret plan, no? Coincidences are given to us so that we may feel there is a pattern that there is a pattern in life, that things mean something. Of course, there is a pattern in the sense that we have night and day, the four seasons, being born, living and dying, the stars and so on, but there may be a more subtle kind of pattern, no? Burgin: Within each individuals life. Borges: Yes, within each individuals life, because I find so many coincidences. Of course, as many things happen, coincidences are bound to happen also, but I find very strange coincidences and they are of no use whatever to me except for the fact that they leave a pattern. For example, Bioy Casares and I were working on a translation of Sir Thomas Browne. That translation never found its way into print, because the editors said there was no interest in that and forgot all about it. Now we found a sentence in Sir Thomas Browne in Spanish, defindeme Dios de m. Only he made a mistake and he wrote defindeme Dios de me. Now where else could he have got that from? Well, of course, we corrected the mistake and wrote defindeme Dios de m. A day or so later, I went to Mitchells Book Store in Buenos Aires [] and in the basement I found a new translation of Montaigne into English. I opened one of the volumes at random and there I found defindeme Dios de m, and with the same misprint, de me. The editor, of course he had no Spanish, he thought that Montaigne knew all about it. And then, as I knew that Sir Thomas Browne had been a close reader of Montaigne, there was the clue I had been looking for. He had found that quotation in Montaigne, and the proof lay in the misprint, no? Well, I felt greatly elated at the discovery and I went that night to see Bioy Casares and I had jotted down where the edition of Montaigne might be

Introduction

27
found. And we were working over an anthology of Spanish verse. He had those books of Rivadeneyra in a collection, he had a pile of them on the table. While I was talking to him, he opened one of the books, and there he found a poem of Cristbal de Castillejo, Garcilasos enemy, glossing the line defindeme Dios de m. I said, Look here, I found it in Montaigne this morning. We would have had to have examined thousands of volumes in thousands of years and perhaps never found out these things. And then we felt very proud. Of course, we wrote a short note (in the translation), saying Sir Thomas Browne took this quotation from essay number so and so of Montaigne where the same misprint is found and so on. [] You see, there you had a coincidence, and the coincidence was of no use whatever. (Burgin 1969: 11012)13

There is much to glean from this quite remarkable episode. Firstly, and significantly, Burgin does not respond to Borges lengthy account, but changes the subject. This demonstrates the unease that such a radical position presented by Borges can occasion in his readers and listeners. Secondly, it is striking how like a ficcin this episode is, most of all the parallels with Tln: a furtive citation discovered by Borges and Bioy; further discoveries of the citation in arcane volumes; links through literary-philosophical authors: Castillejo, Garcilaso, Montaigne; and the shadowy presence of Sir Thomas Brown. Borges language is also revealing. He suggests, for example, that coincidences are given to us, and that there may be a more subtle kind of pattern. Such statements, whimsical as they may be, nevertheless imply some manner of extrinsic guiding principle upon life an external authorship a divine force. Again, I am not seeking the deist in Borges, but I am revealing the Jungian perspective present in Borges of perceiving an interrelationship between psyche and matter. He also twice mentions the uselessness of the coincidence, emphasizing that the only use was the fact that they leave a pattern. This, conversely, is a most valuable use as it serves
13 Importantly, Bioy Casares writes of this episode, presenting it with exactly the same detail as Borges. He titles it un recuerdo (2006: 1540). So close is Bioys rendition of the episode to Borges that one wonders whether he was using Borges interview extract as his basis. Bioy obviously felt the episode to be intriguing enough to warrant its own inclusion in his memoirs, yet he offers no assessment of the nature of the coincidence, nor any examination of the phrase itself.

28 Introduction

to demonstrate this challenging assumption that there may be a conscious dimension to what is otherwise considered mere non-conscious matter. Furthermore, as any Jungian analyst would immediately do, one must consider the nature of the mysterious phrase itself, defindeme Dios de me/ m. The issue of misspelling is important, as curiously both Montaigne and then Brown write: Defenda me Dios de me. Montaigne includes it whilst discussing the pain to the soul of physical illness,14 Browne, whilst inveighing against the split between spiritual righteousness and bodily desire.15 The phrase itself, as Bioy suggested, originated from St Augustines City of God, in which Augustine pertinently confronts the tension between righteousness and the desire for sin, though why Montaigne selected the Spanish version is unclear. Montaigne, Browne and, by extension, Augustine, are consequently concerned with the tension of opposites, and they summon God to help reconcile these opposites. Yet Montaigne and Brown resort to a misspelt expression in Spanish in order to summon that help, thereby unwittingly entangling themselves in the very human limitations of language. Borges, in highlighting this episode, appears fully cognizant of its curious nature, yet he appears not to dwell on the phrase itself. Why the curious plea to the divine? Why should Borges call on God to save himself from himself ? One might argue that the phrase embodies the friction generated between rational, sceptical enquiry and an intuition of the non-rational. There is far more to be elucidated from this, not least an exploration of Castillejo. However, this wholly overlooked episode, ignored even by the interviewer, is charged with meaningful relationship with the very tension that I have highlighted in Borges.

14

15

Defenda me Dios de me. I am sorry when I am sick, that I have not some longing that might give me the pleasure of satisfying it; all the rules of physic would hardly be able to divert me from it. I do the same when I am well; I can see very little more to be hoped or wished for. Twere pity a man should be so weak and languishing, as not to have even wishing left to him (Montaigne 1910: 613). I feel that original canker corrode and devour me; and therefore Defenda me DIOS de me, LORD deliver me from my self, is a part of my Letany, and the first voice of my retired imaginations. There is no man alone, because every man is a Microcosm, and carries the whole World about him (Browne 2003: 114).

Introduction

29

Like Jung, Borges achieved fame and success in his life, travelled widely and met with many well-known figures. Jung describes at the beginning of Memories, Dreams, Reflections that none of these experiences was of lasting importance in his later reminiscences; instead it was the experience of the unconscious of the numinous that characterized his lifes work.
In the end the only events in my life worth telling are those when the imperishable world irrupted into this transitory one. That is why I speak chiefly of inner experiences, amongst which I include my dreams and visions. These form the prima materia of my scientific work. They were the fiery magma out of which the stone that had to be worked was crystallized. All other memories of travels, people and my surroundings have paled beside these interior happenings. ( Jung 1989: 45)

Were Borges to have produced the equivalent of Jungs memoirs (beyond the Autobiographical essay) it is highly likely that his recollections would likewise have concentrated on the more timeless aspects of his life experiences, and not on the more mundane. I would argue, indeed, that the many interviews of the 1970s and 80s themselves constitute his oral autobiography, and that his dialogues with Burgin, Barnstone, Engudanos, di Giovanni, Barili and others inevitably encircle the deep wells of timeless moments poetry, dreams, literature, symbols rather than his encounters with political and cultural figures. Mystical experience, as we will investigate in Chapters Two and Three, was for Borges a sensation of moving beyond the mundane passage of time into a of state of timelessness. It is at this level, as Jung also acknowledged, that the intersticios de sinrazn are most prone to occur: a conversation with a dead friend, a glimpse of the future or a moment of deep inspiration.16 Borges paid particular attention to this deeper area of consciousness, suggesting in two particular texts that

16

[Y]ou know there are these peculiar faculties of the psyche, that it isnt entirely confined to space and time. You can have dreams or visions of the future, you can see around corners, and such things. Only ignorance denies these facts, you know; its quite evident that they do exist, and have existed always. Now these facts show that the psyche, in part at least, is not dependent upon these confinements. And then what? When the psyche is not under that obligation to live in time and space alone, and obviously it doesnt, then to that extent the psyche is not subjected to those

30 Introduction

his truest sense of self was that area of the psyche untouched by time. He dedicated Historia universal de la infamia to S.D., offering her [in English] that kernel of myself that I have saved, somehow the central heart that deals not in words, traffics not with dreams, and is untouched by time, by joy, by adversities (1974: 293). He dedicated the Two English Poems (1934) to Beatriz Bibiloni Webster de Bullrich offering her also that kernel of myself that I have saved, / somehow the central heart that deals not / in words, traffics not with dreams, and is / untouched by time, by joy, by adversities (1993: 179). This is the visionary element, the deeper, transpersonal part of his being, the dark layers of unconscious described by Jung. These are the depths that I seek to explore in this book.

Hypotheses that transcend reason are more appealing


But wait! The reader may cry, the fact that Borges wrote fictions in which anomalous episodes emerge does not mean either that he experienced such matters nor that he gave them any credence. This is a valid point, and indeed we should never forget that Borges was an artist, and therefore a merchant of artifice. The writer of a ghost story need not believe in ghosts; a scholar of religion need not be religious. For example, when Borges writes in Atlas (1985): veo en los sueos o converso con muertos, sin que ninguna de esas dos cosas me asombre (1989: 430) [Asleep, in my dreams, I see or converse with the dead. None of these things surprises me in the least] (1985: 54); or when he writes of a dream, also in Atlas: En un restaurante del centro, Hayde Lange y yo conversbamos. [] De pronto record que Hayde Lange haba muerto hace mucho tiempo. Era un fantasma y no lo saba. No sent miedo; sent que era imposible y quiz descorts revelarle que era un fantasma, un hermoso fantasma (1989: 438) [Hayde Lange and I
laws, and that means a practical continuation of life, of a sort of psychical existence beyond time and space ( Jung 1993: 437).

Introduction

31

were conversing in a restaurant in the center of town. [] All of a sudden, I remembered that Hayde Lange had died a long time ago. She was a ghost and didnt know it. I felt no fear, but felt it would not be right, and perhaps rude, to reveal to her that she was a ghost, a lovely ghost] (1985: 67), one can only conjecture what level of personal experience provided the background for such textual creations. We know, for example, that Borges placed great noetic value on dreams and nightmares. What level of communication, consequently, occurred between Borges and the dead Hayde Lange? I argue in Chapter Two, with reference to Jeffrey Kripals (2001) evaluation of the key scholars of mysticism, that a level is clearly reached at which thorough exploration of a phenomenon like mysticism cannot be sustained by sceptical, objective, impartiality if it is to succeed with any integrity. A threshold of scepticism is always crossed if the scholar of mysticism is able to contribute anything of any value to the scholarship. This, I argue, is the case with Borges. And yet, in true mercurial fashion, Borges danced back and forth across this threshold; in his earlier writings demonstrating a more rigorous, intellectual scepticism, in his later works displaying a more world-weary, whimsical acquiescence to the persistence of mystery. Nevertheless, like Jung, he brandished his keen intellect and encyclopaedic knowledge of texts as the means of preventing credulity or adherence to doctrine. There is not the sense, such as Lachman identifies in Jung, that Borges was determined not to be draped in the unwanted robes of mysticism (2010: 4); rather I would argue that his inveterate iconoclasm, mistrust of doctrine, and admiration of heresy made him defensive of being taken for credulous. Note that in the essay on nightmares in Siete Noches, Borges criticizes British anthropologist, folklorist, and classical scholar, Sir James Frazer for being muy crdulo, ya que parece aceptar todo cuanto le cuentan los viajeros (1989: 222) [extremely credulous, as it seems he believed everything reported by the various travellers] (1984: 28). Borges, it would appear, would be more wary of being labelled credulous than a mystic. As his numerous interviews and essays testify, Borges appeared to equate belief whether religious, philosophical or even political with a surrender of ones intellect and faculty of critical enquiry. One senses in Borges that believers are somehow gullible. When evaluating a peculiar coincidence of dreams associated

32 Introduction

with Coleridges poem Kubla Khan, for example, Borges displays a similar defensive position observable in Jung: Quienes de antemano rechazan lo sobrenatural (yo trato, siempre, de pertenecer, a ese gremio) juzgarn que la historia de los dos sueos es una coincidencia, un dibujo trazado por el azar, como las formas de leones o de caballos que a veces configuran las nubes (1974: 644) [Those who automatically reject the supernatural (I try, always, to belong to this group) will claim that the story ofthe two dreams is merely a coincidence, a chance delineation, like the outlines of lions or horses we sometimes see in the clouds] (1964: 16). This may sound a straightforward comment, in which Borges maintains that the narrative similarities across time are merely coincidental and inconsequential. Yet like Lnnrot rejecting Treviranuss suggestion that the murder of Yarmolinsky was a blunder, and choosing instead to seek the symbolic, Borges rejects his declared position to explore the more poetic, mysterious dimension of this parallel.
Otros argirn que el poeta supo de algn modo que el emperador haba soado el palacio y dijo haber soado el poema para crear una esplndida ficcin que asimismo paliara o justificara lo truncado y rapsdico de los versos. Esta conjetura es verosmil, pero nos obliga a postular, arbitrariamente, un texto no identificado por los sinlogos en el que Coleridge pudo leer, antes de 1816, el sueo de Kubla. Ms encantadoras son las hiptesis que transcienden lo racional. Por ejemplo, cabe suponer que el alma del emperador, destruido el palacio, penetr en el alma de Coleridge, para que ste lo reconstruyera en palabras, ms duraderas que los mrmoles y los metales. (1974: 644) [Others will argue that the poet somehow found out that the Emperor had dreamed the palace, and then said he had dreamed the poem in order to create a splendid fiction that would also palliate or justify the truncated and rhapsodic quality of the verses. That conjecture seems reasonable, but it obliges us to postulate, arbitrarily, a text not identified by Sinologists in which Coleridge was able to read, before 1816, and about Kublas dream. Hypotheses that transcend reason are more appealing. One such theory is that the Emperors soul penetrated Coleridges, enabling Coleridge to rebuild the destroyed palace in words that would be more lasting than marble and metal.] (1964: 16, emphasis mine)

The implications of Borges comments are striking. He would reject a priori the supernatural, and yet the explanation of the repeated vision of Kubla Khan he most favours is one of the transmigration of souls. This appears contradictory, not least when we correlate this assertion with Borges other

Introduction

33

speculation on transmigration. Reason cannot accommodate the possibility of transmigration of the soul, he suggests in the lecture Inmortalidad (2005: 18594), as it is inherently unreasonable for the soul to remember who it has been in previous incarnations. It would require a passage back to the source as each life recalls the previous; and a passage forward to the eschaton, as each life resounds in the next. Furthermore, he argues in the lecture El Tiempo [Time], an awareness of such plenitude would overwhelm and annihilate us, and hence whether there is or not transmigration of the soul, we cannot be aware of it: felizmente no lo sabemos. Felizmente, creemos en individuos. Porque si no estaramos abrumados, estaramos aniquilados por esa plenitud (2005: 217) [happily we do not know it. Happily, we believe in individuals. Because if not we would be overwhelmed, annihilated by this plenitude] (my translation).17 It is, however, a great theme of literature and the imagination that persists across the centuries. La transmigracin he writes in the lecture Budismo of Siete Noches, ha sido un gran tema de la literatura. La encontramos, tambin entre los msticos. Plotino dice que pasar de una vida a otra es como dormir en distintos lechos y en distintas habitaciones. Creo que todos hemos tenido alguna vez la sensacin de haber vivido un momento parecido en vidas anteriores (1989: 2489) [Transmigration has been a great theme of literature. We also encounter it among the mystics. Plotinus says that to pass from one life to another is like sleeping in different beds in different rooms. I imagine all of us have had the sensation of having lived previous
17 Borges returns to this theme in a later interview: William Blake says: Time is the gift of eternity. Lets try to expand on those truly wise words: if all Being were revealed to us the Being rather than the world at a single instant, undoubtedly we would be annihilated, killed. Thus, as Blake says, time is the gift of eternity; that is to say, eternity allows us all those experiences in succession. Thus, we have days and nights, hours and years. We have memory, we have our present perceptions, and then we have the future whose shape we are ignorant of, but which we foresee or fear. All, absolutely all, is given to us sequentially, and wisely so, I should add, for if it were given to us all of a sudden, it would be impossible for human beings to endure such a terrible vision the unbearable burden of the whole Being of the universe. [] The totality of Being is unattainable to us. All is given us, but, thankfully, gradually (Alifano 1984: 634).

34 Introduction

lives] (1984: 68). Again a dialogue between opposing perspectives is visible here: transmigration of souls is a literary artifice, and yet it has resonance because, he argues, it is an intrinsic aspect of human experience; indeed he declares outright that it is a feeling that all of us have shared. It is, he describes in the essay Quevedo, a false doctrine, but it is nevertheless enchanting and compelling: Hay en la historia de la filosofa doctrinas, probablemente falsas, que ejercen un oscuro encanto sobre la imaginacin de los hombres: la doctrina platnica y pitagrica del trnsito del alma por muchos cuerpos (1974: 661) [In the history of philosophy are doctrines, probably false, that exercise an obscure charm on human imagination: the Platonic and Pythagorean doctrine of the transmigration of the soul through many bodies] (1964: 38). He qualifies this tension between perspectives further by suggesting that discrediting a priori the notion of transmigration is the activity of a dry empiricist, resistant to the literary charms of the concept. He criticizes Quevedo, who being slo estudioso de la verdad, es invulnerable a ese encanto. Escribe que la transmigracin de las almas es bobera bestial y locura bruta (1974: 661) [merely a student of the truth, is invulnerable to that charm. He writes that the transmigration of souls is bestial foolishness and brutish folly] (1964: 38). Herein lies the conundrum: Borges would reject the supernatural out of principle, yet he ridicules Quevedo for upholding this very position. He would prefer to call himself a rationalist, a sceptic and a disbeliever, and yet his natural affinities lie with the non-rational, the mysterious, the poetic and those fields of experience beyond the confines of materialist philosophies the intersticios de sinrazn. It becomes clear that despite his misgivings on matters of faith, Borges placed great epistemological importance in the non-causal, the non-rational, the non-logical. In this realm we find dreams, nightmares, fantasy, mystical vision, poetry, otherworld journeys, daimonic beings, communication with the dead, ancestral voices, timelessness and ecstasy. In addition to favouring the supernatural whilst simultaneously disavowing the supernatural, we find numerous instances in Borges essays and interviews in which, like Lnnrot, he seeks the anomalous aspect of human experience before the strictly rational. He writes longingly, for example, about Stevensons accounts of receiving inspiration and fully-formed narratives, such as Strange Case of

Introduction

35

Dr Jekyll and Mr Hyde, from the Brownies whom he encountered in his dreams and reveries.18 He cites Bedes description of how Cdmon was first amongst poets, porque no aprendi de los hombres sino de Dios [because he did not learn from men, but from God], and he indicates that esperemos que [Caedmon] volvi a encontrarse con su ngel (1974: 643) [Let us hope he met his angel again] (1964: 16). He writes in absolutely clear terms that he gave great credence to the possibility that nightmares have a demonic origin, writing in the lecture on nightmares in Siete Noches:
Ya que hemos visto estas diversas etimologas, tenemos en francs la palabra cauchemar, vinculada, sin duda, con la nightmare del ingls. En todas ellas hay una idea (voy a volver sobre ellas) de origen demonaco, la idea de un demonio que causa la pesadilla. Creo que no se trata simplemente de una supersticin: creo que puede haber y estoy hablando con toda ingenuidad y toda sinceridad , algo verdadero en este concepto. (1989: 225) [We also have the French word, cauchemar, which is probably linked to nightmare. In all of these words there is an idea of demonic origin, the idea of a demon who causes the nightmare. I believe it does not derive simply from a superstition. I believe that there is and I speak with complete honesty and sincerity something true in this idea.] (1984: 32)

18

Son hombrecitos serviciales de color pardo, del cual han tomado su nombre. Suelen visitar las granjas de Escocia y durante el sueo de la familia, colaboran en las tareas domsticas. Uno de los cuentos de Grimm refiere un hecho anlogo. El ilustre escritor Robert Louis Stevenson afirm que haba adiestrado a sus Brownies en el oficio literario. Cuando soaba, stos le sugeran temas fantsticos; por ejemplo, la extraa transformacin del doctor Jekyll en el diablico seor Hyde, y aquel episodio de Olalla en el cual un joven, de una antigua casa espaola, muerde la mano de su hermana (1978: 17) [Brownies are helpful little men of a brownish hue, which gives them their name. It is their habit to visit Scottish farms and, while the household sleeps, to perform domestic chores. One of the tales by the Grimms deals with the same subject. Robert Louis Stevenson said he had trained his Brownies in the craft of literature. Brownies visited him in his dreams and told him wondrous tales; for instance the strange transformation of Dr Jekyll into the diabolical Mr Hyde, and that episode of Olalla, in which the scion of an old Spanish family bites his sisters hand] (1974: 32).

36 Introduction

Again we must ask, if he automatically reject[ed] the supernatural then how does one reconcile his inclination towards demons? When he emphasized that Swedenborg recorri este mundo y los otros, lcido y laborioso. [] ese escandinavo sanguneo, que fue mucho ms lejos que Erico el Rojo (2005: 152) [journeyed, lucid and laborious, through this and all other worlds [] that sanguine Scandinavian who went much further than Eric the Red] (1995: 3), and at the same time compared Swedenborgs authentic experiences with Dantes poetic ones, upon what basis was he making this most radical of distinctions? Reason can be an unwieldy tool, Borges appeared to argue, as it can disprove phenomena that can be experienced as real, such as transmigration of the soul or Stevensons Brownies. Annette Flynn, in her recent meticulous appraisal of the spiritual quest that dominates Borges work, identifies the paradox in Borges relationship with God in which reason can be employed to disprove God, but experience compelled him to a recognition that there is nevertheless some divine order, some divine force or presence remaining in this absence.
He oscillates between disavowal of God, and desire for verification of a divine existence. On the one hand he at times intellectualizes God and seems to be dismissing his existence on rational grounds; on the other, he continuously searches for something bigger than himself or the intellect. [] The tension lies in the balance which Borges struggles to strike between his enquiring intellect and a faith reality. (Flynn 2009: 45)

In a similar fashion Borges employed logical, reasoned, arguments to disprove the existence of time, arguing that there is no extension to the present, being the mere conjunction of past and future, and thus it cannot be considered as occupying any time. Accordingly the past, which is the mere congregation of such non-extant moments, can have no extension, and neither can the future. There is, consequently, no time; and yet we experience time.
Se ha dicho que si el tiempo es infinito, el nmero infinito de vidas hacia el pasado es una contradiccin. Si el nmero es infinito, cmo una cosa infinita puede llegar hasta ahora? Pensamos que si un tiempo es infinito, creo yo, ese tiempo infinito tiene que abarcar todos los presentes y, en todos los presentes, por qu no este presente,

Introduction

37

en Belgrano, en la Universidad de Belgrano, ustedes conmigo, juntos? Por qu no ese tiempo tambin? Si el tiempo es infinito, en cualquier instante estamos en el centro del tiempo. (2005: 189) [It has been said that if time is infinite, how can an infinite thing reach the present? We think that if time is infinite, and I believe it is, then that infinite time must include all the presents and, among all the presents, why not this present here, in the University of Belgrano, with you and I together? Why not that time also? If time is infinite, at any given moment we are in the center of time.] (2000: 4878)

The self, Borges argues in La nadera de la personalidad is equally devoid of extension or location, and consequently cannot exist; and yet Borges, desgraciademente was Borges and therefore experienced some state of selfhood. Reason and experience are not, therefore, necessarily in concord. In many respects, this dialectic may be considered a fundamental response to the dualist binary developed with Enlightenment thought, in which faith and reason, science and magic, history and myth, are assigned firmly contraposed locations. Borges was sensitive to this catalogue of binaries, and wrote with admiration of the ability of Swedenborg to harmonize his pursuit of knowledge in material sciences with his explorations of spiritual realities. Repeatedly Borges emphasized that there simply was no epistemological division, that Swedenborgs immense intellect bore him as deeply into the material as into the non-material. Plato and Socrates, for Borges, likewise did not feel compelled to distinguish one mode of enquiry from another, and were as comfortable exploring the dreamworld as the waking world. Indeed, suggested Borges, it is not only a consequence of modernity that we are unable to treat both with the same lucidity, but only modern man would even assume that a division existed.
With Plato, you feel that he would reason in an abstract way and would also use myth. He would do those two things at the same time. But now we seem to have lost that gift. I mean, you have gone from myth to abstract thinking. But Plato could do both at the same time. [] I suppose at that time it could be done. But nowadays those things seem to be in watertight compartments. Either we are thinking or we are dreaming. But Plato and Socrates could do both. (Burgin 1998: 160)

38 Introduction

This harmonising of opposites appears to be the most compelling epistemological attraction for Borges in the varied traditions of mystical texts. Reality is poetic and poetry is reality; Swedenborgs heavens were as real to Swedenborg as the minerals that he catalogued. As discussed above, Borges entire literary career, both as a reader and a writer, was grounded in his fascination with the intersticios de sinrazn that have characterized human experience since the earliest texts. Poets, artists, dreamers and mystics have explored such liminal matters, and in this respect the aesthetic allied to dreams, visions and the imagination constitutes the avenue of exploration into such mysterious interstices in the fabric of reality. We recall the labyrinth as a perennial symbol in the work of Borges to signify, amongst other things, the human state of unknowing. Whilst the critical attention to the labyrinth over the years is colossal, of greatest pertinence to our present study is a question that di Giovanni posed Borges in interview, concerning the possibility of mysticism to shine some light into the darkness and to provide some genuine insights into the inherent mysteries: Do you see mysticism as a way out of the maze? Borges replies: For all I know, mysticism is the only way; but my gods, whoever they may be, have not allowed me that particular way (Burgin 1998: 129, emphasis mine). This is a powerful response, as Borges suggested that the walls of the labyrinth may not be as impregnable as imagined, and that the mystic may be capable, through exploring the intersticios, of increasing our knowledge of reality. Swedenborgian scholar Wilson Van Dusen, whose chapter accompanies Borges in Testimony to the Invisible writes that: A mystic is one who experiences God. [] Some might ask, Dont all people experience God? And I would answer yes, but many are not aware of it. The mystic is aware of it (1995: 105). In the perspective of Borges such a statement could be rephrased: Dont all people experience intersticios de sinrazn? Yes, but the mystic is aware of it. Indeed, one may argue, the whole heavenly theology of Swedenborg constitutes a dazzling penetration into such intersticios. Hence one can query Borges interest in such mysterious matters as being merely for aesthetic purposes and merely as fodder for fiction. Flynn addresses this very issue: can we trust Borges statement of critical distance?

Introduction

39

Certain much-quoted declarations by Borges which do deserve closer attention as to the purely aesthetic, intellectual, narratorial and inspirational value of philosophical and theological doctrines, may have to be reconsidered, and the role ofthe divine assigned a more prominent place than accorded by the majority canon of critics, and not least, as is often held, by Borges himself. His remarks, typically understated and subtle, as to the significance of theologies and philosophies have been taken as categorical dismissals of these influences, or as admitting to an agnostic outlook. This is a view which is highly contestable. Far from solely driving the story or supplying intriguing, inspirational or outlandish backdrops to the events narrated, the desire for a union with the absolute, a divine, higher order is not only what underlies and drives the story, it also compels Borges. (Flynn 2009: 12)

This is a compelling statement, and an invitation to pay closer attention to Borges repeated declarations. This book is such a response.

Teaching a contemplative methodology that fosters insight (Amelia Barili)


Kripal (2001: 3) argues that there is a general reluctance within academia to incorporate into the research and teaching methodology the academics or the students own religious, mystical, numinous, transpersonal or anomalous experiences. There is a sense that the numinous is somehow taboo, and consequently is hidden in the shadows of self-censorship, discretion, and whispered enthusiasms. Borges himself, as I have argued above, maintained a critical distance that displays a tension between intellect and intuition, reason and faith, fact and fiction. The Borges scholarship, with some notable exceptions, has tended likewise and with good reason to follow Borges lead, and explore the areas of Borges interest Kabbalah, esotericism, mysticism, Buddhism with the same necessary critical distance. This, I emphasize, is fully commensurate with the critical distance that Borges himself maintained. There is, however, a tendency to treat this scholarly method of critical distance not as a hermeneutic tool to analyse the texts and phenomena encountered, but as a defence to prevent further

40 Introduction

exploration; that is to say, to take Borges on his word and treat these subjects as mere picturesque arcana and entertaining superstitions worthy only of providing thematic for fiction. Academic analysis, I would argue, should in no way prohibit a close, personal, transformative, engagement with Borges texts, and an equally close engagement with the texts and philosophies that he explored. Amelia Barili (2009: 478), who knew Borges when she was editor of La Prensa, outlines this pedagogical tension in brave and lucid terms:
I have sensed more and more that our times demand that we integrate into our teaching a contemplative methodology that fosters insight. We are in the midst of a content explosion that quickly outdates any instruction based on content alone. Further, students are increasingly anguished, and it is important that they find ways to more deeply understand this vast amount of information, to sort out what matters to them and to their communities, and to create new meaning from what is present to them. [] We need a paradigm shift in education. Universities need to be sources of creative solutions and of engaged citizens. They should be centers oftransformation, not just repositories of information. [] For deep learning to occur, there needs to be reflection about intra- and inter- subjectivity.

Barili perceives a tendency within the academic environment to favour the transmission and recollection of information over the assimilation of knowledge within a process of personal development. This is clearly a highly generalized statement, but nevertheless such a tendency is visible, especially as at least in the UK universities are under increasing pressure to market degree programmes according to a narrative of employability and are thus placing non-vocational courses (the reading of Borges poetry for its own sake, rather than as a tool to learning Spanish or Latin American literatures) under increasing scrutiny. Barili is one of the few scholars that I have encountered to incorporate the teaching of Borges texts in a fully integrated environment that encourages uniting discussion of the texts with attention to transformative processes of the readers. She seems fully cognizant of the tension present within modes of critical enquiry between reason and feeling, intellect and intuition, theory and practice. In particular, she concentrates on Borges close involvement with Buddhist texts as a rich pathway towards a full engagement with Buddhism itself. Accordingly

Introduction

41

there is no disconnection in beginning a seminar of the course Borges, Buddhism, and Cognitive Science with meditation sessions prior to a critical reading of Qu es el Budismo? or Ficciones. Buddhism itself is of key importance, she suggests, as it chimes perfectly with the mode of critical enquiry present within Borges himself: A characteristic that Borges greatly valued in Buddhism is that its core teachings are more a process of critical enquiry than an assertion of certitude. Borges found this uncertainty very liberating and stimulating, since it frees us to create our own meaning (2009: 52). It also, she argues, chimes with Borges inherently accommodating views of religion and spiritual practices: Borges attributed the durability of Buddhism over the centuries to this characteristic of tolerance, which is naturally related to an emphasis on personal inquiry and verification (2009: 52). Barilis consideration of the Buddhist sensibilities of Borges is fully borne out by an evaluation of his philosophical critical attitude and his wariness to commit to faith. In the lecture Budismo of Siete Noches Borges makes much of the demands of credulity that most faiths place upon the faithful. Las otras religiones exigen mucho de nuestra credulidad. Si somos cristianos, debemos creer que una de las tres personas de la Divinidad condescendi a ser hombre y fue crucificado en Judea. Si somos musulmanes tenemos que creer que no hay otro dios que Dios y que Muhammad es su apstol. Podemos ser buenos budistas y negar que el Buddha existi (1989: 243) [The other religions demand much more credulity on our part. If we are Christians we must believe that one of the three persons of the Divinity condescended to become a man and was crucified in Judea. If we are Muslims we must believe that there is no other god than God and that Mohammad is his apostle. We can be good Buddhists and deny that Buddha existed].19 There is, consequently, a harmonious balancing of opposites in Borges relationship with Buddhism; it is a religious path that, for him, places doubt at the heart of the spiritual attitude. Consequently, one may well argue that his closing comments of the lecture, in which he professes not to be

19

Translation Frank Thomas Smith <http://www.southerncrossreview.org/48/borgesbuddhism.htm>.

42 Introduction

Buddhist, are conversely strikingly Buddhist sentiments: Lo que he dicho hoy es fragmentario. Hubiera sido absurdo que yo expusiera una doctrina a la cual he dedicado tantos aos y de la que he entendido poco, realmente con nimo de mostrar una pieza de museo. Para m el budismo no es una pieza de museo: es un camino de salvacin (1989: 254) [What I have said tonight is fragmentary. It would have been absurd if I had expounded a doctrine to which I have dedicated some years and of which I have actually understood little with the intention of displaying a museum piece. Buddhism is not a museum piece; it is a path to salvation] (trans. Smith). It is likewise perfectly commensurate with a reading of Borges works on Buddhism to include a meditation session. Borges himself spoke about Buddhism that Lo que nos pide es la meditacin, una meditacin que no tiene que ser sobre nuestras culpas, sobre nuestra vida pasada (1989: 252) [What it requires is meditation, and meditation that has nothing to do with our sins, with our past lives] (trans. Smith). In the pedagogical method described by Barili, therefore, centred on Borges relationship with Buddhism, a certain gulf is bridged between theory and practice, reason and faith, text and meta-text; and the tension of opposites described above is tempered and harmonized. In this way Barili would appear to perceive in Borges a greater degree of investment in the mystical, spiritual, religious and metaphysical texts than is customarily afforded him. Here one may see a method developed cognate with the call for transformation outlined by Ferrer (2002: 123):
The transformative quality of the human participation in transpersonal and spiritual phenomena has been observed by a number of modern consciousness researchers (e.g. Grof, 1985, 1988; Harman, 1994) and scholars of mysticism (e.g. Barnard, 1994, Staal, 1975). One needs to be willing to be personally transformed in order to access and fully understand most spiritual phenomena. The epistemological significance of such personal transformation cannot be emphasized enough, especially given that the positivist denial of such a requisite is clearly one of the main obstacles for the epistemic legitimization of transpersonal and spiritual claims in the modern West.

I would argue that the participatory turn discussed by Ferrer is present in two fundamental levels in Borges: firstly, through a broad reading of his many tales, poems, essays and interviews, it becomes clear that despite his

Introduction

43

oft-proclaimed radical scepticism and his mistrust of faith and religious doctrine, as a reader he himself was deeply affected and transformed by the mystical and religious texts that he read. Secondly, it becomes clear that many of Borges texts themselves may be considered deeply transformative texts if the reader is open to such qualities in the works. Thus, as I explore in Chapter Two, whilst El Aleph and La escritura del dios may be interpreted as parodies or even satires of mystical texts, they may also be considered profoundly mystical texts in their own right. Such an interpretation, as I explore, is not without its difficulties, yet such a quality must be addressed. Both Barili and Ferrer would argue, furthermore, that the personal and transpersonal experiences of the students may be given greater value than many traditional pedagogical practices would customarily permit. In this work I hope to pursue the avenue proposed by Barili and Ferrer in exploring Borges relationship with mysticism as a field of investigation that was of greater significance for Borges than mere exercises in gathering material to craft into fiction and poetry.

Borges is our Virgil; only he knows the way (Alastair Reid)


Borges often suggested that he would like to be remembered as a reader more than as a writer; and in particular as a friend, as someone who happily recommends a book, poem or author, and would then delightedly pass the hours discussing the symbols, allusions, references, narrative twists and literary devices of the given texts. As such, it is important to assess the relationship between Borges the reader and the reader of Borges. What terrain does he traverse with us? Into which dark caverns in Dantes circles of hells does he lead us? What interpretative tools does he teach us when reading Swedenborgs dialogues with angels and with the dead? As he explores the intersticios de sinrazn that are themselves explored by Dante, Swedenborg, Silesius or Blake, what knowledge does he reveal to us about the nature of the real? These are also questions that have concerned

44 Introduction

readers and critics of Borges from his early publications to the present. For example, Garayalde (1978: 27), in her exploration of the influence of Sufi mysticism upon Borges works, addresses the aspect of Borges as guide in the dark world beyond reason: Once we have lost our faith in reason as a means of seeking truth, Borges does not abandon us but opens up a new range of possibilities by following the path of intuition. [] Borges is trying in this way to familiarize us with intuition, a kind of knowledge that man no longer takes into account and which he has completely forgotten. As discussed earlier, and as Garayalde identifies, Borges demonstrates a shifting balance of reason and intuition, scepticism and tolerance, in such matters of poetic obscurity. The question of Borges as guide and fellow traveller can perhaps be best illustrated with a literary analogy. In his many writings and lectures about Dante, Borges paid particular attention to the enigmatic figure of Virgil as guide and close friend of the poet-narrator Dante. There are many attributes to Virgil in the Commedia which, as Borges notes, the scholarship over the centuries has investigated. What concerned Borges above all other matters was the friendship between Dante and Virgil and the consequent anguish that Dante experienced in acknowledging that Virgil, as pagan, would be forever consigned to the nobile castello and would be unable to achieve union with the godhead:
Dante viene a ser un hijo de Virgilio y al mismo tiempo es superior a Virgilio porque se cree salvado. Cree que merecer la gracia o que la ha merecido, ya que le ha sido dada la visin. En cambio, desde el comienzo del Infierno sabe que Virgilio es un alma perdida, un rprobo; cuando Virgilio le dice que no podr acompaarlo ms all del Purgatorio, siente que el latino ser para siempre un habitante del terrible nobile castello donde estn las grandes sombras de los grandes muertos de la Antigedad, los que por ignorancia invencible no alcanzaron la palabra de Cristo. En ese mismo momento, Dante dice: Tu, duca; tu, signore; tu, maestro Para cubrir ese momento, Dante lo saluda con palabras magnficas y habla del largo estudio y del gran amor que le han hecho buscar su volumen y siempre se mantiene esa relacin entre los dos. Esa figura esencialmente triste de Virgilio, que se sabe condenado a habitar para siempre en el nobile castello lleno de la ausencia de Dios En cambio, a Dante le ser permitido ver a Dios, le ser permitido comprender el universe. (1989: 213)

Introduction

45

[Dante comes to be the son of Virgil, yet at the same time he is superior to Virgil for he believes he will be saved, since he has been given the vision. But he knows, from the beginning, that Virgil is a lost soul, a reprobate. When Virgil tells him that he cannot accompany him beyond Purgatory, he knows that the Latin poet will always inhabit the terrible nobile castello with the great shades of Antiquity, those who never heard the word of Christ. At that moment, Dante hails him with magnificent words: Tu, duca; tu, signore; tu, maestro He speaks of the great labor and of the great love with which his work has been studied, and this relation is always maintained between the two. But Virgil is essentially a sad figure who knows he is forever condemned to that castle filled with the absence of God. Dante, however, will be permitted to see God; he will be permitted to understand the universe.] (1984: 14)20

As we explore in the following chapter, whilst Borges held Dante in great esteem, he was troubled by the adherence to ecclesiastical doctrine that he perceived throughout the Commedia, and he praised the rebelliousness even heresy that he detected in Dante. Borges was no Dante; the agnosticism and the disdain for faith would likewise condemn him to the nobile castello. As Alastair Reid writes in the Introduction of Seven Nights Borges is our Virgil; only he knows the way. Like Virgil, Borges as reader and as poet has descended with Aeneas through Black Avernus into the realm of the Shades (Aeneid Book VI), and has communicated with the great Classical poets. He leads us through the hellish swamps and the celestial paradise of Swedenborgs Heaven and Hell. He guides us through Blakes complex mythologies. He describes for us the martial halls of Valhalla that he discovers in the Icelandic sagas. He reads to us about the song of Bedes

20 Dante knows that Virgil is a damned soul, and the very moment that Virgil tells him that he will not be able to accompany him beyond purgatory, Dante feels that Virgil will always be an inhabitant of that nobile castello where the great shadows of the great men of antiquity dwell, those that through unavoidable ignorance did not accept or could not reach the word of Christ. [] Dante salutes him with the highest epithets and speaks of the great love and the long study to which Virgils writings have led him, and of their relationship which has always been constant. But Virgil is sad since he knows that he is condemned to the nobile castello, far from salvation and full of Gods absence; Dante, on the other hand, will see God, he will be allowed to, and he will also be allowed to understand the universe. (Alifano 1984: 97)

46 Introduction

Cdmon and he recounts Stevensons relationship with the Brownies. He presents before our gaze oriental celestial dragons, subterranean goblins, elves, hippogriffs, the Minotaur and the Banshee (see El libro de los seres imaginarios). And yet, like Virgil, he cannot lead us to the divine. That is for the faithful and Borges, I imagine, would be happier to remain with the reader in the pagan castle, engaging in merry dialogue with Homer, Ovid, Lucan, Horace and Virgil, than rising towards the heavenly rose. This book, I hope, is part of that dialogue.

Chapter One

Fantastic or real? Borges reading of Dante and Swedenborg1

Hay un curioso gnero literario que independientemente se ha dado en diversas pocas y naciones: la gua del muerto en las regiones ultraterrenas. El Cielo y el Infierno de Swedenborg, las escrituras gnsticas, el Bardo Thdol de los tibetanos (ttulo que, segn Evans-Wentz, debe traducirse Liberacin por Audicin en el Plano de la Posmuerte) y el Libro Egipcio de los Muertos no agotan los ejemplos posibles. Las simpatas y diferencias de los dos ltimos han merecido la atencin de los eruditos; bstenos aqu repetir que para el manual tibetano el otro mundo es tan ilusorio como ste y para el egipcio es real y objetivo. Jorge Luis Borges and Margarita Guerrero, El Libro de los Seres Imaginarios, El Devorador de las Sombras [There is a strange literary genre which, spontaneously, has sprung up in various lands and at various times. This is the manual for the guidance of the dead through the Other World. Heaven and Hell by Swedenborg, the writings of the Gnostics, the Tibetan Bardo Thdol (which, according to Evans-Wentz, should be translated as Liberation by Hearing on the After-Death Plane), and the Egyptian Book of the Dead do not exhaust the possible examples. The similarities and differences of the latter two books have attracted the attention of esoteric scholarship; for us, let it be enough to recall that in the Tibetan manual the Other World is as illusory as this one, while to the Egyptians it has a real and objective existence.] The Book of Imaginary Beings, The Eater of the Dead

An earlier version of this chapter was published as an article in Variaciones Borges: Borgess reading of Dante and Swedenborg: Mysticism and the real, 32 (October 2011), 5985. Many thanks to the journal editors for kind permission to reproduce the text here.

48

Chapter One

Borges, as is well documented, subverts genre distinctions between realism and fantasy, declaring in countless interviews, prologues and essays that the joy of literature is the appeal to the imagination, that history is memory and that a literary experience is as real as any other experience. Furthermore, he famously equates metaphysics with the fantastic, claiming, for example, in a review of a work of the English theologian Leslie Weatherhead: qu son las prodigios de Wells o de Poe [] confrontados con la invencin de Dios? [] Quin en el unicornio ante la Trinidad? (1974: 281) [What, in fact, are the wonders of Wells or Edgar Allan Poe [] in comparison to the invention of God? [] What is the unicorn to the Trinity?] (2000: 255). However, in his reading of the ill-defined tradition of mystical writing, Borges appears to betray this disdain for genre distinction, and adheres with an odd rigor to a categorical assessment of real versus fictional, fantastic versus genuine, authentic versus inauthentic. Borges wrote passionately about Dante and about Swedenborg, both of whom depicted heaven and the angelic denizens therein. He pursues, as we shall see, a line of enquiry in which he asserts that Dantes visions were purely aesthetic, purely artistic, and did not hail from genuine experience; whilst Swedenborgs visions were genuine, authentic and experiential. In this chapter I will appraise Borges abiding admiration of both visionary writers and his critical response to them, and will evaluate the complex and at times paradoxical criteria that Borges employs in his assessment of the authentic in opposition to the imaginal. My hypotheses can be summed up in three statements. Borges writings lead to the erasure of fact and fiction; however, Borges himself retreats into the very realist-fantasy division that he was at pains to dispel in his fictions and essays when evaluating mysticism and mystical vision. Similarly, for Borges originality is not prized. He does, however, place great emphasis on originality in relation to mystical vision. Lastly, his assessment of putative authenticity is itself an aesthetic judgment based upon his own iconoclasm and mistrust of doctrine. This is the touchstone for his emphatic distinction. Borges manifest love for Dantes Divine Comedy is crystallized in his laudatory lecture in Siete Noches: La Comedia es un libro que todos debemos leer. No hacerlo es privarnos del mejor don que la literatura puede darnos, es entregarnos a un extrao ascetismo. Por qu negarnos la felicidad de leer la

Fantastic or real? Borges reading of Dante and Swedenborg

49

Comedia? (1989: 217) [The Comedia is a book that everyone ought to read. Not to do so is to deprive oneself of the greatest gift that literature can give us; it is to submit to a strange asceticism. Why should we deny ourselves the joy of reading the Comedia?] (1984: 20). The Divine Comedy is also the book that he would choose to rescue from the hypothetical destruction of all books (Cortnez 1986: 87). There is much to say about Borges appreciation of Dante, and whilst the Borges scholarship has approached numerous elements, one central feature prevalent in most of Borges writings of Dante has been curiously overlooked. This is Borges strident affirmation that Dante was not a visionary, but that he was a visionary poet. Borges explains: No creo que Dante fuera un visionario. Una visin es breve. Es imposible una visin tan larga como la de la Comedia. La visin fue voluntaria: debemos abandonarnos a ella y leerla, con fe potica. Dijo Coleridge que la fe potica es una voluntaria suspensin de la incredulidad (1989: 211) [I dont think that Dante was a visionary. A vision is brief. A vision as large as the Comedia is impossible. His vision was voluntary: we may abandon ourselves to it and read it with poetic faith. Coleridge said that poetic faith is the willing suspension of disbelief ] (1984: 12).2 Firstly, therefore, Borges asserts that Dantes vision was not a vision in the mystical sense, because, rather than being spontaneous and unbidden (i.e. grace of the divine), it was voluntary. Secondly, Dante was not a visionary because of the length of this vision, which, Borges maintains, would be unsustainable. Thirdly, Dante was not a visionary because the
2 This affirmation is reiterated elsewhere. He tells Roberto Alifano: Dante reveals to us in his narrative that at thirty-five (Nel mezzo del cammin di nostra vita) a vision comes to him. I dont believe that Dante was a visionary; a vision is something more fleeting, something more ethereal. A vision as prolonged as The Divine Comedy is impossible. I think that his vision was voluntary. His vision was the result ofhis poetic faith but that would be a theme in itself, a very interesting one which should be pursued (Alifano 1984: 95). He tells Willis Barnstone: It is very clear to me that when Dante had his dream of hell and his dream of purgatory, he was imagining things (Barnstone 1982: 95); and he writes in the last of the Nueve ensayos dantescos: Retengamos un hecho incontrovertible, un solo hecho humildsimo: la escena ha sido imaginada por Dante (1989: 374) [We must keep one incontrovertible fact in mind, a single, humble fact: the scene was imagined by Dante] (2000: 3045).

50

Chapter One

vision itself was inspired by poetic faith, and was therefore culturally conditioned within established theological and artistic frameworks. Furthermore, argues Borges elsewhere, Dante wrote in verse, and there is no possible way that he could have experienced the various circles of the Divine Comedy in such an aesthetic language.
En el caso de Dante, que tambin nos ofrece una descripcin del Infierno, del Purgatorio y del Paraso, entendemos que se trata de una ficcin literaria. No podemos creer realmente que todo lo que relata se refiere a una vivencia personal. Adems, ah est el verseo que lo ata: l no pudo haber experimentado el verso. (2005: 202) [In the case of Dante, who also offers us a description ofHell, Purgatory and Paradise, we understand that were dealing with literary fiction. We cannot really believe that all that he relates refers to personal experience. Furthermore, there is the verse which binds it: he could not have experienced verse.] (My translation)

The whole poetic cycle is thus, for Borges, resolutely and beautifully a literary fiction, a poetic text, an artifice. At face value this assertion does not seem too problematic, indeed it attunes perfectly to Borges love of fantasy and fiction in all their guises. However, complications begin to emerge when assessing Borges discussion of Swedenborg. The most extensive appraisal of Swedenborg in Borges works is his biographical essay on Swedenborg.3 This text abounds in highly revealing passages in which Borges affirms the authentic, non-fictive, genuine experiences of Swedenborg, and in which he emphasizes precisely the opposite of what he maintains about Dante, that Swedenborg was a visionary.

Borges 1972 essay Swedenborg, testigo de lo invisible was published as prologue to a Spanish edition of The Essential Swedenborg by Sig Synnestvedt: Swedenborg, testigo de lo invisible (1982), translated into English by Richard Howard and Cesar Rennert as Testimony to the Invisible in the homonymous volume of essays edited by James F. Lawrence (1995). The original prologue is also found in the section Prlogos, con un prlogo de prlogos (2005, 15260), entitled, Emmanuel Swedenborg: Mystical Works. Eliot Weinbergers English translation of this prologue/essay appears in Total Library: Non-Fiction (2000a) 44957.

Fantastic or real? Borges reading of Dante and Swedenborg

51

En una epstola famosa dirigida a Cangrande Della Scala, Dante Alighieri advierte qu su Comedia, como la Sagrada Escritura, puede leerse de cuatro modos distintos y que el literal no es ms que Uno de ellos []. Pasajes como Lasciate ogni speranza, voi chentrate fortalecen esa conviccin topogrfica, realizada por el arte. Nada ms diverso de los destinos ultraterrenos de Swedenborg. (2005: 156) [In a famous letter to Cangrande Della Scala, Dante Alighieri points out that his Commedia, like Sacred Scripture, can be read four different ways, of which the literal way is only one []. Passages such as Lasciate ogni speranza, voi chentrate (All hope abandon, ye who enter here) reinforce the topographical conviction created through art. Nothing is farther from the ultra-terrestrial destinations of Swedenborg.] (1995: 9)

The Divine Comedy, he asserts, is the pinnacle of artistic expression, and the fact that Dante outlines modes of reading (literal, allegorical, moral, anagogical), testifies to this artifice. The mystical works of Swedenborg, however, are wholly free from artifice, being the direct account of genuine experience of a man que recorri este mundo y los otros, lcido y laborioso. [] ese escandinavo sanguneo, que fue mucho ms lejos que Erico el Rojo (2005: 152) [who journeyed, lucid and laborious, through this and all other worlds [] that sanguine Scandinavian who went much further than Eric the Red] (1995: 3). Significantly, Borges maintains that the literal reading of the Divine Comedy would impoverish the text, as the reader would fail to appreciate the allegorical, moral and mystical levels of meaning.4 It would also betray a stultifying credulity on behalf of the reader. To illustrate this, Borges makes reference on more than one occasion to the observation that the heaven of Dante would correspond to no heaven putatively encountered after death.
Paul Claudel ha observado que los espectculos que nos aguardan despus de la agona no sern verosmilmente los nueve crculos infernales, las terrazas del Purgatorio o los cielos concntricos. Dante, sin duda, habra estado de acuerdo con l; ide su

Aside, however, from the opening couplet of the cycle: Nel mezzo del cammin di nostra vita / mi ritrovai per una selva oscura. Es decir, a los treinta y cinco aos me encontr en mitad de una selva oscura que puede ser alegrica, pero en la cual creemos fsicamente (1989: 211) [That is, at thirty-five I found myself in a dark forest. It may be allegorical, but we physically believe it] (1984: 12).

52

Chapter One
topografa de la muerte como un artificio exigido por la escolstica y por la forma de su poema. (1989: 344) [Paul Claudel has observed that the sights that await us after dying will not, in all likelihood, include the nine circles of Hell, the terraces of Purgatory, or the concentric heavens. Dante would undoubtedly have agreed; he devised his topography of death as an artifice demanded by Scholasticism and by the form of his poem.] (2000: 268)5

On the contrary, he maintains, it would be difficult to read the works of Swedenborg in any manner other than the literal. This is because, for Borges, Swedenborgs writings were the genuine expression of experience, and were not written with any attempt at parable, symbol or allegory. He emphasizes Swedenborgs dry and meticulous Latin prose as being wholly free from flowery literary technique, especially metaphor: A diferencia de otros msticos, prescindi de la metfora, de la exaltacin y de la vaga y fogosa hiprbole (2005: 154) [unlike other mystics, he eschewed metaphor, exaltation, and vague, fiery hyperbole] (1995: 6).6 He examines the
5 Borges also derives this observation from Flaubert: Por eso me parece justo lo que ha dicho Flaubert diciendo que Dante al morir debe haberse asombrado al ver que el Infierno, el Purgatorio o el Paraso vamos a suponer que le toc la ltima regin no corresponda a su imaginacin. Yo creo que Dante no crea, al escribir el poema, haber hecho otra cosa sino haber encontrado smbolos adecuados para expresar de un modo sensible los estados de nimo del pecador, del penitente y del justo (Borges 2002: 2056) [For that reason, Flauberts comments seem to me apt, that Dante, upon dying, must have been astonished to see that Hell, Purgatory and Paradise let us suppose that he reached this final region did not correspond to his imagination. I believe that Dante did not believe, when he wrote his poem, that he was doing anything other than finding symbols to express in an understandable manner the states of the soul of the sinner, the penitent, and the just] (my translation). The literary style of Swedenborg intrigues his readers. Henry James Sr. (father of William and Henry) labels him insipid with veracity (in Johnson 2003), which is echoed in his friend Emersons comments that Swedenborg remained entirely devoid of the whole apparatus of poetic expression (Emerson 2003: 54). This is then further iterated in William James: But why should he be so prolix and so toneless so without emphasis? (in Johnson 2003) W.B. Yeats comments: And all this happened to a man without egotism, without drama, without a sense of the picturesque, and who wrote a dry language, lacking fire and emotion (1920: 299). Kathleen Raine,

Fantastic or real? Borges reading of Dante and Swedenborg

53

objective of such a studious and prosaic language, suggesting that it was the product of an almost mimetic reproduction of his visionary experiences.
La explicacin es obvia. El empleo de cualquier vocablo presupone una experiencia compartida, de la que el vocablo es el smbolo. Si nos hablan del sabor del caf, es porque ya lo hemos probado, si nos hablan del color amarillo, es porque ya hemos visto limones, oro, trigo y puestas del sol. Para sugerir la inefable unin del alma del hombre con la divinidad, los sufes del Islam se vieron obligados a recurrir a analogas prodigiosas, a imgenes de rosas, de embriaguez o de amor carnal; Swedenborg pudo renunciar a tales artificios retricos porque su tema no era el xtasis del alma arrebatada y enajenada, sino la puntual descripcin de regiones ultraterrenas, pero precisas. Con el fin de que imaginemos, o empecemos a imaginar, la nfima hondura del Infierno, Milton nos habla de No light, but rather darkness visible; Swedenborg prefiere el rigor y por qu no decirlo? las eventuales prolijidades del explorador o del gegrafo que registra reinos desconocidos. (2005: 154) [The explanation is obvious. The use of any word whatsoever presupposes a shared experience, for which the word is the symbol. If someone speaks to us about the flavor of coffee, it is because we have already tasted it; if about the color yellow, because we have already seen lemons, gold, wheat, and sunsets. To suggest the ineffable union of mans soul with the divine being, the Sufis of Islam found themselves obliged to resort to prodigious analogies, to images of roses, intoxication, or carnal love. Swedenborg was able to abstain from this kind of rhetorical artifice because his subject matter was not the ecstasy of a rapt and fainting soul but, rather, the accurate description of regions that, though ultra-terrestrial, were clearly defined. In order for us to imagine, or to begin to imagine, the lowest depth of hell, John Milton speaks to us of No light, but rather darkness visible. Swedenborg prefers the rigor and why not say it? possible wordiness of the explorer or geographer who is recording unknown kingdoms.] (1995: 7)

Borges admires the intellectual capacity, determinism and exploratory drive of Swedenborg the very qualities that had furnished his abilities to write tables of mining and metallurgy, design aircraft and submarines, and create un mtodo personal para fijar las longitudes y un tratado sobre el dimetro de la luna (2005: 153) [a personal method of fixing longitudes

meanwhile, calls his writing stilted and voluminous (1995: 54). Borges is part of a long tradition of critical reception of Swedenborgs language.

54

Chapter One

and a treatise on the diameter of the moon] (1995: 4).7 These accounts of heaven and hell, Borges maintains, were subject to the same degree of rational scrutiny that Swedenborg employed in his assessment of the natural world, and consequently were unadulterated by religious dogma.8 Similarly, Borges emphatically defends Swedenborg against the readers incredulity, stressing that any of the arguments commonly employed to discredit Swedenborg deceit or madness are invalid. Swedenborg was not attempting to proselytize, because, Borges asserts, A la manera de Emerson (Arguments convince nobody) y de Walt Whitman, crea que los argumentos no persuaden a nadie y que basta enunciar una verdad para que los interlocutores la acepten (2005: 155) [Like Emerson and Walt Whitman, he believed that arguments persuade no one and that stating a truth is sufficient for its acceptance by those who hear it] (1995: 8). Had he been mad, he argues, no deberamos a su pluma tenaz la ulterior redaccin de miles de metdicas pginas, que representan una labor de casi treinta aos y que nada tienen que ver con el frenes (2005: 155) [we would not owe to his tenacious pen the thousands of methodical pages he wrote during the following thirty years or so, pages that have nothing at all to do with frenzy] (1995: 8). Herein lies a puzzling feature of Borges admiration of Swedenborg. Who, we may ask, is this reader that Borges so stridently conceptualizes and answers? Why would he seek to defend Swedenborg
7 Conan Doyle (in McNeilly ed., 2005: 105) suggests that Swedenborg was a great authority upon [] the determination of latitude [2005: 96], whilst Borges asserts: We are indebted to him for a personal method of fixing longitude. It would appear, however, that Conan Doyle mistook latitude for longitude, as the title of the work in which Swedenborg established this nagivational principle is the delightfullynamed Frsk at finna stra och westra lengden igen, igenom mnan, som til the lrdas omprfwande framstelles [Attempt to find the East and West Longitude by means of the moon. Put forward for the examination of the learned]. I have not seen any attempt to correct Conan Doyles (or his editors) mistake. Yeats also notes the similarity in style between Swedenborgs scientific journals and his visionary journals: He considered heaven and hell and God, the angels, the whole destiny of man, as if he were sitting before a large table in a Government office putting little pieces of mineral ore into small square boxes for an assistant to pack away in drawers (1920: 299).

Fantastic or real? Borges reading of Dante and Swedenborg

55

(and himself ) against the charge of la deliberada impostura de quien ha escrito esas cosas extraas (2005: 154) [deliberate imposture on the part of the man who wrote such strange things] (1995: 7) if, having included Swedenborg in El libro de los seres imaginarios he had already established his fantastical nature? To address this question, it is first necessary to qualify the statement made earlier that the distinction between fact and fiction, reality and imagination, is not present in Borges as writer or reader. Whilst we may assert, as Borges himself repeatedly does, that his admiration of philosophical and theological discourses lay in their aesthetic value, this should not impoverish the aesthetic as mere elegance or literary finery. In the work of Borges the aesthetic as related to poesis and imagination is a pathway to knowledge. Like Lezama Limas vision of poetry, in which there is a gnosis in the aesthetic, or Blakes Imagination or imaginative energy, which is the true path to the divine, or Corbins mundus imaginalis, in which the secret nature of the divine is revealed, Borges places a strong epistemological value to the imagination, the dreamworld, and the aesthetic.9 The aesthetic is neither simply linguistic nor simply the sonorous play of words. Arguments themselves can be the index of aesthetic brilliance, typified by Schopenhauers elegant philosophy. Borges professes an admiration for Blake, emphasizing that Blake asimismo afirmar que no bastan la inteligencia y la rectitud y que la salvacin del hombre exige un tercer requisito: ser un artista (2005: 158) [Blake also affirms that the salvation of man demands a third requirement: that he be an artist] (1995: 13). Such a sentiment is strikingly akin to Borges own ars poetica, exemplified in his calm belief in the persistence ofliterature: I dont think of life as being pitted against literature. I believe that art is a part of life (Barnstone 1982: 96). Borges paid close attention to the spiritual power that Blake associated with the aesthetic, and it would seem that this Blakean vision inspired his relationship to Art and Imagination, borne out in his comment

See Mualem 2004. See also Nez-Faraco (2009: 41): Despite his scepticism and anti-religious stance, there is in Borges a conspicuous interest in mysticism and in its revelation of divine truth. [] Borgess interest in religion, like his fascination with metaphysics, hinges on an aesthetic perception of the world.

56

Chapter One

to Barnstone (1982: 102): We are creating God every time that we attain beauty. This moving aphorism could come from the illuminated pages of Blakes Marriage of Heaven and Hell. Borges relationship to imagination, to fantasy and to the dreamworld is perhaps the most striking feature of his poetics, is discussed in the majority of his interviews, and is illustrated in so many of his tales. Yet to approach the dreamworld epistemologically is an intriguing endeavour which reveals Borges kinship with, amongst others, Blake, Corbin and Jung. Kathleen Raine, whose essay appears alongside Borges in Lawrences Testimony to the Invisible, emphasizes this path of wisdom:
The ultimate knowledge, according to Blake and Swedenborg, is that the universe is contained in mind a view to be found also in the Gnostic writings, in the Vedas, and in other spiritually profound cosmologies of the East, but long forgotten in the West with its preoccupation with externality. (Raine 1995: 62)

Blake, it should be remembered, explicitly equated the imaginal world with the eternal, with the space-time the discarnate soul enters after death: This world of the Imagination is the world of Eternity; it is the divine bosom into which we shall all go after the death of the Vegetated body. This World of Imagination is Infinite and Eternal, whereas the world of Generation, or Vegetation, is Finite & Temporal (in Raine 1995: 70). Likewise, innumerable passages from Borges testify to the power of dreams to grant the dreamer knowledge of further dimensions, landscapes and times. Borges often alludes to the poetic question of Coleridges flower retrieved from the dreamworld, and he contemplates whether Chuang Tzu experienced being a butterfly in his dream or whether the butterfly experienced being Chuang Tzu. Most well known are the multiple layers of dream creation in Las ruinas circulares [The Circular Ruins]. It is therefore striking to note that Swedenborgs initiation into the heavenly realm lay in his troubled dreams. As is so clear from a reading of any of Borges work, the distinctions between fiction and reality, history and myth, fact and artifice, are hazy: I suppose there is no difference between fact and fiction. [] What is the past but all memory? What is the past but memories that have become myth? (Barnstone 1982: 117), or, to borrow an expression from Lezama

Fantastic or real? Borges reading of Dante and Swedenborg

57

Lima: no hay nada ms real que la imaginacin (2001: 133) [there is nothing more real than the imagination] (my translation). Furthermore, and considering the imagination epistemologically, the question of authenticity of experience is problematic. Borges discusses the tale El Congreso [The Congress] in the afterword to El Libro de Arena, suggesting that el fin quiere elevarse, sin duda en vano, a los xtasis de Chesterton o de John Bunyan. No he merecido nunca semejante revelacin, pero he procurado soarla (1989: 72) [its end tries, doubtless in vain, to match the ecstasies of Chesterton and John Bunyan. I have never been worthy of such a revelation, but I managed to dream one up] (1979: 93). This is paradoxical if we follow the very fluidity of fact and fiction, reality and fantasy, present in Borges. If he has dreamt one up then he has been worthy of such a revelation. Upon what principles could a distinction be based, if we judge imagination to be itself experiential? Borges repeatedly emphasizes that dreaming and artistic poetic creativity are aspects of the same process:
The essential difference between the waking experience and the sleeping or dreaming experience must lie in the fact that the dreaming experience is something that can be begotten by you, created by you, evolved out of you [] not necessarily in sleep. When youre thinking out a poem, there is little difference between the fact of being asleep and that of being awake, no? And so they stand for the same thing. If youre thinking, if youre inventing, or if youre dreaming, then the dream may correspond to vision or to sleep. That hardly matters. (Barnstone 1982: 29)

Surely one of the most abiding sensations delivered to the reader of Borges is that reality is fictional and fiction is real. Is he not declaring at every stage, therefore, that we really are in no position to judge so firmly between an event of the imagination and one of empirical experience? Borges, for example, makes no distinction between the experience of reading and the experience of travelling. That is to say, the textual and the meta-textual are epistemologically no different. He declares to Richard Burgin:
I think of reading a book as no less an experience than traveling or falling in love. I think that reading Berkeley or Shaw or Emerson, those are quite as real experiences to me as seeing London, for example. Of course, I saw London through Dickens and through Chesterton and through Stevenson, no? Many people are apt to think of real life on the one side, that means toothache, headache, traveling and so on, and

58

Chapter One
then you have on the other side, you have imaginary life and fancy and that means the arts. But I dont think that that distinction holds water. I think that everything is a part of life. (Burgin 1998: 14)

Bioy Casares and Borges dined together regularly, whilst discussing literature, poetry and metaphysics. One conversation could be recorded by Borges in a recollection; another could be recorded at the beginning of Tln, Uqbar, Orbis Tertius. It would be a step into a rigid binary pattern of thinking to attempt to distinguish between a factual and a fictional conversation between these two. Both are fantastic, both are textual, both are factual and fictional at the same time. I dont see how things can be unreal Borges opined. I dont see any valid reason why Hamlet, for example, should be less real than Lloyd George (Burgin 1998: 77), or why Macbeth should be less real than todays newspaper (Burgin 1998: 85). It is abidingly evident, therefore, that in all matters of human expression, and in whichever system he was contemplating whether fantastical, poetical, mythological, theological, philosophical, or political experience is experience whether it derives from physical or imaginal travel. Memory is creative and thus a fiction, and yet the experience of fiction is tangible and real. Why, therefore, does Borges draw such a firm distinction between the real experiences of Swedenborg and the unreal or fictional experiences of Dante? In order to address this question, it is important to focus on Borges assessment of other writers of mystical vision and eschatology, and in particular, on the presence of doctrine that Borges could perceive looming over them. Borges reviewed Leslie Weatherheads After Death, and he damns Weatherhead for being a mediocre and almost non-existent writer, for being estimulatado por lecturas piadosas [stimulated by pious readings] and for making unconvincing conjeturas semiteosficas (1974: 282) [semitheosophical conjectures] (2000: 2556). Weatherheads poor writing status betrays an aesthetic poverty that is not only clearly indicative of a wholly unappealing metaphysical vision, but is, furthermore, inauthentic, derivative, and, importantly, non-experiential. At the beginning of his pugnacious review, Borges reasserts the famous declaration of the narrator of Tln, that metaphysics is but another branch of fantastic literature. Here

Fantastic or real? Borges reading of Dante and Swedenborg

59

he embellishes this with a mention of his own book of fantastic literature, and his guilty omission of the masters of the fantastic genre: Parmnides, Platn, Juan Escoto Ergena, Alberto Magno, Spinoza, Leibniz, Kant, Francis Bradley (1974: 280) [Parmenides, Plato, John Scotus Erigena, Albertus Magnus, Spinoza, Leibniz, Kant, Francis Bradley] (2000: 255). He then, as if to confirm his agnostic credentials, compares the fantastic with the religious, mocking the theological discourse that Weatherhead presents:
En efecto, qu son los prodigios de Wells o de Edgar Allan Poe una flor que nos llega del porvenir, un muerto sometido a la hipnosis confrontados con la invencin de Dios, con la teora laboriosa de un ser que de algn modo es tres y que solitariamente perdura fuera del tiempo? Qu es la piedra bezoar ante la armona preestablecida, quin es el unicornio ante la Trinidad, quin es Lucio Apuleyo ante los multiplicadores de Buddhas del Gran Vehculo, qu son todas las noches de Shahrazad junto a un argumento de Berkeley? He venerado la gradual invencin de Dios; tambin el Infierno y el Cielo (una remuneracin inmortal, un castigo inmortal) son admirables y curiosos designios de la imaginacin de los hombres. (1974: 2801) [What, in fact, are the wonders of Wells or Edgar Allan Poe a flower that visits us from the future, a dead man under hypnosis in comparison to the invention of God, the labored theory of a being who in some way is three and who endures alone outside of time? What is the bezoar stone to pre-established harmony, what is the unicorn to the Trinity, who is Lucius Apuleius to the multipliers of Buddhas of the Greater Vehicle, what are all the nights of Scheherazade next to an argument by Berkeley? I have worshiped the gradual invention of God; Heaven and Hell (an immortal punishment, an immortal reward) are also admirable and curious designs of mans imagination.] (2000: 255)

A beautiful Borgesian conundrum is thus established. Heaven and hell derive from imagination, and yet they are nevertheless real. Herein lie his motives for including Swedenborgs angels and devils in El libro de los seres imaginarios yet all the while proclaiming the authenticity of Swedenborgs visions.10 How real are the angels, and can we detect in Borges any attempt

10

One might assume that Borges could well have included a passage from Swedenborg in his Extraordinary Tales (1973). As it is, he and Bioy Casares include a brief text

60

Chapter One

however futile it may be to separate an empirical angel somehow extrinsic to human imagination from an intrinsic, imaginative angel? Borges sister, Norah, a painter whose impact on Borges writing career has now been fairly deeply studied, painted angels (indeed, one of her angel paintings hung in the parlour of Borges apartment on Belgrano [Burgin 1998: 100]), and allegedly maintained conversations with angels as a child. Borges develops a strikingly Jungian approach to angels, in that they are creatures of the imagination, but that consequently they are real. They develop the particular substance of Jungs archetypal beings, in that they belong to the psyche, but that the realm of the psyche extends into transpersonal, timeless dimensions, beyond the control of the individual ego, and therefore operational, as it were, extrinsic to the individual.11 For Borges, angels, for example, are one more creation of the imagination, but whose persistence in the human imagination grants them some undefined ontological status. A 1926 essay entitled A History of Angels describes this perspective.
Ya estamos orillando el casi milagro que es la verdadera motivacin de este escrito: lo que podramos denominar la supervivencia del ngel. La imaginacin de los hombres ha figurado tandas de monstruos (tritones, hipogrifos, quimeras, serpientes de mar, unicornios, diablos, dragones, lobizones, cclopes, faunos, basiliscos, semidioses, leviatanes y otros que son caterva) y todos ellos han desaparecido, salvo los ngeles. Qu verso de hoy se atrevera a mentar la fnix o a ser paseo de un centauro? Ninguno; pero a cualquier poesa, por moderna que sea, no le desplace ser nidal de ngeles y resplandecerse con ellos. Yo me los imagino siempre al anochecer, en la tardecita de los arrabales o de los descampados, en ese largo y quieto instante en que se van quedando solas las cosas a espaldas del ocaso y en que los colores distintos parecen recuerdos o presentimientos de otros colores. No hay que gastarlos mucho a los ngeles; son las divinidades ltimas que hospedamos y a lo mejor se vuelan. (1994: 67)

11

from The False Swedenborg of 1873. I have not been able to locate this source. It might well be one of their many invented texts. Philemon, for example, was both real and psychological for Jung. The distinction is, ultimately, irrelevant. It must also be noted that Borges was a sympathetic reader of Jung: Ive always been a great reader of Jung (Burgin 1969: 109). He also makes reference to Jung in Nathaniel Hawthorne (1974: 670), and to Jungs Psychologie und alchemie in Kafka y sus precursores (1974: 710) and in El libro de los seres imaginarios.

Fantastic or real? Borges reading of Dante and Swedenborg

61

[Here we arrive at the near miracle that is the true motive for this writing: what we might call the survival of the angel. The human imagination has pictured a horde of monsters (tritons, hippogriffs, chimeras, sea serpents, unicorns, devils, dragons, werewolves, cyclopes, fauns, basilisks, demigods, leviathans, and a legion of others) and all have disappeared, except angels. Today, what line of poetry would dare allude to the phoenix or make itself the promenade of a centaur? None; but no poetry, however modern, is unhappy to be a nest of angels and to shine brightly with them. I always imagine them at nightfall, in the dusk of a slum or a vacant lot, in that long, quiet moment when things are gradually left alone, with their backs to the sunset, and when colors are like memories or premonitions of other colors. We must not be too prodigal with our angels; they are the last divinities we harbor, and they might fly away.] (2000: 19)12

It is interesting to note that all the monsters he mentions in this passage later appear in El libro de los seres imaginarios, yet he awards a different degree of compassion to angels, derived perhaps from his sisters relationship with them. The hard-lined Kantian logic present in the 1922 essay La nadera de la personalidad appears to be able to dismiss angels as creatures of the imagination, yet unlike Kant, this approach would nevertheless permit such imaginary beings to be more real than simple illusions and, furthermore, to be worthy of philosophical speculation. And yet the paradox runs deeper: he praises Swedenborgs visions yet derides Weatherheads on the assumption that the formers are genuine whilst the latters are merely conforming to dogmatic theology. Borges assertion of authenticity is itself a clear reflection of his own free-thinking or agnostic (both terms which he regularly employs) position. His mistrust of Christian doctrine was such that Carlos Cortnez observes it even manifesting in a distrust of the treasured dreamworld, when Borges
12 Borges was notoriously scathing of the book in which this essay appeared El tamao de mi esperanza: I am thoroughly ashamed of that book [] I try to forget it. A very poor book (Barnstone 1982: 82). The legend (that Borges promoted) was that he gathered any copies of the book he could find and burned them. He also, though, says the same about Inquisiciones: (Barnstone 1982: 110). One cannot help feeling that Borges is actually a canny promoter of his own works; by claiming in countless interviews that both Tamao and Inquisiciones should not be read, he is actually encouraging people to read them.

62

Chapter One

mother claims that her dead father had returned to her in a dream to assure her of the existence of God.13 He unpicks the nature of vision of Swedenborg, and opens (though does not explore) a thorny question that arises regularly in the nebulous scholarship of mysticism: are experiences unique to the individual or are they universal? Are experiences exceptional or culturally conditioned? Or, put in a different way, did Teresa de vila encounter Christ, or did she encounter the same source or power that non-Christian mystics might encounter, but that she interpreted this power as Christ? Yeats, for example, attributes a strong cultural influence upon Swedenborgs own appreciation of the angelic realm: Swedenborg because he belongs to an eighteenth century not yet touched by the romantic revival feels horror amid rocky uninhabited places, and so believes that the evil are in such places while the good are amid smooth grass and garden walks and the clear sunlight of Claude Lorraine (1920: 303), and he maintains that

13

En la entrevista con Carlos Cortnez encontramos, por desgracia, muy sintetizada, aquella famosa conversacin que tuvieron Borges con su madre acerca de Dios. No recuerdo cmo la conversacin deriv hacia las creencias religiosas de cada cual. Entonces ella me declar su fe con una simplicidad no exenta de dramatismo me cont un sueo que ella tuvo cuando muri su padre: l se le acercaba, muy fatigado, y le aseguraba, de un modo que no ha podido olvidar, que Dios existe. Dos o tres veces fue interrumpido por su hijo que opona razones de su escepticismo. Era paradjico or a Borges desconfiar de la seriedad de los sueos, para no dejarse convencer por la belleza del relato de su madre. En una de esas, ella sin molestarse pero con la superioridad del creyente lo hizo callar: Deja Georgie, t no piensas en estas cosas! (Romero 1977: 492) [In the interview with Carlos Cortnez we regretfully find that famous conversation that Borges had with his mother about God: I dont remember how the conversation moved towards their religious beliefs. She declared to me her faith with a simplicity not lacking drama she told me about a dream she had when her father died: he, exhausted, had approached her and had assured her in a way she could not forget that God exists. Two or three times she was interrupted by her son who put forward reasons for his scepticism. It was paradoxical to hear Borges mistrust the seriousness of dreams, in order not to allow himself to be convinced by the beauty of his mothers tale. On one of those interruptions she calmly and with the superiority of a believer made him silent: Enough Georgie! You dont believe in such matters!] (my translation).

Fantastic or real? Borges reading of Dante and Swedenborg

63

Blakes outlandish mythologies derived from the absence of established doctrine.14 Raine addresses this perennial question when considering the influence of Swedenborg on Blake: it may be that we also have to conclude that those gifted with the clear vision of the imaginal world are in essential agreement because describing the same reality (Raine 1995: 67). Borges brushes aside the implications of specific doctrinal mystical experiences: Swedenborg, como Spinoza o Francis Bacon, fue un pensador por cuenta propia y que cometi un incmodo error cuando resolvi ajustar sus ideas al marco de los dos Testamentos (2005: 155) [Swedenborg, like Spinoza or Francis Bacon, was a thinker in his own right who made an awkward mistake when he decided to adapt his ideas to the framework of the two Testaments] (1995: 9).15 Quite clearly, for Borges, the aesthetic power of
14 He was a man crying out for a mythology, and trying to make one because he could not find one to his hand. Had he been a Catholic of Dantes time he would have been well content with Mary and the angels; or had he been a scholar of our time he would have taken his symbols where Wagner took his, from Norse mythology (1903: 174). Borges, it must be recalled, was often reserved about Blakes complex mythologies, claiming: La obra de Blake es una obra de lectura extraordinariamente difcil, ya que Blake haba creado un sistema teolgico, pero para exponerlo, se le ocurri inventar una mitologa sobre cuyo sentido no estn de acuerdo los comentadores (Borges 2002: 215) [The work of Blake is extraordinarily difficult to read, seeing that Blake created a theological system, but that, in order to express it, it occurred to him to invent a mythology that none of the commentators can agree upon] (my translation). He also at one stage calls Blake generally long-winded and ponderous (Barnstone 1982: 26), and he states that one would need a dictionary of Blake to understand Blake. This is, indeed, a pervasive question. Robert Moss suggests that Swedenborgs religious upbringing was contributory towards his visions: These encounters [with the dead] also gave him a first-hand understanding of the conditions of the afterlife. Previously, his religious faith had convinced him that the spirit survives physical death. Now he could begin to study how it survives (1998: 188). Colin Wilson, meanwhile, pursues a line similar to that of Yeats and Borges: [Swedenborg] lived in a religious age; his father was a bishop; he had studied the Bible since childhood. It was, therefore, natural that his visions expressed themselves in terms of the Bible. If he had been brought up on the works of Shakespeare or Dante, no doubt his ideas would have expressed themselves in the form of gigantic commentaries on Shakespeares tragedies or the Divine Comedy. The chief obstacle to the modern understanding of Swedenborg is

15

64

Chapter One

Swedenborg lay in an authentic experience unmediated by doctrine aside from in a few infelicitous moments and despite its Christian clothing, whereas the mediocre Weatherhead simply reproduced established dogma. In a similar fashion, Barnstone asks Borges about the Spanish mystics, and about his own mystical experiences:
Barnstone: Youve been immersed in the writings of the Gnostics, the mystics, in the Kabbalah, the Book of Splendor. Borges: Ive done my best, but I am very ignorant. Barnstone: You have been interested in the mystics Borges: At the same time I am no mystic myself. Barnstone: I imagine that you would consider the voyage of the mystics a true experience but a secular one. Could you comment on the mystical experience in other writing, in Fray Luis de Len Borges: I wonder if Fray Luis de Len had any mystical experience. I should say not. When I talk of mystics, I think of Swedenborg, Angelus Silesius, and the Persians also. Not the Spaniards. I dont think they had any mystical experiences. Barnstone: John of the Cross? Borges: I think that Saint John of the Cross was following the pattern of the Song of Songs. And thats that. I suppose he never had any actual experience. In my life I only had two mystical experiences and I cant tell them because what happened is not to be put in words, since words, after all, stand for a shared experience. And if you have not had the experience you cant share it as if you were to talk about the taste of coffee and had never tried coffee. Twice in my life I had a feeling, a feeling rather agreeable than otherwise. It was astonishing, astounding. I was overwhelmed, taken aback. I had the feeling of living not in time but outside time. It may have been a minute or so, it may have been longer. [] Somehow the feeling came over me that I was living beyond time, and I did my best to capture it, but it came and went. I wrote poems about it, but they are normal poems and do not tell the experience. I cannot tell it to you, since I cannot retell it to myself, but I had that experience, and I had it twice over, and maybe it will be granted me to have it one more time before I die. (Barnstone 1982: 1011)

that few of us can take the Bible for granted in the way that our great-grandfathers did. This is a sad reflection on the modern age (1995: 100).

Fantastic or real? Borges reading of Dante and Swedenborg

65

Again, his dismissal of the Spaniards lies in his sense of their doctrinal adherence. Whilst Borges admires John of the Crosss poetic craft, he nevertheless perceives the same sense of inauthenticity of experience that he does in Weatherhead. John of the Cross was merely following the pattern of the Song of Songs in the same fashion that Weatherhead was merely parroting conjeturas semiteosficas (1974: 282). Furthermore, he derides Pascal for doctrinal adherence claiming that his derision of Pascal was itself derived from Swedenborg: No es [Pascal] un mstico; pertenece a aquellos cristianos denunciados por Swedenborg, que suponen que el cielo es un galardn y el infierno un castigo y que, habituados a la meditacin melanclica, no saben hablar con los ngeles (1974: 704) [He is not a mystic; he belongs to those Christians, denounced by Swedenborg, who suppose that heaven is a reward and hell a punishment and who, accustomed to melancholy meditation, do not know how to speak with the angels] (1964: 99). Borges own mystical experiences, as he describes, were unique and personal, purportedly uninspired by textual sources, and consequently inexpressible. Here lies the nub of the paradox. Whilst we are all the products of our influences, and whilst he repeatedly maintains that all great literature is merely the re-articulation of a few perennial symbols, nevertheless, for Borges the mystical experience by necessity must be somehow free of influence in order to shine with authenticity. It is my hypothesis that this opinion of authenticity is a smokescreen, and that what really is at stake is not a metaphysical judgment about the true substance and structure of heaven, nor of the ontology of angelic beings. Rather, it is Borges inveterate iconoclasm, his mistrust of doctrine, and his love of heterodoxy, heretics, heresy and heresiarchs. Doctrine, and its constellation as dogma, was, for Borges a denial of individual will and creative liberty. Political doctrine merely entertains people, or, in the case of Juan and Evita Pern, only entertains the ignorant.16 In the case of Nazism, its appeal can lead them to outrageous acts

16

See Lillusion Comique (Borges 2000a: 40911).

66

Chapter One

of brutality.17 Philosophical doctrine, he argues, is really mere guesswork (Barnstone 1982: 111). Theological doctrine, especially if allied to blind faith, naturally and reasonably, leads to great intolerance.18 Borges even declares that his abiding love for Dante and for the Divine Comedy derives from its aesthetics in spite of the theology: Lo que menos me ha interesado en La divina comedia es el valor religioso. Es decir, me han interesado los personajes [] sus destinos, pero todo el concepto religioso, la idea de premios y de castigos, es una idea que no he entendido nunca (Sorrentino 2001: 144) [What least interests me in The Divine Comedy is the religious value. Thats to say, I am interested in the characters [] their destinies, but all the religious dimension, the idea of reward and punishment, is an idea that I have never understood] (my translation). Swedenborg, conversely in Borges view, underwent journeys into imaginal landscapes of heavens and hells and was so untouched by the pressure of doctrinal adherence that he risked being branded a heretic. Whilst observing the doctrinal geometry of Dantes Divine Comedy, it becomes clear that a central thrust of Borges veneration for Dante lies, conversely, in his subtle heterodox, even heretical, dimensions. In the Nueve ensayos dantescos (1989: 33972), Borges elaborates the degree to which Dante pushes the boundaries of orthodoxy to an alarming degree. There are many facets to this reading ofDante, and many areas that Borges investigates
17 Recall the oft-quoted statement of the narrator of Tln Hace diez aos bastaba cualquier simetra con apariencia de orden el materialismo dialctico, el antisemitismo, el nazismo para embelesar a los hombres. Cmo no someterse a Tln, a la minuciosa y vasta evidencia de un planeta ordenado? Intil responder que la realidad tambin est ordenada (1974: 442) [Ten years ago, any symmetrical system whatsoever which gave the appearance of order dialectical materialism, anti-Semitism, Nazism was enough to fascinate men. Why not fall under the spell of Tln and submit to the minute and vast evidence of an ordered planet? Useless to reply that reality, too is ordered] (1976: 34). No church whether Catholic or Protestant has ever been tolerant, nor is there any reason for them to be tolerant. If I believe I am in possession of the truth there is no reason for me to be tolerant of those who are risking their own salvation by holding erroneous beliefs. On the contrary, its my duty to persecute them (Burgin 1998: 734).

18

Fantastic or real? Borges reading of Dante and Swedenborg

67

are common to exegetic commentaries on the Comedy; other areas are pertinent, so it would appear, only to Borges. Firstly, Borges identifies in almost every passage that he composed on Dante the essential motivation behind Dantes vast poetic cycle: the union not with the godhead but with Beatrice.
Retengamos un hecho incontrovertible, un solo hecho humildsimo: la escena ha sido imaginada por Dante. Para nosotros, es muy real; para l, lo fue menos. (La realidad, para l, era que primero la vida y despus la muerte le haban arrebatado a Beatriz). Ausente para siempre de Beatriz, solo y quiz humillado, imagin la escena para imaginar que estaba con ella. Desdichadamente para l, felizmente para los siglos que lo leeran, la conciencia de que el encuentro era imaginario deform la visin. De ah las circunstancias atroces, tanto ms infernales, claro est, por ocurrir en el empreo la desaparicin de Beatriz, el anciano que toma su lugar, su brusca elevacin a la Rosa, la fugacidad de la sonrisa y de la mirada, el desvo eterno del rostro. En las palabras se trasluce el horror: come parea se refiere a lontana pero contamina a sorrise y as Longfellow pudo traducir en su versin de 1867: Thus I implored; and she, so far away, Smiled as it seemed, and looked once more at me Tambin eterna parece contaminar a si torn. (1989: 374) [We must keep one incontrovertible fact in mind, a single, humble fact: the scene was imagined by Dante. For us, it is very real; for him, it was less so. (The reality, for him, was that first life and then death had taken Beatrice from him.) Forever absent from Beatrice, alone and perhaps humiliated, he imagined the scene in order to imagine he was with her. Unhappily for him, happily for the centuries that would read him, his consciousness that the meeting was imaginary distorted the vision. Hence the appalling circumstances, all the more infernal for taking place in the empyrean: the disappearance of Beatrice, the elder who replaces her, her abrupt elevation to the Rose, the fleetingness of her glance and smile, the eternal turning away of the face. The horror shows through in the words: come parea refers to lontana but contaminates sorrise, and therefore Longfellow could translate, in his 1867 version: Thus I implored; and she, so far away, Smiled as it seemed, and looked once more at me And eternal seems to contaminate si torn.] (2000: 3045)19

19

Enamorarse es crear una religin cuyo dios es falible. Que Dante profes por Beatriz una adoracin idoltrica es una verdad que no cabe contradecir; que ella una vez se burl de l y otra lo desair son hechos que registra la Vita nuova. Hay quien mantiene que esos hechos son imgenes de otros; ello, a ser as, reforzara an ms nuestra

68

Chapter One

This immediately evokes a pathetic quality to the cycle that betrays Dantes earthly, human love over the love of the divine. Secondly, this aspect cannot be separated from the equally pathetic envy and regret that Borges identifies in Dantes portrayal of the lovers Paola and Francesco:
Infinitamente existi Beatriz para Dante; Dante, muy poco, tal vez nada, para Beatriz; todos nosotros propendemos, por piedad, por veneracin a olvidar esa lastimosa

certidumbre de un amor desdichado y supersticioso. Dante, muerta Beatriz, perdida para siempre Beatriz, jug con la ficcin de encontrarla, para mitigar su tristeza; yo tengo para m que edific la triple arquitectura de su poema para intercalar ese encuentro. Le ocurri entonces lo que suele ocurrir en los sueos, manchndolo de tristes estorbos. Tal fue el caso de Dante. Negado para siempre por Beatriz, so con Beatriz, pero la so seversima, pero la so inaccesible, pero la so en un carro tirado por un len que era un pjaro y que era todo pjaro o todo len cuando los ojos de Beatriz lo esperaban (Purgatorio XXXI, 121). Tales hechos pueden prefigurar una pesadilla; sta se fija y se dilata en el otro canto. Beatriz desaparece; un guila, una zorra y un dragn atacan el carro; las ruedas y el timn se cubren de plumas; el carro, entonces, echa siete cabezas (Transformato cosl dificio santo/mise fuor teste); un gigante y una ramera usurpan el lugar de Beatriz. (1989: 371) [To fall in love is to create a religion with a fallible god. That Dante professed an idolatrous adoration for Beatrice is a truth that cannot be contradicted; that she once mocked and on another occasion snubbed him are facts registered in the Vita nuova. Some would maintain that these facts are the images of others; if so, this would further reinforce our certainty of an unhappy and superstitious love. With Beatrice dead, lost forever, Dante, to assuage his sorrow, played with the fiction of meeting her again. It is my belief that he constructed the triple architecture of his poem in order to insert this encounter into it. What then happened is what often happens in dreams: they are stained by sad obstructions. Such was Dantes case. Forever denied Beatrice, he dreamed of Beatrice, but dreamed her as terribly severe, dreamed her as inaccessible, dreamed her in a chariot pulled by a lion that was a bird and that was all bird or all lion while Beatrices eyes were awaiting him (Purgatorio XXXI, 121). Such images can prefigure a nightmare; and it is a nightmare that begins here and will expand in the next canto. Beatrice disappears; an eagle, a she-fox, and a dragon attack the chariot, and its wheels and body grow feathers: the chariot then sprouts seven heads (Transformato cosl dificio santo/mise fuor teste {Thus transformed, the holy structure put forth heads upon its parts}); a giant and a harlot usurp Beatrices place] (2000a: 3001).

Fantastic or real? Borges reading of Dante and Swedenborg

69

discordia inolvidable para Dante. Leo y releo los azares de su ilusorio encuentro y pienso en dos amantes que el Alighieri so en el huracn del segundo crculo y que son emblemas oscuros, aunque l no lo entendiera o no lo quisiera, de esa dicha que no logr. Pienso en Francesca y en Paolo, unidos para siempre en su Infierno (Questi, che mai da me non fia diviso) Con espantoso amor, con ansiedad, con admiracin, con envidia. (1989: 371). [Beatrice existed infinitely for Dante. Dante very little, perhaps not at all for Beatrice. All of us tend to forget, out of pity, out of veneration, this grievous discord which for Dante was unforgettable. Reading and rereading the vicissitudes of his illusory meeting, I think of the two lovers that Alighieri dreamed in the hurricane of the second circle and who, whether or not he understood or wanted them to be, were obscure emblems of the joy he did not attain. I think of Paolo and Francesca, forever united in their Inferno: questi, che mai da me non fia diviso (this one, who never shall be parted from me). With appalling love, with anxiety, with admiration, with envy.] (2000: 3001)20

Thirdly, Borges writes with passion of the abiding love and respect that Dante bore for Virgil, and for Homer, Horace, Ovid and Lucan, and the deep sadness and regret that Dante experienced in acknowledging their banishment to the nobile castello.
Dante knows that Virgil is a damned soul, and the very moment that Virgil tells him that he will not be able to accompany him beyond purgatory, Dante feels that Virgil will always be an inhabitant of that nobile castello where the great shadows of the great men of antiquity dwell, those that through unavoidable ignorance did not accept or could not reach the word of Christ. [] Dante salutes him with the highest epithets and speaks of the great love and the long study to which Virgils writings

20 He also reiterates this in Siete noches: esos dos rprobos estn juntos, no pueden hablarse, giran en el negro remolino sin ninguna esperanza, ni siquiera nos dice Dante la esperanza de que los sufrimientos cesen, pero estn juntos. Cuando ella habla, usa el nosotros: habla por los dos, otra forma de estar juntos. Estn juntos para la eternidad, comparten el Infierno y eso para Dante tiene que haber sido una suerte de Paraso (1989: 216) [They cannot speak to each other, they turn in the black whirlwind without hope, yet they are together. When she speaks, she says we, speaking for the two of them, another form of being together. They are together for eternity; they share Hell and that, for Dante, must have been a kind of Paradise] (1984: 18).

70

Chapter One
have led him, and of their relationship which has always been constant. But Virgil is sad since he knows that he is condemned to the nobile castello, far from salvation and full of Gods absence; Dante, on the other hand, will see God, he will be allowed to, and he will also be allowed to understand the universe. (Alifano 1984: 97)21

Fourthly, in composing the cycle, and thus acting as judge in condemning Virgil to the absence of God, Dante, in Borges eyes, was deeply unsettled at his own god-like status.

21

En el caso de Dante, el procedimiento es ms delicado. No es exactamente un contraste, aunque tenemos la actitud filial: Dante viene a ser un hijo de Virgilio y al mismo tiempo es superior a Virgilio porque se cree salvado. Cree que merecer la gracia o que la ha merecido, ya que le ha sido dada la visin. En cambio, desde el comienzo del Infierno sabe que Virgilio es un alma perdida, un rprobo; cuando Virgilio le dice que no podr acompaarlo ms all del Purgatorio, siente que el latino ser para siempre un habitante del terrible nobile castello donde estn las grandes sombras de los grandes muertos de la Antigedad, los que por ignorancia invencible no alcanzaron la palabra de Cristo. En ese mismo momento, Dante dice: Tu, duca; tu, signore; tu, maestro Para cubrir ese momento, Dante lo saluda con palabras magnficas y habla del largo estudio y del gran amor que le han hecho buscar su volumen y siempre se mantiene esa relacin entre los dos. Esa figura esencialmente triste de Virgilio, que se sabe condenado a habitar para siempre en el nobile castello lleno de la ausencia de Dios En cambio, a Dante le ser permitido ver a Dios, le ser permitido comprender el universo (1989: 213). [In the case of Dante, the matter is more delicate. It is not exactly a contrast, although there is a filial relationship. Dante comes to be the son of Virgil, yet at the same time he is superior to Virgil for he believes he will be saved, since he has been given the vision. But he knows, from the beginning, that Virgil is a lost soul, a reprobate. When Virgil tells him that he cannot accompany him beyond Purgatory, he knows that the Latin poet will always inhabit the terrible nobile castello with the great shades of Antiquity, those who never heard the word of Christ. At that moment, Dante hails him with magnificent words: Tu, duca; tu, signore; tu, maestro He speaks of the great labor and of the great love with which his work has been studied, and this relation is always maintained between the two. But Virgil is essentially a sad figure who knows he is forever condemned to that castle filled with the absence of God. Dante, however, will be permitted to see God; he will be permitted to understand the universe] (1984: 14).

Fantastic or real? Borges reading of Dante and Swedenborg

71

Otra razn, de tipo tcnico, explica la dureza y la crueldad de que Dante ha sido acusado. La nocin pantesta de un Dios que tambin es el universo, de un Dios que es cada una de sus criaturas y el destino de esas criaturas, es quiz una hereja y un error si la aplicamos a la realidad, pero es indiscutible en su aplicacin al poeta y a su obra. El poeta es cada uno de los hombres de su mundo ficticio, es cada soplo y cada pormenor. Una de sus tareas, no la ms fcil, es ocultar o disimular esa omnipresencia. El problema era singularmente arduo en el caso de Dante, obligado por el carcter de su poema a adjudicar la gloria o la perdicin, sin que pudieran advertir los lectores que la Justicia que emita los fallos era, en ltimo trmino, l mismo. Para conseguir ese fin, se incluy como personaje de la Comedia, e hizo que sus reacciones no coincidieran, o slo coincidieran alguna vez en el caso de Filippo Argenti, o en el de Judas, con las decisiones divinas. (1989: 346) [There is a technical explanation for the hardheartedness and cruelty of which Dante has been accused. The pantheistic idea of a god who is also the universe, a god who is every one of his creatures and the destiny of those creatures, may be a heresy and an error if we apply it to reality, but it is indisputable when applied to the poet and his work. The poet is each one of the men in his fictive world, he is every breath and every detail. One of his tasks, and not the easiest of them, is to hide or disguise this omnipresence. The problem was particularly burdensome in Dantes case, for he was forced by the nature of his poem to mete out glory or damnation, but in such a way as to keep his readers from noticing that the Justice handing down these sentences was, in the final analysis, he himself. To achieve this, he included himself as a character in the Commedia, and made his own reactions contrast or only rarely coincide in the case of Filippo Argenti, or in that of Judas with the divine decisions.] (2000: 270)

Lastly, Borges acknowledges with great respect that Dante himself was torn between the need (and desire) to adhere to orthodoxy, and the desire to operate with poetic, aesthetic and, indeed, metaphysical freedom. In almost all the nine Dantesque essays, and in Siete noches, Borges describes the tension apparent in Dante between adhering to doctrine and expressing his own artistic vision. He talks of Dantes own invention of the limbo for the pre-Christian elevated souls (the Classical poets):
Para mitigar el horror de una poca adversa, el poeta busc refugio en la gran memoria romana. Quiso honrarla en su libro, pero no pudo entender la observacin pertenece a Guido Vitali que insistir demasiado sobre el mundo clsico no convena a sus propsitos doctrinales. Dante no poda, contra la Fe, salvar a sus hroes; los pens en un Infierno negativo, privados de la vista y posesin de Dios en el cielo, y

72

Chapter One
se apiad de su misterioso destino. [] En la invencin y ejecucin de este canto IV Dante urdi una serie de circunstancias, alguna de ndole teolgica. Devoto lector de la Eneida, imagin a los muertos en el Elseo, o en una variacin medieval de esos campos dichosos. [] Urgido por razones dogmticas, debi situar en el Infierno a su noble castillo. (1989: 348) [To allay the horror of an adverse era, the poet sought refuge in the great memory of Rome. He wished to honor it in his book, but could not help understanding the observation is Guido Vitalis that too great an insistence on the classical world did not accord well with his doctrinal aims. Dante, who could not go against the Faith to save his heroes, envisioned them in a negative Hell, denied the sight and possession of God in heaven, and took pity on their mysterious fate. [] In the invention and execution of Canto IV, Dante plotted out a series of circumstances, some of them theological in nature. A devout reader of the Aeneid, he imagined the dead in the Elysium or in a medieval variant of those glad fields. [] For pressing reasons of dogma, Dante had to situate his noble castle in Hell.] (2000: 274 italics mine)

These central arguments of Borges appreciation of Dante reveal a similar element of disdain for the doctrinal that we see manifest in his dismissal of the visions of St John of the Cross and of the eschatology of Weatherhead. Beyond the beauty of the couplets, Borges aesthetic appreciation of Dante lay, precisely, in this tension between doctrine and originality. We can see, therefore, that whilst originality is a quality rarely prized elsewhere in Borges, viz his inclusion of other authors tales in his tales, his recognition that the Las ruinas circulares is a rewriting of El Golem, his admission in the prologue to El informe de Brodie [Dr Brodies Report] that unos pocos argumentos me han hostigado a lo largo del tiempo; soy decididamente montono (1974: 1022) [A mere handful of arguments have haunted me all these years; I am decidedly monotonous] (2006: 20), and his assertion that all great literature is merely the repetition of certain perennial symbols within shifting cultural contexts; nevertheless, in matters of metaphysics and mysticism, originality is a treasured value due to its resistance to doctrine and dogma.

Fantastic or real? Borges reading of Dante and Swedenborg

73

Conclusion
The presence of Dante in Borges has been widely acknowledged. The presence of Swedenborg has not. It is striking, however, to notice the depth of influence of Swedenborgs thought upon Borges. This influence is visible not least the inclusion of extracts of Swedenborgs texts in Historia Universal de la Infamia and in El libro de los seres imaginarios, but through the adumbration of Swedenborgs visions in so many of Borges tales, and the manifest affinity to Swedenborg. This forms the basis of Chapter Five. Similarly, such considerations must be accompanied with an assessment of Borges own considerations of the landscape of death. Whilst again here is not the space to elaborate, it is worth explaining that throughout his work, in many facets of his writing, Borges appears pulled by two polarities: the inevitability of oblivion or annihilation and the possibility of continuity. In countless interviews, especially in his later years, he expresses a firm wish for annihilation:
I look forward to being blotted out. But if I thought that my death was a mere illusion, that after death I would go on, then I would feel very, very unhappy. For really, Im sick and tired of myself. Now, of course if I go on and I have no personal memory of having ever been Borges, then in that case, it wont matter to me; because I may have been hundreds of odd people before I was born, but those things wont worry me, since I will have forgotten them. When I think of mortality, of death, I think of those things in a hopeful way, in an expectant way. I should say I am greedy for death, that I want to stop waking up every morning, finding: Well, here I am, I have to go back to Borges. (Barnstone 1982: 17)

His reading, however, of Plato and other philosophers reveals a curiosity about the souls persistence after corporeal death, and even the transmigration of souls. The Borges-protagonist of Delia Elena San Marco, for example, lamenting Delias loss, declares: Anoche no sal despus de comer y rele, para comprender estas cosas, la ltima enseanza que Platn pone en boca de su maestro. Le que el alma puede huir cuando muere la carne (1974: 790) [Last night I stayed in after dinner and reread, in order to understand these things, the last teaching Plato put in his masters mouth. I read that

74

Chapter One

the soul may escape when the flesh dies] (1970: 32). There are many tales and poems that demonstrate this tension between olvido [oblivion] and afterlife, expressed most succinctly in a brief comment in interview:
In spite of oneself, one thinks. I am almost sure to be blotted out by death, but sometimes I think it is not impossible that I may continue to live in some other manner after my physical death. I feel every suicide has that doubt: Is what I am going to do worthwhile? Will I be blotted out, or will I continue to live on another world? Or as Hamlet wonders, what dreams will come when we leave this body? It could be a nightmare. And then we would be in hell. Christians believe that one continues after death to be who he has been and that he is punished or rewarded forever, according to what he has done in this brief time that was given to him. I would prefer to continue living after death if I have but to forget the life I lived. (Burgin 1998: 240)

The question of faith here arises. Borges position as agnostic is of crucial concern for us, and it is important to note that for Borges agnosticism was not apathy to spiritual matters; on the contrary, it leads to a greater opening to the numinous.22 Faith, in Borges worldview, is an indication of belief in matters about which we have no knowledge, and thus betrays a limitation of ones imagination. It would seem restrictive, he maintains, to limit oneself to a particular doctrine of life after death unless, as in the case of Swedenborg, one has visited such a realm. His statement that I have never been worthy of such an experience is the acknowledgment that in matters metaphysical, he must rely on his reading and his imagination. In both cases, though, no firm conviction can be reached.
There are many speculations about life after death. Swedenborg describes in detail hells and paradises. Dantes poem is also about hell, purgatory, paradise. Where does this tendency of man come from, to try to imagine and describe something that he cannot possibly know? (Burgin 1998: 247)

22 Being an agnostic means all things are possible, even God, even the Holy Trinity. This world is so strange that anything may happen, or may not happen. Being an agnostic makes me live in a larger, a more fantastic kind of world, almost uncanny. It makes me more tolerant (Shenker 1971).

Fantastic or real? Borges reading of Dante and Swedenborg

75

In the absence of empirical, experiential evidence, how can we judge Borges criteria for appraising authenticity to such metaphysical matters of heaven or eschatology? Logic, for example, cannot be employed in such matters. An example of this is that Borges, as mentioned, quotes Flaubert and Claudel in suggesting that Dante would be horrified to see, when dying, that the Otherworld has no resemblance to his poetic vision. Borges also quotes Swedenborg in stating that the dead project a vision oftheir bidding around them. According to this logic, Dante would justifiably have been able, upon death, to be surrounded by the landscape of his poetic cycle, in the presence of Virgil. Logic is an inappropriate system in such matters. James Lawrence, editor of Testimony to the Invisible, seizes this question of credibility, and suggests that for Borges the criteria for judging authenticity lie within a certain aesthetic integrity. So convinced is Lawrence that Borges is convinced by Swedenborg, he goes so far as to claim Borges as one of their own a Swedenborgian:
Borges professes his profound admiration of Swedenborgs mode of knowing in this essay, and one quickly discerns that he also feels a kindred spirit to the Swedish mystic. Borges declares that he himself is not a mystic, but that mysticism is an important and fascinating subject for him. When the epistemology of the knower is of solid pedigree, he believed, then the ensuing perceptions are the most sublime humanity has known. Borges felt that he shared with Swedenborg the same fundamental objectives; they simply traversed the same terrain in somewhat different ways. [] Borges believed in Swedenborgs spiritual journeys more profoundly than many artists and poets who have expressed perhaps some admiration or inspiration but who have not been so deeply inclined to explore the same realities with as much conviction and daring as Borges. It is in this sense that Borges is most deeply Swedenborgian. (Lawrence 1995: xxi)23

23

Swedenborgian need not mean being a member of any Swedenborgian church. Eugene Taylor, a scholar of Swedenborg and his influence on Emerson and his companions, writes: Swedenborgianism [] refers to a Christian denomination that follows the biblical interpretation of Emanuel Swedenborg, an eighteenth-century scientist and interpreter of religious experience. It can also refer more generally to avid readers of Swedenborgs works, such as the New England transcendentalists, who were not members of the religious movement, but who used Swedenborgs ideas to corroborate their own interior journey toward self-realization (1997: xvii).

76

Chapter One

This is a powerful assessment of Borges, and whilst readers familiar with Borges would smirk at Lawrences navet in assuming that Borges was a believer in a particular theological tradition (albeit heterodox), such a reading is nevertheless fully borne out both in the language ofBorges and, as mentioned, in the strong presence of Swedenborg in Borges. So what is the nature of this belief ? Clearly, as this chapter has elucidated, there is a paradoxical question at the heart of Borges reading of mystics. Reality and artifice are indistinguishable. The text and the meta-text are both text. Hamlet is as real as Bioy Casares. This, as established, is an abiding element of Borges. Upon this basis, therefore, an invented text of heaven is as real as a genuinely experienced text of heaven. And upon this basis, despite Borges acknowledgment that the mystical passage in The Aleph was an imitation of mystical texts, it is nonetheless a mystical text.24 If we follow the Borges who maintains that the London of Chesterton or Dickens is as real as the real London and that there is no dif ference between fact and fiction (Barnstone 1982: 117), then the Aleph, the Spaniards, Dante
24 Borges explains the artifice, or the invention, of this passage: A man in Spain asked me whether the aleph actually existed. Of course it doesnt. He thought the whole thing was true. I gave him the name of the street and the number of the house. He was taken in very easily. [] That piece gave me great trouble, yes. I mean, I had to give a sensation of endless things in a single paragraph. Somehow, I got away with it. Q: Is that an invention, the aleph, or did you find it in some reference? No. Ill tell you, I was reading about time and eternity. Now eternity is supposed to be timeless. I mean, God or a mystic perceives in one moment all of our yesterdays, Shakespeare says, all the past, all the present, all the future. And I said, why not apply that, well, that invention to another category, not to time, but to space? Why not imagine a point in space wherein the observer may find all the rest. I mean, who invented space? And that was the central idea. Then I had to invent all the other things, to make it into a funny story, to make it into a pathetic story, that came afterwards. My first aim was this: in the same way that many mystics have talked of eternity thats a big word, an eternity, an everness. And also neverness; thats an awful word. Since we have an idea of eternity, of foreverness in time, why not apply the same idea to space, and think of a single point in space wherein the whole of space may be found? I began with that abstract idea, and then, somehow, I came to that quite enjoyable story. (Burgin 1998: 212)

Fantastic or real? Borges reading of Dante and Swedenborg

77

and Weatherhead are all as authentic as Swedenborg. But if we follow the Borges who maintains that John of the Cross is simply parodying the Song of Songs, and Fray Luis de Len is simply doctrinally-inspired, then we have a separate order of hermeneutics, and, despite its numinous glow, the Aleph is simply an imitation and is consequently inauthentic. The judgment, as Lawrence suggests, lies in the solid pedigree of the epistemology of the author and the text, not in the experience qua experience.25 To complete the circle of this argument, therefore, we can maintain that the appreciation of mimesis of a real description of experience unbiased by artifice, is in essence an aesthetic judgment. Borges as reader of mystics does not require empirical proof of their experiences; what he requires is persuasion that the vision is genuine. If Swedenborg is convincing, it is because, for Borges, the texts are suitably persuasive, precisely through their lack of rhetorical features, artifice and doctrine. Ultimately it is a question of style. Borges sums this up succinctly in his description of the mimetic style of his friend and mystic Xul Solar: I once asked Xul how he defined his own painting, and he told me that he considered himself a Realist painter, since the things he painted were what he saw in his visions (Alifano 1984: 120). Thus the riddle unfolds. Realism, for Borges, is a fiction, and yet realism, for Borges, is fully operational in the peculiar and perplexing theory of mimesis of the imagination. Swedenborg, for Borges, is a Realist of the Fantastic.

25

A colleague of mine made this clear to me, stating that reading the paragraph in The Aleph in which the narrator attempts to vocalize the vision of the Aleph affected her in a profound and spiritual manner.

Chapter Two

Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter?

The range of mystical experience is very wide, much too wide for us to cover in the time at our disposal. William James, Varieties of Religious Experience Knowledge of God, the realization of ones union with God, in a word, mysticism, is necessary. Alan Watts, Behold the Spirit

Borges repeatedly denied being a mystic:


Many people have thought of me as a thinker, as a philosopher, or even as a mystic. [] People think that Ive committed myself to idealism, to solipsism, or to doctrines of the cabala, because Ive used them in my tales. But really I was only trying to see what could be done with them. (Burgin 1998: 79)

At the same time, he recognized that he experienced two mystical states in his life:
In my life I only had two mystical experiences and I cant tell them because what happened is not to be put in words, since words, after all, stand for a shared experience. And if you have not had the experience you cant share it as if you were to talk about the taste of coffee and had never tried coffee. Twice in my life I had a feeling, a feeling rather agreeable than otherwise. It was astonishing, astounding. I was overwhelmed, taken aback. I had the feeling of living not in time but outside time. It may have been a minute or so, it may have been longer. [] Somehow the feeling came over me that I was living beyond time, and I did my best to capture it, but it came and went. I wrote poems about it, but they are normal poems and do not tell the experience. I cannot tell it to you, since I cannot retell it to myself, but I had that experience, and I had it twice over, and maybe it will be granted me to have it one more time before I die. (Barnstone 1982: 1011)

80

Chapter Two

An important distinction is made here that we will explore in this chapter and the next: a mystic is not necessarily someone who has mystical experiences. Borges, of course, did do his best to capture the experience, describing it in a passage which he labelled sentirse en muerte [feeling in death] in El idioma de los argentinos (1928), in Historia de la eternidad (1936) and in Nueva refutacin del tiempo (1952), and referring to it in many interviews. When discussing his two timeless moments, he even compared himself to his mystic friend: My friend, a mystic, abounds in ecstasies. I dont. Ive had only two experiences of timeless time in eighty years (Barnstone 1982: 73). It is highly likely, given his other discussions, that he is referring to Xul Solar in this comment. Estela Canto recalled the mystical spirit of Borges, whom she did not consider a mystic even though she saw in him a tendency towards becoming one: Cuando se public El Aleph, yo lo coment en una revista (Sur). All me refera yo a un estado de nimo mstico; a l le gust el comentario. El agnstico Borges no era un mstico, por supuesto, pero s una persona capaz de momentos msticos (1999: 13) [When The Aleph was published, I wrote about it in the literary journal Sur, referring to a state of mystical rapture. He liked my comment. The agnostic Borges was no mystic, clearly, but he was someone capable of mystical moments] (my translation). It is significant for this study that Canto declares assertively that an agnostic, por supuesto, could not be a mystic; the implications being that some adherence to religious orthodoxy is a pre-requisite. This, as will be explored, is a problematic assertion. Canto further explains that Borges, many years later, congratulated her on her acuity in the article:
Muchos aos ms tarde, un periodista me pregunt de repente: Qu es El Aleph? y yo contest: Es el relato de una experiencia mstica. Cuando mencion esto a Georgie, me encontr con que l no haba olvidado mi artculo, escrito treinta y cinco aos antes. Me dijo: Has sido la nica persona que ha dicho eso, dando a entender que poda haber cierta verdad en la cosa. Le gustaba esta apreciacin, que se opona a la difundida idea entre los escritores argentinos, que lo juzgaban un autor fro y geomtrico, un creador de juegos puramente intelectuales. (1999: 14) [Many years later, a journalist suddenly asked me, What is the Aleph? and I replied, it is the tale of a mystical experience. When I mentioned this to Georgie, I realized that he hadnt forgotten my article, written thirty-five years earlier. He said to me,

Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter?

81

you have been the only person to say this, implying that I had been right in my suggestion. He liked my appreciation, which was contrary to the idea circulated around Argentine writers, which depicted Borges as a cold and geometric author, a creator of purely intellectual games.] (My translation)

Importantly, according to Canto, Borges was dismayed that his fellow Argentines ignored the mystic rapture of his tales in favour of intellectual game-playing. This is a valid perspective; the Borges-narrator of El Aleph does, after all, ridicule the mystical illumination it grants by highlighting the overwrought poetry of the Alephs custodian, Daneri; and by dismissing the Aleph as falso. Canto further explores this mystical/non-mystical aspect of Borges, suggesting that whilst not a mystic, he nevertheless strove to achieve the state of enlightenment commonly attributed to mystics:
Los msticos hablan de la noche oscura del alma. Quin puede distinguir entre la oscuridad y el alma?, se pregunta Yeats, un poeta muy admirado por Borges. Y ms all de esa noche estn los xtasis de la liberacin. A su manera tenue, pero empecinada, l luchaba por alcanzar esa liberacin. Los msticos suelen ser tcitos, a veces escriben, rara vez hablan. (1999: 14) [Mystics speak of the dark night of the soul. Who can distinguish darkness from the soul? asks Yeats, a poet whom Borges admired. Beyond the dark night are the ecstasies of liberation. In his own tenuous yet tenacious way, Borges strove to achieve that liberation. Mystics are often taciturn, they sometimes write but they rarely speak.] (My translation)

With further reference to El Aleph, Canto then appears to contradict herself by saying that Borges was a mystic, albeit an unsuspecting one: La diferencia est en que Borges era un mstico sin quererlo. Los msticos buscan el xtasis y a veces lo alcanzan tras sacrificios, ascesis, renuncias. Borges no renunciaba a nada: el elemento mstico estaba en l, funcionaba sin que l lo quisiera, tal vez sin que lo sospechara (1999: 211). [The difference is that Borges was a mystic without wishing to be so. Mystics seek ecstasy and at times they achieve it through sacrifice, aestheticism, renunciation. Borges renounced nothing: the mystical element was in him without him desiring it, perhaps without him even aware of it] (my translation). Canto, as we shall see, unwittingly enters the perennial debate within the scholarship of

82

Chapter Two

mysticism concerning bidden or unbidden states of mystical consciousness, the category of mysticism defined by William James as passive.1 Alicia Jurado cites Estela Canto (from what I assume was the same review to which Canto herself was referring), revealing that Canto went further than suggesting that Borges merely had the potential to be a mystic, but that he was one of the greatest mystical thinkers of our time:
Pocas personas han advertido las relaciones de Borges con el misticismo; una de ellas fue Estela Canto. Dijo, en una crtica sobre los cuentos de El Aleph, que llam relatos, ensayos y tambin leyendas: El universo, su contradiccin aparente, sus sentidos ocultos y la angustia del hombre frente a l, aparece de lleno en todos los cuentos de Borges. Una de las caractersticas de los pensadores msticos es su aficin a expresarse por smbolos. Yo dira que la mejor definicin de Borges es la de unos de los grandes y escassimos pensadores msticos de nuestra poca. Pensador mstico, desde luego; no mstico a secas. (1996: 98) [Few people have noticed Borges relationship with mysticism; one of them was Estela Canto. In a review of the tales in El Aleph, which she called tales, essays and also legends, she said: The universe, its apparent contradictions, its hidden meanings and mans anxieties faced with it, are the mainstay of all of Borges tales. One of the characteristics of mystical thinkers is their inclination to express themselves by means of symbols. I would say that the best definition of Borges is that he is one of the greatest and rarest mystical thinkers of our time. Mystical thinker, obviously, not just mystic.] (My translation)

It is revealing that Jurados desde luego echoes Cantos por supuesto, as in both cases their statements are grounded in the postulate that it is consensually recognized that Borges was no mystic. As we investigate in the following chapter, the distinction between mystic and mystical thinker is of prime importance in the scholarship of mysticism, with countless scholars, such James, Underhill and Jung denying their own mystical experiences yet manifestly appraising such experiences in their overall evaluation of mysticism.2

1 2

James use of passive as a definition of mysticism is problematic owing to his own use of nitrous oxide and ether to activate the mystical consciousness in himself. Kripal (2001) investigates the extent to which the mystical experiences of James and Underhill influenced their scholarship.

Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter?

83

I would argue that there is no consensus on the matter of whether Borges was or was not a mystic, as I hope to demonstrate in this chapter. J.M. Cohen, translator and friend of Borges, was likewise curious about the depiction of mystical experiences in Borges work, especially in the three tales: El Aleph, El Zahir and La escritura del dios. Similar to the discussion in the Introduction concerning Borges perplexing statements about employing mystical themes for purely aesthetic purposes, Cohen appears similarly suspicious of such simple assertions, arguing that Borges maintained a deep interest in such matters owing in part to his own mystical experiences:
It is true that he talked about the mystics, but as writers who recorded certain curious experiences, whose statements concerning time and timelessness, recurrence, cosmology had a great speculative interest for him, but nothing more. He did not admit to any personal concern with such things. Yet so many of Borges stories [] firmly contradict Borges defensive denial of personal involvement in this matter []. His references to Christianity or Buddhism, to Plato, Swedenborg, the Sufis, show a fascination with magic, and particularly with the magical moment, which is identified in his poetry with the moment of dj vu in which he first saw the pink painted street corner in the Buenos Aires suburb, and to other such moments in childhood or in his nocturnal walking in which things looked different; moments, one may say, in which time stopped, as it did for Hladk when he faced the firing squad. We may leave the subject of Borges personal involvement in this area with the remark that he shows an uncanny familiarity with the stages of the mystic search for one only speculatively interested in such matters. (1973: 789).

Cohen judiciously avoids labelling Borges a mystic, primarily in respect to Borges insistence that he had no religious or mystical inclination: My own attempts to open the subject in 1953 [with Borges] were brusquely repulsed (1973: 78). Consequently he entitles the chapter in which he analyses these matters The mystical experience, where the inverted commas imply a sense of parody or critical distance in the treatment of mysticism in Borges tales. Nevertheless it is significant that Cohen cannot accept Borges claims and argues coherently that, parody aside, the three tales in particular constitute powerfully mystical texts. Mara Kodama discusses mysticism in the introduction of her edited volume of Borges works On Mysticism (Borges 2010). Kodama, who

84

Chapter Two

through her employment of the terms passive and ineffable appears in her understanding of mysticism to be influenced by both Borges and William James, does an admirable job in making simple a strikingly complex area of thought, though in so doing she overlooks some of these complexities. For example, she cites St John of the Crosss description of the contemplative, spiritual path that can lead to the mystical state, yet fails to appreciate that Borges himself denied that St John of the Cross was a mystic (Barnstone 1982: 11). She concludes her overview of the essential characteristics of the mystical state by stating: Once we have determined these characteristics, we can see that they appear repeatedly in Borges poems and short stories (Borges 2010: viii). Again, this position is more complex than it may appear. The fact that mystical states are represented in poems and stories does not necessarily imply that the author experienced this particular state. And yet this assertion is problematic: as I argue in Chapter One, Borges constantly blurs the division between text and meta-text, and emphasizes the Blakean position that imagination is experiential. Consequently one can argue that the invention of a text describing a mystical state constitutes an experience of the mystical state. The text is the experience. Kodama appears to intuit this conundrum, suggesting that I believe that we could speak, in the case of Borges, of a mysticism of creation (viii), where, I suppose, she locates the mystical moment in the act of textual creation. Giskin (1990) considers Borges fictions in the light of the principles of mysticism as defined by William James: Ineffability, Noetic experience, Transiency, and Passivity. Giskins analysis has provided a fruitful avenue of enquiry in the Borges course at the University of Kent, and students find it a helpful guide for orientating themselves through the unnerving texts of El milagro secreto, Las ruinas circulares, La escritura del dios, and in particular, El Aleph. Giskin concludes that owing to the fact that certain texts of Borges embody the defining characteristics of mysticism as articulated by William James, Borges was consequently a mystic. This conclusion, however, leaves many questions unanswered: is a mystical text necessarily the work of a mystic? Can an author parody a mystical text, and if so, does that negate the mystical qualities of the text? What on earth is a mystical text? What on earth is a mystic? These questions are not mere frivolidad escolstica [scholastic frivolity] (a term Borges employs in

Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter?

85

Duracin del Infierno) nor specious hair-splitting, as the discussion of mysticism, as we shall see, raises questions that strike at the heart of our understanding of reality and challenge our ontological certainties. It seems, therefore, that whilst Giskin may be praised for his clarity in making the equation: The mystical experience in Borges includes four characteristics which are common to all epiphany, as cited by William James (Giskin 1990: 71) ergo Borges was a mystic, his analysis raises far more questions at levels of literary, phenomenological and ontological analysis than he had perhaps intended. Lastly, Wallace, writing in the New York Times, suggests that Borges was, indeed, a mystic, and he offers his own brief exposition of the meaning of such a term:
Borgess stories [] are designed primarily as metaphysical arguments; they are dense, self-enclosed, with their own deviant logics. Above all, they are meant to be impersonal, to transcend individual consciousness [] One reason for this is that Borges is a mystic, or at least a sort of radical Neoplatonist human thought, behavior and history are all the product of one big Mind, or are elements of an immense cabalistic Book that includes its own decoding. (2004)

There is an evident problem in all these assertions, as the authors avow that Borges was or was not a mystic based upon a rudimentary examination of what the word itself means, and without any exploration of the long and often contradictory nature of the scholarship of mysticism, which has for decades grappled precisely with the definition of this troublesome term. As such, Cantos analysis almost inevitably trips over itself as her position appears derived more from an ethical and perhaps emotive than an intellectual response to the question in the assumption that agnosticism and mysticism are contradictory enterprises. Kodama does venture away from the James/Borges position to include a Vedantic perspective, but still the reader is left with questions about the nature of experience-author-textreader. Wallace, meanwhile, makes one sweeping comment about one big Mind as the determining position, and concludes that Borges fits within this category. Giskin, perhaps the most thorough examiner of the mystical aspect of Borges, nevertheless bases his full analysis only on the four characteristics outlined by James, with no exploration either of the distinction

86

Chapter Two

between author, text and reader (that is to say, is the text mystical, or is it the readers response?), nor of the many other scholars of mysticism, such as Underhill, Zaehner, Stace, Watts or Staal, who often refuted James and whose salient characteristics are markedly different. It is doubtful, for example, that Borges scepticism, agnosticism and literary game-playing would qualify him as a mystic in Zaehners strictly theistic and theological approach to mysticism. Nez-Faraco (2006: 41) sums up the nature ofthe problem, indicating that if the term mystic applies to Borges, it becomes necessary to define the precise meaning of such a designation. Promising as this sounds, Nez-Faraco pursues this line no further, and so the reader is left in suspense as to how such a designation is, indeed, defined. It becomes clear that we cannot rely on any immediate consensual understanding of the term mystic in order to judge whether a certain individual was or was not a mystic. One can only arrive at such a conclusion by plotting the figure and his/her literary works against a checklist of defining characteristics as determined by a respected scholar such as James. This implies, however, not only an agreement with these characteristics as suitable definitions of mystic and mysticism, but, importantly, an accord over the meaning of the terms employed in these characteristics themselves. As such, when James suggests noetic as one such criterion, we must assume a consensual understanding of this term. This may sound pedantic, but it is alarming how often one encounters a declaration that a certain poetauthor-theologian was or was not a mystic because their experience was or was not unitive, extravertive or ineffable. These terms themselves are thorny. Surely the root of the ineffability of the mystical state might lie less with the experience than with the linguistic skills of the experiencer? As we examine in Chapter Four, for over a century readers of Emerson have battled over whether he was or was not a mystic through arguing, for example, that he may not have experienced God, but that he did experience Nature, and hence he was a nature mystic (Quinn 1950).3 Little, I would argue, is clarified in employing God or Nature as distinctive definitions

A new term, indeed, was coined for Emerson based on his particular religious yet anti-ecclesiastical spiritual philosophy: Yankee mystic (Hurth 2005: 336).

Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter?

87

of mysticism, as owing to their inherent arbitrariness they would themselves require further definition. Bertrand Russell (1961) pays particular attention to these semantic vagaries in his essay Mysticism, suggesting three definitions of mysticism,4 then enquiring exactly what is meant by, for example, his own definition that time is unreal. As is customary with Russells meticulous method, he takes nothing for granted either regarding mysticism or regarding the many proffered defining characteristics.

What is mysticism?
So how does one judge these textual accounts of mystical experiences against the scholarship? Which of the many classifications does one turn to in order to qualify or refute the mystical nature of a given author or text? The essential standpoint for many of the scholars that justifies this array of offerings is the inherent inexplicability of the mystical experience. From the early scholarship of the end of the nineteenth century through to the present, scholars have identified the initial problem of identifying what exactly it is that they are investigating. William Ralph Inge (known normally as Dean Inge), in his Christian Mysticism (1899) begins his investigation with the assertion that the word itself is semantically slippery:
No word in our language not even Socialism has been employed more loosely than Mysticism. Sometimes it is used as an equivalent for symbolism or allegorism, sometimes for theosophy or occult science; and sometimes it merely suggests the mental state of a dreamer, or vague and fantastic opinions about God and the world. In Roman Catholic writers, mystical phenomena mean supernatural suspensions of physical law. Even those writers who have made a special study of the subject, show by their definitions of the word how uncertain is its connotation. (1913: 3) 4 (1) that all division and separateness is unreal, and that the universe is a single indivisible unity; (2) that evil is illusory, and that the illusion arises through falsely regarding a part as self-subsistent; (3) that time is unreal, and that reality is eternal, not in the sense of being everlasting, but in the sense of being wholly outside time (Russell 1961: 179).

88

Chapter Two

However, many years later Inge revisited the designations, this time categorically expunging from his definitions those matters contrary to orthodoxy, such as supernatural, erotic, etc.
I cannot accept any definition which identifies mysticism with excited or hysterical emotionalism, with sublimated eroticism, with visions and revelations, with supernatural (dualistically opposed to natural) activities, nor, on the philosophical side, with irrationalism. I suggest that a generation which treats its experience of ghosts with respect ought not to be rude about the experience of God. I propose to divide my subject into three sections ontological, the doctrine of ultimate reality; epistemological, the doctrine of knowledge; and ethical, the chart by which the mystic finds his way up the hill of the Lord. (Inge 1947: 154)

William James, who cited Inge in Varieties of Religious Experience and who argued like Schopenhauer that the mystical experience is at the heart of all religious experience, maintained that both mysticism and religion are themselves impossible to define: Most books on the philosophy of religion try to begin with a precise definition of what its essence consists of. [] The very fact that they are so many and so dif ferent from one another is enough to prove that the word religion cannot stand for any single principle or essence, but is rather a collective name (1913: 26). Like Inges use of socialism James used as analogy the word government, suggesting that it signifies many different and at times conflicting things, yet its full meaning relies on a composite of all these disparate meanings. Importantly, and in tune with so much of Borges philosophical outlook, James acknowledged that in so many cases, an investigation into religion or mysticism is in essence an investigation into the language employed to describe these ideas: the question of definition tends to become a dispute about names (1913: 30). This linguistic variance, as we shall see later in this chapter when discussing the problem of textual hermeneutics of mystical texts, is of crucial importance. Frits Staal, in Exploring Mysticism (1975: 8), likewise identified the problem of names, arguing that The study of mysticism [has] tended to deteriorate into enumerations and classifications of a variety of narratives, without any attempt at a critical evaluation. Whilst I would argue that there is critical evaluation (as, curiously, does Staal himself in his book),

Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter?

89

Staal does identify the problem that I will discuss in the following chapter concerning the semantic circularity that can ensue in a debate about mysticism. It is defined according to other terms whose meaning then often needs defining. In some cases this chain of signifiers can lead back to the use of the word mysticism to define one of these sequential terms. Jaff (1989: 12) is, for example, admirably precise in suggesting that mysticism is the experience of the numinous, but in this matter one needs to define the term numinous, a similarly tricky exercise. Staal also identifies the many difficulties in studying mysticism; most notable among them is that it is not so simple (1975: 124). We call a mystic anyone who for a certain length of time has mystical experiences (125). That is fair enough, but what exactly is a mystical experience? More recently, David Wulff, in one of the chapters of Cardea, Lynn and Krippners James-inspired Varieties of Anomalous Experience (2000), has argued that: Falling by definition outside the realm of ordinary discourse, mystical experience eludes any precise description or characterization. Furthermore, as relatively recent constructions that serve diverse and even opposing purposes, the terms mystical and mysticism are themselves hard to pin down (2000: 397). This emphasis on meaning variance is important, as whilst Canto and Jurado assert that por supuesto Borges was no mystic, they offer little explanation as to why this assertion is so immediately obvious. Were they to have attempted to qualify the assertion with a more thorough investigation into the meaning of the term mystic, they would have encountered many choices of definitions, often contradictory. James suggested that the terms can have different values attached to them depending on the situation in which they are employed. Likewise, he explored the definitions of mysticism according to certain aspects of human experience that are not mysticism:
The words mysticism and mystical are often used as terms of mere reproach, to throw at any opinion which we regard as vague and vast and sentimental, and without a base in either facts or logic. For some writers a mystic is any person who believes in thought-transference, or spirit-return. Employed in this way the word has little value: there are too many less ambiguous synonyms. So, to keep it useful by restricting it, I will do what I did in the case of the word religion, and simply propose to you four

90

Chapter Two
marks which, when an experience has them, may justify us in calling it mystical for the purpose of the present lectures. In this way we shall save verbal disputation, and the recriminations that generally go therewith. (1913: 379)

Evelyn Underhill, whose influential work Mysticism challenged Jamess definitions in Varieties, likewise attempted to define mysticism initially by suggesting some aspects of human experience that are categorically not mysticism:
What then do we really mean by mysticism? A word which is impartially applied to the performances of mediums and the ecstasies of the saints, to menticulture and sorcery, dreamy poetry and mediaeval art, to prayer and palmistry, the doctrinal excesses of Gnosticism, and the tepid speculations of the Cambridge Platonists even, according to William James, to the higher branches of intoxication soon ceases to have any useful meaning. (1912: 86)

This method of defining mysticism according to that which it is not was pursued also by Walter Stace (1960: 1012) in his attempt to isolate the specifics of the term mystic from a catalogue of other terms popularly employed interchangeably with mystic:
Some Things Which Mysticism Is Not. The word mysticism is popularly used in a variety of loose and inaccurate ways. Sometimes anything is called mystical which is misty, foggy, vague, or sloppy. It is absurd that mysticism should be associated with what is misty because of the similar sound of the words. And there is nothing misty, foggy, vague, or sloppy about mysticism. A second absurd association is to suppose that mysticism is sort of mystery-mongering. There is, of course, an etymological connection between mysticism and mystery. But mysticism is not any sort of hocus-pocus such as we commonly associate with claims to be the elucidation of sensational mysteries. Mysticism is not the same as what is commonly called the occult whatever that may mean. Nor has it anything to do with spiritualism, or ghosts, or table-turning. Nor does it include what are commonly called parapsychological phenomena such as telepathy, telekinesis, clairvoyance, precognition. These are not mystical phenomena. It is perhaps true that mystics may sometimes claim to possess such special powers, but even when they do so they are well aware that such powers are not part of, and are to be clearly distinguished from, their mystical experience []. Finally, it is most important to realize that visions and voices are not mystical phenomena, though here again it seems to be the case that the sort of persons who are mystics may often be the sort of persons who see visions and hear

Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter?

91

voices []. What mystics say is that a genuine mystical experience is nonsensuous. It is formless, shapeless, colorless, odorless, soundless. But a vision is a piece of visual imagery having color and shape. A voice is an auditory image. Visions and voices are sensuous experiences.

The separation of mysticism from other anomalous experiences, therefore, is a mainstay in the scholarship. Yet mysticism can involve much more than a mere transient experience. Such other matters are themselves hard to define and evaluate, and the scholarship here is also large and varied. Whilst James, Underhill and Stace have listed such non-mystical aspects as thought-transference or spirit-return, sorcery, dreamy poetry and mediaeval art, prayer and palmistry visions and hearing voices, the chapter headings of Varieties of Anomalous Experience provide an indication of what, precisely, these matters are: Hallucinatory Experiences, Synaesthesia, Lucid Dreaming, Out-of-Body Experiences, Psi-related Experiences, Alien Abduction Experiences, Past-Life Experiences, Near-Death Experiences, and Anomalous Healing Experiences (viiviii). Importantly, Wulff s chapter, Mystical Experiences, demonstrates the kinship between mysticism and these other matters, principally because the non-ordinary activities occur to a mystic alongside the more definite mystical experiences. Indeed in many cases the category of mystic depends precisely upon these anomalous experiences. The case of Swedenborg is a pertinent example. Not one of the many biographies of Swedenborg, from Wilkinsons Emanuel Swedenborg: A Biography (1849), which informed Emerson, to Borges biographical essay Testigo de lo invisible (1995) which was informed by Emerson, to Gary Lachmans recent Swedenborg: An Introduction to His Life and Ideas (2012) fails to emphasize his dazzling psychic abilities. It may even be suggested that Swedenborgs enduring reputation lies not so much with his voluminous biblical exegesis, nor even with his accounts of heavens and hells, but with his well-documented psychic abilities. Conan Doyle, for example, dismisses in one paragraph the entire theological dimension of Swedenborgs works, and his tiresome exegesis of the Scriptures (2005: 97), and focuses exclusively on the psychic powers: Swedenborgs theology is neither simple nor intelligible, and that is its condemnation. [] Not in that direction does the worth of Swedenborg lie. That worth is

92

Chapter Two

really to be found in his psychic powers and in his psychic information which would have been just as valuable had no word oftheology ever come from his pen (978).5 Van Dusen, in his biographical analysis The Presence of Other Worlds (1974) includes a whole chapter on Swedenborgs minor miracles of clairvoyance and mediumship, in particular the location of the

In addition to being creator of Sherlock Holmes, Conan Doyle was a committed researcher into spiritualism and related anomalous matters. Whilst I can find in Borges no mention of Conan Doyles essay on Swedenborg, there are a couple of areas of great similarity with Borges essay Testigo that might indicate that Borges was familiar with the essay: They may say that the man was mad, but his life in the years which followed showed no sign of mental weakness. Or they might say that he lied. But he was a man who was famed for his punctilious veracity (Conan Doyle 2005: 99). Dos conjeturas: La deliberada impostura de quien ha escrito esas cosas extraas o el influjo de una demencia brusca o gradual. La primera es inadmisible. [] La hiptesis de la locura no es menos vana. [] Si se hubiera enloquecido, no deberamos a su pluma tenaz la ulterior redaccin de miles de metdicas pginas, que representan una labor de casi treinta aos y que nada tienen que ver con el frenes (Borges 2005: 155) [Two assumptions: deliberate imposture [] or the influence of sudden or progressive madness. The first is inadmissible. [] The hypothesis of madness is equally unfounded [] If he had gone mad, we would not owe to his tenacious pen the thousands of methodical pages he wrote during the following thirty years or so, pages that have nothing at all to do with frenzy (Borges 1995: 78)]. In spite of all his theological symbolism, his name must live eternally as the first of all modern men who has given a description of the process of death, and of the world beyond, which is not founded upon the vague ecstatic and impossible visions of the old Churches, but which actually corresponds with the descriptions which we ourselves obtain from those who endeavour to convey back to us some clear idea of their new existence (Conan Doyle 2005: 104). Swedenborg pudo renunciar a tales artificios retricos porque su tema no era el xtasis del alma arrebatada y enajenada, sino la puntual descripcin de regiones ultraterrenas, pero precisas (Borges 2005: 154). [Swedenborg was able to abstain from this kind of rhetorical artifice because his subject matter was not the ecstasy of a rapt and fainting soul but, rather, the accurate description of regions that, though ultra-terrestrial, were clearly defined] (Borges 1995: 7).

Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter?

93

lost receipt,6 the knowledge of the queens secret,7 and, most famously, his contemporaneous knowledge of the fire in Stockholm whilst he was dining in Gothenburg.8 Kant, it is to be assumed, would have paid little attention
6 In April or May 1761, a countess de Marteville came to Swedenborg. Her husband, ambassador extraordinary of the Netherlands, had died in Sweden. He had given her a valuable silver service before he died. Now the silversmith was demanding a payment she could not afford even though she was sure her husband had paid for it. The matter was urgent to the woman. She had heard Swedenborg could contact the souls of the departed. Would he contact her husband and ask of the receipt? Swedenborg said he would. Three days later he returned and said he had spoken with her husband. The receipt was in a bureau upstairs. The woman said she had already searched the bureau. The husband had told Swedenborg that a certain drawer was to be pulled out and a false back removed. The woman and her company went upstairs and found the receipt and other lost papers as directed. This incident was related by eleven different sources, most of whom agreed on the above account. When questioned on the matter Swedenborg also affirmed its occurrence (Van Dusen 1974: 142). Swedenborg met the queen [Louisa Ulrica of Sweden] [who] lightly asked if he had a message from her [dead] brother. Swedenborg answered yes and suggested that they speak alone, and he related what he had learned from the queens brother. The queen was variously described as in shock, disturbed, or so indisposed that she had to retire. She said later that Swedenborg had reported what no other living person knew (Van Dusen 1974: 143). On July 17, 1759, Swedenborg and fifteen others were guests of the prominent merchant William Castel in Gothenburg at his fine home on Canal Street. At six in the evening Swedenborg appeared quite pale and alarmed. When asked what was wrong, he described a fire burning at that moment in Stockholm, three hundred miles away. He paced in and out of the house evidently agitated by the fire. His detailed description and evident sincerity upset the guests, many of whom were from Stockholm. Swedenborg described exactly where the fire was burning, where it had started, and when, and was dismayed to see a friends house already in ashes. The next day, Sunday, the governor, having heard of the incident, asked to see Swedenborg and received a detailed report. The news spread through the city. Two days after the fire, messengers arrived and confirmed every detail as Swedenborg had reported it, including when and how it started, what it burned, and where and when it was contained. There were several separate reports of this incident that agreed on essentials. Even the German philosopher Immanuel Kant was impressed and sent his own agent to check the details (Van Dusen 1974: 141).

94

Chapter Two

to Swedenborgs extensive theology and his mystical explorations had he not become intrigued by these psychic occurrences. Van Dusen even suggests that Swedenborg himself was aware that without these demonstrated psychic abilities, his readership would remain limited. This statement implies that the acts of mediumship and clairvoyance were themselves miracles for the purpose of bringing his heavenly theology to public attention. Borges, as is clear from a reading of his many texts dealing with Swedenborg, was equally unconcerned with the theological works and treated the doctrine of correspondences with tepid reservation, but was fascinated particularly by Swedenborgs declared explorations of other worlds. This last attribute of Swedenborgs voyages to other dimensions is rarely one of the characteristics of mysticism in the scholarship, and would fit more within aspects of anomalous, parapsychological experiences. (In fact, claims of planetary voyages by non-astronauts would normally be considered delusions, and hence psychopathological. We recall that Conan Doyle and Borges insisted on Swedenborgs lucidity). Furthermore, as is to be expected in such a nebulous field as mysticism, terms merge with each other, despite the attempts to maintain strict divisions. As such Ottos exploration of the numinous, Suzukis satori, Jungs studies of religiosity and the numinous, Joseph Campbells transparent to the transcendent (2004), Wilber or Daniels transpersonal, Stanislav Grof s holotropic,9 Huxleys self-transcendence, Humphry Osmonds psychedelic, Terence McKennas shamanic, Borges timelessness, inevitably embody much that may be integrally related to the mystical.

The content of holotropic states of consciousness is often philosophical and mystical. In these episodes, we can experience sequences of psychospiritual death and rebirth or feelings of oneness with other people, nature, the universe, and God. We might uncover what seem to be memories from other incarnations, encounter powerful archetypal beings, communicate with discarnate entities, and visit numerous mythological domains (Grof 1998: 7).

Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter?

95

The varieties of taxonomies


The eccentric Chinese encyclopaedia entitled Emporio celestial de conocimientos benvolos [Celestial Empire of benevolent Knowledge] that Borges describes in El idioma analtico de John Wilkins and that so tickled Michel Foucault demonstrates the possible arbitrariness of systems of classification. Borges would have delighted in the colourful and at times contradictory taxonomies that have been proposed to define mysticism over the last century. Inge, in an appendix of Christian Mysticism, cites the definitions of mysticism of twenty-six separate poets and theologians, in a heterogeneous list that includes Goethe and Charles Kingsley. Striking to note that in the time of Inge, as with today (see Daniels 2003), the most notable feature of any compendium of definitions is the level of contradiction between one definition and another (to say nothing of the level of passion and invective). William James, the grandfather of the systematic appraisal of the mystical traditions, concluded his inclusive analysis with the well-known four marks which, when an experience has them, may justify us in calling it mystical [] ineffability, noetic quality, transiency, passivity ( James 1913: 380). Underhill (1911) dismissed Jamess categories, snidely rebuking him for daring to include intoxication as a pathway to mystical consciousness, and offered instead:
1. True mysticism is active and practical, not passive and theoretical. It is an organic life-process, a something which the whole self does; not something as to which its intellect holds an opinion. 2. Its aims are wholly transcendental and spiritual. It is in no way concerned with adding to, exploring, re-arranging, or improving anything in the visible universe. [] 3. This One is for the mystic, not merely the Reality of all that is, but also a living and personal Object of Love; never an object of exploration. [] 4. Living union with this One which is the term of his adventure is a definite state or form of enhanced life. It is obtained neither from an intellectual realization of its delights, nor from the most acute emotional longings. (1912: 96)

Underhills classifications were driven, she argued, by five fundamental stages in the development of the mystical individual:

96

Chapter Two
(1) The awakening of the Self to consciousness of Divine Reality. [] (2) Purgation [self-knowledge] [] (3) Illumination [] a certain apprehension of the Absolute, a sense of the Divine Presence: but not true union with it. It is a state of happiness. (4) [] the final and complete purification of the Self, which is called by some contemplatives the mystic pain or mystic death, by others the Purification of the Spirit or Dark Night of the Soul. [] This is the spiritual crucifixion so often described by the mystics: the great desolation in which the soul seems abandoned by the Divine. The Self now surrenders itself, its individuality, and its will, completely. It desires nothing, asks nothing, is utterly passive, and is thus prepared for (5) Union: the true goal of the mystic quest. In this state the Absolute Life is not merely perceived and enjoyed by the Self, as in Illumination: but is one with it. This is the end towards which all the previous oscillations of consciousness have tended. It is a state of equilibrium, of purely spiritual life; characterized by peaceful joy, by enhanced powers, by intense certitude. (1912: 2057)

Suzuki (1956), a close reader of Swedenborg and admirer of James, and the figure widely credited with introducing Zen spiritual practices into the West in the early twentieth century, likened the word Satori to the word mysticism, and thus arrived at his own salient eight characteristics: Irrationality, Intuitive Insight, Authoritativeness, Affirmation, Sense of the Beyond, Impersonal Tone, Feeling of Exaltation, Momentariness (1038). Stace (1961), arguing from a perennialist position i.e. that there is a commonality in the mystical experience across time and cultures divided the mystical experience into extrovertive and introvertive, whose characteristics in common are: 1. The Unifying Vision all things are One. 2. The more concrete apprehension of the One as an inner subjectivity, or life, in all things. 3. Sense of objectivity or reality. 4. Blessedness, peace, etc. 5. Feeling of the holy, sacred, or divine. 6. Paradoxicality 7. Alleged by mystics to be ineffable (1961: 1312). Zaehner (1961), drawing on a wider field than James or Underhill in including his knowledge of Buddhist and Hindu traditions, limited the field to three essential characteristics:
Nature mysticism, based on all-in-one or panenhenic experience, such as the experience of cosmic consciousness (Bucke, 1901/2001). For Zaehner, nature mysticism is essentially non-religious. 2. Monistic mysticism, based on the absorptive experience of ones own self or spirit as the Absolute (e.g., Advaita Vedanta). 3. Theistic mysticism, based on the experience of loving communion or union with a personal God. (Daniels 2003).

Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter?

97

Pahnke, drawing principally on Stace, added: 1) sense of unity, 2) transcendence of time and space, 3) sense of sacredness, 4) sense of objective reality, 5) deeply felt positive mood, 6) ineffability, 7) paradoxicality and 8) transiency (Doblin 1991: 7). In addition to the articulation of defining characteristics, it is characteristic of the scholars to allow their religious, moral, ethical or ideological assumptions to create a hierarchy of the mystical experience. In this sense, there are higher and lower forms of mysticism. Daniels, in his informative essay Making sense of mysticism highlights this particular abiding feature of the scholarship: I see no clear grounds for imputing here any moral, spiritual or developmental hierarchy. There is, in my opinion, no rational basis for assuming that god-focused (theistic) mysticism generally represents a higher (lower), better (worse), or more mature (immature) form than that represented in any of the other contexts (2003, no pagination). And yet, despite this levelling perspective, Daniels still does assume some variance of value based upon intensity or increasing involvement with the Real. Consequently, union is greater in mystical value than mere awareness of the numinous. From this point of view, it seems reasonable to argue, for example, that unitive mysticism is more advanced than numinous mysticism. Thus the spiritual marriage of St Teresa is a more sublime experience than that of the presence of the mysterium because the implied relationship with the Real is closer (2003). Daniels proceeds to construct an alarmingly elaborate model in order to locate every type of mystical experience in the literature, east and west, modern and ancient. Such a complex model may be of use in order to locate a particular mystic, as if pinning them to a grid in order to compare them with other mystics, but I cannot dispel the arbitrariness of Borges Chinese encyclopaedia when considering how such an elaborate model can serve to confuse and befuddle rather than clarify. Whilst this simple catalogue of the scholars classifications does not do justice to the depth and breadth of their research, it must nevertheless be recognized that the scholars themselves engineered their research precisely towards these robust, decisive and portable conclusions, and as such subsequent studies have for many years been fully justified in referring simply to Jamess four, or Staces seven defining points. In appraising this inconclusive list of classifications, therefore, the vision of Borges Chinese

98

Chapter Two

encyclopaedia is again evoked. Taxonomies and lists of definitions seek to order and classify the particular elements under scrutiny, and in this respect they may both be considered, in a manner that so appealed to Borges, maps of reality. However, these catalogues of definitions taken individually subvert the pretence to order through employing defining terms that themselves require further definition, such as objective or ineffable; whilst taken as a composite as Daniels (2003) and I have done the list becomes wild and unwieldy and characterized by contradiction.

Was Borges a mystic?


Therefore, I ask again, was Borges a mystic? Borges himself would answer brusquely of course not! Yet when we scrutinize the scholarship, we encounter many markers that would, indeed, qualify him for the term; and in order to address this question, one would need to position the reading of Borges texts including his autobiographical sketches in interviews alongside the many systems of classification. Underhills insistence upon the intuitive approach over and above the intellectual or the theoretical would fit only uneasily with an approach to mysticism concerning Borges, who, as we have seen, praised the intellectual capacity of Swedenborg and Blake above all other qualities. Williamson (2004: 444) records how Borges was keen to seek the guidance from Shinto monks while in Japan.10 His desire
10 During a visit to the Rioan-ji Temple, a centre of Zen Buddhism, he met a monk, Morinaga Yushoku, with whom he had the most searching conversation ofhis entire visit to Japan. As with the nun, Borges wished to learn something ofYushokus commitment to the contemplative life, but above all he wanted to know whether the monk had ever experienced a mystical enlightenment. Mara recalled that Borges kept pressing this point, and Yushoku replied that he had twice experienced nirvana but that it was impossible to convey such an experience to someone who had not himself found enlightenment. All the same, Borges described to the monk an experience he had undergone one night in the 1920s while roaming the outskirts of Buenos Aires,

Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter?

99

in particular was to correlate his own timeless moments with the pathways to enlightenment developed by the religious teachings of Japan. Borges refers to Suzuki in the essay El Budismo of Siete Noches as one of the leading scholars of Buddhism in his time, to be applauded furthermore for revitalizing Zen in his own native Japan. Consequently Suzukis equation of satori and mystical vision is perfectly in tune with Borges meditation on the close affinities between Oriental spiritual practices and western mystical traditions. Schopenhauer, whom Borges acclaimed as the most lucid and sound of all philosophers, argued that mysticism is the origin and also the culmination of all religion, but that, unlike Jamess suggestion of noetic value, no knowledge is to be derived from the ecstatic mystical state. Indeed, argued Schopenhauer in The World as Will and Representation (a book of which Borges was particularly fond), mysticism opposes philosophy and cannot constitute a pathway to consensual knowledge owing its inherently subjective rather than objective relationship with the individual.
[] we see all religions at their highest point end in mysticism and mysteries, that is to say, in darkness and veiled obscurity. These really indicate merely a blank spot for knowledge, the point where all knowledge necessarily ceases. Hence for thought this can be expressed only by negations, but for sense-perception it is indicated by symbolical signs, in temples by dim light and silence, in Brahmanism even by the required suspension of all thought and perception for the purpose of entering into the deepest communion with ones own self, by mentally uttering the mysterious Om. In the widest sense, mysticism is every guidance to the immediate awareness

when the sight of a particular moonlit street had induced a preternatural sense that time was an illusion [Sentirse en muerte (Feeling in Death)]. Might such an episode qualify as a mystical illumination? That was possible, came the reply, since an illumination could be prompted by any number of things, such as the ringing of a bell or the sound of water flowing over a stone, but true enlightenment would entail a complete transformation of the soul and would change everything in a mans life. The monk explained that one must dispel the illusion of selfhood in order to experience enlightenment: our sense of personal identity was the product of our conditioning, but otherwise there was nothing within us, not basis for the existence of the self, and so one must shed all notions of individuality and start again from zero before one could reach nirvana (Williamson 2004: 443).

100

Chapter Two
of that which is not reached by either perception or conception, or generally by any knowledge. The mystic is opposed to the philosopher by the fact that he begins from within, whereas the philosopher begins from without. The mystic starts from his inner, positive, individual experience, in which he finds himself as the eternal and only being, and so on. But nothing of this is communicable except the assertions that we have to accept on his word; consequently he is unable to convince. (Schopenhauer 1966: 610)

Borges, as we shall see, would appear to agree with this sentiment with regards his own mystical, timeless experiences, and one might argue that the repeated fictional representations of that state the Aleph and Tzinacns ecstasy were means of objectifying and thereby abstracting the ineffability of the experience. Consequently one might suggest that Borges was a mystic in the Schopenhauerian sense. However, Schopenhauer emphasizes the blank spot for knowledge, which would entail a contrary position to Jamess noetic value. We will explore in the following chapter the degree to which Borges assumed that knowledge may or may not be derived from the mystical experience. Schopenhauer, although rarely cited in the scholarship of mysticism, nevertheless identified a binary division that pervades all approaches to mysticism, what Daniels (2003) labels Essentialism versus Constructivism. This particular division, as we will also see in Chapter Three, is integral to Borges understanding both of the mystical texts that he read, and of his own mystical experiences. Some definitions of mysticism are complex; others are simple. One of the most basic definitions I have encountered comes from Wilson Van Dusen, Swedenborg scholar and self-avowed mystic:
I use the word mystic in its simplest and most basic sense. A mystic is one who experiences God. There are other associated meanings and very complex analyses in religious encyclopaedias, but they all rest in this the experience of God. Some might ask, Dont all people experience God? And I would answer yes, but many are not aware of it. The mystic is aware of it. (Van Dusen 1995: 105)

Compelling as this is, we are nevertheless still in the dark non-consensual waters when we try to establish what Van Dusen means by God. This, as most people would agree, is far from easy. Van Dusen, therefore, falls into the trap of defining one problematic term with another. His perspective,

Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter?

101

however, is perfectly aligned with Ellwood (1999: 2): For others direct experience of God is the pinnacle of what religion is all about. Experiences like these are often called mystical experiences. Did Borges have direct experience with God? Flynn (2009) was only able to identify the ceaseless philosophical search for God, not the encounter. Borges would argue with reference to Shaw that God is in the making, and hence the divine is immanent, not transcendent, and within the human soul. It is unlikely that such an expression would chime with the more orthodox Zaehner. Ellwood, however, appears fully cognizant ofthe problem inherent in defining mysticism, poignantly remarking that: What is it that thousands of other accounts of transcendent experience have or do not have in common? A host of scholars have wrestled with this question in attempting to define mysticism and mystical experience (1999: 15). Alan Watts describes the mystical experience as the opposite of feeling that one is a separate individual in confrontation with a world that is foreign to ones self, that is not me. In the mystical kind of experience, though, that separate individual finds itself to be of one and the same nature or identity as the outside world. In other words the individual no longer feels a stranger in the world; rather, the external world feels as if it were his or her own body (2006: 35). The crucial aspect here in relation to Watts is the notion of harmony and purpose: It is the overwhelming sense that everything that happens everything that I or anybody else has done is part of a harmonious design and that there is no error at all (2006: 36). Be that as it may, in tune with Borges, the reason for life need not be necessarily to accomplish any thing directed by a divine will the purpose may simply to be alive. The mystic has seen that the meaning of being alive is just to be alive (2006: 37). Furthermore, owing to Borges inherently ludic quality, he would fit with Watts description of the mystic: The mystic is the person who has realised that the game is a game (2006: 39). As identified, these definitions cannot be considered conclusive, not least owing to the contradictions amongst them when read as a body. Likewise, as identified, the practices or experiences that are proposed that are categorically not mystical experiences cannot be considered either so easily identifiable or definable, nor so necessarily removed from the mystical experience. Most of the features of anomalous experiences that Stace would

102

Chapter Two

so firmly assert do not constitute the mystical are, indeed, the prominent features of many mystics appraised in the scholarship: Swedenborg, for example, was a dedicated practitioner of breath control similar to yogic techniques, seemingly with no knowledge of eastern practices (Van Dusen 1974: 1921). One might argue, consequently, that his mystical experiences were induced and therefore not at all passive in the Jamesian sense. His psychic abilities are described above, and yet they cannot be divorced from his explorations of the realm of the dead indeed such explorations are the psychic abilities. Lastly, his remarkably lucid dreams are of paramount importance, as they both herald the onset of a mystical experience yet also provide the very doorway into these other landscapes. In the case of Swedenborg, therefore, breath control, psychic abilities and lucid dreaming added to his meditative constitution, his dazzling intellect, his energy and determination, his vast knowledge of the Bible and, let us not overlook, his wealth were all factors that together constituted the mystic. Therefore it would seem pernickety to isolate his talents as being individually not mystic, corporately mystic. The purpose of this preamble concerning Swedenborg is not to demonstrate that Borges was divested with similar talents, but to give some platform from which to demonstrate that those talents that Borges did have are not so easily consigned to the category of mere mystery-mongering (Stace 1960), and may be appraised as manifest mystical attributes.

Borges the lucid dreamer


Borges was a remarkably consummate lucid dreamer, appearing fully cognizant of the dreams whilst dreaming. He discussed a vivid dream to Barnstone, in which the way out of the dream of the maze is to sit down and wait to wake up a fascinating position. When I realized it and said, this is the nightmare of the maze, and since I knew all about it, I wasnt taken in by the maze. I merely sat down on the floor. [] I waited a moment

Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter?

103

and woke up (Barnstone 1982: 21).11 This deserves greater consideration than has been hitherto granted, as the ability to take positive, conscious decisions within a dream, to the point of choosing to wake and depart the dream state, is one that few possess and many strive to achieve. Green (1994), in her ground-breaking study: Lucid dreaming: the paradox of consciousness during sleep, notes that the technique of lucid dreaming has for centuries and in many different cultures been integrally related to matters of religious experience and spiritual practice, and has been the hallmark of so many accounts of mystical experiences. Borges also remarks in the essay on nightmares in Siete Noches that the experience of vivid dreams of such lucidity that they resemble waking life is an attribute of children (his nephew) and mystics: Todo corra para l en un solo plano, la vigilia y el sueo. Lo que nos lleva a otra hiptesis, a la hiptesis de los msticos []. Para el salvaje [de Frazer] o para el nio los sueos son un episodio de la vigilia, para los poetas y los msticos no es imposible que toda la vigilia sea un sueo (1989: 223) [Everything, waking and dream, occurred to him on a single plane. This brings us to another, similar but contrary, hypothesis: that of the mystics and the metaphysicians. For [Frazers] savage and for the child, dreams are episodes of the waking life; for poets and mystics, it is not impossible for all of the waking life to be a dream] (1984: 29).12 It is clear from this and from many other similar assertions of Borges, that one of the central features of the mystical life, that he himself shared, was the vivid, lucid, intense dream.

11 12

He repeats this, almost verbatim, in another interview in the same volume (Barnstone 1982: 73). It must be noted for the record that Weinbergers translation ofthis passage is wrong and radically alters the sense of the text. Borges writes that his nephew, having recounted his dream to Borges in which his uncle had appeared: Se interrumpi bruscamente y agreg: Decime, qu estabas haciendo en esa casita? (1989: 223). Weinberger translates: I interrupted him sharply: Stop making things up about my house! (1984: 29). Unfortunately the translation contrasts with the sense of the passage, as it suggests that Borges was unsympathetic to his nephews confusion, when in the original text he is delighted by it.

104

Chapter Two

Whilst Borges dramatizes the faculty of lucid dreaming in the fiction of the mago of Las ruinas circulares, a more precise and less dramatic account, which seems less fictional and more autobiographical, is Episodio del enemigo [Episode of the Enemy] from Elogio de la sombra. In this brief text, the Borges-protagonist is confronted by an ancient rival whom he has evaded for years. At the point in which the antagonist is about to murder him, Borges only strategy to save himself is to wake up, which he does. The perennial narrative motif of revealing that it was all a dream, when correlated with Borges comments to Barnstone, further demonstrates his vivid experience of lucid dreaming. Furthermore, and whilst I am aware that we should treat the passages of Atlas with the same critical scrutiny as one should treat any of the Ficciones, nevertheless there is a strong autobiographical, reminiscent quality to the pieces. In Atlas, as I remarked in the Introduction, are passages in which Borges recounts dreamdialogues with the dead, in particular with Hayde Lange. Three lines of argument can be pursued. Firstly, as mentioned, one may argue that this is merely a fiction and therefore of no consequence in the meta-fictional world; secondly, that it was not a fiction per se, but was only a dream and therefore likewise of no consequence in the real world. The third line of argument is of interest to me and was of manifest interest to Borges: that in this mysterious world many things are possible, such as the persistence of the soul after death, and the possibility for that discarnate soul (Lange) to enter dialogue with an incarnate soul (Borges) through dreams. This last possibility was of great interest also to Jung, and was explored by him in his private accounts that became The Red Book. One question that arises in this work, in relation to Jungs dream of his father, was whether he dreamt of his father, or whether his father visited him in his dream. Answers to this question are unlikely to be forthcoming, but the purpose is to show that such a question was of great concern to Borges, the non-mystic por supuesto; and yet dream encounters of this nature were the bedrock of Swedenborgs communication with spirits of the spirit-world, and were thus integrally related to those qualities considered mystical. The importance of dreams and dream-creativity in Borges poems and fictions is well-documented, and indeed, reading through my extensive notes of Borges citations that serve as background for this work, I am struck

Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter?

105

by the hundreds of appearances of the words dream and sueo. There is scarcely an essay, tale, poem or interview in which Borges does not discuss the creative possibility of dreams, the timeless dimension encountered, the epistemological capacity ( Jamess noetic), the traditional ancient dialectic, from Chuang-Tzu to Caldern and Shakespeare, of life as a dream, and, importantly, his intuition that dreams and visions are a pathway to the eternal. He declares, for example, in the lecture on the nightmare in Siete Noches, apropos J.W. Dunnes Experiments with Time: A cada hombre le est dado, con el sueo, una pequea eternidad personal que le permite ver su pasado cercano y su porvenir cercano (1989: 222) [Each man is given, in dreams, a little personal eternity which allows him to see the recent past and the near future] (1984: 28). Borges concludes the lecture with the observation que los sueos son una obra esttica, quiz la expresin esttica ms antigua (1989: 231) [that dreams are an aesthetic work, perhaps the most ancient aesthetic expression] (1984: 40). He describes in Inferno, I, 32 (El Hacedor) how Dante was touched by the divine in a dream and was given an image that would crown his poetic cycle (a narrative not dissimilar from El milagro secreto). He wrote plentifully about Coleridges reverieinspired poem Kubla Khan, and he was likewise fascinated by Stevensons account of receiving plots fully formed in his dreams from the Brownies, whom Stevenson formally acknowledges and thanks. However, Borges was not merely speculating on the creative power of dreams, nor was he merely illustrating an abstract idea in his fictions. He also described receiving poems and plots fully fledged in his reveries. For example, he described to Barnstone how the poem El ciervo blanco [The White Deer] came to him in its entirety in a dream: I dont feel that I wrote that poem []. I physically dictated the words. The poem was given to me, in a dream, some minutes before dawn. At times dreams are painful and tedious, and I object to their outrage and say, enough, this is only a dream, stop. But this time it was an oral picture that I saw and heard. I simply copied it, exactly as it was given to me (Barnstone 2000: 30). He recalled to Burgin that El Hacedor was his favourite book because it wrote itself (Burgin 1969: 125). He described in other interviews that sonnets appeared to enter his conscious mind from some apparent source beyond consciousness; he described dreams and nightmares as being given to him

106

Chapter Two

for the purpose of making poetry; and he repeatedly described the divine or demonic source of dreams and nightmares. So whilst Underhill might boldly assert that mysticism is not a term to be applied to menticulture and sorcery, dreamy poetry, nevertheless we can assess these matters in light of their collective relationship to what may be considered a mystical nature. We are, consequently, in a difficult position with mysticism. Too much worrying about a definition is proscriptive and becomes an exercise of hairsplitting. Too little concern for a definition allows any experience to muscle in under its banner, and the word becomes meaningless. One solution is to combine together all the defining characteristics as put forward by over a century of scholars. This then becomes a wild and unwieldy shopping list riddled with contradictions, and the selection of one defining category over another becomes either arbitrary or an attempt to match the text with the theory. Another solution is to seek a general term, generous enough to embrace the various scholars findings, yet limited enough to guarantee some purchase on the term. This, of course, is what so many scholars have attempted to do, and yet no unified theory has emerged that does not jar with some previous attempt at the unified theory. The only workable solution, therefore, is to enquire exactly why such a definition is required. Is it in order to assess whether one figure was or was not a mystic, as is Quinns case with Emerson (see Chapter Four)? If so, the response can only be articulated by stating that, for the purposes of the present study, the definition of the term as offered by, say, Underhill, or James, will suffice; but that this definition is by no means foundational. The conclusion will be, therefore, that so-and-so was a mystic, according to certain principles of James, was not according to the principles of Underhill, equally was not according to the principles of Zaehner, but may have been according to Stace. Consequently, and notwithstanding its inconsequentiality, in relation to our investigation into Borges, one might suggest that he was a mystic and he was not a mystic. Borges, as we explored in Chapter One, emphasized the authority of the mystical experience unmediated by doctrine or dogma, which makes the experience somehow atextual. He established a forthright distinction between the authentic experiences of Swedenborg, and the textuallyinspired, and consequently invented texts of Dante. He declared that the

Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter?

107

visions of Dante could not have occurred in verse, and that Fray Luis de Len was merely mimicking the Song of Songs. His own mystical experiences he described as being genuine and therefore likewise unmediated by prior textual assumptions. I suggested that this distinction is itself highly problematic because it implies that an experience may be free from textual inspiration a position that appears contradictory to the whole Borges project, where texts inspire experiences, experiences inspire texts, texts are experiences and experiences are texts. The vast scholarship of mysticism concentrates on approaching the mystical experience through a variety of epistemological avenues: historical, theological, psychological (and psychopathological), sociological, philosophical, and phenomenological. Inge, James, Underhill, Zaehner, Stace, Otto, Watts, Staal, and other scholars, in their variegated and thorough approaches to the fields of mysticism, move towards helpful categorical distinctions of the mystical experience. Yet despite this comprehensive critical approach, few scholars appear to have considered the complex dynamic concerning experience, recollection, textual reproduction of the experience, and the ensuing act of reading. Where is the mystical moment? Is there a transmission through these levels? Can there be betrayal of the experience, falsehood, parody? Can the putative mystical experience be invented? If so, and allowing the noetic value of the imagination as suggested by Blake, Jung, Corbin and Borges himself, can the invention of a mystical text constitute for the inventor a mystical experience? Stace (1960: 9) was emphatic that the mystic always mean[s] a person who himself has had mystical experience and that the word should not be applied simply to anyone who is sympathetic to mysticism. This would imply that the mystical encounter is between the experiencer (mystic) and the experience (mystical state) and not between the textual account ofthe experience and the reader or scholar. How do we define the mystical text itself ? William James, for example, defines ineffability as one of the four attributes of the mystical experience, yet can effability be given such a clear category? If the experience is truly ineffable then both the mystic and the reader of the mystics text rely on a textual approximation of the experience, not the experience itself; and thus a highly accomplished writer would be capable of crafting a text closer to the experience than one inexperienced in expressive

108

Chapter Two

writing. That is to say, if a mystic is a poor writer or narrator, does he/she cease to be considered a mystic if the experience is so poorly related? We recall that Borges dismissed Weatherhead on being a mediocre writer. And is not the readers response also an indicator of precision of the text? That is to say, if a text of seeming senselessness is understood by a reader, does the original mystical experience now cease to have been ineffable? If the experience were truly ineffable, then what does the text describe other than precisely that which was not the experience? I would argue, furthermore, that it is precisely the effability or clarity of Swedenborg that Borges enthuses about.

Sentirse en muerte and the vision of the Aleph: fiction and reality
Thus I wish to emphasize the role of the text, and in order to do so, and in order to address more fully the position maintained by Stace of distinguishing mystic from scholar, I shall compare two mystical texts ofBorges one real and one fictional, allowing for the permeability of these terms. The first, which he labelled sentirse en muerte, is a purportedly honest (i.e. non-fictional) account of a moment of eternity that Borges experienced as a young man. It is the experience that he later discussed with Barnstone as one of his mystical moments and which, according to Williamson (2004: 444), spurred him to an exploration of its meaning with Japanese Shinto monks in 1979. The second is the oft-quoted mystical moment in El Aleph, an invented, fictional account of ecstatic vision which Borges described as based on his reading about time and eternity (Burgin 1998: 212). By the standards that Borges himself applied in his appraisal of Swedenborg and Dante, can we establish that the first passage is authentic and the second not so? My first hypothesis here would be that both are real and both are textual indeed both are real because they are both textual. My second position would be that the texts mystical qualities can only be judged through

Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter?

109

an understanding of the transformative effect upon the reader, and that if this moment of textual jouissance is somehow impaired by the readers assumption that the text is merely fictional, then the text, for that reader, is not mystical. However, as a colleague of mine averred, if the reading of the fictional Aleph constitutes a truly transformative experience, then, for that particular reader, the text is manifestly mystical. No cross-referencing the scholarship of mysticism in order to determine the texts characteristics will affect that. Borges emphasis on authenticity and fictionality are thus unworkable platforms for an understanding of mystical texts. Furthermore, to muddy the waters even more, I hope to establish that the text of sentirse en muerte reads like one of Borges fictions, and that both his evaluation of his own mystical experience and the experience itself were influenced by Borges reading of James. Consequently, and in tune with Borges visions of the textual nature of experience, I would argue that the non-fictional account is, itself, strikingly fictional. As Flynn identifies, Borges was clearly moved by his experiences of timelessness, motivating him to recount the most profound of the two in three separate essays; and in the essay Historia de la Eternidad to appraise the experience as a corollary of the many treatments of eternity and infinity that he analyses.
The liminal revelation of the timeless moment in Sentirse en muerte recalls the experience of the nullity of self and personality which Borges had recounted in La nadera de la personalidad. The fundamental difference between the two, despite their shared revelatory character, is that the experience of 1923 is perceived as negative, of annihilating any notion of oneness and plenitude, whereas the experience of 1928 is positive, albeit unsustained, and recounted by Borges as addenda to various other texts over three successive decades. It is what he longs for and yet only ever experiences as a fleeting state of utter contentedness. Sentirse en muerte is about the experience of a union with, and at the same time a transcendence of, the material universe; at once becoming one with the material universe, and dissolving its very constituents: time and selfhood. This is reminiscent of the mystic who, in union with the divine, passes from time to eternity. But is Borges ecstatic moment a life-transforming, mystical union with God? It surely is a case of momentary transcendence and may well have been a spiritual moment that was perhaps over analysed and therefore only wistfully remembered and reiterated over decades. (Flynn 2009: 656)

110

Chapter Two

It is important to note that Flynn suggests that the over-interpretation of the moment somehow diminishes the ecstatic nature of the experience. This would imply that each level of textual recreation somehow fictionalizes the original non-fictional moment and thereby falsifies it. This, as we will examine, is a highly problematic assertion, as it implies firstly that an experience may be free of textual influence something Borges would refute at once and secondly, that the textual recreation is necessarily less authentic than the original experience an assumption that would nullify centuries of mystical texts. Borges foregrounds the essay with an idea that remained a key concern throughout his life: that the principle metaphysical problem is time. He postulated, with reference to Plato, that eternity is not una agregacin mecnica del pasado, del presente y del porvenir. Es una cosa ms sencilla y ms mgica: es la simultaneidad de esos tiempos (1974: 354) [a mechanical aggregate of past, present, and future. Eternity is something simpler and more magical: the simultaneity of the three tenses] (2000: 124). He located his experience alongside the textual recollections of Plato, Plotinus and Augustine of Hippo. Therefore whilst Borges claimed that Swedenborg cometi un incmodo error cuando resolvi ajustar sus ideas al marco de los dos Testamentos (2005: 155) [made an awkward mistake when he decided to adapt his ideas to the framework of the two Testaments] (1995: 9), the reader will naturally conjecture how far the ideas of Borges concerning his experience were adapted to the ideas of Plotinus.
Deseo registrar aqu una experiencia que tuve hace unas noches: fruslera demasiado evanescente y exttica para que la llame aventura; demasiado irrazonable y sentimental para pensamiento. Se trata de una escena y de su palabra: palabra ya antedicha por m, pero no vivida hasta entonces con entera dedicacin de mi yo. Paso a historiarla, con los accidentes de tiempo y de lugar que la declararon. (1974: 3656) [I wish to record an experience I had a few nights ago: a triviality too evanescent and ecstatic to be called an adventure, too irrational and sentimental for thought. It was a scene and its word: a word I had spoken but had not fully lived with all my being until then. I will recount its history and the accidents of time and place that revealed it to me.] (2000: 137)

Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter?

111

What was this word, with which he was familiar in theory but not in practical experience? In tune with the essay, the word would be eternity, but in tune with other essays, it would be mysticism. Borges makes firm declarations about the nature of the experience. It was too flighty to be called adventure, which would chime immediately with Jamess decree of transiency. We recall that it was the extensive duration of Dantes vision, the fact that it was not transient (plus the versification) that led Borges to suggest that Dante was not a mystic. Borges experience was also too full of feeling, too removed from reason, to be called a thought. This would appear perfectly cognate with Jamess category of ineffable, which James qualifies as [t]he subject of it immediately says that it defies expression, that no adequate report of its contents can be given in words. [] its quality must be directly experienced; it cannot be imparted or transferred to others. In this peculiarity mystical states are more like states of feeling than like states of intellect (1913: 380). However, he describes a great many thoughts that he had whilst undergoing this experience; or are these the thoughts that he had when recalling the experience? The passage itself is highly textual, reading like one of his tales; with familiar symbols that he notes are symbols in his fiction: the dark grasslands of the South, the lonely streets of the rough suburbs, the humble houses, the scattered symbols of the bird and crickets. No quiero significar as el barrio mo, el preciso mbito de la infancia, sino sus todava misteriosas inmediaciones: confn que he posedo entero en palabras y poco en realidad, vecino y mitolgico a un tiempo (1974: 366) [I am not alluding to my own neighborhood, the precise circumference of my childhood, but to its still mysterious outskirts; a frontier region I have possessed fully in words and very little in reality, at once adjacent and mythical] (2000: 137). He feels that he is walking in a landscape already made literature by him. He is therefore the character in a fiction, and everything is being fictionalized by him, either at the point of experience or in its retelling: No habr manera de nombrar la ternura mejor que ese rosado (1974: 366) [Tenderness could have no better name than that rose color] (138). This is qualified by his inability to escape literary allusion in the text: me alej hacia unos barrios, de cuyo nombre quiero siempre acordarme (1974: 366) [gravitation pushed me toward neighborhoods whose name I wish always

112

Chapter Two

to remember] (2000: 137), and one wonders whether this Cervantine line came to him at the point of the experience, during a reminiscence, or at the point of writing the text.
Pens, con seguridad en voz alta: Esto es lo mismo de hace treinta aos. [] El fcil pensamiento Estoy en mil ochocientos y tantos dej de ser unas cuantas aproximativas palabras y se profundiz a realidad. Me sent muerto, me sent percibidor abstracto del mundo: indefinido temor imbuido de ciencia que es la mejor claridad de la metafsica. No cre, no, haber remontado las presuntivas aguas del Tiempo; ms bien me sospech poseedor del sentido reticente o ausente de la inconcebible palabra eternidad. Slo despus alcanc a definir esa imaginacin. (1974: 3667) [I stood there looking at this simplicity. I thought, undoubtedly aloud: This is the same as it was thirty years ago. [] The glib thought I am in the year eighteen hundred and something ceased to be a few approximate words and deepened into reality. I felt as the dead feel, I felt myself to be an abstract observer of the world; an indefinite fear imbued with knowledge that is the greater clarity of metaphysics. No, I did not believe I had made my way upstream on the presumptive waters of Time. Rather, I suspected myself to be in possession of the reticent or absent meaning of the inconceivable word eternity. Only later did I succeed in defining this figment of my imagination.] (2000: 138)

These seemingly innocent expressions of description are deceptively complex. Was he experiencing something that he was fully able to comprehend and assimilate at the time of the experience? Was it the recollection after the event (prior to the writing) that was now problematic? Or was it the moment of recording the experience in words where its full ineffability is felt? It would appear from these brief descriptions of his thought processes at the time that he was fully cognizant of the experience as it was unfolding, and that the words began to fail him only at a later moment of textual recording. Be that as it may, Borges mastery of style would suggest that he was not lost for words, that he was able to capture the experience, and that consequently the experience was not ineffable. It is impossible to say how close the textual description is to the experience. Ineffability is a tricky word. As discussed in the beginning of this chapter, the impact of this episode (plus another un-narrated one) upon Borges was tremendous, and

Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter?

113

motivated him to seek deeper knowledge of the experience years later in Japan. One would suggest that the experience also fuelled his interest in mystical writers across the worlds literatures. And yet can we consider this episode to have been, as Borges emphasizes with Swedenborg, somehow outside of textual influence? As we have seen, the episode conforms closely to two of Jamess categories: transiency and passivity. Its ineffability is impossible to judge, as without being Borges we are in no position to determine the proximity between the textual reproduction and the experience itself. Its noetic value an arbitrary definition, to be sure would appear to be codified into Borges philosophical perspective regarding the flexibility of time. Indeed his inclusion of this episode in the various essays would demonstrate his consideration of it as an ideal case study to defend his radical theories of time. The inclusion of the passage in the essay Historia de la Eternidad indicates the relationship with the many philosophical accounts of eternity that Borges encountered in literature, and his own transient experience. As Kripal argues about the scholarship of mysticism, James, Underhill and other writers were only able to explore the nebulous fields of mysticism with such integrity because the texts they read chimed so closely with their own, often unstated, mystical experiences. Would Borges the reader, however, judge his own text as a fiction? This is an important question based, as discussed, on his division of Dante and Swedenborg into the fictional (poetic) and the non-fictional (authentic). Firstly, this may be merely a question of style: many readers across the decades have been unsettled by the exquisitely realist nature of some of Borges tales in which times flexibility is explored. El encuentro [The Meeting] from El Libro de Arena concerns the young and the old Borges sitting by a river each attempting to establish who is dreaming who. Its realism makes it uncanny, and yet we read it as a fiction primarily because, despite its outlandishness, it accompanies a selection of fantastic tales in the volume. Yet were it to have been included as an episode in one or more philosophical essays (as in the case of sentirse en muerte) and were Borges to have discussed it autobiographically in interviews, then our interpretative position would be different. It is thus the contextual quality beyond the textual that will determine the readers judgment of authenticity. The sister tale to El encuentro is Veinticinco de agosto, 1983, from La Memoria

114

Chapter Two

de Shakespeare (1980), which has received so little critical attention it could have been written by an unknown writer. This oneiric Swedenborg-inspired tale has only the vaguest pretence to realism, and thus, whilst still haunting and unsettling, nevertheless is evidently fictional. But is it any less mystical for its fictionality? In order to explore this question further, the episode of sentirse en muerte can be appraised alongside the particular ecstatic episode of the Borges-narrator of El Aleph (a tale, it must be emphasized, included in Kodamas edited volume On Mysticism). The scholarship on El Aleph is too vast to enumerate, and no stone has been left unturned in pursuing the many cryptic, cabalistic, literary and autobiographical pathways and references that are embedded in this perplexing text. Wilson (2006: 46), for example, argues that Borgess wicked mockery of Gmez de la Serna as Alef is hidden (few literary critics have noted this), and that the tale is a mere study in literary and sexual envy. What is of interest here, however, is not to wander in the literary labyrinth of the tale, but to consider the well-identified uselessness of mysticism that is presented; something Bossart (2003: 146) associates also with El Zahir and dubs failed enlightenment, [by which] I mean those occasions on which the conditions for enlightenment seem to be present but are not utilized. The Zahir and The Aleph are two examples of such a situation. Whilst I find Bossarts term problematic, for the simple reason stated above that it is not at all clear how we should interpret a putative successful enlightenment, nevertheless I would agree with Bossart, Alazraki and others that the tale constitutes an overall sense of failure and futility. Annette Flynn encapsulates this sentiment in acknowledging that the powerful epiphany depicted in the tale is, essentially, useless: The experience of divine vision is ultimately inconsequential (2009: 6). I would argue that a prominent aspect of the tale is the slightly melancholy mocking of textual attempts to capture the moment of mystical rapture. Does Daneri have a mystical experience? One would assume so, if his experience was similar to the Borges-narrators. Is he consequently a mystic? Absolutely not, as all he is capable of performing as a consequence is clumsy, verbose and voluminous poetry. But, we must ask, is his poetic output the only measure of his character, and is the description of his character the only measure of whether he was or was not a mystic? I doubt a

Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter?

115

single of the myriad readers of the tale could ever have considered Daneri a mystic his character is too asinine, what Molloy (1994: 54) describes as an affected middle-brow braggart and thus one must assume that as readers we have already made the basic assumption that a mystical experience does not necessarily make a mystic. This essential assumption forms the basis of another tremendous debate that has dominated the scholarship of mysticism since William James and which fuelled Underhills critique of James: the relationship between drugs (psychedelics) and mystical states (see Huston Smith [2000], Rowlandson [2013]). Cohen (1973: 83) perhaps alludes to this matter when suggesting that The Zahir and The Aleph describe false ways of inducing vision which, as Borges admits, produce false or partial, and always terrible, experiences. Such a statement is reminiscent of so much of the literature (Underhill, Zaehner, Von Franz) in which psychedelic experiences are described as false pathways towards knowledge, or the divine. Nez-Faraco (2006: 47) is the only critic to my knowledge to have likened the experience of the Aleph to a drug-induced vision, suggesting that the use of the words veneno and narctico is particularly interesting for its many literary associations, both ancient and modern; and whilst a case could be made that Borges may have been aware of, for example, Jamess description of the state of nitrous oxide intoxication, this is not my purpose here. It is pertinent, I would argue, simply to highlight the basic postulation, related to Bossarts failed enlightenment, that a mystic is characterized as a mystic not for the experiences he has undergone, but for some visible manifestation of those experiences upon his character and behaviour. Furthermore, such assumptions would not necessarily correlate with the definitions of William James, who, unlike Stace and Pahnke, did not appraise the legacy of the experience upon the individual beyond the notion of noetic value. Had Daneri composed splendid poetry, like Dante, San Juan de la Cruz or William Blake, would the noetic value be of greater worth here? The Borges-narrator presents a phenomenological problem with his description of the Aleph which exposes the curious relationship between Borges-author and the Borges-narrator-character. Both identify the Jamesian ineffable quality of a mystical experience, and express the problem of ineffability as a linguistic problem based not on the lack of

116

Chapter Two

consensual understanding of a word, but of the non-consensual nature of the experience. The Borges-narrator of El Aleph laments that he is unable to describe fully the experience of the Aleph because of the singularity of the experience:
Todo lenguaje es un alfabeto de smbolos cuyo ejercicio presupone un pasado que los interlocutores comparten; [] Los msticos, en anlogo trance, prodigan los emblemas: para significar la divinidad, un persa habla de un pjaro que de algn modo es todos los pjaros; Alanus de Insulis, de una esfera cuyo centro est en todas partes y la circunferencia en ninguna; Ezequiel, de un ngel de cuatro caras que a un tiempo se dirige al Oriente y al Occidente, al Norte y al Sur. (1974: 6245) [All language is a set of symbols whose use among its speakers assumes a shared past. [] Mystics, faced with the same problem, fall back on symbols: to signify the godhead, one Persian speaks of a bird that somehow is all birds; Alanus de Insulis, of a sphere whose center is everywhere and circumference is nowhere; Ezekiel, of a four-faced angel who at one and the same time moves east and west, north and south.] (1971a: 26)

Borges (the Borges-author), meanwhile, many years later, would foreground his exploration of Swedenborg by identifying the very same phenomenological problem:
El empleo de cualquier vocablo presupone una experiencia compartida, de la que el vocablo es el smbolo. Si nos hablan del sabor del caf, es porque ya lo hemos probado; si nos hablan del color amarillo, es porque ya hemos visto limones, oro, trigo y puestas del sol. Para sugerir la inefable unin del alma del hombre con la divinidad, los sufes del Islam se vieron obligados a recurrir a alegoras prodigiosas, a imgenes de rosas, de embriaguez o de amor carnal; Swedenborg pudo renunciar a tales artificios retricos, porque su tema no era el xtasis del alma arrebatada y enajenada, sino la puntual descripcin de regiones ultraterrenas, pero precisas. (2005: 154) [The use of any word whatsoever presupposes a shared experience, for which the word is the symbol. If someone speaks to us about the flavor of coffee, it is because we have already tasted it; if about the color yellow, because we have already seen lemons, gold, wheat, and sunsets. To suggest the ineffable union of mans soul with the divine being, the Sufis of Islam found themselves obliged to resort to prodigious analogies, to images of roses, intoxication, or carnal love. Swedenborg was able to abstain from this kind of rhetorical artifice because his subject matter was not the

Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter?

117

ecstasy of a rapt and fainting soul but, rather, the accurate description of regions that, though ultra-terrestrial, were clearly defined.] (1995: 7)13

Importantly, and as already examined, Borges implies here that Swedenborg was unlike other mystics because his experiences were essentially effable. Following the logic of this argument, if Swedenborg had no need to resort to symbolic approximations to the experience, this would imply that his language presupposes a shared experience; a problematic assertion, to be sure, when the reader is confronted with discarnate souls and angels discussing theology. It is apparent that the Borges-author of El Aleph speaks through the Borges-narrator with similar concerns about the textual inspiration behind the description of a mystical experience that we analysed in Chapter One. As with Borges claims about Swedenborgs non-literary textual description of his otherworld journeys, so the Borgesnarrator of El Aleph consciously chooses not to resort to the poetic symbols employed by Alanus de Insulis (Alain de Lille) or Ezekiel so as to keep his text somehow pure and uncontaminated by the influence of their texts. Quiz los dioses no me negaran el hallazgo de una imagen equivalente, pero este informe quedara contaminado de literatura, de falsedad (1974: 625) [Perhaps the gods might grant me a similar metaphor, but then this account would become contaminated by literature, by fiction] (1971a: 26).

13

Borges argues this elsewhere, in another essay on Swedenborg from 1978: Hay una diferencia esencial entre Swedenborg y los otros msticos. En el caso de San Juan de la Cruz, tenemos descripciones muy vividas del xtasis. Tenemos el xtasis referido en trminos de experiencias erticas o con metforas de vino. Por ejemplo, un hombre que se encuentra con Dios, y Dios es igual a s mismo. Hay un sistema de metforas. En cambio, en la obra de Swedenborg no hay nada de eso. Es la obra de un viajero que ha recorrido tierras desconocidas y que las describe tranquila y minuciosamente (2005: 200) [There is an essential difference between Swedenborg and the other mystics. In the case of St John of the Cross, we have very vivid descriptions of ecstasy. Ecstasy referred to in erotic terms or with metaphors of wine. For example, a man encounters God, and God is the same as the man. There is a system of metaphors. In the work of Swedenborg, on the other hand, there is none of this. It is the work of a traveller who has explored unknown lands and who describes them in precise detail] (my translation).

118

Chapter Two

The Borges-narrator is thus making the same assumptions that we later find in Borges many statements about Pascal, Dante, Luis de Len, Juan de la Cruz and Weatherhead; that their texts are somehow non-mystical or even false because they are literary i.e. textually-inspired. As discussed in the previous chapter, this is a perplexing conundrum, as it implies both the possibility of a non-literary text and, more subtle yet equally Borgesian, the possibility of a non-textual experience. Despite, therefore, his knowledge of de Lille and Ezekiel, the Borges-narrator is suggesting not only that his description of the vision of the Aleph in the basement of Daneris house was somehow free of prior textual influence, but that the experience itself was somehow free of this influence. As suggested earlier, this division between experience and textual account of the experience, which can constitute a tremendous gulf, is scarcely addressed in the scholarship of mysticism. It is abundantly clear that the ecstatic passage at the heart of El Aleph, [e]l inefable centro de mi relato, is absurd, and, akin to the absurdity of Funes perpetual ecstasy, constitutes a parodic inversion of possible mystical rapture. Whilst we may assert that Borges was employing a fictional space in order to appraise his own prior experience, so may we justifiably argue that the tale is merely an exquisitely crafted parody of mysticism; and whilst Borges praised Estela Canto for appreciating that the text was mystical, so Borges himself argued that it was nothing more than an invented tale inspired by his reading material. Borges explains the artifice, or the invention, of this passage:
A man in Spain asked me whether the aleph actually existed. Of course it doesnt. He thought the whole thing was true. I gave him the name of the street and the number of the house. He was taken in very easily. [] That piece gave me great trouble, yes. I mean, I had to give a sensation of endless things in a single paragraph. Somehow, I got away with it. Q: Is that an invention, the aleph, or did you find it in some reference? No. Ill tell you, I was reading about time and eternity. Now eternity is supposed to be timeless. I mean, God or a mystic perceives in one moment all of our yesterdays, Shakespeare says, all the past, all the present, all the future. And I said, why not apply that, well, that invention to another category, not to time, but to space? Why not imagine a point in space wherein the observer may find all the rest. I mean, who invented space? And that was the central idea. Then I had to invent all the other things, to make it into a funny story, to make it into a pathetic story, that came

Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter?

119

afterwards. My first aim was this: in the same way that many mystics have talked of eternity thats a big word, an eternity, an everness. And also neverness; thats an awful word. Since we have an idea of eternity, of foreverness in time, why not apply the same idea to space, and think of a single point in space wherein the whole of space may be found? I began with that abstract idea, and then, somehow, I came to that quite enjoyable story. (Burgin 1998: 212)

Such is the power of the fiction that the man in Spain failed to perceive the artifice and sought the actual Aleph. One must assume, therefore, that fact or fiction, genuine or imagined, the tale clearly is capable of delivering a tremendous impact upon the reader. J.M. Cohen (1973: 81), meanwhile, argued that Borges was attempting to mimic the ecstasies of Bhme: The idea for the Aleph itself came, I believe, from a passage in the biography of Jakob Boehme which describes his first illumination in 1599. It is quoted by William James in his Varieties of Religious Experience. This is a powerful statement, as it implies not only a familiarity with the mystical text of Bhme, but also with James scholarship of mysticism, something we will explore in the next chapter. Likewise, whilst it has been suggested that Borges was searching for a fictional text in which to explore his own timeless moment (sentirse en muerte), the ineffable centre of El Aleph appears less a reaction to his own personal experience than to the philosophical perplexity caused by the gulf between personal experience and textual accounts of mystical ecstasy. Countless responses to El Aleph, from academic articles and book chapters, to biographical accounts and reviews, describe the central episode as being mystical. Canto and Kodama, as mentioned above, both identify a strong mystical dimension to it; Alazraki calls the Aleph a mystic symbol (1988: 49); Jason Wilson (2006: 1617) considers it an extensive Buddhist joke ridiculing the inability to capture Nirvana, and qualifying this perspective by suggesting that this is the predicament that mystics encounter.
Buddhism also warns that language cannot communicate Nirvana, the void beyond appearances. Truth is not found in words; Borgess greatest fable, the fiction The Aleph, is also a Buddhist joke. The vision granted to Borges under the staircase in the story cannot be recreated in sequential words, despite Borgess lists. Only a mystic outside time can see everything at once, but then cannot communicate it.

120

Chapter Two

Yet is the text truly mystical? The ecstatic heart of the tale evokes the visionary raptures of Meister Eckhart, Hildegard of Bingen or Teresa de vila. In particular, and reflecting Borges familiarity with the poetry of William Blake, the tale may appear to suggest Blakes Auguries of Innocence: To see a world in a grain of sand, / And a heaven in a wild flower, / Hold infinity in the palm of your hand, / And eternity in an hour. Despite these illustrious antecedents, the tales complex intertextuality and its metatextual gameplaying with regards literary figures of Argentine letters (Williamson 2004) provide a context in which the mystical rapture appears wantonly parodic to the extent of ridicule. It is also the most extreme of images the vision of totality. Amidst the mundane context of a basement in a soon-to-be-demolished house belonging to a pompous poet, the narrator appears to experience a vision of totality that far exceeds even the most sublime descriptions of visionary poets. Whereas Henry Vaughans cosmic poem A vision (1650) begins I saw Eternity the other Night, this poem is generally considered a dream-like poetic image rather than the description of a genuine experience. The Borges-narrator, however, is attempting not poetry (that is Daneris hapless task) but prosaic description. It is, therefore, by Borges own standards, genuine. Borges presents something beyond our most basic powers of cognition. What can it possibly mean to see everything? Everything as a word and as a concept becomes meaningless, as there can be no division between one thing oftotality and another. The vision of El Aleph becomes as harrowingly impossible as Funes total memory it simply cannot be.14 Consequently, the enumeration of the things that the Borges-narrator does see is ridiculous, as it is like measuring an inch in infinity. It is neither a portion oftotality nor any approximation of it. The vision of the Aleph is a nominalist chaos, where ultimately all we have is a random succession of words and no things in themselves. He may just as well have listed twenty other things, or twenty further things, ad infinitum. Or no things at all.
14 The hyperbolic nature of the vision of the Aleph is similar to Douglas Adams torture device the Total Perspective Vortex from The Hitchhikers Guide to the Galaxy, in which the victim is annihilated through being forced to see himself in relation to the enormity of the cosmos.

Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter?

121

Conclusion
As established, it is something of a mainstay in the scholarship of mysticism to produce specific defining characteristics. What had scarcely been addressed until Kripal (2001), however, is the inseparable relationship between the scholar him/herself and the articulation of the approach to mysticism. Dean Inges perspectives on mysticism, for example, are inevitably bound up with his adherence to Anglican orthodoxy.15 For example, he rejects outright the heresy of which Borges professed, that of God in the making:
The common assumption that God is so bound up with the world that it is as necessary to Him as He is to it is incompatible with mysticism. The Supreme, whether we call it God or with Plotinus the One or with Eckhart the Godhead, or with some moderns the Absolute, is transcendent. The notion that God is evolving with His universe, coming into His own, realizing Himself, or emerging, owes its popularity to the last Western heresy, the idea that the macrocosm is moving towards one far-off divine event. There can be no process of the Absolute, no progress, and no change. Exhortations to take time seriously may be in place when we are dealing with history; but to subordinate the Eternal to space and time is a fatal error in metaphysics. (Inge 1947: 154)

William James cannot be separated from his upbringing amidst New England Transcendentalism, Evelyn Underhill is in so many ways herself the focus of her whole system of investigation. This is not such an obvious statement as it could appear, as in many cases the philosophical, religious, political or even cultural assumptions and belief systems of the scholars feed into their scholarship in subtle ways. Sometimes, however,

15

Note that Russell (1961: 179) mocks Inges favouring of Christian mysticism over the mysticism of other faiths: The chief argument in favour of the mystics is their agreement with each other. I know nothing more remarkable, says Dean Inge, than the unanimity of the mystics, ancient, mediaeval, and modern, Protestant, Catholic, and even Buddhist or Mohammedan, though the Christian mystics are the most trustworthy.

122

Chapter Two

such positions are at once visible. Staal, for example, identifies this striking feature of Zaehner, arguing that his religious beliefs led him to a narrow view of other beliefs and practices. The main difficulty with this book as a whole [Zaehners Hindu & Muslim Mysticism (1960)] is the authors own religious allegiance, which clearly prevents a fair and adequate description and evaluation of differing points of view and which leads the author to a classification which is nothing but a reflection of his own belief (1975: 67). Zaehner similarly weighed into the debate on mysticism and psychedelics with a level of invective that revealed deep-seated moral concerns with the proposal that mystical states are achievable through such means. Zaehner criticized Huxleys exuberant use of words from Catholic and Hindu traditions, arguing that Huxley had no right to make these bold declarations about gratuitous grace, Beatic state or one-ness, as these are matters of spiritual practice within established traditions of faith. The mescaline experience, he argued, aside from specific Native American traditions, lies outside established traditions of faith. It is clear that Zaehner is arguing not from a phenomenological position i.e. is a mystical state possible with mescaline but a theological is such a state permissible. There is also the tendency present within the whole scholarship of mysticism to reduce the mystical aspect of a text to mere textual markers, and to correlate these textual instances against the check-list of the scholarship of mysticism, such as James, Underhill or Stace. Whilst this may be a justifiable exercise in attempts to determine whether a text is, for example, a good example of Modernist or postcolonial literature, there is something slightly disjointed when such textual scrutiny occurs with the study of mysticism, in that the ceaseless attempts to pin it down to the salient characteristics can seem contradictory to the very fluid and mysterious nature that is, itself, mysticism. There is consequently something exasperating in running through endless academic approaches to deistic or non-deistic, extravertive or intravertive, hot or cool, perennialist or essentialist, as these questions rarely confront actual and pressing ontological questions. The questions, in my opinion, should not concern whether Emerson was a religious mystic or a nature mystic, nor whether Swedenborgs experiences were hot or cool, structured or unstructured (Rawlinson 1998: 120), but what are we, as readers, to do with his texts? It occurred to me

Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter?

123

that Blake (regardless of whether he was or was not a mystic) would have railed against so much scholastic inactivity. Swedenborg, likewise, was highly critical of scholastic debates that served as mere displays of erudition rather than interrogating the nature of reality,16 and would have been equally dismayed at seeing his moral theology ignored and his own status pinned to a graph of hot unstructured, or having his experiences forensically analysed according to whether they satisfy the requirements of transiency (no), ineffability (no), passivity (no), noetic quality (yes) and so on. Kripal (2001) has bravely attempted to realign the scholars and their scholarship with their own mystic-erotic experiences, but even his study leaves many questions unaddressed concerning the nature of the mystical experience itself. The fact that James called the debate one of names is of key importance here, as there appears to be an endless circling above the experience described in the text without the courage to plunge into the very questions that mysticism itself raises. Borges was manifestly astonished by his own experiences of timelessness, and, whilst he may not have engaged in theological discussions with angels, as Swedenborg did, he nevertheless invested deeply in an aesthetic and intellectual effort to understand the full significance of his experiences. It is consequently of little importance whether Borges was or was not a mystic. What is certain is that Borges experienced many matters that habitually appear in the repertoire of mystical experiences: a sense of the numinous and the ineffable, noesis, ecstasy and a sense of moving outside of time, lucid dreams, possible communication with the dead, synchronicities, awe at the mystery of existence, and other experiences of intersticios de sinrazn. These matters delighted and puzzled him, and his encyclopaedic reading of other accounts of mystical and anomalous experience, especially
16 If people have loved the academic disciplines only in order to sound learned, without using them to develop their ability to reason, taking delight in their pride at the contents of their memories, they love sandy areas and prefer them to meadows and gardens because sandy areas correspond to these kinds of study. People who are wrapped up in knowing the doctrines of churches, their own and others, without applying them to life, love stony areas and live among rock piles. They avoid cultivated land because it is repulsive to them (Heaven & Hell 488).

124

Chapter Two

Swedenborg, assisted him in attempting to make sense of such matters. The beauty of Borges is that no sense is made at all. The mystic may receive some sense of the divine purpose, but as the experience, in Borges view, is inherently ineffable, such revelation can never be transcribed. The universe, Borges repeatedly maintained, is ultimately mysterious. The mystics seize this mystery and, despite the inevitability that ultimate answers will not be forthcoming, devote themselves to this intellectual and intuitive search. Perhaps as the final word on the long scholarship of mysticism, we might, like Underhill and Stace, offer an explanation of precisely what a mystic is not. It is not, as Borges describes, taking the universe for granted: nonmystics: take the universe for granted. They take things for granted. They take themselves for granted. Thats true. They never wonder at anything, no? They dont think its strange that they should be living (1969: 6). This touching aphorism could be taken as Borges poignant contribution to the long and contradictory scholarship. From such a consideration, one could suggest that for Borges the mystic is the one who is mystified; the one who enters the mystery; the one who, at the final measure, is aware of the mystery. As I hope to have demonstrated, there is a tendency in the critical studies of Borges to make assertions about the mystical or non-mystical nature both of himself and of his texts. Such assertions assume a consensual understanding of the term mystic. However, as I analyse above, not only is there no consensus, but the term itself is immensely complicated. The most thorough attempt to qualify such an assertion seems to be Howard Giskin, with his correlation of Borges texts with the four categories defined by William James. An analysis as thorough as Giskins, though, leaves many questions unanswered about the relationship between a mystical text and the texts author, between the fictionality or potential parodic nature of the text and its mystical attributes, between the wide variety of readers responses. It becomes clear that we cannot rely on a simple set of co-ordinates in order to establish whether Borges was or was not a mystic, as so many conflicting avenues of enquiry need to be taken into consideration before any suitable conclusion is reached. This chapter has attempted to consider certain texts of Borges in the light of a number ofthese variant enquiries into mysticism. The conclusion is, consequently, notably inconclusive.

Chapter Three

In the shadow of William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism

In order to be able to decide if the prophet is telling the truth or lying, we shall have to investigate the mystical experience for ourselves. This can be done in two ways: from the outside, by studying the biographies and writings of the saints; and from the inside, by following the instructions they have given us. Christopher Isherwood, Vedanta for The Western World

Was Borges a theorist of mysticism? As established in the previous chapter, it is characteristic of scholars of mysticism to define the terms mystic and mysticism by enumerating the salient features following analysis of both mystical texts and, in some cases, personal experience. William Jamess four principles are doubtless the best known. Borges is not a name generally associated with the long tradition of the scholarship of mysticism, for the same reason that he is not included, for example, in the Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy. This is because he always eschewed defining a particular theory or method whether philosophical, theological or metaphysical preferring to be considered un mero hombre de letras y no un investigador o de un telogo (2005: 155) [a mere man of letters and not a researcher or theologian] (1995: 8). He affirms this to Burgin in interview: Im not sure whether Im a Christian, but Ive read a great many books on theology for the sake of their theological problems free will, punishment, and eternal happiness. All these problems have interested me as food for my imagination (Burgin 1998: 57). Again, therefore, we are presented with the problem that Borges himself would appear to distance himself from a critical appraisal of the tradition of mysticism whilst, as

126

Chapter Three

discussed in Chapter One, making some forthright assertions about his interpretation of certain mystical texts. The question of separating mystic from scholar of mysticism is complicated; and here we can perceive a thread developed by William James, and running through Walter Stace to Frits Staal. How are we to establish a suitable distinction between the mystic and the scholar of mysticism? This may sound self-evident, but if we appraise the question in light of Borges, then we can perceive some problematic twists to the analysis. Stace (1960: 9), one of the most prominent researchers into the variegated field of mysticism, was outspoken in separating the mystic from the scholar.
By the word mystic I shall always mean a person who himself has had mystical experience. Often the word is used in a much wider and looser way. Anyone who is sympathetic to mysticism is apt to be labeled a mystic. But I shall use the word always in a stricter sense. However sympathetic toward mysticism a man may be, however deeply interested, involved, enthusiastic, or learned in the subject, he will not be called a mystic unless he has, or has had, mystical experience.

Can we suitably distinguish between the mystical experiences and the evaluation of the experience? That is to say, can we distinguish so clearly between the mystic and what Staal calls the student of mysticism (1975: 135)? Firstly, it is unlikely that anyone experiencing a state of consciousness wholly extraordinary would feel inclined not to evaluate the experience; Teresa de vila, for example, dedicated many pages of her autobiography and El Castillo Interior [The Interior Castle] to an appraisal of the spiritual exercises that led to her states of ecstasy. Swedenborg described his specific breathing and meditative techniques that prefaced his voyages to the heavens. Teresa and Swedenborg are consequently as much students of mysticism as they are mystics. Borges was as keen to evaluate his own two mystical outside of time experiences as he was to discuss Swedenborg, Silesius or his friend Xul Solar. In a similar fashion, it would be remiss to assume that students (scholars) of mysticism are not informed by experience, and are only working at textual analysis. Emerson, for example, correlated his

In the shadow of William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism

127

reading of Jakob Bhme and Swedenborg with his own ecstatic experience.1 William James, like Borges, denied his own mystical nature, yet nevertheless emphasized that his mystical sensibilities predisposed him towards a study of mysticism: I have no mystical experiences of my own, but just enough of the germ of mysticism in me to recognize the region from which their voice comes when I hear it ( James 2003: 210). Indeed, like Borges, he describes in great detail four particular experiences which could only be described as very sudden and incomprehensible enlargements of the conscious field, bringing with them a curious sense of cognition of real fact ( James 1910: 87). It has been argued, indeed, that James was describing himself when describing the divided self that an anonymous Frenchman suffered, in the chapter The Sick Soul of Varieties.2 Alicia Jurado, we recall from the previous chapter, focuses on Estela Cantos suggestion that Borges was one of the greatest and they are extremely rare mystical thinkers of our time, and reaffirms the idea of Borges as Mystical thinker, naturally, not just mystic (1996: 98). Again, how are we to distinguish between the terms mystic and mystical thinker? Would we approach this laudatory comment from a different angle if she had called Borges one of the greatest mystics of our time? Does mystical thinker permit the marriage of intellect with spiritual sensibility, i.e. does it imply critical distance, even scepticism, whilst mystic would imply abandonment to irrationality or to faith? The subtlety of distinction is important. To pursue a study of mystical texts and scholarly analyses thereof, one must already accept at least the possibility of certain postulates: that the term mysticism is worthy of investigation and that something useful may be derived from this study. This would imply that the student of mysticism would take seriously the claims made both by those known as mystics, and
1 We return to reason and faith. There I feel that nothing can befall me in life, no disgrace, no calamity, (leaving me my eyes,) which nature cannot repair. Standing on the bare ground, my head bathed by the blithe air, and uplifted into infinite spaces, all mean egotism vanishes. I become a transparent eye-ball; I am nothing; I see all; the currents of the Universal Being circulate through me; I am part or particle of God. (Emerson 2005: 12) I am grateful to Jeremy Carrette for this information.

128

Chapter Three

the conclusions drawn by scholars. Ultimately, as with Borges defence of Swedenborg, the student of mysticism would likely be prepared to accept the texts of mystics as not being the ramblings of the insane or outright lies; and if they are not fantasy or lies, then there is the possibility that Swedenborgs accounts of conversations with angels and demons and his voyages to heaven and hell are true. Therefore the student of mysticism will likely be open to the possibility of a mystical state of consciousness him/herself. The diligent student of mysticism is necessarily sympathetic to mysticism, if, indeed only so as to attempt to refute it. This may sound trite, but seeing as the field itself is of an order that can challenge certainties about time, space, life and death, one can assume that in order to investigate this curious area, and in order for the texts to inform the researcher in some measure, the researcher must already be prepared to accept these challenges to his/her ontological assumptions. Such an equation between subject (mysticism) and observer (researcher) is succinctly encapsulated by Kripal (2001), who argues that the scholarship has been driven by the psychic energy bestowed upon the researchers by their own (secret and erotic) experiences: I would go so far as to argue that, without these subjective experiences and the creative energies they release in the psyches (and bodies) of the scholars who undergo them, there would be no study of mysticism, at least as it has been practiced for the past one hundred years (27).3 Furthermore, Kripal argues:
It is not just that these experiences are methodologically important because they provide the historian of religions with the energy to carry through a particular project. Second, and more important, they are methodologically significant because they structure, inform, and even determine the hermeneutical choices of the historians who have undergone them. Which texts are studied, which passages come alive and

I hope to establish [that] the modern, and now postmodern, study of mysticism, from its early beginnings to its contemporary practice, has been largely inspired, sustained, and rhetorically formed by the unitive, ecstatic, visionary, and mysticohermeneutical experiences of the scholars themselves. The mystical experiences of scholars of mysticism no archaeology of the comparative study of mysticism can justifiably ignore this weirdly beautiful, if ethically ambiguous, source of inspiration, theory, and writing (Kripal 2001: 3).

In the shadow of William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism

129

so receive hermeneutical attention, which theoretical tool the hermeneut employs, what interpretations are finally reached all of these are profoundly influenced by the mystical experiences of the historians themselves. (2001: 27)

Nevertheless, whilst acknowledging the interrelationship between mysticism and the scholarship of mysticism, one should be careful not to assume too close an interdependence. If we follow Staces judgment, then we can assume that Borges was, indeed, a mystic, based upon his two related timeless experiences; and we would assume that he was not a mystic if we consider only his close and sympathetic reading of mystical texts. Likewise, need we divide the Borges of Historia de la Eternidad into two the researcher of centuries of theologians and mystics who have written about eternity, and the narrator of a personal moment of timelessness? Borges was desgraciadamente Borges, and consequently it seems disjointed to separate one aspect from another, especially seeing that he was insistent in claiming that a textual experience was as real as a non-textual one. We recall the Swedenborgian Lawrence writing about the Swedenborgian Borges, calling him a kindred spirit to the Swedish mystic and suggesting that he shared with Swedenborg the same fundamental objectives; they simply traversed the same terrain in somewhat different ways (1995: x). In that respect a close and sympathetic reading of Swedenborg becomes itself a certain experience of Swedenborgs otherworld experiences. Here we open another question in the thorny scholarship of mysticism, reflected in Kathleen Raines (1995) avowal that Blakes poetry provides tangible experience of divine bliss rather than merely describing it. This question is integral to the matter that preoccupied William James and Bertrand Russell concerning the epistemology of experience: what is the gulf that separates knowledge-by-acquaintance from knowledge-bydescription? As discussed in Chapter One, Borges placed such experiential value on the text that the reading of the content constitutes an experience of that very content. In this sense, knowledge-by-description is knowledge-by-acquaintance, and in this case, a dedicated student of mysticism is capable of experiencing through the mediation of the text some aspect of the mystical reality. Such a position would chime with Jamess understanding that, as Eugene Taylor suggests, [r]elations in experience also lie

130

Chapter Three

at the heart of Jamess epistemology. Since experience is all that exists and all that exists is experience (Taylor 1996), and yet would jar with Russells emphasis on distinguishing the two modes of knowledge. Van Dusen suggests that Swedenborgs writings, beyond describing the otherworld realities, provide direct experience to the dedicated reader, and thus enact a didactic method that can, if read properly, make a mystic of the reader:
If I had to describe Swedenborgs spiritual writings and their fundamental purpose in one line, it would be this: the writings are a clear presentation meant to be used by individuals to lead them into the life of God as an actual part of their experience. His writings are rational, but that is their style, not pre-eminently their nature. Their nature and overwhelming purpose are to lead to God, which accounts for many aspects of their structure. So in this sense, not only are his writings the work of a mystic, they are meant to help create mystics, that is, to lead others to the Divine. (1995: 134)

In this sense the writings of Swedenborg become sacred texts texts whose oral transmission enacts a spiritual and numinous reaction in the readers or listeners. This assertion is itself problematic if we follow the comments of Emerson, Henry James Sr., William James, Yeats, and Borges about how dry and insipid was the style of Swedenborg. From Van Dusens perspective, the text is not the narrative of an experience, it is the experience, and thus the sympathetic reader (the student of mysticism) is the mystic. Van Dusen takes this perspective to another level in the essay Swedenborgs Spiritual Method (1991), where he cites his friend, a Swedenborgian scholar named David St Amour, who derives great spiritual solace from Swedenborgs texts even when he did not understand them (original emphasis). In this sense the text is authoritative and somehow above the interaction of critical scrutiny. Whilst Stace would balk at this muddying of the waters of mystic, text and researcher of mysticism, it is important for a study of Borges to acknowledge that the distinctions are not so radically distinct. Staal (1975) approaches the question of the researcher of mysticism from another angle, and whilst recognising the necessary distinction between mystic and scholar, suggests that the examination of the mystical state requires methodical and dispassionate (i.e. unmystical) approaches to the phenomenon: He also suggests that mystics are probably not the best to formulate theories of mysticism: It is the students of mysticism whose

In the shadow of William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism

131

task it is to evolve a theory (63). This seems to imply that if the mystic were the intrepid explorer, then the scholar is the cartographer; the two have a natural symbiosis where the mystic provides the raw data, and the scholar assimilates, contrasts and analyses the material and prepares it for the wider readership. This perspective is again not without its difficulties, as evinced by James and Borges, in that the scholar himself may derive his knowledge experientially (that is to say, non-textually, if such is possible) as much as textually. With this distinction established, however, Staal was also keen to emphasize that attempts by the scholar to detach him/herself altogether from the field of study can lead to an impoverishment both of the scholarship and of the possible experiences of the researcher. It is incumbent upon the researcher to have some working experience of the matters that are under investigation:
No linguist would refuse to study sentences because we cannot perceive how they are internally produced. Nor would a physicist be content with mere speculation and refuse to devise experiments to test some part of a hypothesis, on the grounds that such experiments might be difficult to carry out, might be of uncertain outcome, or might be time-consuming or expensive. And neither would a person interested in reaching the South Pole, out of fear that he might not be able to get there, stay at home and refuse even to move in a southerly direction. Yet students of mysticism have, in their field, left all such things undone. Content with mere speculation and talking, they have not even considered the possibility of traveling themselves that part of the road that appears to be within reach even though not very well paved. This can only be understood if it is the outcome of a deep-seated prejudice, for such a negative attitude has in no domain of knowledge been taken seriously or been expected to lead to results. (Staal 1975: 127)

As established in the previous chapter, there is every indication to suggest that Borges was familiar with many experiences that generally serve the definition of the mystic. However, like Jung he would have had no truck with any suggestion that he himself was a mystic. Few scholars, despite their personal experiences, would likely declare within their scholarly writing that they themselves are mystics. There are many reasons for this. Firstly, as Aniela Jaff describes about Jung, there is a tendency to assume that mystical experiences are non-rational, and that they consequently run contrary to the academic pursuit of truth.

132

Chapter Three
Jung did not like to be regarded as a mystic: he preferred to be recognized as an empiricist, i.e., a scientist whose research is based on a careful observation of facts. In this sense, he thought of himself as a natural scientist. One can understand why Jung disliked being included in the ranks of mystics when one considers that in his time, and essentially also today, to characterize a scientific author as mystic casts a doubt on the reliability or validity of his ideas and his work. (1989: 1)4

This division between truth claims of the empiricist over those of the mystic is a central concern of the scholarship of mysticism, and forms the central area of concern for the conclusion of William Jamess chapter on mysticism in Varieties, and the central focus of Russells chapter on mysticism in Religion and Science. James would argue that the mystic is empowered with knowledge through the mystical experience, Russell would argue that we have no way of knowing, if such an experience and such an account cannot be transmitted successfully. The essence of both arguments, though, as reflected also in Jaffs comments about Jung, is that scholars are likely to be reticent in suggesting their own mystical nature for fear of accusations of subjectivity, irrationality, or even outright delusion. In the case of Borges, as discussed in the previous chapter, his desire not to be considered a mystic appears less a fear of academic malpractice than an eagerness not to be considered credulous, nor to have given himself over to statements of faith. Whilst one may justifiably object to the equation of mysticism with faith, one can perceive in Borges many comments concerning the faculty of critical enquiry, and his other comments about the faint and rapt outpourings of mystics, that he was keen to have been seen, like Jung, as a sober and intellectual empiricist. So much value is placed upon the term mystic that derives from the period, culture and environment in which the term is used. As Jaf f observed, the term had
4 Van Dusen (1995: 129) would reinforce the non-rational aspect of mysticism, though more needs to be discussed in order to determine exactly what non-rational means: Mysticism is nonrational; this is again from the laypersons definition. As a matter of fact, mystical writings vary across the whole spectrum of clarity and nonrationality. Basically, mysticism, or the experience of God, is irrational to those outside the experience. It is rational, true, and clear to those in the experience. It informs reason of higher truths.

In the shadow of William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism

133

implications of unreliability both in the time of Jung and today (1980s). At the time of Emerson, the term was employed ostensibly to designate a vapid and over-emotional religiously-inclined personality (Hurth 2005). In other times and cultures the term and its cognate expressions can have notably divergent significations.5 This contradiction established between intellectual pursuit and mystical experience is problematic for two reasons: firstly it implies that the scholarly method can only be efficacious if all steps of rigorous analysis are both expressed and expressible, and secondly, that epistemological pathways that fall outside of such a scholarly method are somehow inferior. Both assumptions are based on a dichotomy built up since the Enlightenment but made more robust within academic scholarship over the last century of prioritizing to an alarming degree one method of enquiry over another. Borges himself alluded to this division within modernity, arguing, as mentioned earlier, that Plato and Socrates considered reason and myth as similar epistemological pathways (Burgin 1998: 160), and that the Paris of the Enlightenment worshipped el culto de la razn (1989: 235) [the cult of reason]. Similarly, when discussing Buddhism in Siete Noches, Borges dwells on the many binaries that characterize modern western thought and that prevent a full engagement in Buddhist spiritual practice: Nosotros pensamos siempre en trminos de sujeto, objeto, causa, efecto, lgico, ilgico, algo y su contrario; tenemos que rebasar esas categoras. Segn los doctores de la zen, llegar a la verdad por una intuicin brusca, mediante una respuesta ilgica (1989: 252) [We always think in terms of subject-object, cause-effect, logic-illogic, a thing and its opposite. We must go beyond these categories. According to the Zen masters, to reach truth through sudden intuition requires an illogical answer] (1984: 73). Many scholars, such as Kripal (2001) and Ferrer (2002, 2008), have attempted to redress this radical division, and, in the

Hurths mention of the historical variance of the use of the term mysticism is of crucial importance here, and we must also consider possible differences between English and Spanish when considering Borges. I have heard l es un mstico in Spain to refer to a daydreamy man who regularly missed appointments.

134

Chapter Three

case of Ferrer, propose a participatory method in which the subjectobject division is surpassed. In this sense, a scholar may be more inclined to describe and assimilate within his/her scholarship the life experiences of a transpersonal, mystical or anomalous nature. Yet the term mystic also has ethical implications that would dissuade the scholar from expressing the experiential dimension in clear terms, for fear of being seen to assume a brazenly superior position. That is to say, most of the scholarship of mysticism highlights the ethical aspect of the mystical experience, whereby the mystic gains some moral insight into the nature of human affairs. That being the case, to declare oneself a mystic may equate to declaring oneself better than the non-mystic, or to declaring oneself privileged above others, singled out by divine grace. Van Dusen is the only scholar I have encountered to declare unabashedly his own mystical nature; indeed his contribution to Testimony to the Invisible is entitled A mystic looks at Swedenborg. Rigorous and informative as his chapter is, there is an unsettling self-assurance in the opening pages when he recounts when I first became aware that I was a mystic (1995: 106). Clearly he had no intention of implying moral superiority, but it is difficult as a reader not to respond with a certain misgiving. Where Borges describes Swedenborg as el elegido (2005: 154) [the chosen one] (1995: 6), he implies the special nature with which Swedenborg was endowed, and he pays close attention to Swedenborgs ethical and admirable nature. In tune with Borges widely discussed modesty, therefore, and regardless of his awareness that his own experiences may have been termed mystical, it is highly unlikely that he ever would have called himself a mystic for fear of presumption. Thus there are many reasons that the scholarship of mysticism is replete with subtle implications and allusions to personal experience with few outright declarations, as the scholars may consider themselves risking the integrity of their scholarship by drawing too heavily on the personal, experiential nature of mysticism.

In the shadow of William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism

135

Borges varieties of mystical experience


Although he never expressed a definitive theory of mysticism, Borges may nevertheless be considered a scholar of mysticism in the tradition of James, Underhill, Stace and Zaehner. Despite his jocular insistence that he was a man of the nineteenth century, Borges was a man of his times. As such, in appraising his views on mystics, mysticism and mystical consciousness, it is pertinent to see him not as a contemporary of Blake, Coleridge and de Quincey, nor of Emerson, Thoreau, Melville and Whitman, but as an inheritor of the long shadow cast at the beginning of the twentieth century by William James. The manifest affinities between William James and Borges have attracted surprisingly little critical research. The most extensive investigation that I have encountered is the unpublished 2008 PhD thesis of Marcel Fernandes: Borges and Pragmatism: Jorge Luis Borges, William James, and the Destruction of Philosophy. This exemplary piece of scholarship coherently argues for a Jamesian reading of Borges shifting philosophies, aligned both to Pragmatism, Radical Empiricism, and the religious-philosophical-psychological outlook of Varieties. In particular, Fernandes argues that whilst Borges himselflocates James on the nominalist side of the historical realist-nominalist divide, as outlined in El Ruiseor de Keats [The Nightingale of Keats] and La Flor de Coleridge [The Flower of Coleridge], Borges himself would occupy a position alongside James. However, Fernandes proposes, both James and Borges share an ironizing perspective a pragmatic sensibility that truth is variable that grants them a more mobile position than that of an outright nominalist: Borges is best described as a pragmatist rather than a nominalist since he is self-reflexive enough to be aware that such a division is after all itself a Platonic construct, and that nominalism can itself become a general dogma. Instead, he makes aesthetic use of the division (2008: 23). Fernandes insightful and close reading of Borges tales reveals a strongly pragmatic aspect to Borges which allows Borges to explore the aesthetic wonders of Platonic Idealism against the anarchic chaos of nominalism:

136

Chapter Three
Borges stories were to make more obvious use of philosophy than did any of his previous writing [prior to his head injury], and in a way that pitted one type of Jamess binary firmly against the other: the idealist or pantheistic aspects of the history of philosophy, from Plato to Plotinus to Schopenhauer, were to be set against the most hard-headed nominalism of Aristotle, Hume or James himself. Yet, instead of the agons of dialectic and argument, Borges was to allow realism (in the Platonic, idealist sense) to inspire and structure and inform his short stories, relishing the aesthetic potential of idealism while always holding it in abeyance, checking it with an irony both recalcitrant and deflationary, ludic and nominalist. (2008: 22)

He also highlights the paucity of scholarship into the JamesBorges connection, focusing on Borges decision to omit from the 1975 Prlogo con un prlogo de prlogos his own 1945 introduction to the Spanish translation of James Pragmatism. Following Nubiola (2000), Fernandes proposes that this omission may derive firstly from Borges mistrust ofhis writings from thirty years earlier. Secondly, and more audaciously, Fernandes proposes that:
Borges felt that this prologue to Jamess book gave his game away, so to speak; it was too close to the marrow of his creative praxis. [] If I am correct in arguing that Borges utilizes a Jamesian pragmatism to engage the history of philosophy for aesthetic ends, and makes pragmatic use of the nominalist-realist controversy and empiricalrationalist binary that was central to Jamess own historiography of philosophy, then it is unsurprising that he sought to avoid any obvious giveaways. Perhaps revealing the intellectual engine of his fictions was anathema to Borges; he may have viewed such an admission as a kind of self-incrimination. (2008: 32)

Fernandes thesis maintains in essence that Borges repeated claims to use philosophy for aesthetic purposes, itself disguises a pragmatic employment of philosophical discourses in a manner that reveals the influence of James. This compelling hypothesis is fully borne out by his analysis of essays, fictions and poems of Borges. The presence ofWilliam James in Borges forms the focus of an exchange of articles in the James journal Streams of William James. Nubiola (2000) issued a call for further research into the Jamesian influence on Borges; Stephens (2000: 1) responded with a suggestion that two of James essays: Does Consciousness Exist? and A World of Pure Experience are manifest influence upon Borges youthful essay entitled The Nothingness of

In the shadow of William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism

137

Personality. Nubiola (2001) responded with an insightful investigation into the link between Borges and James provided by Macedonio Fernndez, a connection that he explored with great attention in a later article (2005). The only other scholars I have encountered are Stephens (2000: 1), who argues that Borgess literary style is built on, or presupposes, a foundation of Jamesian empiricism, Almeida (2002), who explored the influence of James and Peirce upon Borges, and Bosteels (2007), whose analysis also looks at the influence of Pragmatism upon Borges. Were Fernandes thesis to be published, then this would add great substance to this fascinating area. The stream of influence in the arena of mysticism, however, has been less analysed. Although Giskin pursues a Jamesian reading of Borges fiction, Bez-Rivera (2004) is the only scholar that I have identified to establish the connection between Borges appraisal of his own mystical experience and his reading of William James. Borges, the meticulous reader of William James, did not hesitate to describe his two experiences as mystical whenever urged to speak on it, either by his own initiative or for the insistence of his audience (2004: 85). Bez-Rivera draws on the notion of Borges not as agnostic but as agnosttico, which has its root in the term agnostotesmo, coined by Julin Velarde to properly denote those who, starting from Kant, affirm that God cannot be known, we can only believe in him (2004: 87). This agnosttico aspect of Borges is worthy of further exploration, as it ties in with so much of the Borges scholarship concerning the imminence of a revelation, and it bears particular relevance to Flynns The Quest for God in the work of Borges. William James has defined the landscape of scholarly approaches to mysticism more than any other scholar, and his method of examining the traditions of mysticism from an essentially psychological perspective remains influential. His analysis of mysticism is found primarily the Varieties of Religious Experience (1902) and two little-known essays A Suggestion about Mysticism (1910) and A Pluralistic Mystic (1910). As Fernandes, Nubiola and Stephens argue, Borges inherited a fondness for William James from his father and Macedonio Fernndez, and references to James are scattered amongst his work. He pays particular attention to Varieties, stating to di Giovanni how James seminal volume inspired his own interpretation of mysticism: except for that one strange experience I had, really

138

Chapter Three

I can say very little about mysticism personally, though of course I have studied, I have read my Varieties of Religious Experience, and I have done much reading in the mystics, especially Swedenborg, also Blake (Burgin 1998: 130). Cohen (1973: 81), we recall from the previous chapter, also argues that Borges found the inspiration for the Aleph from a biography of Jakob Bhme, which he found reproduced in James Varieties. James, as we also recall from the previous chapter, set a standard that ensuing scholars would inevitably measure themselves against in the production of discrete defining characteristics. In the absence of a list of the salient characteristics we can work through the Borges obra tales, poems, essays, lectures and interviews and assemble from these varied texts a working theory that Borges applied when considering mysticism. I will hereby list these characteristics, and then, following James model in Varieties, examine them in the light of Borges work in greater detail. Mysticism, according to Borges is: 1) pre-religious 2) original 3) spontaneous 4) revelatory 5) ineffable 6) outside of time 7) transient 8) transformative Whilst not all these aspects are necessarily articulated by William James, nevertheless my hypothesis, as will now be examined, is that Borges understanding of mysticism is inherently influenced by his reading of William James. Pre-religious Borges, as analysed in Chapter One, prized Swedenborgs critique of the institution of the church, and felt that cometi un incmodo error cuando resolvi ajustar sus ideas al marco de los dos Testamentos (2005: 155)

In the shadow of William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism

139

[he made an awkward mistake when he decided to adapt his ideas to the framework of the two Testaments] (1995: 9). I also argued that this is an abiding perspective in the scholarship of Swedenborg. What lies at the heart of Borges position is on the one hand an iconoclastic commendation of rebelliousness and heterodoxy, but on the other a declaration that the experience of the Swedish mystic could have somehow occurred in a pure state that was coloured a posteriori by the embellishment of religious authority. Like his godfather, Emerson, and like his father, Henry James Sr., William James was a close reader of Swedenborg. Although Swedenborg is scarcely mentioned in Varieties, and whilst he did not write about him in the same fashion as Emerson, nevertheless, as Eugene Taylor suggests, James reading of Swedenborg was essential to his discussion of metaphysics, religious experience and mysticism. Taylor, indeed, suggests that the Swedenborgian Doctrine of the Rational and the Doctrine of Use [were] key influences on Charles Peirce as well as William James (2003: 4). Taylor also affirms that: the origin of his philosophy is neither Cartesian, Kantian, nor Hegelian, but rather Swedenborgian and transcendentalist (2003: 5).6 Emerson and William James critiqued the ecclesiastical or church-bound manner of Swedenborg, maintaining that the essence of the mystical experience is transcultural, but that the transmission is both individually and culturally determined.
James had said in the Varieties that religious experience could be understood both in terms of what was generic to all human beings and what was idiosyncratic to the individual. From the generic could be derived an understanding of psychological processes common to all men and women insofar as phenomenological accounts of spiritual experience was concerned. What was idiosyncratic to the individual was an expression of that persons personal beliefs about the ultimate nature of reality, which might or might not have relevance for anyone else except that one person.

This statement is challenged by James scholar Jeremy Carrette, who, having scrutinized the correspondence of James in which he openly distances himself both from his fathers Swedenborgian perspective and from Swedenborg himself, argues that Swedenborg may not have been such a significant influence on James as Taylor indicates (personal discussion).

140

Chapter Three
These beliefs held by the individual over and above what was common to all human beings regarding religious experience James called overbeliefs. (Taylor 2003: 3)

Borges follows the tradition particular to William James and his Transcendentalist forefathers in concentrating not on traditional religion but on the interior religious capacity. This is what Taylor calls the central point of Jamess work: namely, organized religion and personal spiritual experience are substantially different (2003: 2). This perspective, as analysed in Chapter One, is fundamental to Borges reading not only of Swedenborg, but of other writers of the mystical traditions. For example, he suggests that Luis de Len never experienced the poetic revelations that he describes, but merely mimicked the Song of Songs. He argues that Blake, whom he describes as el gran mstico ingls (2005: 216) experienced some tremendous revelations which he then awkwardly framed within his own complex mythologies. In this respect Borges demonstrates the same perspective that he maintains for Swedenborg, not so much that the experience is translated into the textual reproduction, which is inevitable, but that the experience may be fundamentally different from the textual description, as the text demands conformity to certain theological or poetic codes. This would imply that in his readings of Swedenborg and Blake, certain passages shine through their doctrinal embellishments to represent some pure, essential, experience. I would argue, furthermore, that this position of the pre-religious is not to be considered perennialist, but should be seen as pragmatic in the manner that Daniels (2003) describes below as the third, middle, position. Daniels examines the critical position within the scholarship of the mystical experience that may be viewed as perennialist or essentialist; an approach to mysticism that we already encountered with Schopenhauers view that the mystical experience is the prime material of all subsequent religious codes. This position opposes the more modern Constructivist position, which, Daniels argues, sees the mystical experience as being only the product of social and linguistic codes. This particular division is integral to Borges understanding both of the mystical texts that he read and of his own mystical experiences. Daniels writes:

In the shadow of William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism

141

All investigators recognise that there are many varieties of mystical experience. The major debate centres on whether these many forms represent different interpretations or accounts of what is essentially the same experience (or a few basic types of experience) or whether, on the other hand, the experiences themselves are fundamentally different. According to the first, perennialist, view (e.g., Forman, 1998; Huxley, 1947; Smith, 1976; Stace, 1960; Underhill, 1911/1995) people everywhere have the same basic experience(s) but they may interpret and describe them rather differently depending upon the personal, social, cultural and linguistic context. If this view is correct, it makes sense, as Wainwright (1981) has argued, to try to identify the essential cross-cultural characteristics and types of mystical experience (i.e., the characteristics and types that exist prior to any secondary interpretative differences). At the other extreme are the constructivists (e.g., Gimello, 1978, 1983; Katz, 1978) who argue that the experiences themselves (rather than simply their post-hoc interpretations) are profoundly and irrevocably determined by predisposing personal, social, and cultural factors, including religious doctrines and particular forms of spiritual practice. Thus there are, according to Katz (1978), no pure or unmediated experiences. For this reason there can be no true common experiential denominators in mysticism. The implication of this second view is that there is, in principle, an indefinite number of different mystical experiences, each one potentially unique to the individual experiencer although there may be identifiable commonalities of experience within particular mystical traditions. (2003 no pagination)

Whilst Daniels identifies this particular polarity in the debate, he recognizes that there is a third avenue of enquiry that seeks the commonality between these positions:
A third, middle, position (e.g., Hick, 1989; Zaehner, 1961) argues that while mystical experiences themselves (rather than just their interpretations) are strongly influenced by their personal, social and cultural contexts, it is possible to recognise certain cross-cultural family resemblances among them (Hick, 1989). For Hick, these family resemblances result because the experiences represent various encounters with the Real (which Hick believes is an actual ontological reality). For this reason, mystical experiences must reflect in an important way the qualities that are manifested in human consciousness by the Real (e.g., they will express love, knowledge, understanding and bliss rather than hatred, ignorance, bigotry and pain). (2003)

This is a pervasive division in the scholarship, and it becomes clear that no assessment of mysticism can lie outside of one of the three positions. I would argue that Borges naturally swings between the twin pole positions

142

Chapter Three

in a manner that would resemble Daniels third way. As Fernandes (2008) identifies, Borges examines nominalist and realist philosophical positions in his fictions, aesthetically evaluating the very dialectic between the Aristotelian and the Platonic that he outlines in Ruiseor de Keats and Flor de Coleridge.7 This exploration of both poles, Fernandes argues, may best be described as pragmatic. The perennialist perspective is associated with hermetic traditions, the Aurea Catena,8 Neoplatonism and western esotericism, all of which were of great interest to Borges; whilst the constructivist may be transcribed into the homonymous schools of thought of the 1960s, linked to semiotics and structuralism, which would uphold an ultimately linguistic construction of experience. Again, this perspective is close to Borges views of fluctuating linguistic systems and nominalist language structures, and certainly has guaranteed his standing in late twentieth century literary theory. Yet this third way would be the one closest to James and to Borges, as it allows for some stable, empirical experience whilst acknowledging the influence of social, literary, cultural, even political systems upon the textual reproduction. Original The temptation is to include the characteristic of originality in the analysis above about the pre-religious aspect of the mystical experience. However, there are subtle distinctions that demand a separate appraisal. Borges wrote in numerous passages that one of the most praiseworthy aspects of Swedenborg was his originality. Swedenborgs radical theology, for example, in which Man, and not God, is the arbiter and judge of whether the dead soul will inhabit heaven or hell, was the most original and innovative of all Swedenborgs visions. He also described Swedenborgs vision

7 8

Funes may be seen as a nominalist in extremis; Lonrot, as the realist. The Golden (or Homeric) Chain in alchemy is the series of great wise men, beginning with Hermes Trismesgitos, which links earth with heaven (Aniela Jaff, in Jung 1989: 189).

In the shadow of William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism

143

of heaven and hell as su concepto originalsimo (2005: 155) [extremely original concept] (1995: 9). When describing Swedenborgs vision of the hermit who through his own asceticism had denied himself the company of the intellectually engaged angels in heaven, Borges employed the term innovacin:
sta es una innovacin de Swedenborg. Porque siempre se ha pensado que la salvacin es de carcter tico. Se entiende que si un hombre es justo, se salva. El reino de los cielos es de los pobres de espritu, etctera. Eso lo comunica Jess. Pero Swedenborg va ms all. Dice que eso no basta, que un hombre tiene que salvarse tambin intelectualmente. l se imagina el cielo, sobre todo, como una serie de conversaciones teolgicas entre los ngeles. Y si un hombre no puede seguir esas conversaciones es indigno del cielo. As, debe vivir solo. Y luego vendr William Blake, que agrega una tercera salvacin. Dice que podemos que tenemos que salvarnos tambin por medio del arte. Blake explica que Cristo tambin fue un artista, ya que no predicaba por medio de palabras sino de parbolas. Y las parbolas son, desde luego, expresiones estticas. Es decir, que la salvacin sera por la inteligencia, por la tica y por el ejercicio del arte. (2005: 199) [This is an innovation of Swedenborg, because it has always been thought that salvation is ethical in its nature. It is understood that if a man is just, he is saved. Blessed are the poor in spirit, for theirs is the Kingdom of Heaven, etc. Jesus proclaimed this. But Swedenborg went further. He writes that this is not enough, that a man must save himself intellectually also. He pictured heaven, above all, as a series of theological conversations amongst angels. And if a man is unable to follow these conversations he is not worthy of heaven, and he must live alone. He was followed by William Blake, who added a third means of salvation. He says that we can that we must save ourselves through Art. Blake explains that Christ was also an artist, as he did not preach through words but through parables. And parables are, clearly, an aesthetic expression. That is to say that salvation is through intelligence, ethics and Art.] (My translation)

What is particularly striking is that Borges judgement itself is both aesthetic and ethical. It is aesthetic because Borges interprets Swedenborgs provocative and curious narrative as inventive and compelling. Just as with any other literary concern of Borges, derivative, imitative texts are of lesser appeal than innovative and original texts. And yet, as Borges was keen to emphasize, mystical texts are no ordinary works of art, seeing that they place curious interpretative demands upon the reader in relation to discerning

144

Chapter Three

between authentic and inauthentic (see Chapter One). It is ethical on two levels: firstly because Swedenborgs position, as Borges identifies, demands of man a seizure of his own destiny and an appeal to develop the critical faculty governed by the intellect. Borges emphasized the moral aspect of this vision: es innegable que la doctrina revelada por Swedenborg es ms moral y ms razonable que la de un misterioso don que se obtiene, casi al azar, a ltima hora. Nos lleva, por lo pronto, al ejercicio de una vida virtuosa (2005: 157) [we must recognize that the doctrine revealed by Swedenborg is more moral and reasonable than one that postulates a mysterious gift gotten, almost by chance, at the eleventh hour. To begin with, it leads us to the practice of virtue in our lives] (1995: 11). Secondly, it is ethical because Borges perceived Swedenborgs challenge to tradition and orthodoxy as itself being a moral declaration of intellectual will and philosophical freedom. Blake also, for Borges, was markedly original, though in Blakes case the originality implied a concomitant difficulty to provide a framework in which to express the visions. Thus the textual reproduction, from an ethical position, becomes the heterodox position of the writer, and is thus integrally related to power. In this sense, one would even argue that Borges view of mysticism is political, in that the mystical authority constitutes a challenge to the hegemony what Staal (1975: 135) would call the superstructure upon which the mystical experience and text are held. This is something Jeremy Carrette pointed out to me in a private conversation in relation to Foucaults analysis of structures of power, and traditions of mystical writers and the texts to which they may or may not have had access. It is reflected in the analysis of Jantzen (1995: 12):
The idea of mysticism is a social construction and that it has been constructed in different ways at different times. Although [] medieval mystics and ecclesiastics did not work with a concept of mysticism they did have strong views about who should count as a mystic, views which changed over the course of time. Furthermore, those changes were linked to changes in patterns of authority and gender relations. [] The current philosophical construction of mysticism is therefore only one in a series of social constructions of mysticism.

It becomes clear through an analysis of Borges many comments on mystical texts that part of their impact for him lay with the challenge to dogma

In the shadow of William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism

145

whether political, social, cultural or theological present throughout time and place. Here we may therefore agree with Bez-Rivera that Borges forthright dismissal of Juan de la Cruz, Teresa de vila and Luis de Len as mystics could be considered a joke (2004: 86), in order to rock the traditionalist and conservative boat. This is a reasonable assertion, as Borges was ever keen to throw incendiary comments at his audience; yet even its jocular dimension reveals a deep desire to locate the mystical experience not only outside of orthodoxy, religious or otherwise, but, in the best of cases, in opposition to it. Thus for Borges Swedenborgs innovacin is an aspect of his rebelliousness and resistance to canonical authority. However, the matter of originality and innovation is not as clear as it may seem. In his desire to paint Swedenborg as a natural mystic endowed with the innate gift of communicating with the spirit world, free from the influence of ecclesiastical dogma, and conforming to Christian teachings only, as it were, as an afterthought, Borges displayed a very selective reading of the Swedish seer. Not one biography of Swedenborg fails to emphasize that the boy was born into a notably religious and church-orientated family, that, as Conan Doyle succinctly writes, Swedenborg sucked in theology with his mothers milk (2005: 96). Whilst the matter of Swedenborgs orthodoxy deserves far greater appraisal than is possible here, the point must be made that the church-bound nature of his texts, something with which Emerson, William James, Conan Doyle and Borges were uncomfortable, is indicative of the religious milieu which he inhabited, at least in his early years. In emphasizing the pre-religious, perennial, mystical aspect of Swedenborg, and in focusing on innovation and originality, Borges appears keen to separate Swedenborg from the theological dimension around which his texts are intimately entwined. Swedenborgs Biblical exegesis cannot be so easily divorced from his voyages to the heavens and from his psychic abilities. To confuse matters further, neither can we argue, as Borges also did, that Swedenborgs heterodox nature was so original and free from the influence of tradition and peers. Borges suggested that La doctrina de las correspondencias me ha llevado a la mencin de la cbala. Que yo sepa o recuerde, nadie ha investigado hasta ahora su ntima afinidad (2005: 159) [The doctrine of correspondences has brought me to mention the Cabala.

146

Chapter Three

No one whom I know of or remember has yet investigated its intimate affinity] (1995: 14). There are two fundamental concerns of which Borges appears unaware: firstly the Kabbalistic environment in which Swedenborg himself moved and the abiding influence upon his thought such traditions imparted; and secondly the long tradition of interest in Swedenborg amongst esoteric societies from his age up to the present. Whilst references to Swedenborgs esoteric and Kabbalistic practices are referred to in many biographical studies, Schuchard (2006) investigates further than any other scholar Swedenborgs connection with the Moravian Chapel in Fetter Lane, London, and his participation in their erotic spiritual practices under the leadership of the eccentric Count Zinzendorf. She explores his association with Kabbalists, Rosicrucian and other esoteric communities across Europe, and paints a picture of a man whose spiritual experiences and religious texts owe much to the influence of such traditions. In the early 1730s, while travelling in eastern Europe, Swedenborg began to search in Neoplatonic, Hermetic and Kabbalistic literature for the means of demonstrating scientifically the reality of the soul. He studied the works of Comenius, the spiritual father of the Moravians, who attempted to portray the soul in human form, using a hieroglyphical signification (2006: 70). Schuchard further explores Swedenborgs alleged relationship with Freemasonry. However, no biographical study fully bears out the supposition that Swedenborg paid more than a passing interest to the Freemasons or any other esoteric community. By nature, rather like Borges, Swedenborg does not seem to have been interested in joining the inner ranks of secretive organizations, and a more reasonable line of analysis would be that the similarity between his spiritual systems and Masonic and Moravian ideas would be the Kabbalistic and Neoplatonic influence upon them all. Although Schuchard paints a Swedenborg fully initiated into the inner circles of European Kabbalistic, Rosicrucian and Masonic groups, it appears that this may be more of guilt by association. Talbot (2007) published a stinging refutation of Schuchards thesis, arguing that many of her claims are based upon Swedenborgs geographical proximity to such circles. Talbot cites numerous other scholars over the past two centuries who have investigated the Kabbalistic claims, and suggests that

In the shadow of William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism

147

Swedenborg was either merely curious, or was even unsympathetic to Kabbalistic thought. Citing Antn Pacheco (who also wrote about Borges reading of Swedenborg), Talbot suggests that the similarities between Swedenborgs biblical exegesis and Kabbalistic biblical scholarship does not necessarily mean that they are related: The phenomenology of interpreting the Bible or the Quran according to visionary experiences might be common to Swedenborg, Kabbalists, and Muslim mystics, but, as Pacheco points out, it does not necessarily imply direct borrowing between any of them (Talbot 2007: 187). What is particularly striking about Talbots critique of Schuchard is that amongst the many areas in which he feels she has misinterpreted the biographies of Swedenborg he feels in particular that she has misinterpreted Swedenborgs writings themselves. Her biography of Swedenborg is based on selections from Toksvigs and Whites biographies (sometimes misinterpreted), each of which have their own prejudices and biases, and she rarely discusses the firsthand sources behind their interpretations (2007: 204). Herein lies the most splendid of misreadings that would have delighted Borges: Talbot argues that Schuchard takes Swedenborgs erotic texts to be descriptions of this world, when Talbot argues that they are descriptions of the next one:
On a positive note, Schuchard does seem to have documented contemporary accounts of antinomian sexual practices on the part of some Moravians and Jews, which could illustrate accounts in the Spiritual Diary or Spiritual Experiences. However, unlike Schuchard, I think that the vast majority of these, and probably all of them, occurred or were presented to Swedenborg in his travels in the next world, not this one. (2007: 206)

Only in the Swedenborg scholarship could such confusion between mundane and celestial descriptions occur!9
9 Continuing this extraordinary dichotomy whereby Swedenborgs spiritual experiences may be confused with his physical experiences, a similar confusion may also be found in Emersons analysis of Swedenborg. According to Emerson, Swedenborg predicted the discovery of Uranus: It seems that he anticipated much science of the nineteenth century; anticipated, in astronomy, the discovery of the seventh planet

148

Chapter Three

Of greater importance is the influence that Swedenborgs writings had on many streams of esoteric thought, from Freemasonry to Theosophy, after his death. Of this matter, Garrett (1984) recounts Swedenborgs prominent position amongst, in particular, Kabbalistic and Masonic sects:
On the continent, in places as diverse as Paris, Avignon, St. Petersburg, and Stockholm, Swedenborgs imagery was absorbed into the rituals of occultist freemasonry by individuals who recognized its affinity with alchemical and cabalistic conceptions of spiritual reality. [] Throughout Europe, those who dabbled in alchemy, cabalism, and Mesmerism found in Swedenborgs spiritual experiences one more confirmation of the existence of truths beyond the reach of the five senses. Many of them were Freemasons, associated with the various occultist and mystical lodges that had sprung up in the eighteenth century. (Garrett 1984: 70 & 74)

Bergquist (2002: 98) similarly acknowledges that the Kabbalistic aspect of Swedenborg was discussed amongst the Eranos Circle, a group of existentially oriented philosophers, theologians, psychologists, linguists and historians who regularly met in Ascona in Switzerland bringing scholars like C G Jung, Henry Corbin, Mircea Eliade, Ernst Benz and Gershom Scholem together. Borges stated on numerous occasions that his understanding of the Kabbalah derived from Scholem, whom he once met on a trip to Israel. Therefore it is possible that Borges was aware that other scholars had pursued this angle. In sum, therefore, Borges presented a curiously nave position when suggesting that he was the first to pursue the connection between Swedenborgs doctrine of correspondence and the Kabbalah. The scholarship in this area is large.

[Uranus], but, unhappily, not also of the eighth [Neptune] (2003: 10). I have not found anyone aside from Emerson claim this, so it could be that Emerson was mistaking Swedenborgs scientific statements with a visionary one. Swedenborg, after all, did communicate in visions with inhabitants of other planets. It would be astonishing indeed if Swedenborg described the planets Uranus and Neptune in a manner that would tally with their descriptions by Herschel (Uranus) and Le Verrier and Adams (Neptune).

In the shadow of William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism

149

Spontaneous I have found no indication that Borges was familiar with the branch of the scholarship of mysticism concerning psychedelics and the supposed dangers of electing what Indian guru Meher Baba (1966) condemned as short-cuts to the divine, or what Huxley (1954: 59) called gratuitous grace. That he was familiar with Huxley is certain from his reviews of Huxleys works; that he engaged with the arguments put forth in The Doors of Perception (1954) and Heaven and Hell (1956) is less certain. Nevertheless this is an integral aspect of the scholarship of mysticism, originating a century before James in both scientific and Romantic literature, and reaching its apogee in the 1960s (see Jay 2000, Doblin 1991, Rowlandson 2013). Borges misgivings of subversive social movements in the 1960s and his self-proclaimed conservatism in his later decades would imply a rejection of any proposals that mystical consciousness may be experienced through the ingestion of psychoactive substances. Yet without encountering any specific declaration on the matter, we can nevertheless conclude that Borges would posit that such activities cannot constitute genuine mystical experience, as he indicated that the mystical state is spontaneous and unmediated. Describing his timeless moment, Borges often suggested that the experience was some manner of divine gift: I had that experience, and I had it twice over, and maybe it will be granted me to have it one more time before I die (Barnstone 1982: 1011). He made no suggestion that the experience was in any way inspired by the subject matter of his reading material, nor the consequence of his meditative, trance-inducing strolls; rather that the experience was somehow granted to him. When he suggested that el fin [de El Congreso] quiere elevarse, sin duda en vano, a los xtasis de Chesterton o de John Bunyan. No he merecido nunca semejante revelacin, pero he procurado soarla (1989: 72) [its end tries, doubtless in vain, to match the ecstasies of Chesterton and John Bunyan. I have never been worthy of such a revelation, but I managed to dream one up] (1979: 93), this would imply an extrinsic, perhaps divine, agency that judges whether an individual may or may not experience mystical consciousness. Borges likewise emphasized that the first profound mystical experience of Swedenborg came upon him utterly unbidden. Despite the fact that Lo

150

Chapter Three

precedieron sueos, plegarias, perodos de incertidumbre y de ayuno y, lo que es harto ms singular, de aplicada labor cientfica y filosfica (2005: 154) [the experience was preceded by dreams, prayers, periods of fasting, and much more surprisingly by diligent scientific and philosophical work] (1995: 6), the appearance of the phantom being that bespoke the initiation of the ensuing decades of mystical encounters was wholly a matter of divine grace, unwilled by Swedenborg. Indeed Borges referred to Swedenborg during this episode as el elegido (2005: 154) [the chosen one] (1995: 6), an image that suggests godly agency beyond Swedenborg. He also referred to Swedenborgs London as la ciudad en que Dios le haba encomendado una noche la misin que lo hara nico entre los hombres (2005: 160) [the city in which God had one night entrusted to him the mission that would make him unique among men] (1995: 15). Likewise, when comparing Swedenborg with Dante, Borges emphasized that owing to the length of Dantes vision, it must have been not the product of grace, but of his own poetic faith; it was, accordingly, self-willed: I think that his vision was voluntary. His vision was the result of his poetic faith (Alifano 1984: 95). Although Staal (1975) and Zaehner (1961) identify that there are many complications in the correlation of western, Christian, mystical traditions and eastern traditions, whether Hindu, Buddhist, Tao or Zen, nevertheless many scholars have noted affinities in the experience of practitioners across these traditions. Borges wrote extensively about Buddhism, and, like Suzuki, perceived the similarities between the meditative, non-rational aspect of Zen and aspects of western mysticism. In particular, Borges indicated that whilst the Zen practitioner may engage in many years of arduous training, the moment of sudden enlightenment satori arrives unbidden and unannounced: En la zen se ha descubierto un procedimiento para llegar a la iluminacin. Slo sirve despus de aos de meditacin. Se llega bruscamente; no se trata de una serie de silogismos. Uno debe intuir de pronto la verdad. El procedimiento se llama satori y consiste en un hecho brusco, que est ms all de la lgica (1989: 2512) [In Zen they have discovered a procedure to reach illumination. It only works after years of meditation. It arrives suddenly: it is not the product of a series of syllogisms. One must suddenly intuit the truth. The process is called satori, and it consists of a

In the shadow of William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism

151

sudden event that is beyond logic] (1984: 72). The mystical experience, therefore, in its brief and rare occurrence for Borges, and in its repeated and sustained occurrences for Swedenborg, is not to be considered the result of will or conscious desire, but as grace of the divine. Revelatory The matter of revelation is intimately associated with James category of noetic, but there is a slight variance of meaning. The revelation that Borges would suggest is possible in the mystical experience is not only noetic but is a revelation of matters that are beyond the scope of our normal conscious understanding. In this respect mystics, according to Borges, are privy to matters that non-mystics (the vast majority of us) are only able to comprehend second-hand. This is thus the most important of the many categories, as it is intimately tied into philosophical, religious and spiritual speculations about death. It is also intimately tied to the category outlined above about divine grace. To begin with, one must evaluate the state of unknowing in which, in Borges universe, it is our lot to be imprisoned. The labyrinth, as analysed in so many critical studies of Borges work, is the abiding symbol for this state of inhabiting a universe whose meaning we are forever in ignorance. Mazes are to be explained by the fact that I live in a wonderful world. I mean, I am baffled all the time by things. I am astonished at things (Barnstone 1982: 36).10 Perhaps one of the closest affinities with Schopenhauers thought is the absence of divine purpose of any knowable telos. As such we are all governed by the impulsive will which drives us ever onwards towards no known place. Just as Schopenhauer rejected Schelling and Hegels hope for eventual harmony and reconciliation, so we see in Borges the absence of a knowable end, but the recognition of a will that drives us onwards. During life, as exemplified by the rapt conclusion of Undr, a moment of

10

I think of the world as a riddle. And the one beautiful thing about it is that it cant be solved (Barnstone 1982: 8).

152

Chapter Three

ecstatic revelation is in relation to the here and now, that a m tambin la vida me dio todo (1989: 51) [life gave me everything as well] (1979: 63). This is no revelation of divine purpose but only that the mystery itself may be a source of wonder and joy. However, those mystic few Swedenborg, the Kabbalists may receive illumination that transcends the mundane and through which they understand aspects both of human purpose and the future of the soul after death. Di Giovanni thus struck at the core of the problem when he asked Borges Do you see mysticism as a way out of the maze? Borges replied: For all I know, mysticism is the only way; but my gods, whoever they may be, have not allowed me that particular way (Burgin 1998: 129, emphasis added). It would appear to Borges that divine grace reveals answers to these mysteries to the mystics. Those less fortunate, like Borges, are trapped between disbelief and cynicism and a sense that the mystical texts may be bearers of truth. However, seeing as the revelation occurred to the mystic and not to the reader, the reader must go on trust if he is to presume the text to be truthful. As such, Borges read Plato, and consequently Socrates, in order to appraise the condition of the soul after death. Anoche no sal despus de comer y rele, para comprender estas cosas, la ltima enseanza que Platn pone en boca de su maestro. Le que el alma puede huir cuando muere la carne (1974: 790) [Last night I stayed in after dinner and reread, in order to understand these things, the last teaching Plato put in his masters mouth. I read that the soul may escape when the f lesh dies] (1970: 32). Borges similarly speaks to his dead friend not knowing if his words will be heard: No s si todava eres alguien, no s si ests oyndome (1989: 466) [I do not know if you are still someone, if you are hearing me] (my translation). A 1940 review of J.W. Dunne concludes with Borges sublime sharing of Dunnes ultimate thesis on time. [Dunne] nos asegura que despus de la muerte aprenderemos el manejo feliz de la eternidad. Recobraremos todos los instantes de nuestra vida y los combinaremos como nos plazca. Dios y nuestros amigos y Shakespeare colaborarn con nosotros (2005: 564) [Dunne assures us that in death we shall finally learn how to handle eternity. We shall recover all the moments of our lives and combine them as we please. God and our friends and Shakespeare will collaborate with us] (2000: 219). He cannot deny the possibility of the immortality of the

In the shadow of William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism

153

soul, something that appears in so many of his poems, yet he cannot accept it unconditionally. Likewise, and especially in his later poetry, Borges presents death and mystical revelation through a Platonic perspective as the possibility that the true nature of things will be revealed. In the poem The Unending Rose (from La Rosa Profunda) the blind, old, and desert-battered Attar of Nishapur caresses a rose and lovingly lists its qualities. He wistfully imagines the eternal Rose Que el Seor mostrar a mis ojos muertos (1993: 465) [the Lord will show my dead eyes] (Alifano 1984: 137). The poem Elogio de la sombra concludes with the poignant hope that the poets forthcoming death will be the revelation of his true identity: Llego a mi centro, / a mi lgebra y mi clave, / a mi espejo. / Pronto sabr quin soy (1975a: 126) [I reach my center, / my algebra and my key, / my mirror. / Soon I shall know who I am] (1975a: 127). Borges ceaseless search for meaning, though, compelled him to acknowledge that textual descriptions of the mystics cannot, despite the best powers of imagination, constitute true knowledge or experience. As such the lucid prose of Swedenborg, in which he reveals his vision and experience of the otherworld, cannot be construed as empirical proof. Indeed a further aspect of the Borges obra suggests that even in death, and even with the possibility of the souls survival, the solution to the riddle of existence will not be forthcoming. Death may be neither oblivion and annihilation nor revelation of divine purpose. It may be simply another area of ignorance, and consequently the dead may be no nearer illumination than the living. Jung found the souls of the dead to be keen for human contact as their own knowledge was lacking, describing in the opening lines of Seven Sermons to the Dead how the dead came seeking him as they remained frustrated by ignorance.11 Swedenborg found dead wandering aimlessly
11 Around five oclock in the afternoon on Sunday the front doorbell began ringing frantically. It was a bright summer day; the two maids were in the kitchen, from which the open square outside the front door could be seen. Everyone immediately looked to see who was there, but there was no one in sight. I was sitting near the doorbell, and not only heard it but saw it moving. We all simply stared at one another. The atmosphere was thick, believe me! Then I knew that something had to happen. The

154

Chapter Three

around unable to grasp anything. He also describes the angels as engaging in constant debates and discussions. If death were revelation, then the dead and the angels would have nothing to discuss in the theological disputes that Swedenborg observed in heaven, unless it were simply to pass the time. Many psychopomps throughout the ages have had precisely this role in leading the confused dead into the further realms of the afterlife; indeed Borges himself writes in Atlas that he was wary of revealing to Hayde Lange that she was dead for fear that it would be rude. Furthermore, if death did constitute revelation, then the many channels of communication between the living and the dead would, at some stage, have transmitted this knowledge. This, Borges notes, has not happened. Hence we have this predicament built up in the poem Ajedrez [Chess]. The chess pieces are unaware that their fate is determined by the hands of the players; yet even so the players are unaware of the hand of God controlling them; yet even so God is unaware of the hand of a further god and so on. This god, therefore, could become aware of the contingent nature of his own existence, could begin to question the nature of his reality, and could, indeed, become burdened with existential angst, as could the further gods along this endless trajectory. One reading of this poem is that existential angst might be an inherent characteristic in Swedenborgs communities of the dead as much as it is amongst living humans. This extensive analysis of the notion of revelation of Borges inevitably reflects the position that I identified in the Introduction between reason and intuition, credulity and scepticism. Yet it also demonstrates the notion of the paradox that James identified in the arena of mysticism: something is learned, yet that something is ineffable. Consequently, how can the mystic transmit the true noetic nature of the experience?

whole house was filled as if there were a crowd present, crammed full of spirits. They were packed deep right up to the door, and the air was so thick it was scarcely possible to breathe. As for myself, I was all a-quiver with the question: For Gods sake, what in the world is this? Then they cried out in chorus, We have come back from Jerusalem where we found not what we sought. That is the beginning of the Septem Sermones ( Jung 1989: 1901).

In the shadow of William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism

155

Ineffable Ineffability, as already mentioned, is a thorny question. Borges repeatedly discussed the ability of language to operate through reference to a consensual experience: In my life I only had two mystical experiences and I cant tell them because what happened is not to be put in words, since words, after all, stand for a shared experience. And if you have not had the experience you cant share it as if you were to talk about the taste of coffee and had never tried coffee (Barnstone 1982: 1011). It is noteworthy that the Borges-narrators account of the impossibility to articulate the experience of the Aleph, and Borges description of the difficulty of expressing the timeless moment of Sentirse en muerte, are perfectly in tune with James explanation of his defining characteristic ineffability:
The handiest of the marks by which I classify a state of mind as mystical is negative. The subject of it immediately says that it defies expression, that no adequate report of its contents can be given in words. It follows from this that its quality must be directly experienced; it cannot be imparted or transferred to others. In this peculiarity mystical states are more like states of feeling than like states of intellect. No one can make clear to another who has never had a certain feeling, in what the quality or worth of it consists. One must have musical ears to know the value of a symphony; one must have been in love ones self to understand a lovers state of mind. Lacking the heart or ear, we cannot interpret the musician or the lover justly, and are even likely to consider him weak-minded or absurd. The mystic finds that most of us accord to his experiences an equally incompetent treatment. ( James 1913: 380)

The sense that Borges developed is that the mystical experience is described only in terms that necessarily fail to describe it, and hence Para sugerir la inefable unin del alma del hombre con la divinidad, los sufes del Islam se vieron obligados a recurrir a alegoras prodigiosas, a imgenes de rosas, de embriaguez o de amor carnal (2005: 154) [To suggest the ineffable union of mans soul with the divine being, the Sufis of Islam found themselves obliged to resort to prodigious analogies, to images of roses, intoxication, or carnal love] (1995: 7). Not so with Swedenborg, Borges argued, who was fully able to capture the essence of his experience through scholarly Latin. Herein one finds the Jamesian angle of Borges comments, as James

156

Chapter Three

argues that the ineffability of the experience lies not so much with the transmission from experience to text, but from text to reader: The mystic finds that most of us accord to his experiences an equally incompetent treatment ( James 1913: 380 emphasis added). As such, unlike Borges Sufis, it is the reader who is unable to grasp the text rather than the text unable to grasp the mystical moment. As I also suggest earlier, if Borges emphasized the inability of the Sufi poets to represent their experience, this itself implies not so much the ineffable nature of the experience, but the limited vocabulary of the Sufi poets. As such, Swedenborg was unique amongst mystics not for the radicality of his visions, but for his dazzling command of Latin. Despite the best efforts of both James and Borges to present the category of ineffability as definitive, it is clear that many questions remain. Outside of time Time, for Borges, is the essential mystery. There is scarcely an essay, fiction or poem in which Borges did not discuss or illustrate the anomaly that is time; indeed for Borges an experience of the flexibility of time is perhaps the primary constituent of the mystical experience. He described in great detail in Sentirse en muerte that the abiding sense was that of moving outside of time and experiencing eternity. He discussed this matter in interview: Somehow the feeling came over me that I was living beyond time (Barnstone 1982: 1011). Concerning mysticism he stated that Ive had only two experiences of timeless time in eighty years (Barnstone 1982: 73). Barnstone even cites Borges sense of the mystery of time as a chapter heading in Borges at Eighty: Time is the Essential Mystery. This is the chapter in which Borges refers to St Augustines legendary bafflement at the strangeness that is time:
I think that time is the one essential mystery. Other things may be mysterious. Space is unimportant. You can think of a spaceless universe, for example, a universe made of music. We are listeners of course. But as for time, you have the one problem of definition. I remember what Saint Augustine said: What is time? If nobody asks me, I know what it is. If I am asked, I am ignorant, I do not know. I think that the problem of time is the problem. (Barnstone 1982: 111)

In the shadow of William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism

157

We recall that the nature of the vision of the Aleph is both infinite space and infinite time, and thus no distinction is to be made between the past, present and future. He expressed to Biguenet and Whalen that eternity is supposed to be timeless. God or a mystic perceives in one moment all of our yesterdays (Burgin 1998: 212). In this we can understand that the vision of the Aleph was an attempt albeit ironic and parodic to portray such a mystical rapture. The dominant characteristic of the mystical experience was, for Borges, the transcending of mundane time. Writing about Swedenborgs angels in El Libro de los Seres Imaginarios Borges declared that En el Cielo no existe el tiempo (1967: 63) [In Heaven there is no time] (1974: 137). Ayora (1973: 595) identifies a strongly Gnostic aspect to Borges treatment of time, suggesting that Borges views of the circularity of time over linearity constitute of a rejection of the hegemonic Christian worldview, and that Any reader of Borges works will agree that Borges whole being rebels against the power of time as a crucial dimension of reality. He discussed with Burgin the idea of different times. Of different time schemes (Burgin 1998: 39) which he had depicted in New Refutation of Time, and he discussed in the same interview Psychological time, which implies the dimension in which the most synchronistic of Jungs psychic phenomena can occur. This irregular pattern of time, upon consideration, can be considered the mainstay of his entire fictional and poetic work: Hladk experiences a year in a moment of temporal stasis; Menard becomes the seventeenth century Cervantes; the younger and elder Borges bend time to meet each other both in El Encuentro and Veinticinco de agosto, 1983; the players in the poem Truco are plunged into archetypal time through entering the ludic space; and so on. The instances are too numerous to cover and would constitute a critical study in its own right. In addition to other aspects of the mystical experience, therefore, the most profound and recurrent characteristic of the descriptions provided in mystical texts from Plato and Plotinus through to Blake and Xul Solar is this sense of transcending the regular linear pattern of time.

158

Chapter Three

Transient There is a beautiful paradox exposed in this matter oftime and the mystical experience. The mystic, for both James and Borges, experiences a radically altered perspective of time, and yet this vision can only be transient, not persistent. Eternity, in this sense, can only be experienced in an instant. James describes the essence of this transience:
Mystical states cannot be sustained for long. Except in rare instances, half an hour, or at most an hour or two, seems to be the limit beyond which they fade into the light of common day. Often, when faded, their quality can but imperfectly be reproduced in memory; but when they recur it is recognized; and from one recurrence to another it is susceptible of continuous development in what is felt as inner richness and importance. (1913: 381)

We recall Borges assertion that Dantes vision could not have been truly mystical: I dont believe that Dante was a visionary; a vision is something more fleeting, something more ethereal. A vision as prolonged as The Divine Comedy is impossible (Alifano 1984: 95). He also described his own mystical experiences as mystical in part because of their transiency: It may have been a minute or so, it may have been longer. [] Somehow the feeling came over me that I was living beyond time, and I did my best to capture it, but it came and went (Barnstone 1982: 11). Despite the regularity of Swedenborgs visions, Borges likewise emphasized their transiency, examining in Testigo how dreams and daylight visions would occur to Swedenborg in brief and illuminating spells, rarely of any duration. Whilst one may pursue the lasting legacy of the mystical vision James category of noetic the vision itself in both James and Borges assessment is necessarily of a transient nature. Transformative As established, it is clear that Borges own transient, timeless, mystical moments were of such transformative power that they constituted the prime motivation for his abiding fascination with mysticism, the anomalies of

In the shadow of William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism

159

time, exploration of consciousness, studies of religious texts and anomalous human experiences. It is thus particularly important to consider his desire as an octogenarian to spend a sustained period in retreat in Japan in order, precisely, to correlate his own experiences with those engraved in eastern spiritual traditions. That the experience was transformative is one matter; that it constituted a source of knowledge of the structure of reality is of far greater significance. In this respect, one can appraise what for Borges was the epistemological value of mysticism, a perspective that may be aligned closely with James category of noetic quality:
Although so similar to states of feeling, mystical states seem to those who experience them to be also states of knowledge. They are states of insight into depths of truth unplumbed by the discursive intellect. They are illuminations, revelations, full of significance and importance, all inarticulate though they remain; and as a rule they carry with them a curious sense of authority for after-time. ( James 1913: 3801)

The central thesis of James chapter on mysticism in Varieties is that the mystical experience grants the mystic authority in his understanding of reality that stands beyond analytical scrutiny. This, clearly, is the chief rationalist concern with the mystical experience, something present in Kants dismissal of Swedenborgs theological authority in his dense, bewildering and under-studied Dreams of a Spirit-seer, and present in Russells critique of the alleged authority of the mystic. In Borges analysis, Silesius, Swedenborg and Blake gained true insight into the mysteries of existence through the intuitive, experiential pathway of vision. This, he emphasized repeatedly in discussion about Swedenborg, was neither falsehood, madness, delusion nor hallucination, but a perspective on the real as epistemologically valid as any rationalistic discourse. Indeed one senses that for Borges this mode of enquiry into the nature of existence was of greater epistemological worth than any other discourse because, in its pre-religious, perennial nature, it transcends the limitations of orthodox structures of thought, whether, as discussed, philosophical, theological, cultural or political. James concludes his exploration of mysticism with the strikingly pragmatic summary of the authority that the mystical experience confers:

160

Chapter Three
(1) Mystical states, when well developed, usually are, and have the right to be, absolutely authoritative over the individuals to whom they come. (2) No authority emanates from them which should make it a duty for those who stand outside of them to accept their revelations uncritically. (3) They break down the authority of the non-mystical or rationalistic consciousness, based upon the understanding and the senses alone. They show it to be only one kind of consciousness. They open out the possibility of other orders of truth, in which, so far as anything in us vitally responds to them, we may freely continue to have faith. ( James 1913: 4223)12

That Borges perspective is Jamesian is at once evident, although we cannot at this level determine whether James was the prime influence upon Borges in this matter. That James pragmatic conclusion is strikingly Borgesian avant la lettre might also be argued.
12 Once more, then, I repeat that non-mystics are under no obligation to acknowledge in mystical states a superior authority conferred on them by their intrinsic nature. Yet, I repeat once more, the existence of mystical states absolutely overthrows the pretension of non-mystical states to be the sole and ultimate dictators of what we may believe. As a rule, mystical states merely add a supersensuous meaning to the ordinary outward data of consciousness. They are excitements like the emotions of love or ambition, gifts to our spirit by means of which facts already objectively before us fall into a new expressiveness and make a new connection with our active life. They do not contradict these facts as such, or deny anything that our senses have immediately seized. It is the rationalistic critic rather who plays the part of denier in the controversy, and his denials have no strength, for there never can be a state of facts to which new meaning may not truthfully be added, provided the mind ascend to a more enveloping point of view. It must always remain an open question whether mystical states may not possibly be such superior points of view, windows through which the mind looks out upon a more extensive and inclusive world. The difference of the views seen from the different mystical windows need not prevent us from entertaining this supposition. The wider world would in that case prove to have a mixed constitution like that of this world, that is all. It would have its celestial and its infernal regions, its tempting and its saving moments, its valid experiences and its counterfeit ones, just as our world has them; but it would be a wider world all the same. We should have to use its experiences by selecting and subordinating and substituting just as is our custom in this ordinary naturalistic world; we should be liable to error just as we are now; yet the counting in of that wider world of meanings, and the serious dealing with it, might, in spite of all the perplexity, be indispensable stages in our approach to the final fullness of the truth ( James 1913: 4278).

In the shadow of William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism

161

Conclusion
As established in the previous chapter, in addition to the articulation of the defining characteristics of mysticism, which I have now performed for Borges, there is no way that the hierarchical judgement of value of the mystical experience can be divorced from the scholars own theological, moral, ethical, assumptions. One might argue that if a scholar has tabulated the defining criteria for mysticism, then, in order to determine whether a particular figure was or was not a mystic, a simple cross-referencing of the texts/biography against the criteria would suffice to determine the mystical status of that figure. Yet, as I have argued, we are not dealing with a scientific matter of clear classificatory divisions vertebrate/invertebrate, mammal/ reptile but a deeply personal, fluid and mercurial set of determinants that defy rigid categorisation. As such it is inevitable that the personal preferences of the scholars should be immediately influential upon the scholarly investigation, and it is to be expected that no two approaches to mysticism will be in perfect accord. Furthermore, owing to the fluidity of the whole field, one scholar may be able to align a particular poet or religious figure with the defining characteristics of, say, James, whilst another will deny that this figure fits these criteria. This, as established, has been the case in the scholarship of, amongst others, Blake, Emerson, Yeats and Borges. In appraising Borges perspectives on mysticism and mystics, it becomes clear that there is nothing objective that is to say removed from the subject and unbiased by personal will, desire or experience in his views; and neither should there. As such, the evaluation of mysticism is in every sense an evaluation of Borgesian mysticism. Swedenborg, here, is not Swedenborg, but Borges Swedenborg Swedenborges. In his biographical studies of Swedenborg, Borges emphasized those characteristics that were closest to his own philosophical perspectives: the prodigious intellect, choice of literature,13 studious and solitary existence, disdain for orthodoxy, interest
13 Dej buenos hexmetros latinos y la literatura inglesa Spencer, Shakespeare, Cowley, Milton y Dryden le interes por su poder imaginativo (2005: 153) [He wrote good

162

Chapter Three

in original texts over translations, relationship with the Kabbalah, measured and sober prose, etc. J.M. Cohen is the only critic I have encountered to notice the kinship between the figure of Swedenborg depicted in Borges poem Emanuel Swedenborg and Borges himself, arguing that the poem is in some respects a self-portrait of the private Borges, disguised under the name of Emanuel Swedenborg (1973: 95). In the same way, one must suppose that Borges dismissal of Pascal, Luis de Len, Juan de la Cruz and Teresa de vila has less to do with a full evaluation of their supposed mystical attributes, and more in relation to Borges desire to mock sacred cows, upset Catholic traditionalists, and choose his cultural heroes from the northern climes. Thus his love for Swedenborg cannot be separated from his love of Icelandic sagas, Anglo-Saxon poetry and his own Northumberland ancestry. He contrasted Swedenborg both with those mystics one may consider apart from las circunstancias y urgencias que llamamos, nunca sabr por qu, la realidad (2005: 152) [removed from the circumstances and urgencies we call [] reality] (1995: 3), and those characterized by el xtasis del alma arrebatada y enajenada (2005: 153) [the ecstasy of a rapt and fainting soul] (1995: 7). As such, in his few comments about Teresa and the Spaniards, one may suggest that Borges would judge Teresa to be pious, orthodox, ecstatic and removed from worldly concerns. Whilst she may have been both pious and ecstatic, one cannot judge her to be either docile or obedient to church authority, nor anything other than deeply involved in the political ecclesiastical machinations of her time. Thus it would seem that Borges conducted a fairly selective reading of those mystics he contrasted with Swedenborg owing to his own personal affinities and inclinations. A selective reading, though, is inevitable. Borges constructed a narrative in which Swedenborg was only Christian by default i.e. not by intellectual choice whose very experiences were of an order both beyond and superior to the orthodox teachings of his day. This, as discussed, is a familiar feature in the Swedenborg scholarship, as each critic or biographer

Latin hexameters and was interested in English literature Spenser, Shakespeare, Cowley, Milton, and Dryden because of its imaginative power [1995: 5]).

In the shadow of William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism

163

concentrates on those biographical matters most dear to him/herself. Conan Doyle, for example, eschews Swedenborgs theological works in favour of his spirit mediumship. James, like Borges, emphasized the dialectic apparent in Swedenborg between orthopraxy and heteropraxy. Schuchard pays great attention to the erotic and esoteric world in which she portrays Swedenborg as inseparably enmeshed. Her critical reviewer, Talbot, a dedicated Swedenborgian, refutes such erotic claims both with substantial evidence and, it appears, with personal moralistic disgust, and proposes that Swedenborgs piety would have prevented him being drawn into such dubious occult practices. In sum, therefore, it is clear that Borges paid great attention not only to the aesthetic and imaginative nature of mystical texts, but to the ontological and epistemological challenges that the texts engendered. Like James he correlated his own experiences (though not induced by nitrous oxide) with his profound reading of the wide and varied literature, and from this twin reading synthesized a series of defining characteristics of the mystical experience. However, unlike James, Borges claimed to be no theorist or philosopher, and consequently he never articulated these defining characteristics in a simple enumeration. From a reading of his many essays, tales, reviews and interviews, it is possible to establish the theoretical platform from which he based his interpretation of the mystical texts. As I hope to have demonstrated, the figure of William James and his work in Varieties is manifestly present.

Chapter Four

Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges

The Arabians say, that Abul Khair, the mystic, and Abu Ali Seena, the philosopher, conferred together; and, on parting, the philosopher said, All that he sees, I know; and the mystic said, All that he knows, I see. Ralph Waldo Emerson, Representative Men Why was he gazing upwards from the steps of the porch, hearing their shrill twofold cry, watching their flight? For an augury of good or evil? A phrase of Cornelius Agrippa flew through his mind and then there flew hither and thither shapeless thoughts from Swedenborg on the correspondence of birds to things of the intellect and of how the creatures of the air have their knowledge and know their times and seasons because they, unlike man, are in the order of their life and have not perverted that order by reason. James Joyce, A Portrait of the Artist As a Young Man

Ralph Waldo Emerson is a powerful presence in Borges. He is referred to in many essays, interviews, tales and poems. Borges dedicated a sonnet to him and listed him amongst his enumeration of treasures in the poem Elogio de la sombra. He also translated Emersons Representative Men into Spanish. Far too many to list here, the many references to Emerson in Borges works are invariably employed as herald for an exploration of a particular literary or philosophical theme.1 Most importantly and most frequently, Borges

Emerson, lector de los hindes y de Attar, deja el poema Brahma (1974: 251) [Emerson, reader of the Hindus and of Attar, left us the poem Attar] (my translation); Esa misma intuicin de que el universo es una proyeccin de nuestra alma y de que la historia universal est en cada hombre, hizo escribir a Emerson el poema

166

Chapter Four

refers to Emersons notion of the One Book in which all books are written, citing (and translating) Emerson in La Flor de Coleridge: Dirase que una sola persona ha redactado cuantos libros hay en el mundo; tal unidad central hay en ellos que es innegable que son obra de un solo caballero omnisciente (1974: 639) [I am very much struck in literature by the appearance that one person wrote all the books] (1964: 9). It is significant that Borges quotes from this particular essay of Emerson Nominalist and Realist in the very essay in which he presents the historical polarity of nominalists and realists; indeed one can see La Flor de Coleridge in many respects as a condensed edition of Emersons essay.2 Borges was effusive about his own admiration of and debt to Emerson, stating: I like to be indebted to Emerson, one of my heroes (Barnstone 1982: 67), and I greatly admired Emerson (1975b: 717), calling Emerson un caballero y un clsico (2005: 44) [a gentleman and a classic] (my
que se titula History (1974: 679) [That same intuition that the universo is a projection of our soul and that universal history is within every man, compeled Emerson to write the poem entitled History] (my translation). Emerson dijo que una biblioteca es un gabinete mgico en el que hay muchos espritus hechizados (1989: 254) [Emerson said that a library is a magic cabinet full of bewitched spirits] (my translation). Emerson dijo que el lenguaje es poesa fsil (1989: 440) [Emerson said that language is fossil poetry] (my translation). We find this in Borges at Eighty: I remember what Emerson said: language is fossil poetry. He said every word is a metaphor. You can verify that by looking a word up in the dictionary. All words are metaphors or fossil poetry, a fine metaphor itself (Barnstone 1982: 165). Emerson wrote that arguments convince nobody and that it is sufficient to state a truth for it to be accepted (1971b: 26). This line also appears in Borges essay on Swedenborg: A la manera de Emerson y de Walt Whitman, crea que los argumentos no persuaden a nadie y que basta enunciar una verdad para que los interlocutores la acepten (2005: 155) [Like Emerson and Walt Whitman he [Swedenborg] believed that arguments persuade no one and that stating a truth is sufficient for its acceptance by those who hear it (1995: 8)]. In the essay that Borges cites, Nominalist and Realist, Emerson writes: I am very much struck in literature by the appearance, that one person wrote all the books; as if the editor of a journal planted his body of reporters in different parts of the field of action, and relieved some by others from time to time; but there is such equality and identity both of judgment and point of view in the narrative, that it is plainly the work of one all-seeing, all-hearing gentleman (2005: 270).

Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges

167

translation), and praising his intellectual poetry: I love Emerson and I am very fond of his poetry. He is to me the one intellectual poet in any case, the one intellectual poet who has ideas. The others are merely intellectual with no ideas at all. In the case of Emerson he had ideas and was thoroughly a poet (Barnstone 1982: 5). There are many ways of assessing this debt that Borges owes Emerson. To begin with, one can start from the outside and acknowledge the innumerable occasions Borges praises the large body of nineteenth century writers from the East Coast of the US: Literature would not be what it is today had there been no Edgar Allan Poe, no Walt Whitman [] no Herman Melville, no Thoreau, and no Emerson (Barnstone 1982: 5); to whom one would add other of Borges prized authors: Longfellow, Hawthorne, Emily Dickinson (perhaps the greatest lady writer and the greatest poet that America Im thinking of our America also has yet produced (Barnstone 1982: 5)), and, though of a younger generation, William and Henry James.3 All these writers were to a greater or lesser degree influenced by Emerson as the leading figure in a literary, philosophical and social movement known as Transcendentalism. The affinity between Borges and this movement is visible in Borges own description of its history and genesis:
The roots of transcendentalism were multiple: Hindu pantheism, Neoplatonic speculations, the Persian mystics, the visionary theology ofSwedenborg, German idealism, and the writings of Coleridge and Carlyle. It also inherited the ethical preoccupations of the Puritans. Edwards had taught that God can infuse the soul ofthe chosen with a supernatural light; Swedenborg and the cabalists, that the external world is a mirror of the spiritual. Such ideas influenced both the poets and the prose writers of Concord. The immanence of God in the universe was perhaps the central doctrine. Emerson reiterated that there is no being who is not a microcosm, a minuscule universe. The soul of the individual is identified with the soul of the world; physical laws are mingled with moral laws. If God is in every soul, all external authority disappears. All that each man needs is his own profound and secret divinity. Emerson and Thoreau are now the most prominent names in the movement, which also influenced Longfellow, Melville, and Whitman. The most illustrious individual example of the movement was Emerson (18031882). (Borges 1971b: 245)

Mark Twain must also be mentioned, though he was from Missouri.

168

Chapter Four

Quite clearly, noting these influences upon Emerson and his group, and noting the influence ofthese differing streams of philosophical and religious thought upon Borges, one must readily conjecture that Borges membership in the Transcendentalists was only prevented by time and geography.4 Barnstone identifies the Emersonian aspect of Borges, employing a peculiarly problematic judgment of secular mystic:
So, along with the mathematician of time and the cerebral master, intensely passionate and despondent, there is the exquisitely calm and wise man who is reconciled to human limitations, and to a godless world that will forever suggest yet disguise its mystery. There is the Borges of Emersonian transcendence, the secular mystic, and [] there is the man waiting in the ghetto of his earthly blindness, free from the tyranny of metaphor and myth. (Barnstone 2000: 47)

There are many similarities between Borges and Emerson at the level of literary taste, style, poetics, secular religiosity, af finity to mysticism, and a philosophical outlook coloured by Stoicism, Idealism, Puritanism and Americanism.5 The debt that Borges owes to Emersons particular style can

That is, despite the assertion of Holditch: Any attempt to make a case for Borges as a Transcendentalist in the Emersonian sense would be foolish and futile, but what is apparent from the evidence offered above, incomplete as it may be, is the fact that Borges feels for that tall gentleman of Concord both an admiration and an affinity. The value of finding and analyzing such a relationship is the evidence it offers for the value of tradition and the relationship of that tradition to poets and poetry, and the insight which such a study can afford readers to the writings of two great intellectual poets, one of the nineteenth century, one of the present; of two as Borges himself might express it amanuenses of the one great Spirit that connects all literature of the past and present and if human beings continue to read of the future (1986: 206). Borges also attributes his dislike of newspapers to Emerson: Borges: La crucifixin de Cristo fue importante despus, no cuando ocurri. Por eso yo jams he ledo un diario, siguiendo el consejo de Emerson. Sbato: Quin? Borges: Emerson, que recomendaba leer libros, no diarios (Borges & Sbato 2002: 18). [Borges: The crucifixion of Christ was important afterwards, not when it occurred. Thats why I have never read a newspaper, following the advice of Emerson. Sbato: Who? Borges: Emerson, who recommended reading books, not newspapers] (my translation).

Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges

169

be appraised by a comparison of these two passages, the first from Emersons 1841 essay The Transcendentalist, the second from Borges essay on Keats:
What is popularly called Transcendentalism among us, is Idealism. [] As thinkers, mankind have ever divided into two sects, Materialists and Idealists; the first class founding on experience, the second on consciousness; the first class beginning to think from the data of the senses, the second class perceive that the senses are not final, and say, the senses gives us representations of things, but what are the things themselves, they cannot tell. The materialist insists on facts, on history, on the force of circumstances, and the animal wants of man; the idealist on the power of Thought and of Will, on inspiration, on miracle, on individual culture. (Emerson 2005: 98) Coleridge observes that all men are born Aristotelians or Platonists. The latter feel that classes, orders, and genres are realities; the former, that they are generalizations. For the latter, language is nothing but an approximative set of symbols; for the former, it is the map of the universe. The Platonist knows that the universe is somehow a cosmos, an order; that order, for the Aristotelian, can be an error or a fiction of our partial knowledge. Across the latitudes and the epochs, the two immortal antagonists change their name and language: one is Parmenides, Plato, Spinoza, Kant, Francis Bradley; the other, Heraclitus, Aristotle, Locke, Hume, William James. In the arduous schools of the Middle Ages they all invoke Aristotle, the master of human reason (Convivio, IV, 2), but the nominalists are Aristotle; the realists, Plato. The English nominalism of the fourteenth century reappears in the scrupulous English idealism of the eighteenth century; the economy of Occam formula, entia sunt multiplicanda praetor necessitatem, permits or prefigures the no less precise esse est percipi. Men, said Coleridge, are born Aristotelians or Platonists; one can state of the English mind that it as born Aristotelian. For that mind, not abstract concepts but individual ones are real; not the generic nightingale, but concrete nightingales. It is natural, it is perhaps inevitable, that in England the Ode to a Nightingale is not understood correctly. (Borges 1964: 129)6

For ease of comparison I have placed the translation first. Herewith the original: Observa Coleridge que todos los hombres nacen aristotlicos o platnicos. Los ltimos sienten que las clases, los rdenes y los gneros son realidades; los primeros, que son generalizaciones; para stos, el lenguaje no es otra cosa que un aproximativo juego de smbolos; para aquellos es el mapa del universo. El platnico sabe que el universo es de algn modo un cosmos, un orden; ese orden, para el aristotlico, puede ser un error o una ficcin de nuestro conocimiento parcial. A travs de las latitudes y de las pocas, los dos antagonistas inmortales cambian de dialecto y de

170

Chapter Four

For further and more detailed appraisal ofthis influence, see, Christ (1969), Coleman (1972), Goloboff (1977), Holditch (1986). It is Emerson, indeed, whom Coleman refers to as at the heart of Borges Aesthetics (1972: 359). The avenue of enquiry that is of interest to us here, though, is the particular relationship to mysticism, and in particular to Swedenborg, that links Emerson to Borges. Borges suggests further that it was thanks to Emerson that he, as a young man in Geneva, first encountered Swedenborg:
Lo conoc por Emerson. Porque Emerson tiene un libro: Representative Men. Ese libro est escrito un poco a la manera de On Heroes Heroworship and the Heroic In History, de Carlyle, que fue de algn modo su maestro; entonces, l toma distintos tipos humanos. Recuerdo que son: Montaigne o el escptico, Swedenborg o el mstico, Shakespeare o el poeta, Napolen o el hombre del mundo y Goethe o el escritor. Yo comenc leyendo ese libro. Ese libro lo le en Ginebra en el ao 14 5; y luego, mi padre tena un ejemplar de Heaven and Hell, Caelo et Inferno; l lo tena en una edicin de la Everymans Library. Bien, yo le ese libro y encargu a Inglaterra los otros tres publicados por la misma editorial. Publicaron cuatro libros de Swedenborg de acuerdo con la Sociedad Swedenborg de Londres. Y luego en francs conozco solamente una versin de Caelo et lnferno. Swedenborg fue a Inglaterra porque quera conocer a Newton, y finalmente no pudo lograrlo, qu raro, eh? Yo he hablado mucho sobre Swedenborg con el pintor y mstico argentino Xul Solar, yo era muy amigo de Xul, iba a casa de l en la calle Laprida 1214, y leamos a Swedenborg, leamos a Blake, leamos a los poetas alemanes, leamos al poeta ingls Swinburne y muchos otros textos. (Wildner 1991)

nombre: uno es Parmnides, Platn, Spinoza, Kant, Francis Bradley; el otro, Herclito, Aristteles, Locke, Hume, William James. En las arduas escuelas de la Edad Media, todos invocan a Aristteles, maestro de la humana razn (Convivio IV 2), pero los nominalistas son Aristteles; los realistas Platn. El nominalismo ingls del siglo xiv resurge en el escrupuloso idealismo ingls del siglo xvii; la economa de la frmula de Occam, entia non sunt multiplicanda, praeter necessitatem permite o prefigura el no menos taxativo esse est percipi. Los hombres, dijo Coleridge, nacen aristotlicos o platnicos; de la mente inglesa cabe afirmar que naci aristotlica. Lo real, para esa mente, no son los conceptos abstractos, sino los individuos; no el ruiseor genrico, sino los ruiseores concretos. Es natural, es acaso inevitable, que en Inglaterra no sea comprendida rectamente la Oda a un ruiseor (1974: 71819).

Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges

171

[I encountered Swedenborg through Emerson, through his Representative men, a book written somewhat in the style of On Heroes and Hero Worship and the Heroic in History by Carlyle, who was in some sense his master. Emerson, as such, used the model of distinct human types. I remember who they were: Montaigne or the Sceptic, Swedenborg or the Mystic, Shakespeare or the Poet, Napoleon or the Man of the World, and Goethe or the Writer. I began to read this book in Geneva in 1914 or 15. Later my father had a copy of Heaven and Hell (Caelo et Inferno) in the edition of Everymans Library. Well, I read this book and ordered from England the other three of his works published by the same publisher. They published four Swedenborg works in collaboration with the Swedenborg Society in London. In French I know of only one edition of Caelo et Inferno. Swedenborg went to England because he wanted to meet Newton, and yet in the end he never did meet him. Strange, eh? I have spoken on many occasions about Swedenborg with the Argentine painter and mystic Xul Solar, who was a good friend of mine. I would go to his house on Calle Laprida 1214 and we would read Swedenborg, we would read Blake, we would read the German poets, we would read the English poet Swinburne and many other texts.] (My translation)

McNeilly, in the introduction to Emerson on Swedenborg: introducing the mystic, perceived the legacy of Emersons essay on Borges: Jorge Luis Borges, some 50 years later, indicated its continued importance by utilising its premise as a counterpoint for his own essay on Swedenborg (Emerson 2003: viii). McNeilly refers to Emersons Representative Men, which Borges translated and whose centrepiece, for Borges, was the essay on Swedenborg. The particular premise is not specified, but as we shall now analyse, Emersons essay served as something of a blueprint for Borges biographical essay of Swedenborg, Testigo de lo invisible; indeed Borges pays respects to Emersons essay in the opening lines: En su admirable conferencia de 1845 Ralph Waldo Emerson eligi a Emanuel Swedenborg como prototipo del mstico (2005: 152) [In his famous lecture of 1845, Ralph Waldo Emerson cited Emanuel Swedenborg as a classic example of the mystic] (1995: 3). Borges also referred elsewhere to Emersons essay as aquella esplndida conferencia que dio Emerson (2005: 201) [that splendid address that Emerson delivered] (my translation). What is of crucial concern in charting the trajectory of influence is that both Emerson and Borges based much of their overall principles of mysticism and mystics on their reading ofSwedenborg, and thus their respective essays constitute their

172

Chapter Four

essential theoretical model of the enigmatic phenomenon. The influence of Emerson on Borges thus becomes a determining factor in Borges understanding of mysticism.

Emerson and Borges on Swedenborg


It is important to stress the impact that Swedenborg had on Emerson and his companions, many of whom as we have seen, were favourite authors of Borges. Colin Wilson (1995: 90) considers the reasons behind this, examining the difficulty of those nineteenth century writers who were sceptical of the church yet profoundly religious:
Swedenborg belonged to an age of faith, when the majority of people believed in angels and devils; now, the new German critics insisted that the Bible was merely a piece of imaginative fiction, and that Jesus never existed. Intellectual men began to look back on the age of faith with nostalgia. Many of them like Carlyle, Tennyson, Emerson, Melville were men of religious feelings who were totally unable to accept traditional Christianity; they felt stranded in an emotional wasteland.

Wilsons comments are strangely reminiscent of so many of the descriptions of Borges: mistrustful of orthodoxy whether religious, political or even literary yet invested with an intense respect for the numinous. Emersons essay on Swedenborg was delivered as a series of public lectures; he only submitted the manuscript for publication a number of years later. This also is reminiscent of Borges, who delivered a series of lectures on Swedenborg, most famously at the University of Belgrano, Buenos Aires. In both cases, furthermore, their essays are biographical sketches with interpolated philosophical commentaries. Both Emerson and Borges wrote short poems on Swedenborg which were included alongside the essays in later publications. There are striking similarities in the poems, not least their peculiarly bombastic and unemotive style, what Borges would praise in Emerson as intellectual. Note, for example, Emersons line: In spirit-worlds he trod alone, / But walked the

Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges

173

earth unmarked, unknown, and Borges: Ms alto que los otros, caminaba/ Aquel hombre lejano entre los hombres [Taller than the others, this man/ Walked among them, at a distance]. Or Emersons line: Through snows above, mines underground, / The inks of Erebus he found, and Borges: Lo que no ven los otros terrenales: / La ardiente geometra, el cristalino / Laberinto de Dios y el remolino / Srdido de los goces infernales. [That which earthly eyes do not see: / The fierce geometry, the crystal / Labyrinth of God and the sordid / Milling of infernal delights]. That Borges found inspiration for his laudatory sonnet in Emersons verse is at once evident. There is much to compare between the two essays, and there are many identifiable hooks that link the two. Borges, for example, mimics Emerson in the equation of Swedenborgs voyages to the otherworld with his Viking heritage and the legacy of epic voyages. Emerson writes that Swedenborg laboured with the heart and strength of the rudest Viking that his rough Sweden ever sent to battle (2003: 15). Borges writes: No one was less like a monk than that sanguine Scandinavian who went much farther than Erik the Red (1995: 3).7 Emerson writes: This man, who appeared to his contemporaries a visionary, and elixir of moonbeams, no doubt led the most real life of any man then in the world (2003: 7).8 Borges writes: The word [mystic] runs the risk of suggesting a man apart [] No one is less like that image than Emanuel Swedenborg. [] No one accepted life more fully, no one investigated it with such passion, with the same intellectual love, or with such impatience to understand it (1995: 3).9 Emerson writes: Having adopted the belief that certain books of the Old and New Testaments were

7 8 9

Nadie ms distinto de un monje que ese escandinavo sanguneo, que fue mucho ms lejos que Enrico el Rojo (2005: 152). Borges repeats this line of Emersons in the lecture Emanuel Swedenborg (2005: 195). Esta palabra, aunque justsima, corre el albur de sugerir un hombre lateral, un hombre que instintivamente se aparta de las circunstancias y urgencias que llamamos, nunca sabr por qu, la realidad. Nadie menos parecido a esa imagen que Emanuel Swedenborg, que recorri este mundo y los otros, lcido y laborioso. Nadie acept la vida con mayor plenitud, nadie la investig con igual pasin, con idntico amor intelectual y con tanta impaciencia de conocerla (2005: 152).

174

Chapter Four

exact allegories, or written in the angelic and ecstatic mode, he employed his remaining years in extricating from the literal, the universal sense (2003: 29). Borges writes: it was thought that the lord had written two books, one of which we call the Bible and the other of which we call the universe. [] Swedenborg began with the exegesis of the first (1995: 14).10 Whilst we may suggest that Borges owes much of his essay to Emerson, it is of greater importance to scrutinize the essential concepts of mysticism that derived from their studies of Swedenborg and which they presented in their essays. Both Emerson and Borges recognized that the Doctrine of Correspondences was at the heart of Swedenborgs mystical theology. However, neither was comfortable either with the dazzling complexity of such a system, nor with the implicit reduction ofhuman existence into mere functional modules of a divine matrix. Emerson, in particular, criticized this doctrine as being arbitrary yet harrowingly deterministic and at odds with the inherent fluidity of nature:
This design of exhibiting such correspondences, which, if adequately executed, would be the poem of the world, in which all history and science would play an essential part, was narrowed and defeated by the exclusively theologic direction which his inquiries took. His perception of nature is not human and universal, but is mystical and Hebraic. He fastens each natural object to a theologic notion: a horse signifies carnal understanding; a tree, perception; the moon, faith; a cat means this; an ostrich, that; an artichoke, this other; and poorly tethers every symbol to a several ecclesiastic sense. The slippery Proteus is not so easily caught. In nature, each individual symbol plays innumerable parts, as each particle of matter circulates in turn through every system. The central identity enables any one symbol to express successively all the qualities and shades of the real being. In the transmission of the heavenly waters, every hose fits every hydrant. Nature avenges herself speedily on the hard pedantry that would chain her waves. She is no literalist. Everything must be taken genially, and we must be at the top of our condition to understand anything rightly. His theological bias thus fatally narrowed his interpretation of nature, and the dictionary of symbols is yet to be written. But the interpreter, whom mankind must still expect, will find no predecessor who has approached so near to the true problem. (2003: 30)

10

Se pens que el Seor haba escrito dos libros, el que denominamos la Biblia y el que denominamos el universo. Interpretarlos era nuestro deber. Swedenborg, lo sospecho, empez por la exgesis del primero (2005: 159).

Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges

175

Emersons ecstatic and romantic vision of nature would clearly differ from Swedenborgs meticulous cataloguing of all aspects of material and spiritual reality, an approach cognate with the Enlightenment spirit of his intellectual powers. Eugene Taylor pays attention to Emersons misgivings on this matter: Emerson rejected as too absolute the so-called Swedenborgian dictionary of correspondences, which required the reader to accept as gospel the exact spiritual meaning Swedenborg himself had placed on each object in nature (1995: 153). Borges, like Emerson, was uneasy with this notion of correspondence, and, like Emerson, his description of it bears something of the absurdity of taxonomy that we famously encounter in El idioma analtico de John Wilkens. Borges continues in Testigo:
Swedenborg [] lleg a elaborar un vasto sistema de significaciones ocultas. Las piedras, por ejemplo, representan las verdades naturales; las piedras preciosas, las verdades espirituales; los astros, el conocimiento divino; el caballo, la recta comprensin de la Escritura, pero tambin su tergiversacin por obra de sofismas; la Abominacin de la Desolacin, la Trinidad; el abismo, Dios o el Infierno; etctera. [] no hay un solo ser en la tierra que no perdure sino por el influjo constante de la divinidad. [] Esa perturbadora sospecha de que somos cifras y smbolos de una criptografa divina, cuyo sentido verdadero ignoramos, abunda en los volmenes de Lon Bloy, y los cabalistas la conocieron. (2005: 159) [Swedenborg [] prepared a vast system of hidden meanings. Stones, for example, represent natural truths; precious stones, spiritual truths; stars, divine knowledge; the horse, a correct understanding of Scripture but also its distortion through sophistry; the abomination of desolation, the Trinity; the abyss, God or hell; etc. [] There is not a single creature on earth that does not owe its continued existence to the constant influence of the Divine Being. [] The disturbing suspicion that we are ciphers and symbols in a divine cryptography whose true meaning we do not know abounds in the volumes of Leon Bloy, and the Jewish Cabalists knew of it.] (1995: 14)

Borges appears to derive from this aspect of correspondences the uncanny notion of predetermination, as this disturbing suspicion might relate to the interplay between divine will and free will, where humans are led to believe that they have free agency in choices, all the while ignorant that

176

Chapter Four

these choices are predetermined by divine plan.11 This is a theme we encounter in many of Borges tales and poems. One might see El muerto [The Dead Man] as allegorising this predicament: Otlora comprende, antes de morir, que desde el principio lo han traicionado, que ha sido condenado a muerte, que le han permitido el amor, el mando y el triunfo, porque ya lo daban por muerto, porque para Bandeira ya estaba muerto (1974: 549) [Otlora realizes, before dying, that he has been betrayed from the start, that he has been sentenced to death that love and command and triumph have been accorded him because his companions already thought of him as a dead man, because to Bandeira he already was a dead man] (1971a: 99). The protagonist only understands at the point of death that his imagined freedom to choose had been an illusion carefully orchestrated by his omniscient chief, Bandeira. In La Biblioteca de Babel, chaos and order are unnervingly harmonized in an infinite, labyrinthine, library in which one book must contain all books. In the oppressive atmosphere of this tale there is infinite choice but all choices are limited by the vertiginous infinite order of the library. Borges comments that in Swedenborgs visionary world the soul is free (unlike in Dantes) but that all souls are nevertheless within the gravitational orbit of God: En la Divina Comedia de Dante esa obra tan hermosa literariamente el libre albedro cesa en el momento de la muerte. Los muertos son condenados por un tribunal y merecen el cielo o el infierno. En cambio, en la obra de Swedenborg nada de eso ocurre. Nos dice que cuando un hombre muere no se da cuenta de que ha muerto, ya que todo lo que lo rodea es igual (2005: 196) [In
11 Need Swedenborgs doctrine of correspondence necessarily equate to predestination? Kathleen Raine would argue that this is cognate with the Hermetic tradition of interrelationship between the heavens and the earth, the subtle paths of communication that connect the spirit world to the material, and not stern paragraphs in the book of destiny: It is the poets and painters task to perfect a language of correspondences the word is Swedenborgs but the concept is Platos and goes back to the famous saying in the Timaeus that the world is a moving image of eternity. Correspondence is the secret of all poetic imagery (2007: 25). Jos Lezama Lima, in his discussion of metaphor, likewise assumed that the poets and painters need to seek this subtle language in order to harmonize the material and spirit forms (see Rowlandson 2007).

Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges

177

Dantes Divine Comedy that beautiful literary work free will ceases upon death. The dead are tried by a tribunal and deserve heaven or hell. None of this occurs in Swedenborgs work. He tells us that when a man dies he is not aware that he has died because everything that surrounds him is the same as before] (my translation). This dimension of free will was another of the significant heterodox claims of Swedenborg, and was one of the litany of accusations (alongside his rejection of the Trinity, his belief that Christ was God on earth, not the son of God, his critique of St Paul, his belief that direct experience of the divine could be achieved without the medium of clergy) that led to his censorship and publication prohibition in his native Sweden: Swedenborg radically departed from the orthodox Christian belief in an individual and final judgment. The spirit, not God, ultimately decided where to spend eternity (McDannell & Lang: 189. See also Bald 2006: 1618).

The excess of influence (Emerson 46)


Emerson, like Borges, perceived in Swedenborg a disquieting yearning to accord his experience of interconnection with these doctrinal traditions: Swedenborg and Behmen [Bhme] both failed by attaching themselves to the Christian symbol, instead of to the moral sentiment, which carries innumerable christianities, humanities, divinities, in its bosom (Emerson: 45). Hurth (2005) examines the degree to which Emerson rejected such schematized visions of nature in both Swedenborg and Bhme: Emerson did not accept the too literal and rapt approach to allegorical truth by mystics like Swedenborg and Bhme, and he incisively criticized that the literary presentations of their mystical visions were too narrow and their symbols too schematic and rigid. They thus established a fixed formula of symbols to render human experience (2005: 335). As discussed in previous chapters, it was Swedenborgs heterodoxy, to the point of heresy, married to his accounts of direct experience of otherworld realities, that particularly

178

Chapter Four

appealed Borges: Swedenborg, como Spinoza o Francis Bacon, fue un pensador por cuenta propia y que cometi un incmodo error cuando resolvi ajustar sus ideas al marco de los dos Testamentos (2005: 155) [Swedenborg, like Spinoza or Francis Bacon, was a thinker in his own right who made an awkward mistake when he decided to adapt his ideas to the framework of the two Testaments] (1995: 9). The full impact of both Emerson and Borges reference to the Viking ancestry is, consequently, striking, as despite Swedenborgs lengthy tomes of scriptural hermeneutics, they considered him the opposite of a theologian. He was an intrepid explorer of other worlds, not a purveyor of scholastic frivolity (Duracin del Infierno). Borges was explicit about this matter, explaining in interview: los msticos, tienden a escribir de un modo vago; l no. La obra de l es, yo no dir prosaica, pero s precisa. Es un poco, como si l hubiera ido a la China, o hubiera ido a la India y describiera lo que ha visto (Wildner 1991) [Mystics tend to write in a vague way. Not Swedenborg. His work is well I wont say prosaic, but I will say precise. It is as if he had gone to China or India, and had described what he had seen] (my translation). His religious arguments, Borges writes, were based upon experience and from a system of morality derived from that experience. Crucially, in Borges judgment, that experience was not mediated by ecclesiastical authority and neither did all of Swedenborgs proclamations conform to orthodoxy. It is, though, a problematic point that both Emerson and Borges raise here, and concerns the boundary between experience and textual reproduction. Where Emerson suggests that Swedenborg was narrowed and defeated by the exclusively theologic direction which his inquiries took, it is unclear whether these inquiries refer to the specific mystical experience (the voyage to heaven and hell), or to the subsequent reflection, interpretation and textual composition of the experience. This is to say, it is unclear whether Emerson is implying that Swedenborgs direct experiences were theologically compromised a priori, which would suggest that he was interpreting his surroundings with adherence to doctrine at the point of experience; or whether his outlandish and original (Borges 1995: 9) experiences were later narrowed and distorted by Swedenborgs conscious desire at the point of reflecting and writing. This is a question that we will find reflected in many different contexts in our study of Borges. The tale is tangled further,

Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges

179

however, when we appreciate that Emerson detects a fictional dimension to Swedenborgs angelic landscapes, based upon Swedenborgs own idea that we project our own will upon the heavenly realm. Emerson, it would appear, criticizes Swedenborgs inability to create interesting, individual, characters. This would appear a purely aesthetic judgment of no ontological import, as Emerson is making a firm assumption about the literary invention that is Swedenborgs account:
The universe, in his poem, suf fers under a magnetic sleep, and only ref lects the mind of the magnetizer. Every thought comes into each mind by influence from a society of spirits that surround it, and into these from a higher society, and so on. All his types mean the same few things. All his figures speak one speech. All his interlocutors Swedenborgize. [] Only when Cicero comes by, our gentle seer sticks a little at saying he talked with Cicero, and, with a touch of human relenting, remarks, one whom it was given me to believe was Cicero; and when the soi disant Roman opens his mouth, Rome and eloquence have ebbed away, it is plain theologic Swedenborg, like the rest. His heavens and hells are dull; fault of want of individualism. (Emerson 2003: 44)

The ontological implications of this statement are profound when we correlate it with other statements of Emerson and Borges about the reality of Swedenborgs visions. If Emerson detects a distinctly Swedenborgian language of the characters then the author of such visions is not God but Swedenborg. Consequently his angels inhabit the same fictional space as H.G. Wells Morlocks, Shakespeares Hamlet or Tolkiens Hobbits. This is the question that concerned us in Chapter One, in which Borges repeatedly separated mystics (When I talk of mystics, I think of Swedenborg, Angelus Silesius, and the Persians also) from non-mystics (Not the Spaniards. I dont think they had any mystical experiences [Barnstone 1982: 11]) based upon, precisely, the non-fictional quality of the mystics texts. We recall that he opined that Dante could not have experienced his vision in verse. This is of crucial concern. Borges argued that Dante, in his letter to Cangrande Della Scala, proposed an allegorical reading ofThe Divine Comedy: Nothing is further from the ultraterrestrial destinations of Swedenborg (1995: 9); they are real, not fictions. Emerson appears to share Borges view about Dante, but here applies the notion to Swedenborg, further emphasising

180

Chapter Four

the a priori nature of Swedenborgs visions and making a brief equation with Dante:
The parish disputes, in the Swedish church, between the friends and foes of Luther and Melancthon, concerning faith alone, and works alone, intrude themselves into his speculations upon the economy of the universe, and of the celestial societies [] He is like Michaelangelo, who, in his frescoes, put the cardinal who had offended him to roast under a mountain of devils; or, like Dante, who avenged, in vindictive melodies, all his private wrongs. (Emerson 2003: 467)

Emersons essay on Swedenborg is significantly longer than Borges. As such, we can perhaps consider Borges brief comment that Swedenborg cometi un incmodo error cuando resolvi ajustar sus ideas al marco de los dos Testamentos (2005: 155) [made an awkward mistake when he decided to adapt his ideas to the framework of the two Testaments] (1995: 9) a synoptic, concise, response to Emersons lengthy diatribe. Emerson, indeed, dwells to a significant degree on a critique of Swedenborgs dense theologisation: The vice of Swedenborgs mind is its theologic determination. Nothing with him has the liberality of universal wisdom, but we are always in a church (2003: 45), a sentiment that is perhaps best summed up by Borges: Los incalculables cielos de Swedenborg estn llenos de amor y de teologa (2005: 158) [The incalculable heavens of Swedenborg are full of love and theology] (1995: 13). Emersons invective culminates in his oft-proclaimed dislike of Swedenborgs passionless tone:
These angels that Swedenborg paints give us no very high idea of their discipline and culture: they are all country parsons; their heaven is a fte champtre, and evangelical picnic, or French distribution of prizes to virtuous peasants. Strange, scholastic, didactic, passionless, bloodless man, who denotes classes of souls as a botanist disposes of a carex, and visits doleful hells as a stratum of chalk or hornblende!12 He has no

12

This is the aspect of Swedenborg that Yeats (1920: 299) famously equated to his work as a mineralogist: He considered heaven and hell and God, the angels, the whole destiny of man, as if he were sitting before a large table in a Government office putting little pieces of mineral ore into small square boxes for an assistant to pack away in drawers, and that Garrett (1984: 68) describes as: an odd, dry precision to his descriptions of Heaven that suggests the engineer far more than the mystic.

Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges

181

sympathy. He goes up and down the world of men, a modern Rhadamanthus in goldheaded cane and peruke, and with nonchalance, and the air of a referee, distributes souls. [] Behmen is healthily and beautifully wise, notwithstanding the mystical narrowness and incommunicableness. Swedenborg is disagreeably wise, and, with all his accumulated gifts, paralyzes and repels. (2003: 53)

Borges, however, offers a slightly more sympathetic appraisal of the persistent biblical, theological tone of Swedenborgs many volumes, suggesting that, despite the unfortunate mistake of adapting his visions to doctrine, Swedenborg would inevitably have experienced such an ecclesiastical vision of the otherworld reality, as this was his vision of the mundane reality also. [] el padre de l era obispo, obispo evanglico, luterano. El tiene que haberse criado en un ambiente muy piadoso. [] l pensaba naturalmente en el espritu de la Biblia (Wildner 1991) [His father was an evangelical Lutheran bishop. He must have been brought up in a very pious environment. [] He must have considered the spirit ofthe Bible quite naturally] (my translation).13 In this respect, Borges would appear more forgiving of Swedenborgs ecclesiastical tone than Emerson; and just as Emerson and Borges were troubled by the presence of orthodoxy in Swedenborg, Emerson was greater troubled by the translation of Swedenborgs visions into doctrine: These books should be used with caution. It is dangerous to sculpture these evanescing images of thought. True in transition, they become false if fixed. It requires, for his just apprehension, almost a genius equal to his own. But when his visions become the stereotyped language of multitudes of persons, of all degrees of age and capacity, they are perverted (2003: 43). Emerson railed against the perversion of Swedenborgs evanescing images ofthought into something quotidian and mundane, arguing that this would remove the mystery and the moral truth of Swedenborgs texts. This again is a sentiment fully visible with Borges, who paid close attention to the original experiences and unorthodox theology of Swedenborg, but was at no stage prepared to accept the constellation of such accounts into doctrine or articles offaith. For both Emerson and Borges, this predicament
13 This is similar to Conan Doyles comment that Swedenborg sucked in theology with his mothers milk (2005: 96).

182

Chapter Four

was at the heart of their strained relationships with orthodox religion: mystery lies at the heart of the religious experience, and yet the conversion of such mystery into matters of faith is the erection of a rigid belief system bereft of the transformative power of mystery.

Intelligence over piety


As Quinn (1950) identifies, Emerson placed the intellect in high esteem, and was vexed by a very good woman with much light in her heart but no equal light in her mind. Well I weary presently of these quiet souls if they cannot rouse me with a thought (in Quinn 1950: 402). In another letter, Emerson writes: Strange strange it seems that I should nowhere find that goodly marriage which everywhere I seek of holiness & genius in one mind, which shall be majesty. Goodness will always be suspicious to me & only half goodness until it attains to become sight, and apprehends Chemistry, for example (in Quinn 1950: 403). Such a position would chime immediately with Borges, who enthused at Swedenborg and Blakes praise of the intellect above simple uncritical piety. We recall that Borges writes that for Swedenborg, intelligence is of more worth in heaven than righteousness. Al requisito de ser justo, Swedenborg aade otro, antes no mencionado por ningn telogo: el de ser inteligente (2005: 158) [To the requirement of righteousness, Swedenborg adds another, never before mentioned by any theologian: intelligence] (1995: 13). Emerson likewise prized Swedenborgs dazzling intellect above all righteousness, communion with God or religious fervour. As Quinn suggests, for Emerson, Swedenborg was a kind of inspired scientist. [] Nowhere in this essay does Emerson dwell on Swedenborgs holiness or estimate the degree to which he realized spiritual perfection (1950: 4067). Quinn then concludes that Emersons judgment of mysticism was essentially that of magic, associated not with the striving to perfection (mysticism, in Quinns terms), but with the pursuit of power which this supernatural reality is thought to contain. It is the art

Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges

183

of getting at that power so as to make use of it in the natural world (1950: 401). The mystic, in Quinns analysis, does not crave this power: He is not interested in wielding supernatural force. In his transaction with the supernatural he is seeking only for union with God. It is his instinct to adore what the magician would use (1950: 401). Borges repeatedly emphasized the intellectual aspect of Swedenborg as the very quality that made possible his intrepid exploration and cataloguing of the angelic worlds, indeed he praised Swedenborg as the epitome of intellectual potency:
Yo escrib un prlogo a un libro sobre Swedenborg a instancias del Sr. Spiers, de la Fundacin Swedenborg. Y tengo en proyecto (claro que a mi edad los proyectos son un tanto aleatorios) un libro sobre las tres salvaciones; la primera es la de Cristo, que es de carcter tico; la segunda es la de Swedenborg, que es tica e intelectual; y la tercera es la de Blake, discpulo rebelde de Swedenborg, que es tica, intelectual y esttica, que se basa en las parbolas de Cristo, que l dice que son obras de arte. (Wildner 1991) [I wrote a prologue for a book about Swedenborg upon the request of the Swedenborg Foundation. I have a project in mind about a book of the three salvations: the first is that of Christ, which is ethical in its nature; the second is that of Swedenborg, which is ethical and intellectual; and the third is that ofBlake, rebel disciple of Swedenborg, which is ethical, intellectual and aesthetic, and which is based in Christs parables, which he calls works of art.] (My translation)

There are aspects of the language of Borges essay on Swedenborg that reveal profound admiration for Swedenborgs mighty intellect; indeed his intellect in many respects supersedes his heavenly visions in Borges esteem. No le bastaron las versiones latinas; investig los textos originales en hebreo y en griego (2005: 153) [He always preferred the study of sacred scripture to that of dogmatic theology. Latin translations were not good enough for him; he studied the original texts in Hebrew and Greek] (1995: 5). Borges, as we recall, likewise preferred the study of sacred scripture to that of dogmatic theology, and in many places describes reading Schopenhauer and Kant in the original German so as to appreciate their authentic style. One might conclude, therefore, that on matters of the intellect, Borges indeed, as Lawrence suggests, felt himself a kindred spirit to the Swedish mystic (1995: x).

184

Chapter Four

Emerson and Borges mystics manqus


Emerson is commonly considered a literary critic, poet, philosopher and religious thinker. He is also known sometimes polemically as a mystic. But despite their notorious imprecision, mystic and its related words are often used by the commentators on Emerson. Indeed it may be said that references to Emerson as a mystic are as common in studies of Emerson as they are rare in studies of mysticism (Quinn 1950: 397, original italics). As with the assessment of Borges mystical attributes, the label mystic is applied to Emerson based often on only a scant understanding of the complexity of the term and the disagreements within the scholarship. Similarly, as with Borges and William James, the term may have different tones depending on how it is applied: Emerson the mystic and Emerson the scholar of mysticism. Quinn coherently argues that Emersons use of the term mysticism is itself problematic due to his casual and conflicting use of the term. In particular, Quinn looks at the celebrated passage in Nature almost too well known to need quoting which reads: Standing on the bare ground my head bathed by the blithe air, and uplifted into infinite space all mean egotism vanishes. I become a transparent eyeball; I am nothing; I see all; the currents of the Universal Being circulate through me; I am part or parcel of God. On the face of it, this would appear to demand interpretation as a mystical document (in Quinn 1950: 408). Quinn argues, however, that Emersons ease of expression, his almost glib attitude concerning the mystical state, makes Emersons mysticism, if this be mysticism, sound[s] suspiciously easy here (409), and he questions Emersons relationship with God prior to this description as a means of demonstrating that he had not fulfilled the requisite steps along the spiritual path. Quinn reflects a century of scholarship and biographical studies which scrutinize the poetic and critical works of Emerson and, as with the Borges scholarship, which assert that Emerson was or was not a mystic. Hurth (2005) suggests that the term that was employed to describe Emerson best by his contemporaries was the Yankee Mystic a term which allowed for his radical departure from Christian orthodoxy, and his assimilation of the democratic new

Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges

185

principles of his county at that period in history; a spirit that later informed his godson William James in his depiction of pragmatism: As a Yankee mystic Emerson was a pragmatic mystic to the core (Hurth 2005: 336). Hurth also concisely addresses the central arguments of this controversy over Emersons mystical credentials.
In 1942 Henry B. Parkes launched an aggressive attack on the allegedly mystical features of Emersons thought. According to Parkes, Emersons epiphanies and visionary moments had no biographical basis. He was only a pseudo-mystic who had no true mystical experience. His mysticism was founded on those moments of exhilaration, caused by a feeling of harmony between oneself and the external world, which everyone occasionally experiences. Emersons contemporary critics were ready to label Emerson a mystic, but to them mysticism was mostly a term of reproach and equivalent to misty or occult. (2005: 333)

Parkes essay is vitriolic against both Emerson and any critic foolhardy enough to call him a mystic. This is familiar in the scholarship of mysticism, for example in Zaehners refutation of Huxley, and demonstrates, as I mentioned in Chapter Two, the degree of reliance that many scholars place on one or other of the defining categories of the term mystic and mysticism. In Parkess case mysticism cannot be a common-or-garden sensation of harmony, but is something far more closely aligned to religious orthodoxy. What is visible in Quinns firm assertion is a bias of the work ethic that we encounter with Zaehners rejection of Huxleys gratuitous grace and Meher Babas God in a Pill? Apotheosis does not come cheaply. One cannot take a shortcut to the divine. It is the perennial argument concerning difficult or easy spiritual paths, characterized (and satirized) by Alan Watts division of the easy approach to satori: Beat Zen and the difficult approach: Square Zen (Watts 2006). Quinn qualifies his assertion with a definition of what the true mystic is: For the mystics we know of, in the East as in the West, dedicated years to the spiritual exercises by which they might become united with God. Emerson would have this rare phenomenon take place almost instantaneously. It is obvious that whatever we may call this theory of Emersons, it will hardly do to call it mysticism (1950: 411). Quinn would doubtless reject Watts Beat Zen.

186

Chapter Four

Both Quinn and Hurth evaluate the many scholars who have assessed Emersons works, in particular the famed passage from Nature, and argue that most scholars agree not only on the literary quality of Emersons text, but that the text was inspired by other texts, in particular Bhme: Emerson welcomed Bhme as someone who was taught directly by God through his own intuitions, not by book learning a mystic in the most exact sense (Hurth 2005: 337). Emersons theoretical position concerning mysticism, therefore, is strikingly close to that of Borges in the emphasis on the unmediated mystical vision. Hurth also points out that since Emerson did read the Aurora shortly before the publication of Nature, one may guardedly assume that Bhmes work was a possible influence for his most famous passage. Emerson may also have noticed that Bhme often used the physical eye as a symbol for the communion between soul and God (2005: 339). Whilst this is a position taken by many of the scholars she mentions, Hurth does allow for the originality of experience which was later framed in a style influenced by Bhme: But while on the surface Bhmes descriptions of mystical experience are largely in accord with the mysticism ofthe transparent eye-ball passage, the underlying beliefs and assumptions are quite different, and the Aurora is thus a source for Emerson only in the sense that it provided him with a vocabulary for his own ideas (2005: 339). Quinn, meanwhile, suggests the Jamesian principle of ineffability: As a rule, most mystics find it exceedingly difficult to describe their mystical experiences. Words fail them. But words do not fail Emerson. He, indeed, is almost glib (1950: 409). Quinn goes on to suggest that Emersons language may be borrowed from Plotinus. This needs emphasising, as it is related to the views of Borges concerning Swedenborg and Dantes mystical texts. What emerges, quite ironically, is that an unliterary description of the experience would testify to a failure of language to accommodate the experience, and would thus testify to the experiences ineffability, which would thus testify to its genuine mystical aspect. In brief, therefore, the better the poet, the worse the mystic. As we assessed in Chapter Three, Borges is also polemically described as a mystic, a mystical thinker, an almost-mystic, a non-mystic, etc., and as discussed the term can only have meaningful value if determined according to one or other of the theoretical positions that define mysticism. What is

Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges

187

interesting to note, nevertheless, is that both Emerson and Borges approach Swedenborg with the assumption that his prime mystical experiences may be somehow divorced from his church-bound experiences or from the church-bound textual recounting. As such they both assume a phenomenological experience somehow unculturated and thus antecedent to the cultural-religious embellishments. But this approach to Swedenborg is derived from their own experiences of mystical consciousness which they would both propose as unmediated by doctrine religious, cultural, aesthetic or otherwise. Thus one can perceive with Emerson and Borges a desire to correlate their misgivings of the church with their enthusiasm for the radical experiences of Swedenborg, set against personal unitive experiences. It would appear, furthermore, that this unease of church-bound mysticism also prevented both Emerson and Borges from a more profound reading of the texts of mystical traditions. Quinn describes how Emerson, in truth, knew precious little of the canon of western mysticism: To read Emerson [] is to be struck by the fact that he seems to have known very few of them [mystics], even by repute. He does not refer to such standard instances as those represented by Dionysius the Areopagite, Meister Eckhart, John of Ruysbroek, St Teresa of Avila, St John of the Cross, or Catherine of Siena (1950: 408). It is likewise interesting to note that Borges invests in Swedenborg with a zeal as powerful as Emersons, and yet rarely discusses other canonical mystics, aside from brief mentions of Angelus Silesius and Jakob Bhme, and dismisses Pascal and the Spaniards as not even being mystics. Again, the mark of Emerson is visible on Borges. We can perceive how both Emerson and Borges were keen to evaluate their own mystical experiences (timeless for Borges, transparent eyeball for Emerson) in light of their reading of Swedenborg. Again, the tension visible in Emersons Nature and in Borges Sentirse en muerte is between the experience and the cognitive powers that attempt to seize, conceptualize and recount the experience.

188

Chapter Four

Conclusion
Analysing the cross-currents and intersections of readers of Swedenborg shows a true web of encounters, friendships, correspondences, influences, antagonisms. Delightfully, one can perceive a direct line of figures which links Borges with Swedenborg, and it runs through William James and his godfather, Ralph Waldo Emerson. Emerson, indeed, is a vital link in this chain. Borges was a close and admiring reader of William James, whose psychological works Borges father taught. Macedonio Fernndez, Jorge Guillermo Borges friend, and friend and mentor to Georgie, corresponded with William James.14 William and his brother Henry the novelist were deeply influenced by their father, Henry James Sr. and his fascination with Swedenborg. James pre was close friends with J.J. Garth Wilkinson (after whom he named his third son), chief translator ofSwedenborg and friend of Carlyle, who first introduced Emerson to Swedenborgs works. Wilkinson was friend of C.A. Tulk (Deck 1977: 217). Tulk was friend and correspondent with S.T. Coleridge. Coleridge was friends with De Quincey, who read Swedenborg owing to his friendship with John Clowes.15 Tulk met William Blake in an early congregation of the London New Church,

14 15

Borges discusses this in Autobiographical Essay. Nubiola (2005) explores the veracity of this claim and locates the correspondence. an Anglican clergy [sic] and Swedenborgian preacher who was a good friend and a frequent visitor in the De Quincey household. [] Clowes even lent copies of Swedenborgs works to De Quincey [who] is known to have given Coleridge the works of Boehme years later (Garca 2007: 64) In his translation of Immanuel Kants Abstract of Swedenborgianism, De Quincey found the Kantian framework for interpreting mystical dreams and divine states compelling enough to translate and publish. Kant argues that Swedenborgs prophecies are a product of a disorder in the faculty of sensibility; and that in communicating with spirits, Swedenborg is simply echoing his inner ideas within himself, projecting what is in the mind outward. For Kant, these mystical visions are therefore a form of madness (Garca 2007: 65).

Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges

189

a Swedenborgian sectarian church in Eastcheap.16 Tulk also introduced the elderly Blake to Coleridge.17 Blake was born into a family deeply versed in Swedenborg, and Blake remained a close and often antagonistic reader of Swedenborg throughout his life.18 It is delightful to imagine the young Blake meeting the elderly Swedenborg, and indeed this legend appears in poetic form in H.N. Morris Flaxman, Blake, Coleridge, and other men of genius influenced by Swedenborg (1915: 76): During the first year of his apprenticeship it is probable that on his [Blakes] way to and from work he often met or walked beside the great Emanuel Swedenborg, then an old man of eighty-four. This legend is coherently refuted, however, by David V. Erdman (1953). Blakes mother became interested in Swedenborg initially through the exposure of Swedenborgs works in the at the Fetter Lane Moravian congregation, an Episcopalian denomination active in London in the eighteenth century which she and her first husband (Thomas Armitage) and second husband ( James Blake) attended.19 Swedenborg was for a while a registered attendee. It is possible, therefore, that there was personal contact between Blakes mother and Swedenborg himself.
16 Toward the end of this decade, Blake began to read Swedenborgs works, and in 1789 he attended the First General Conference of the New Church, which was held at Eastcheap from April 13 to 17, 1789. Here we might speculate on a first meeting of Tulk and Blake (Deck 1977: 218). See also Rix 2007. We can then combine this evidence with Crabb Robinsons statement about Blake and Coleridge to conclude that this meeting occurred in 1825 or very early in 1826 (Deck 1977: 224). Blake must early have been acquainted, inasmuch as his father was a dissenter interested in Swedenborg and sympathetic to his teachings if not, like Williams brother Robert, actively associated with a Community (Schorer 1938: 157). From May 1744, Swedenborg lodged with his Moravian friend John Paul Brockmer. Together they attended Moravian services, and Swedenborg became so attracted to Fetter Lane Chapel (to which Blakes mother was later connected) that he considered formal affiliation (Rix 2007: 51). Ankarsj (2009: 32) is more forthcoming in suggesting a personal connection between Blakes mother and Swedenborg: Swedenborgs affiliation with the Moravians [] coincided with the period when Blakes mother Catherine and her first husband Thomas Armitage and Blakes possible uncle John had their most active years in the church. Particularly, Catherine seems to have been a devoted Moravian member at the time.

17 18 19

190

Chapter Four

Should Catherine Blake and Swedenborg not have met, then a path can be traced from Blake to Robert Hindmarsh, one of the original founders of Swedenborgianism and friend of Tulks father, John Augustus Tulk, whose gatherings Blake attended with his friend and supporter John Flaxman (Rix 2007: 535). Hindmarshs father, James Hindmarsh, was one of John Wesleys preachers, and was trained by Wesley in London. Swedenborg corresponded with Wesley in 1772, inviting the Methodist minister to visit him in London (Synnestvedt 1977: 33).20 John Wesley and his brother Charles were also members of the Fetter Lane Moravian Church at the same time as Swedenborg (Ankarsj 2009: 37). As such, and allowing any number of variant trajectories and alternative figures, there is direct person-to-person contact that links Swedenborg to Borges via Emerson. As established in the previous chapter, Borges adopted a curiously contradictory stance in his evaluation of Swedenborg. His repeated emphasis on the heterodox aspect of the Swedish seer resulted in a judgment about originality of experience that is problematic. It is striking to note, as scholars such as Quinn and Hurth have done so, that Emerson presents an equally problematic and at times inconsistent approach to his evaluation of Swedenborg and Bhme. It is therefore of concern for this study to appraise the strong kinship that Borges felt for Emerson, to note the similarities and the differences in their outlook, and to chart the visible marks of influence. As indicated, both Emerson and Borges delivered lectures on Swedenborg which they later published, in which they presented biographical material alongside a critical evaluation of his work. Emerson and Borges paid particular attention to the magnitude of Swedenborgs intellect. This is of great importance to both, and, as discussed, it becomes clear
20 A word of caution for the scholar approaching Swedenborg for the first time; these three names can be confusing: Toksvig, Signe (1948) Emanuel Swedenborg: Scientist and Mystic (New Haven: Yale University Press). Sigstedt, Cyriel (1952) The Swedenborg Epic: The Life and Works of Emanuel Swedenborg (New York: Bookman Associates,) Synnestvedt, Sig (1970) The Essential Swedenborg. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Co. (The Spanish-language edition of this latter volume is what Borges was invited to contribute to).

Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges

191

from appreciating Borges close attention to Swedenborgs scholastic and linguistic achievements that he felt personal admiration of the skills that were also present in himself. The emphasis on the intellectual dynamic of Swedenborg reflects both Emerson and Borges particular critical focus on the curious relationship between spontaneous, unconscious, mystical experience and the sharp, sceptical, analytical approach to the mystical experience that accompanies the intellect. Swedenborg, Borges suggested, would have been equally prominent in history as a scientist and inventor had he never embarked on his voyages to the otherworld; and yet, Borges stressed he was no retiring monk, nor fainting saint, nor ecstatic holy man. Borges seized on Swedenborgs intellect and not his faith as the vehicle that bore him to these fantastic locations. Hurth charts the evolving relationship that Emerson maintained with the texts of Bhme and Swedenborg, and remarks that he was increasingly troubled by the contradictions thrown up between faith and intellect, and how they are reconciled (though not always) in the two mystical writers. In particular, as Emerson grew older, he came to view the critical apparatus as an impediment to genuine mystical insight, and as a result he viewed Bhmes experiences as increasingly unattainable, and Swedenborgs as a unique and challenging harmony between the forces of faith and reason:
Mystical experience was offset by the sudden influx of skepticism. Bhmes mysticism appeared to Emerson to leave no room for such doubt and skepticism. Emerson acutely sensed the simple sincerity and piety of Bhme and was sure that with this sentiment of piety Bhme experienced ultimate reality as indubitably present. Bhme was aware of this reality with a vividness and vitality that the aging Emerson could only long for. (Hurth 2005: 349)

This touching account of Emerson evokes Williamsons description of Borges eagerness to gain some tangible understanding whilst in Japan of his own previous experiences (Williamson 2004: 444). It similarly relates to the mood that typifies so much ofBorges work and that forms the focus for the study of Flynn (2009) concerning the absence of a revelation, or, as in the final words of Pedro Salvadores: Como todas las cosas, el destino de Pedro Salvadores nos parece un smbolo de algo que estamos a punto de comprender (1975a: 64) [As with so many things, the fate of Pedro

192

Chapter Four

Salvadores strikes us as a symbol of something we are about to understand, but never quite do] (1975a: 65). It is therefore with similar critical eyes that Emerson and Borges appraised the doctrinal, religious, aspect of Swedenborgs works. This is a strong link between them and accords with their understanding of the relationship between intellect, faith and religion, a tension manifest in Emersons 1842 lecture The Transcendentalist. Borges inherited from Emerson this profound awe and respect for religious-inspired texts coupled with a critical and at times cynical regard for religious doctrine and dogma. As such Borges reflected Emersons stern critique of Swedenborgs adherence to certain orthodox codes, although Borges granted him far more freedom from orthodoxy than did Emerson. A brief comment made by Barnstone can now take greater prominence than Barnstone perhaps anticipated: There is the Borges of Emersonian transcendence, the secular mystic (Barnstone 2000: 47). This comment, whilst not without its difficulties in relation to the recurrent ambiguity of the term mystic, is wholly appropriate in this context not only for describing Emerson and Borges, but, importantly, for describing their approach to Swedenborg. If we were to contrast the term secular mystic with religious mystic (again, not without its problems), then we can perceive that what fascinated Emerson and Borges about Swedenborg was precisely the secular, perennial, universal, ancient quality of his recorded experiences; and in this respect Swedenborg belongs to a noble lineage stretching back to pre-Christian epochs. Where they both stumble in their reading of Swedenborg is in his adherence to Scripture and the adaptation of his ideas to the framework of the two Testaments (Borges 1995: 9). This reading of Swedenborg, however, may not be appropriate, whose entire theological/mystical project was deeply religious. What lies at heart of Emerson and Borges reckoning is not so much the secular quality but, as established in the previous chapter, the relationship between institutional religion and personal transcendence.

Chapter Five

The Influence of Swedenborg on Borges

No pasa un da en que no estamos, un instante, en el paraso. [Not a day passes in which we are not, in an instant, in Paradise.] Borges, Los Conjurados oathiose infernals to Booth Salvation, arcane celestials to Sweatenburgs Welhell!! James Joyce, Finnegans Wake Durante los ltimos veinticinco aos de su estudiosa vida, el eminente hombre de ciencia y filsofo Emanuel Swedenborg (16881772) fij su residencia en Londres. Como los ingleses son taciturnos, dio en el hbito cotidiano de conversar con demonios y ngeles. Jorge Luis Borges and Margarita Guerrero, Libro de los seres imaginarios [For the last twenty-five years of his studious life, the eminent philosopher and man of science Emanuel Swedenborg (16881772) resided in London. But as the English are not very talkative, he fell into the habit of conversing with devils and angels.] Book of imaginary beings

As discussed in Chapter One, Swedenborg constitutes a far richer presence in Borges work than the scholarship has hitherto acknowledged. Rodrguez Risquete (2005) enumerates 95 references to Dante in Borges work, dividing his bibliography into five sections. For my own part, I have identified the following appearances of Swedenborg in Borges, some as critical assessments or biographical studies, others as mere references. The list is doubtless incomplete: Testigo a lo invisible, the poem Emmanuel Swedenborg (El otro, el mismo), the poem Doomsday (Los Conjurados),

194

Chapter Five

the poem Otro poema de los dones (El otro, el mismo), El espejo de los enigmas (Otras Inquisiciones), Nueva refutacin del tiempo (Otras Inquisiciones), four tales of El libro de los seres imaginarios: El Devorador de las Sombras, El Monstruo Aqueronte, Los Demonios de Swedenborg and Los ngeles de Swedenborg, La duracin del infierno (Discusin), Historia de la Eternidad (Historia de la Eternidad), La memoria de Shakespeare (La Memoria de Shakespeare), Veinticinco de agosto, 1983 (La Memoria de Shakespeare), Laprida 1214 (Atlas), Sobre Oscar Wilde (Otras Inquisiciones), Pascal (Otras Inquisiciones), Nota sobre (hacia) Bernard Shaw (Otras Inquisiciones), Sobre el Vathek de William Beckford (Otras Inquisiciones), Prlogo de prlogos (2005: 13), Dos interpretaciones de Arthur Rimbaud (2005: 315), Emanuel Swedenborg: Mystical Works (2005: 152), Personality survives death, de Sir William Barrett (2005: 361),1 William Blake. Poesa completa (2005: 554),2 Leon Bloy: La salvacin por los judos. La sangre del pobre. En las tinieblas (2005: 544),3 Leslie Weatherhead: After Death (Discusin), Prologue to Xul Solar, Catlogo de obras del Museo (Borges 1990). He also reproduces a number ofSwedenborg texts: Un telogo en la muerte (Historia universal de la infamia and Antologa de la literatura fantstica), Un doble de Mahoma (Historia universal de la infamia), two passages of El libro de los seres imaginarios: Los Demonios de Swedenborg and Los ngeles de Swedenborg, seven passages of El Libro del cielo y del infierno: Correspondencias arcanas, El hombre elige su eternidad, Las formas del infierno, Infiernos ruinosos, Los ricos en el cielo, Un rprobo en el cielo, Camino de perfeccin [although this latter piece is authored by El Falso Swedenborg]. For the following interviews in which he discusses Swedenborg, please consult bibliography for full details. Salas (1976), Bourne (1980), Engudanos (Barnstone 1982),
1 This is a fascinating brief review, as he recounts Barretts communications from the other side, and remarks that Barretts post-mortem experiences corroborate Swedenborgs. The implications of this are the reinforcement through consensus of Swedenborgs heavenly theology. recorri, como Swedenborg, las regiones de los muertos y de los ngeles (554). He also talks of Blakes homemade mythologies. He calls Bloy profeta y visionario (544) and he likens him to Swedenborg.

2 3

The Influence of Swedenborg on Borges

195

Hughes et.al (Cortnez 1986), Sbato (2002), Barili (Burgin 1998), Christ (Burgin 1998), Yates (Burgin 1998), Engudanos (Burgin 1998). He tells Miguel Engudanos at Indiana University in March 1976 that I also intend to write a book on Swedenborg (Barnstone 1982: 97); he tells Barnstone: I would like to write a book on Swedenborg (Barnstone 1982: 109); and he says to Hughes et.al Im writing a book on him [Swedenborg] (Cortnez 1986: 16). The book was never written, or at least never published. This volume of references cannot indicate by deduction necessary influence, but it certainly demonstrates the perpetual presence of Swedenborg in Borges mind whilst he composed tales or poems, reviewed the works of others, or analysed a particular field in a critical essay. In particular, Borges appraised accounts of life after death, heavenly voyages, communication with the dead or with angels, anomalous experiences with time and heterodox theologies with reference to Swedenborg. It becomes quite clear that for Borges Swedenborg is the yardstick of such mysterious matters against which other accounts are judged. This is most manifest by the proportion of Swedenborg passages that fill the pages of Borges and Bioys Libro del cielo y del infierno. Not only are there seven texts of Swedenborg, but the authors make specific reference to Swedenborg in the prologue. It is clear that on matters eschatological and of the afterlife, Swedenborg constituted the greatest authority for Borges. When did Borges first write about Swedenborg? How did he initially come across his works? Borges relates his introduction to lecturing on Swedenborg in his Autobiographical Essay:
So, at forty-seven, I found a new and exciting life opening up for me. I traveled up and down Argentina and Uruguay, lecturing on Swedenborg, Blake, the Persian and Chinese mystics, Buddhism, gauchesco poetry, Martin Buber, the Kabbalah, the Arabian Nights, T.E. Lawrence, medieval Germanic poetry, the Icelandic sagas, Heine, Dante, expressionism and Cervantes []. Not only did I end up making far more money than at the library, but I enjoyed the work and felt that it justified me. (1971a: 245)

This question of where and when he first encountered Swedenborg, however, is not easily answered, as one must evaluate the profound impact that Swedenborg had on so many of the writers that Borges read with affection:

196

Chapter Five

Goethe,4 Blake, Coleridge,5 De Quincey, Carlyle, Emerson, Thoreau, Whitman, Melville, Hawthorne, Longfellow, Emily Dickinson, Robert Frost, Swinburne, Dante Gabriel Rossetti, Strindberg, von Schelling,6 Tennyson, William James, Henry James, C.S. Peirce, W.B. Yeats,7 E.A. Poe, Victor Hugo, Flaubert, Balzac,8 Baudelaire, Valry, George Sand, Robert Browning, Elizabeth Barrett Browning, G.K. Chesterton,9 Conan Doyle, Schopenhauer, Kant,10 Jung, Henry Corbin, Rudolf Steiner, Tolstoy, Dostoevsky,11 Carl Sandburg, Kierkegaard, Jaspers, Bertrand Russell,12 C.S. Lewis, Joyce, H.P. Lovecraft. Of other writers who were favourites of Borges, I am unable to determine whether they were readers of Swedenborg: Wilde, Kipling, Stevenson, Conrad, G.B. Shaw,13 Dr Johnson, Wordsworth,

4 5 6 7 8 9 10

11 12 13

Goethe once said that only by reading Swedenborgs Heaven and Hell was he enabled to finish his masterpiece, Faustus, which he had put aside in frustration for a decade (Lawrence 1999). See Lawrence 1999. As a reader of Schopenhauer, Borges would likely have been aware of Schelling. Of course I delight in Yeats (Barnstone 1982: 87). His novel Serafita, is an exposition of Swedenborgian spiritual theology. There are only brief mentions of Swedenborg in Chesterton, yet the fact that he wrote a book on Blake indicates his knowledge of him. Borges makes no mention that I can find of Kants Dreams of a Spirit Seer, in which Kant investigates Swedenborg, but he discusses in Autobiographical Essay reading Kant as a young man. He also declares to Christ (1967): I tried my hand at Kants Critique of Pure Reason. Of course, I got bogged down as most people do as most Germans do. Like the discovery of love, like the discovery of the sea, the discovery of Dostoevsky marks an important date in ones life (Borges 2000: 517). Russell wrote about Kants Dreams of a Spirit Seer. Borges declared that Russells History of Western Philosophy would have chosen as his desert-island book (Sorrentino 2001: 230). Shaw, que yo sepa, no habl nunca de Swedenborg; cabe suponer que escribi bajo el estmulo de Blake, a quien menciona con frecuencia y respecto, o, lo que no es inverosmil, que arrib a las mismas ideas por cuenta propia (2005: 1556) [Shaw never, so far as I know, spoke of Swedenborg; it might be supposed that he wrote under the stimulus of Blake, whom he mentions frequently and with respect] (Borges 1995: 9).

The Influence of Swedenborg on Borges

197

Mark Twain, Unamuno, Lewis Carroll, T.S. Eliot, Frost, Ezra Pound, Faulkner, Stephen Crane, Ambrose Bierce, Keats, H.G. Wells, Kafka. Swedenborgian scholars, such as Eugene Taylor, Wilson Van Dusen and James Lawrence have attempted to demonstrate that Swedenborg is a far greater influence upon streams of intellectual, artistic and spiritual thought principally in the West but also, viz Suzuki, in the East than has hitherto been acknowledged. It would appear that Swedenborg constitutes a far less pervasive presence in Hispanic artistic traditions than in the English-speaking world. There are many reason for this, the most immediately apparent being the twofold nature of Swedenborgs relationship to the Enlightenment at a time when the Catholic authorities in Spain were resistant to such secular influences; and secondly his Protestant, non-conformist, anti-ecclesiastical and heterodox religious dimension. Chadwick (2003: 23), Swedenborgian scholar and translator, is the only scholar I have encountered to address the issue of Swedenborgs impact (or lack of ) in the Catholic world:
The Vatican maintained an Index of prohibited books, and I had always assumed that Swedenborgs theological books appeared on it. [] The Vatican Library, which includes the library of the Inquisition, has no copies of the original editions, other than Volume I of the Principia. Similarly the Library of the Institut de France in Paris reports only The Apocalypse Revealed among the major works of which it has first editions. From this I deduce that the educated public of Catholic countries were almost totally unaware of these books when they were published in London and Amsterdam.

As discussed, it is precisely his innovative and anti-ecclesiastical qualities which endeared Borges to Swedenborg. In searching through the extensive articles in Swedenborgian denomination church publications, one finds many references to Borges as a close and sympathetic reader ofSwedenborg we recall Lawrence describing Borges as Swedenborgian. This fact alone stands as testimony to the fact that Borges admiration for Swedenborg outshone his anti-ecclesiastical critical bias in general. Indeed the dissenting, sceptical, critical and yet generously accommodating nature of so many of the published articles by Swedenborgian scholars demonstrates

198

Chapter Five

the spirit of free enquiry typified by such denominations; a far cry from the Argentine Catholicism of which Borges was so critical. However, beyond the many references, and beyond the employment of Swedenborg in his reflections on mysticism, to what extent was Borges poetic and fictional aesthetic influenced by Swedenborg? In this chapter I concentrate on the narrative space of the tales and poems in order to investigate the abiding presence of Swedenborgian ideas of heavens and hells, the persistence of the soul after death, the landscape of the visionary world and the symbolic aspect of dreams. Importantly, and surprisingly given Borges seeming disdain for the moral aspect of theological works, I intuit in Borges work a strong ethical dimension that bears visible hallmarks of the heavenly ethos of Swedenborg. Rarely does the question of ethics in Borges work appear in the scholarship, but I propose that a ethical dimension present in his many interviews and essays demonstrates the influence of Swedenborg. An example of this is his description of a moral law to Amelia Barili: I feel that we all know when we act well or badly. I feel ethics is beyond discussion. For example, I have acted badly many times, but when I do it, I know that it is wrong. It is not because of the consequences. In the long run, consequences even up, dont you think? It is the fact itself of doing good or doing bad (Burgin 1998: 245). As we will explore in this chapter, such a statement reveals the Swedenborgian perspective that heavens and hells are states of the soul that surround us even in life, and that the ethical instinct within us encourages us to choose those pathways most appropriate to our moral state. Borges also discussed the natural ethical nature of man in the preface to Elogio de la Sombra, exclaiming somewhat provocatively, that the Protestant mentality privileges this ethos more than the Catholic: Una de las virtudes por las cuales prefiero las naciones protestantes a las de tradicin catlica es su, cuidado de la tica (1974: 975) [One of the virtues for which I prefer Protestant countries to Catholic is their regard for ethics] (1975a: 10). This Protestant/ Catholic aspect with regards Swedenborg is discussed later in this chapter. The earliest mention of Swedenborg that I have encountered in Borges work is the 1929 essay La Duracin del Infierno. What is curious about this piece is that whilst he refers to Swedenborg only in a footnote, never theless the whole trajectory of his analysis leads to a conclusion of

The Influence of Swedenborg on Borges

199

a uniquely Swedenborgian perspective. With an anti-ecclesiastical vision that is characteristic of Borges entire critical work, the essay considers the theological implications of the notion of hells eternity, suggesting that the ultimate aim of the church in proposing the eternal nature of hell was that of enforcing obedience, and he appraises the various contradictions inherent in the theological arguments. Ahora se levanta sobre m el tercero de los argumentos, el nico. Se escribe as, tal vez: Hay eternidad de cielo y de infierno porque la dignidad del libre albedro as lo precisa; o tenemos la facultad de obrar para siempre o es una delusin este yo (1974: 2378) [Now the third argument looms over me. It may, perhaps, be written thus: Heaven and Hell are eternal because the dignity of free will requires them to be so; either our deeds transcend time, or the I is a delusion] (2000: 51, original italics). This powerful statement demonstrates firstly the similar consideration for the transiency of the state of I that is developed in the essay of 1922 La nadera de la personalidad, and secondly, a Swedenborgian vision of the states of heaven and hell as being selected not by divine judgement but by the human soul. Indeed, without mentioning Swedenborg, Borges presents the argument so heretically maintained by Swedenborg that nos concede el atroz derecho de perdernos, de insistir en el mal, de rechazar las operaciones de la gracia, de ser alimento del fuego que no se acaba, de hacer fracasar a Dios en nuestro destino, del cuerpo sin claridad en lo eterno (1974: 238) [we given the terrifying right to perdition, to persist in evil, to reject all access to grace, to fuel the eternal flames, to make God fail in our destiny, to be forever a shadow] (2000: 51). Swedenborgs Heaven and Hell contains ample descriptions of this state of choice that human souls are given over whether to reside in heaven or in hell: even while we are living in our bodies, each one of us is in a community with spirits as to our own spirits even though we are unaware of it. Good people are in angelic communities by means of [their spirits] and evil people are in hellish communities. Further, we come into those same communities when we die (438). Importantly, Swedenborg suggests that such conditions are states of the soul that are already present in our daily lives: every day we project around us our own heavens and hells, love being the guiding principle of

200

Chapter Five

heaven.14 Borges ethical position can be demonstrated as deriving from his reading of Swedenborg, as he articulates this perspective in the essay on Swedenborg Testigo de lo invisible:
El Infierno es la otra cara del Cielo. Su reverso preciso es necesario para el equilibrio de la Creacin. El Seor lo rige, como a los cielos. El equilibrio de las dos esferas es requerido para el libre albedro, que sin tregua debe elegir entre el bien, que mana del Cielo, y el mal, que mana del Infierno. Cada da, cada instante de cada da, el hombre labra su perdicin eterna o su salvacin. Seremos lo que somos. Los terrores o alarmas de la agona, que suelen darse cuando el moribundo est acobardado y confuso, no tienen mayor importancia. Creamos o no en la inmortalidad personal, es innegable que la doctrina revelada por Swedenborg es ms moral y ms razonable que la de un misterioso don que se obtiene, casi al azar, a ltima hora. Nos lleva, por lo pronto, al ejercicio de una vida virtuosa. (2005: 157) [Hell is the other face of heaven. Its exact opposite is necessary for the balance of creation. The Lord rules over it as he does over heaven. Balance between the two spheres is required for free will, which must unceasingly choose between good, which emanates from heaven, and evil, which emanates from hell. Every day, every instant of every day, man is shaping his eternal damnation or his salvation. We will be what we are. The terrors or anxieties of agony, which usually occur when a dying person is frightened and confused, are of little importance. Whether we believe in the immortality of the soul or not, we must recognize that the doctrine revealed by Swedenborg is more moral and reasonable than one that postulates a mysterious gift gotten, almost by chance, at the eleventh hour. To begin with, it leads us to the practice of virtue in our lives.] (1995: 11)

This is a theological and ethical thread that runs throughout Borges works. In this early essay he evokes Shaws Man and Superman alongside
14 There is infernal freedom and there is heavenly freedom. It is from infernal freedom to think and to will evil, and so far as civil and moral laws do not hinder, to speak and to do it. On the other hand, it is from heavenly freedom to think and to will good, and so far as opportunity is granted, to speak and to do it. Whatever a man thinks, wills, speaks and does from freedom he perceives as his own; for all the freedom which everyone has is from his love. Therefore those who are in the love of evil perceive only that infernal freedom is freedom itself, while those who are in the love of good perceive that heavenly freedom is freedom itself and consequently the evil and the good perceive the opposite to be slavery (Divine Providence, 43).

The Influence of Swedenborg on Borges

201

Swedenborgs works as one of the more compelling aesthetic and ethical depictions of hell. In repeated interviews of his later decades, he continues to draw on these two writers as portraying hell in a manner that champions the human seizure of destiny over either the reward of faith or the arbitrariness of divine will. Importantly, Borges draws from Swedenborgs vision of elected afterlife locations an ethical position that emphasizes the state of rapture at the mystery of existence, and the fulfilment gained from following ones own particular destiny. He returns to these two positions repeatedly in the interviews compiled in Borges at Eighty:
I think that one is dying all the time. Every time we are not feeling something, discovering something, when we are merely repeating something mechanically. At that moment you are dead. Life may come at any moment also. If you take a single day, therein you find many deaths, I suppose, and many births also. But I try not to be dead. I try to be curious concerning things, and now I am receiving experiences all the time, and those experiences will be changed into poems, into short stories, into fables. I am receiving them all the time, although I know that many of the things I do and things I say are mechanical, that is to say, they belong to death rather than to life. (Barnstone 1982: 13)

The ethical instinct, he argues, lies in understanding that right and wrong are aspects of following or not following ones appropriate life pathway. Consequently, the states of heaven or hell are neither for Borges nor Swedenborg exclusively states ofthe soul after death, but are present around us throughout our life: At the very moment of our lives we know whether were acting the right way or the wrong way. We might say that doomsday is going on all the time, that every moment of our lives were acting wrongly or rightly. Doomsday is not something that comes at the end. Its going on all the time. And we know, through some instinct, when we have acted rightly or wrongly (Barnstone 1982: 19). Note how this statement echoes Borges description of the states of the soul that are Swedenborgs heavens and hells: El cielo y el infierno de su doctrina no son lugares, aunque las almas de los muertos que los habitan, y de alguna manera los crean, los ven como situados en el espacio. Son condiciones de las almas, determinadas por su vida anterior. A nadie le est vedado el paraso, a nadie le est impuesto el infierno. Las puertas, por decirlo as, estn abiertas (2005:

202

Chapter Five

156) [The heaven and hell of his doctrine are not places, even though the souls of the dead who inhabit and, in a way, create them perceive them as being situated in space. They are conditions of the soul, determined by its former life. Heaven is forbidden to no one; hell, imposed on no one. The doors, so to speak, are open] (1995: 10). Borges statements thus chime with Swedenborg, and consequently one can allow greater room for manoeuver within Lawrences claim that Borges was himself Swedenborgian. It is also a position that informs Borges reading of Dante. As discussed, whilst Borges praises the Divine Comedy as being the pinnacle of poetic vision, he rejects outright the theological basis of reward and punishment that he perceives in the structure of the poetic cycle. He repeats his gnostic and Swedenborgian credentials in recognising that hell is a state in the present, not a future punishment:
You know, Dante was wrong about hell, wrong about the meaning of that inscription on the gate of the Inferno in the first lines of Canto 3: Lasciate ogni speranza, voi chentrate (Abandon every hope, you who enter). Hell doesnt begin down there. There is no entry to the afterlife. Hell begins here, and here is where we should abandon all hope. Then we have the possibility, the hope, of some momentary happiness. (Barnstone 2000: 31)

As I hope to have demonstrated, there is an ethical attitude present in Borges that clearly derives from his reading of Swedenborg and which informs his reading of Dante, Shaw and other writers. Swedenborg, it must be emphasized, inscribed a strong ethical dimension to his writings indeed an ethos of portraying divine love against demonic vice purveys his works. He explains this repeatedly in Heaven and Hell: All this has been presented to encourage people to examine themselves and to identify their dominant love on the basis of their pleasures, so that according to their grasp of the knowledge of correspondences, they may know their state of life after death (487). I would argue that such an ethical position is visible in Borges, and that it is a position that he defends in interview on many occasions and that, as we shall now see, is presented in many of his poems and fictions. The work of Swedenborg that appears to have been of greatest impact upon Borges is Heaven and Hell, which he cites on numerous occasions, and

The Influence of Swedenborg on Borges

203

which he describes as el ms conocido y hermoso de sus tratados (2005: 155) [the best known and most beautiful of his treatises] (1995: 9). This work is commonly considered the most accessible of Swedenborgs many spiritual volumes, being his most articulate and unambiguous account of his journeys to the angelic realms and his many conversations with angels and the dead. Borges considered this book particularly noteworthy precisely because Swedenborgs clear and lucid descriptions of an otherworld reality are such that this reality appears normal and commonplace, rather than fantastic or fictional. Upon this basis, as discussed in Chapter One, rests so much of Borges confusing hermeneutics of mystical texts.

Los ngeles de Swedenborg


As is to be expected with Swedenborgs extensive and thorough volumes, there is no easy way to summarize the vision ofthis other world, nor its complex structure of hierarchies of angels. Whilst Borges essay on Swedenborg, which we have appraised earlier, is of great synoptic value, one of the most concise prcises of this perplexing landscape is a brief Borges text in Libro de seres imaginarios (with Margarita Guerrero), called Los ngeles de Swedenborg. Borges also includes other passages from Swedenborg in the same work and in Antologa de la literatura fantstica (with Silvina Ocampo and Bioy Casares).15 Of particular importance here, is the selection of a passage from Swedenborgs Arcana Clestia, which Borges entitles Un telogo en la muerte and which he includes in Historia universal de la infamia and Antologa de la literatura fantstica. This brief tale serves as a blueprint both for Borges fictional depiction of otherworld realities, which we will explore below, and as the clearest exposition of the tension

15

Antologa de la literatura fantstica (1940) was originally translated by Anthony Kerrigan as Extraordinary Tales (Herder & Herder 1971c). It was then republished with no translator identified by Viking (1988) with a foreword by Ursula K. Le Guin.

204

Chapter Five

between faith and experience, orthodoxy and heterodoxy, pride and humility, that we find throughout Borges critical work. I have been unable to ascertain whether Borges transcribed the passage from Swedenborgs Arcana Clestia directly from a Spanish translation, or whether he translated it himself from an English (or perhaps other) translation. Borges self-confessed poor Latin would indicate that it is unlikely he translated it directly from Swedenborg himself.16 The passage itself, as one would expect in a piece that Borges chose to incorporate in two of his many anthologies, is arrestingly Borgesian. To begin with, as with so many tales of Borges, whether from the period of Ficciones or the later Brodie, the text is itself second-hand, as Swedenborg remarks that his account had been told him by the angels. Regardless of the ontological question of angels, as a narrative strategy this provides layers of fictionality over the account, inviting the reader into the textual space. This is reinforced by the rendition of the passage in a collection of Borges in which fiction and historical legend are juxtaposed. I have been allowed to talk with some people who lived more than two thousand years ago, people whose lives are described in history books and are therefore familiar (480). Swedenborg recounts the activities of the theologian Melanchthon (who, I conjecture, is Philipp Melanchthon, the German reformer and collaborator with Martin Luther), who upon dying is unable or unwilling to acknowledge that he is dead and continues with his theological entreaties concerning faith as of greater value in heaven than charity. Over a period of time (though as Borges indicates elsewhere, there is no time in Swedenborgs heaven) he becomes entrenched in his dogmatic doctrine of faith, and distances himself ever
16 One can only conjecture whether Borges was really familiar with all the eight volumes of Swedenborgs Arcana Clestia (or more, depending on the edition; Borges refers to the nine volumes of Arcana Clestia in Testigo). Judging by his review of Hesses Glass Bead Game, for example, which is merely a biographical sketch about Hesse, with one empty brief paragraph about the novel, and which thus suggests that he did not read the novel (2005: 512), and by his confession that he could not finish Joyces Ulysses, it is perfectly likely that he skimmed Arcana Clestia (as I confess to have done), selecting the passages relating to the situation of the souls of the dead, the angels and the demons, and hurrying over the extensive biblical exegesis.

The Influence of Swedenborg on Borges

205

more from divine love and wisdom. His pride and obstinacy eventually drive him into consort with magicians and demons and exclude him forever from heaven. This passage demonstrates the severe critique to the point of heresy that Swedenborg maintained concerning doctrines of faith, perfectly encapsulated in Swedenborgs damning sentence in Heaven and Hell: I can bear witness from all my experiences of what happens in heaven and in hell that people who have confessed faith alone as a matter of doctrine and have engaged in evil as regards their lives are all in hell (482). Repeatedly in Arcana Clestia and in Heaven and Hell he depicts the astonishment of newly-dead upon realising that faith alone serves them no purpose if not justified by love and charity a position resonant of St Paul. Faith, Swedenborg argues, must be borne out by manifestation of love, and whilst a cruel heart may be disguised on earth, there is no hypocrisy possible in heaven, as the individuals true nature is visible.17 Furthermore, writes Swedenborg, believers and non-believers alike share the afterlife with no distinction. As I argued in the Introduction, whilst Swedenborg was demonstrably a man of faith, this heterodox theological position would chime at once with Borges intellectual difficulty with the exhortation to treat matters theological or metaphysical as matters of faith. Experience and imagination, not adherence to faith, are the epistemological bases of Borges philosophical outlook, and thus he would have found great accommodation within Swedenborgs vision.

Dilogo de muertos
The extract Los ngeles de Swedenborg also provides the substance for a strikingly Swedenborgian tale, Dilogo de muertos [Dead Mens Dialogue], a brief tale from El Hacedor, which, like many of Borges more

17

In heaven no one can conceal his interiors by his expression, or feign, or really deceive and mislead by craft or hypocrisy (48).

206

Chapter Five

enigmatic shorter pieces, has generated scarcely any critical response. As with Swedenborgs account of Melanchthon, in Borges tale, the two central characters of the tale, former caudillo Rosas and the general Quiroga, are both initially unaware that they are dead, and are both made aware, over the course of the text, of their predicament and of the need to adapt to the new circumstances. The narrative concerns the return of Rosas to Argentina from his burial place ofSouthampton in 1877, where he is greeted by a crowd of soldiers and by his former comrade-in-arms Quiroga. Borges revisits two historical characters who figure largely in his work, granting them thus a post-mortem arena in which to reconcile themselves both to their prior lives and to their current existence in death. Both Rosas and Quiroga constitute important aspects of Borges ancestral history (see Williamson 2004), and both are subjects of early poems: Rosas (Fervor de Buenos Aires [1923]), and El General Quiroga va en coche al muere (Luna de enfrente [1925]). A sense of squalor and putrefaction pervades the tale, and, like a condensed version of Pedro Pramo, the reader is only made aware that the characters are dead once the narrative is truly established.18 Rosas may be seen as embodying aspects of Swedenborgs Melanchthon, in that his pride and haughtiness whilst alive dominate his character whilst dead; whilst Quiroga, who died a heros death at the hands of the treacherous Rosas forty years earlier, allows himself to learn and develop in the realm of the
18 It needs emphasising that Borges paid particular attention to the squalid landscape of hell depicted by Swedenborg. Ahora, qu son los infiernos? Los infiernos, segn Swedenborg, tienen varios aspectos. El aspecto que tendran para nosotros o para los ngeles. Son zonas pantanosas, zonas en las que hay ciudades que parecen destruidas por los incendios; pero ah los rprobos se sienten felices. Se sienten felices a su modo, es decir, estn llenos de odio y no hay un monarca de ese reino; continuamente estn conspirando unos contra otros. Es un mundo de baja poltica, de conspiracin. Eso es el infierno. (2005: 198) [So, what are these hells? Hells, for Swedenborg, have various aspects: one for us and one for the angels. They are swampy places in which there are cities that seem destroyed by fire. But the damned feel happy there. They feel happy in their particular way, thats to say, they are filled with hatred, there is no monarch, and they are continually plotting against each other. It is a world of lowly politics, of conspiracy. This is hell] (my translation).

The Influence of Swedenborg on Borges

207

dead. This putrid landscape is at once resonant of the landscapes of hell described by Swedenborg:
In some hells you can see what look like the ruins ofhouses and cities after a fire, where hellish spirits live and hide out. In the milder hells you can see crude huts, sometimes grouped in something like a city, with alleyways and streets. There are hellish spirits in these homes, with constant quarrels, hostility, beating, and violence. The streets and alleys are full of thieves and robbers. In some hells there are nothing but brothels, foul to look at and full of all kinds of filth and excrement. (Heaven and Hell: 586)

Borges writes about Swedenborgs works that Quienes mueren no saben que estn muertos; durante un tiempo indefinido proyectan una imagen ilusoria de su mbito habitual y de las personas que los rodeaban (2005: 156) [People who have died but fail to realize they are dead project, for an indefinite period of time, an illusory image of their customary ambiance and of the people who surrounded them] (1995: 10). From the imagery of this tale, he presents the characters Quiroga and Rosas as inhabiting a world of projection, and consequently they are recently arrived in the world of the dead. In Swedenborgs account of Melanchthon, as the theologian persists in his drive for authority and in his adamant refusal to accept his own death, his surroundings slowly begin to evanesce: los muebles empezaron a afantasmarse hasta ser invisibles (1974: 335) [the furnishings in his room began to fade away and disappear] (1988: 258), and a group of obsequious admirers gravitate towards him, pero como alguna de esas personas no tena cara y otros parecan muertos, acab por aborrecerlos y desconfiar (1974: 336) [but since some of the visitors were faceless and others seemed dead he ended up hating and distrusting them] (1988: 258). Swedenborg writes in other passages both of Heaven and Hell and Arcana Clestia that like flock to like both in heaven and in hell, and thus souls filled with divine love are attracted towards the angelic realms, and may eventually become angels, whilst hateful and proud souls gravitate towards the demonic realms, and may eventually become demons. One can immediately perceive how Borges reading of Swedenborg informed his conception of the historical re-enactment of Rosas and Quiroga. He writes, for example, that in Swedenborgs accounts Los rprobos no tienen cara o tienen caras mutiladas y atroces (2005: 156) [the damned are faceless or

208

Chapter Five

their features are mutilated, atrocious] (1995: 10). In the tale Dilogo, these faceless or ghoulishly disfigured souls gravitate towards Rosas clearly drawn to his still manifest mundane power. Rosas, like Swedenborgs theologian, likewise seems gravely resistant to abandoning the power and authority that had been his during life. Swedenborg writes in Heaven and Hell that souls filled with hatred and malice naturally are attracted to the regions of hell rather than heaven:
There is no way that people who are engaged in carnal love can live in heavens warmth, because heavens warmth is heavenly love. They can live in hells warmth, though, which is a love of cruelty toward people who do not support them. The pleasures of this love are contempt for others, hostility, hatred, and vengefulness. When they are absorbed in these they are in their very life, with no knowledge whatever of what it means to do good for others out of sheer goodness and for the sake of the good itself. All they know is how to do good out of malice and for the sake of malice. (481)

Borges, perhaps referring to this passage or any of the many similar passages in Heaven and Hell and Arcana Clestia, writes of los rprobos [the damned] that El ejercicio del poder y el odio recproco son su felicidad. Viven entregados a la poltica, en el sentido ms sudamericano de la palabra; es decir, viven para conspirar, mentir e imponerse (2005: 156) [for them, happiness lies in the exercise of power and in mutual hatred. They devote their lives to politics, in the most South American sense of the word: that is, they live to scheme, to lie, and to impose their will on others] (1995: 10). It is clear that his depiction of Rosas is of a soul defiantly unwilling to relinquish such political power, and who is consequently guiding himself towards the demonic regions of hell. Emerson, in his chapter on Swedenborg, concisely describes this desperate nature depicted by Borges in Rosas: The ghosts are tormented with the fear of death, and cannot remember that they have died (2003: 34). Quiroga appears like the brothers Cain and Abel in Leyenda (Elogio de la sombra), Borges brief and Swedenborgian account of the dead brothers meeting in the next world, in that, like Cain, he has forgiven Rosas through his oblivion. Quiroga is consequently fully cognizant of his status, and fully prepared to move on into the further regions of the dead, whereas Rosas, puffed up with pride for his life achievements, wishes to remain Rosas even in death, believing

The Influence of Swedenborg on Borges

209

Ser que no estoy hecho a estar muerto (1974: 792) [It must be that I am not made to be a dead man] (1970: 35). In the poem Rosas, the youthful Borges considers the tremendous presence of Rosas upon contemporary Argentine society. Again, reflecting his abiding interest in the dialectic of memory and oblivion (olvido), Borges concludes the poem with the reflection that to maintain hatred for Rosas is to keep him alive Ya Dios lo habr olvidado / y es menos una injuria que una piedad / demorar su infinita disolucin / con limosnas de odio (1972: 16) [Even God has forgotten him, / and to delay his eternal extinction / for a pittance of hatred / is to turn our contempt into charity now] (1972: 17). The poem El General Quiroga va en coche al muere, meanwhile, presents a proud Quiroga defiantly rejecting his forthcoming death, proclaiming his integral power and importance with the world and the living: Ya muerto, ya de pie, ya inmortal, ya fantasma, / se present al infierno que Dios le haba marcado, / y a sus rdenes iban, rotas y desangradas, / las nimas en pena de hombres y de caballos (1972: 40) [Now dead, now on his feet, now immortal, now a ghost, / he reported to the Hell marked out for him by God, / and under his command there marched, broken and bloodless, / the souls in purgatory of his soldiers and his horses] (1972: 41). These early poetic musings on the deaths of Rosas and Quiroga also present a Swedenborgian vision of the complex web of relationships between the souls of the dead, the people they had been when alive, and their persistent presence in the memory of the living. Rosas, it would seem both from the poem and the tale, is prevented from any development of his soul in the realm of the dead partly because of his towering pride, but partly because of the sustaining force of hatred that the living (Borges, for example) thrust upon him. Quiroga, perhaps as a result of his premature death four decades previously, appears to have overcome the pride that characterized his death, indicated in the poem, and would seem keen to find a passage away from these infernal regions: Yo pensaba como usted cuando entr en la muerte, pero aqu aprend muchas cosas (1974: 792) [I thought as you do when I entered death, but I learned many things here] (1970: 35). In the case of both figures, the thoroughly Swedenborgian approach to the conscious choices that the souls of the dead have is developed; and consequently the hell which the figures inhabit is not one of punishment,

210

Chapter Five

such as depicted by the mediaeval theologians that Borges discusses in Duracin del Infierno, but one of the ongoing squabbles and battles that characterized the lives of these figures. As is typical of Borges, even with such a brief and seemingly simple piece as this, an intriguing narrative device is delivered at the end of the tale a seemingly innocuous statement that strikes at the heart of complex aesthetics of Swedenborg. As discussed throughout this book, the fictional/ poetic space for Borges constitutes far more than mere fiction or mere poetry, as it can be considered of an epistemological order akin to Blakes Imagination or Corbins mundus imaginalis the imaginal. Whilst this is a dominant aspect of his philosophy of aesthetics, nevertheless Borges muddies the hermeneutic waters by emphasising the reality of Swedenborgs visions against the poetic unreality of Dantes (see Chapter One). Borges anticipates the expected reader reaction to the works of Swedenborg when he defends him against charges of madness. This is because when we read certain passages in Swedenborgs Heaven and Hell, the voice of our education tells us that he must be delusional because the alternative is so hard to conceptualize: When I have been allowed to be in the company of angels, I have seen what was there exactly the way I see things in our world, so perceptibly that I did not know I was not in our world and in the court of some king here. I have also talked with angels just as one person here talks to another (174). The alternative to delusion, hallucination or poetic fancy is that Swedenborgs angelic realm is of an order equivalent to an undiscovered island in the Pacific, or a tribal community hidden in the rain forest de carne y hueso. Borges, synthesizing numerous passages from Arcana Clestia and Heaven and Hell, assures us that this is not so, and that El cielo y el infierno de su doctrina no son lugares, aunque las almas de los muertos que los habitan, y de alguna manera los crean, los ven como situados en el espacio. Son condiciones de las almas, determinadas por su vida anterior (2005: 156) [The heaven and hell of his doctrine are not places, even though the souls of the dead who inhabit and, in a way, create them perceive them as being situated in space. They are conditions of the soul, determined by its former life] (1995: 10). The location (for want of a better word), therefore, of Swedenborgs heavens and hells is neither real, as the New World was for Columbus, nor merely fictional, as Mordor or

The Influence of Swedenborg on Borges

211

The Shire were for Tolkien and his readers. They are, as Borges suggests conditions of the soul and thus correspond to the Imagination of Blake and Coleridge, to Corbins imaginal, to Jungs dreamworld, as liminal spaces neither one nor the other. Kathleen Raine lucidly describes this liminal state: For the landscapes of poetry, the landscapes of the great painters are not to be found in nature at all. [] They are landscapes of the soul, and the imagery is not an end but a means a language for discoursing upon realities of the intelligible world, not of the physical world. The theme of imaginative art is not physical but metaphysical (2007: 25). It must be emphasized that Swedenborg did not walk out of his door and into a parallel universe populated with angels and demons, but neither was he making it up in the sense that a novelist might create a fiction.19 This is a difficult idea to conceive of, let alone describe, and yet Corbin succeeds in defining the imaginal as, precisely, this liminal landscape that has characterized religious and mystical experience (both in Christianity and Islam), poetry and art, across time and cultures; and Swedenborg was for Corbin of supreme importance, in the same way that he was for Borges, as recorri este mundo y los otros, lcido y laborioso. [] ese escandinavo sanguneo, que fue mucho ms lejos que Erico el Rojo (2005: 152) [(he) journeyed, lucid and laborious, through this and all other worlds [] that sanguine Scandinavian who went much further than Eric the Red] (1995: 3). This
19 Perhaps, however, his voyages were of such a physical order. Swedenborg writes in Heaven and Hell: As to being carried away by the spirit to another place, I have been shown by living experience what it is, and how it is done, but only two or three times. I will relate a single instance. Walking through the streets of a city and through fields, talking at the same time with spirits, I knew no otherwise than that I was fully awake, and in possession of my usual sight. Thus I walked on without going astray, and all the while with clear vision, seeing groves, rivers, palaces, houses, men, and other objects. But after walking thus for some hours, suddenly I saw with my bodily eyes, and noted that I was in another place. Being greatly astonished I perceived that I had been in the same state as those who were said to have been led away by the spirit into another place. For in this state the distance, even though it be many miles, and the time, though it be many hours or days, are not thought of; neither is there any feeling of fatigue; and one is led unerringly through ways of which he himself is ignorant, even to the destined place (441).

212

Chapter Five

whole dimension of the imaginal is difficult to apprehend cognitively, as it can only be described in terms that create a sense of contradiction neither real nor fantasy yet both real and fantasy. Czeslaw Milosz, another contributor to Lawrences Testimony to the Invisble examines the complex nature of the imaginal with regards Dante, Blake and Swedenborg:
Blakes The Marriage of Heaven and Hell is modeled on Swedenborg, and he would have been amused by an inquiry into whether he had really seen the devils and angels he describes. The crux of the problem and a serious challenge to the mind is Blakes respect for both the imagination of Dante, who was a poet, and the imagination of Swedenborg, whose works are written in quite pedestrian Latin prose. Dante was regarded by his contemporaries as a man who had visited the other world. Yet Jaspers would not have called him a schizophrenic, because the right of the poet to invent that is, to lie was recognized in Jasperss lifetime as something obvious. It is not easy to grasp the consequences of the aesthetic theories which have emerged as the flotsam and jetsam of the scientific and technological revolution. The pressure of habit still forces us to exclaim: Well then, Swedenborg wrote fiction and he was aware it was no more than fiction! But, tempting as it is, the statement would be false. Neither Swedenborg nor Blake were aestheticians; they did not enclose the spiritual within the domain of art and poetry and oppose it to the material. At the risk of simplifying the issue by using a definition, let us say rather that they both were primarily concerned with the energy that reveals itself in a constant interaction of Imagination with the things perceived by our five senses. (1995: 256)

Swedenborgs first profound experience in such altered states of consciousness occurred as a result of dreams and visions, and waking trances brought on by breath control and meditation. His journeys were thus likewise conditions of the soul in the manner in which Borges considered dreams to be, and in the manner in which Jung describes the Transcendental Function.20 There is therefore a relationship between the landscape of Swedenborgs visions and visionary or numinous dreams; indeed Robert Moss (1998), author of many books about dreaming and lucid dreaming, writes that Swedenborgs were dreams of the most ecstatic and potent form.

20 He later renamed this Active Imagination, an aesthetic, contemplative exercise that he pursued in his own visionary quests that led to the composition of the Red Book (see Jung 1997).

The Influence of Swedenborg on Borges

213

Swedenborgs visions have also been appraised as correlating with NDEs (near death experiences) and OBEs (out of body experiences). Raymond Moody, researcher into such experiences, writes in the foreword to Van Dusens Presence of Other Worlds (2004: xi): Swedenborgs reports of his out-of-body experiences resonate well with the legions of contemporary reports of people who find themselves out of their bodies and who are perplexed about the situation. Swedenborg himself describes this distinction between the solid, concrete world of reality, and the visionary dreamworld of the spirits: But it must be remembered that a man cannot see angels with his bodily eyes, but only with the eyes of the spirit within him, because his spirit is in the spiritual world, and all things of the body are in the natural world (Heaven and Hell: 76). With this in mind, we return to the tale. Quiroga explains to Rosas that nothing can persist forever, not even in death, and that even as they speak, Fjese bien, ya estamos cambiando los dos (1974: 792) [Just look, we are both changing already] (1970: 35). The response ofRosas is curious: Ser que no estoy hecho a estar muerto, pero estos lugares y esta discusin me parecen un sueo, y no un sueo soado por m sino por otro, que est por nacer todava (1974: 792) [It must be that I am not made to be a dead man, but these places and this discussion seem like a dream, and not a dream dreamed by me but by someone else still to be born] (1970: 35). The tale then concludes with the equally mysterious commentary of the anonymous narrator: No hablaron ms, porque en ese momento Alguien los llam (1974: 792) [They spoke no more, for at that moment Someone called them] (1970: 35). The tale is set in 1877. Borges was born in 1899. The tale was published in 1960. Following the argument of the parallels between dreams, visions and poetic imagination, one might suggest that there is no difference between Swedenborgs account of Melanchthon and Borges account of Rosas and Quiroga. Why would we assume one to have genuinely (i.e. non-poetically) experienced such an account (although recounted via angels) and the other to have merely invented it? These are the wrong questions. Rosas and Quiroga did engage in this dialogue of the dead, as we have testimony of it in the tale, and they were themselves witness to the dream crafting of the poet Borges who was yet to be born and yet to witness them. Who, consequently, is this Alguien? Could it be

214

Chapter Five

Borges, summoning the dead warriors into his dream/fiction, or could it be the reader, engaging in the poetic act of textual dialogue with these warriors? Or could it be God or an angel, drawing them onwards, as Quiroga declares, towards otra cara y otro destino (792) [another face and another destiny]? No answer is to be expected, and neither should it. As Corbin argues, we tend to approach these imaginal matters with the wrong epistemological tools, seeking concrete answers to mercurial concerns. Borges appears to intuit the same liminal question, and consequently challenges our already challenged critical faculty by provoking this most labyrinthine relationship between fiction and reality, the living and the dead, dream and waking, madness and sanity. Dilogo de muertos, reading like a page from Swedenborg although in a Latin American climate, challenges our most essential ontological certainties and raises questions about the nature of the real.

Fragmentos de un evangelio apcrifo [From an apocryphal gospel]


As I have suggested above, the theological, visionary, works ofSwedenborg constituted a powerful presence within Borges works. I have also argued that Borges inclusion of the passage entitled un telogo en la muerte is significant as numerous Swedenborgian elements in the brief extract are present in Borges later tale Dilogo de muertos. There are further works of Borges that deserve consideration, even if it may be less thorough than the analysis of Dilogo. As I have also suggested, the briefer pieces of Borges later works tend to receive lesser critical attention than his earlier fictions. In Elogio de la sombra, Borges confronts much of his contemplation about the nature of death and the dead that his reading of Swedenborg and other mystics would have fuelled. There is scarcely any critical attention given, for example, to a peculiar and oddly-numbered list of thirtyseven proverbs entitled Fragmentos de un evangelio apcrifo [From an

The Influence of Swedenborg on Borges

215

apocryphal gospel]. Whilst it would be rash to ascribe all or even most of these proverbs to a Swedenborgian source, nevertheless, these proverbs are a clear articulation of the central ethical position, influenced strongly by Swedenborg, that we find Borges discussing in his many later interviews. That they have been so overlooked is a shame, as they truly embody all that is most Borgesian: iconoclastic, ironic, humble, wise, ethical, humorous, whimsical and, importantly, practical. Borges would balk at being called a spiritual teacher, but a perusal of these proverbs reveals a deeply measured and insightful counsel; some proverbs barbed like a Zen kan, others revealing the presence of Swedenborg. Without the space to discuss each one, for the purposes of this study I will appraise the Swedenborgian aspect of a brief selection. 3. Desdichado el pobre en espritu, porque bajo la tierra ser lo que ahora es en la tierra (1975a: 106) [Wretched are the poor in spirit: for what they were on earth, so shall they be in their graves].21 Recounting it in his biographical sketch on Swedenborg, Borges took obvious relish in Swedenborgs account of the hermit who had renounced all worldly goods and activities, who then found himself woefully unfit for heaven. This first proverb appears as a direct allusion to this matter, indicating the position that Swedenborg maintained that full engagement with life and with the world are the essential drives of the living that can only be denied at a price. Swedenborg explains this in detail in Heaven and Hell.
I have spoken with some after death who, while they lived in the world, renounced the world and gave themselves up to an almost solitary life, in order that by an abstraction of the thoughts from worldly things they might have opportunity for pious meditations, believing that thus they might enter the way to heaven. But these in the other life are of a sad disposition; they despise others who are not like themselves; they are indignant that they do not have a happier lot than others, believing that they have merited it; they have no interest in others, and turn away from the duties of charity by which there is conjunction with heaven. They desire heaven more than others; but when they are taken up among the angels they induce anxieties that disturb the

21

In this chapter and the ensuing Conclusion, all translations of texts of Elogio de la sombra are by Di Giovanni and are from the bilingual edition entitled In Praise of Darkness (1975a).

216

Chapter Five
happiness of the angels; and in consequence they are sent away; and when sent away they betake themselves to desert places, where they lead a life like that which they lived in the world. (360)

11. Bienaventurados los misericordiosos, porque su dicha est en el ejercicio de la misericordia y no en la esperanza de un premio (1975a: 106) [Blessed are the merciful: for their happiness is in showing mercy, not in obtaining reward]. 12 Bienaventurados los de limpio corazn, porque ven a Dios (1975a: 106) [Blessed are the pure in heart: for they already see God]. Countless passages in Heaven and Hell testify to the nature of mercy being a natural attribute of divine love, and that to perform acts of mercy or charity for the aggrandizement of the constitute selfish acts:
[] the angels refuse all thanks for the good they do, and are displeased and withdraw if any one attributes good to them. They wonder how any one can believe that he is wise from himself or does anything good from himself. Doing good for ones own sake they do not call good, because it is done from self. But doing good for the sake of good they call good from the Divine; and this they say is the good that makes heaven, because this good is the Lord. (9)

28. Hacer el bien a tu enemigo puede ser obra de justicia y no es arduo; amarlo, tarea de ngeles y no de hombres (1975a: 108) [To bless thine enemy may be righteous and is not dif ficult: but to love him is a task for angels, not for men]. Many passages from Heaven and Hell testify to the biblical entreaty to love thy neighbour, and that this, as with the matter of mercy detailed above, is commonly misapprehended as a means of garnering heavenly favour. The reader may consult paragraphs 1320 for Swedenborgs lengthy account of how true love of the neighbour is an act of such selflessness that, as Borges encapsulates in his brief maxim, only the angels are truly capable of performing. 30. No acumules oro en la tierra, porque el oro es padre del ocio, y ste, de la tristeza y el tedio (1975a: 108) [Lay not up for thyself treasures upon earth: for treasure is the father of idleness, and idleness of boredom and woe]. Again this resonates strongly with Swedenborgs highly unorthodox perspective on the church teaching that the rich man will not enter heaven. The danger, as Swedenborg writes, is that the riches may constitute

The Influence of Swedenborg on Borges

217

a distraction from the true purpose, and that the rich man may become tempted by the temptations of the money system and so neglect his true self. Borges writes in Testigo that wealth is no obstacle for entrance into heaven in Swedenborgs theology, unless it is the cause of greed or sloth. Wealth per se is unimportant. The full exposition of this highly unorthodox revelation appears throughout a series of paragraphs of Heaven and Hell:
Out of a great deal of conversation and living with angels, I have been granted sure knowledge that rich people enter heaven just as easily as poor people do, and that no one is shut out of heaven for having abundant possessions or accepted into heaven because of poverty. There are both rich and poor people there, and many of the rich are in greater splendor and happiness than the poor. (357)22 [] One person can live like another in outward form. As long as there is an inward acknowledgment of the Deity and an intent to serve our neighbor, we can become rich, dine sumptuously, live and dress as elegantly as befits our station and office, enjoy pleasures and amusement, and meet our worldly obligations for the sake of our position and of our business and of the life of both mind and body. So we can see that it is not as hard to follow the path to heaven as many people believe. The only difficulty is finding the power to resist love for ourselves and love of the world and preventing those loves from taking control, since they are the source of all our evils. (359)

This sentiment is also reflected in Borges maxim number 47: Feliz el pobre sin amargura o el rico sin soberbia (1975a: 110) [Happy is the poor man without bitterness, and the rich man without arrogance]. Whilst there are further proverbs that echo a Swedenborgian sentiment, it is perhaps of greatest worth to consider the final two proverbs which, in their simplicity, evoke Swedenborgs works with greatest power: 50. Felices los amados y los amantes y los que pueden prescindir del amor [Happy are the lovers and the loved, and they that can do without love]. 51. Felices los felices (1975a: 110) [Happy are the happy]. Not only in Arcana Clestia and Heaven and Hell, but importantly his work Conjugal Love, Swedenborg goes to tremendous lengths to describe the nature of conjugal love as being the terrestrial portion of divine love, and that true lovers may
22 This is the very passage that Borges and Bioy reproduce as Los ricos en el cielo in Libro del cielo y del infierno. Their brief passage is a composite of sentences from 357 and 361.

218

Chapter Five

remain together in the next world, a matter to which Borges pays attention in his essay Testigo. Beyond the matter of lovers, Swedenborgs entire heavenly opus is dominated by a perpetual return to the idea of happiness as the ultimate state of divine love. Again, as with other matters described above, there are innumerable passages in Heaven and Hell that describe the happiness ofthe angels, the happiness ofthose souls that dwell in the angelic realms, and the absence of happiness for those who reside in the hellish regions. Amidst detailed descriptions of heavenly joy, Swedenborg writes that the angels have everything that is blessed, delightful, and happy, or that which is called heavenly joy (286); Those that are in heaven are continually advancing towards the spring of life, with a greater advance towards a more joyful and happy spring the more thousands of years they live (414). We recall Borges in the poem El remordimiento: He cometido el peor de los pecados / que un hombre puede cometer. No he sido / feliz [I have committed the worse sin of all / That a man can commit. I have not been / happy] (Burgin 1998: 140), and that in his many interviews he writes that whilst sadness, loneliness and suffering are the source of art, happiness is a good in and of itself, and requires neither cause nor objective. Whilst we would be exaggerating to claim that such a sentiment springs directly from his reading of Swedenborg, we can nevertheless determine that amidst so many references to Swedenborg, so many allusions to his heavenly landscape, and so many ethical considerations that echo Swedenborgs ethics, we may determine a respectful thread concerning happiness that Borges identifies in Swedenborg. Such a presence of Swedenborg is not limited to these two texts. Elogio de la sombra contains another brief and wholly under-studied tale titled His end and his beginning (the original title is in English), which relates the activities of a man who has recently died and, in a manner reminiscent of many narratives in Heaven and Hell, begins a process of learning the nature of death. Following the Swedenborgian dimension, one must first identify the curious relationship within the anonymous protagonist between sleep and death. The tale begins: Cumplida la agona, ya solo, ya solo y desgarrado y rechazado, se hundi en el sueo (1975a: 116) [After death, after the wrench and the stark loneliness, he dropped into a deep sleep]. Swedenborg recounts in numerous passages of Heaven and Hell

The Influence of Swedenborg on Borges

219

that discarnate spirits, like living people, wake and sleep and even dream whilst asleep. Indeed, as with the living (as with Swedenborg himself ) the dream of the dead can constitute a journey of discovery into the realms of further mystery. Some spirits who were not evil settled down into a peaceful state, rather like sleep, and in this way were taken into heaven in respect to the deeper levels of their minds (411).23 Whilst Swedenborgs narrative of Melanchthon which Borges reproduced concerns a man whose pride prevents his admission into heaven, in the brief tale His end and his beginning the man is destined to heaven, yet is simply unable to comprehend this most cognitively challenging of matters. Now dead, he returns to work and attempts to maintain the life that he had. Like Melanchthon, however, the material objects surrounding him begin to evanesce and disappear, whilst his former colleagues fail to perceive him. One of the most important matters of this tale for our present analysis is the matter of the protagonists dreams. He is made aware that he is dead through the sudden realisation que no poda recordar las formas, los sonidos y los colores de los sueos (1975a: 116) [that he was unable to recall the shapes or sounds or colours of his dreams]. He is made suddenly aware that his reality is now a dream. This immediately brings us back to the discussion above about the nature of dream, vision and death. Swedenborg, again in Heaven and Hell, recounts in many passages that whilst alive he has been granted entry into the land of the dead through dreams and visions, and that the soul of the dead, upon death, moves into the same dream landscape that he may have experienced once alive. Indeed Swedenborg recounts in 449 that his visions into the land of the dead were of great profundity precisely because his material body was capable of such inactivity (minimal heartbeat and breath) that he effectively was both dead and dreaming. Whilst on the one hand this evokes the metaphor that so intrigued Borges, and which he identified in poets throughout the ages including, obviously,

23

Conan Doyle writes of Swedenborgs works: Death was made easy by the presence of celestial beings who helped the newcomer into his fresh existence. Such newcomers had an immediate period of complete rest. They regained consciousness in a few days of our time (2005: 100).

220

Chapter Five

Shakespeare and Caldern, that life is a dream,24 in this Swedenborgian tale we may perceive an accompanying metaphor: that death is a dream. The nature of this dream/death world in which Borges protagonist finds himself is further reinforced by the similarly Swedenborgian motif, also present in Un telogo en la muerte, that the narrator has been, during this immediately post-death period, creating the world that surrounds him: the office, the people, their faces. He understands, like Quiroga and unlike Rosas, that he must move on: De algn modo sinti que su deber era dejar atrs esas cosas, ahora perteneca a este nuevo mundo, ajeno de pasado, de presente y de porvenir (1975a: 116) [Still, he somehow felt it his duty to be rid of everything. He belonged to another world now, detached from past, present, or future]. This is a painful process, as it demands of him an abandonment of all that had constituted his identity once alive. Again we recall how Rosas is wholly unable to relinquish being Rosas, as Melanchthon cannot abandon being Melanchthon. Both are denied heaven. Swedenborg describes in Heaven and Hell with numerous examples how the angels, acting as psychopomps, assist the dead in adjusting to their new environment and state, and that if the individual resists with sufficient force, then eventually the angels will abandon this soul to his own demonic fate. Angelic identity, in a manner that strangely evokes some of Borges concerns for the status of the I developed in La nadera de la personalidad, Borges y yo and his lectures on Buddhism, is universal, not particular. At the end of the brief tale, the man, having relinquished his past and his self, has attained divine grace: desde su muerte haba estado siempre en el cielo
24 Cuando Shakespeare, por ejemplo, equipara la vida con un sueo, l, en lo que insiste, es en la irrealidad de la vida, en el hecho de que es difcil fijar una diferencia entre lo que soamos y lo que vivimos. En cambio, en el caso de Caldern, creo que la frase tiene un sentido teolgico: la vida es sueo, en el sentido de que nuestra vida, nuestra vigilia, no corresponden a la realidad, sino a una breve parte de la realidad, el sentido de que lo verdadero son el cielo y el infierno (Sorrentino 2001: 133). [When Shakespeare, for example, equates life with a dream, he refers to the unreality of life, in the fact that it is difficult to establish a division between what we dream and what we live. With Caldern, on the other hand, I feel that the phrase Life is a dream has a theological sense, in that our waking life does not correspond to reality, but to a brief part of reality, the sense that heaven and hell are the true reality] (My translation).

The Influence of Swedenborg on Borges

221

(1975a: 118) [from the moment of death he had been in heaven]. Dilogo de muertos and His end and his beginning, therefore, can both be considered remarkably Swedenborgian, and published in the same volume, may be considered synoptic treatments of Swedenborgs heterodox theological perspective on the souls ability to choose his angelic or demonic environment. Rosas, like Melanchthon, chooses hell; the anonymous man of the other tale chooses heaven.

Conclusion
What I have hoped to demonstrate in this study of certain Borges texts is the pervasive presence of Swedenborg that informs the many narrative of death and the afterlife. Whilst it would be remiss to affirm that these texts are conscious reworkings or even respectful parodies of Swedenborgs text, it can be established that Borges close and affectionate reading ofSwedenborg provided essential substance for his own fictional world. Neither are such matters limited to the few texts outlined above; throughout Borges works, from the early essays to the Ficciones of the 1940s, through to the later essays, poems, fictions and interviews, Swedenborgian imagery, landscape and, importantly, ethics, pervades Borges work. For example, few critical studies have considered the curious academy of heavenly students from which the magician of Las ruinas circulares initially attempts to select his future son. This perplexing image of concentric levels of studious discarnate souls eager to be incarnated resembles the many perplexing descriptions of communities of angels and spirits in Swedenborgs Heaven and Hell. The magician in this case clearly has the ability, like Swedenborg, to enter this spiritual landscape through dreams and meditation in his quest for progeny. In his later (and also under-studied) work Atlas, Borges presents an uncanny episode in which he enters into dialogue with the dead soul of Hayde Lange through a dream vision, and decides not to reveal to her that she is dead. In this case, the Borges narrator chooses not to act as

222

Chapter Five

psychopomp that is to say he decides not to help her move further into the heavenly realm resolving, one would assume, that angelic guides would perform that function. One final text may be selected to draw to a close this chapter. The text, entitled Abramowicz, from Borges final published volume before his death, Los Conjurados, bears the hallmarks of Swedenborgs visions of the afterlife with which Borges was so familiar. I deem this text to be of great importance for an understanding of the whole of Borges work, as it can be seen to constitute a state of genuine revelation about the mysteries of death that do not stem from books but from immediate experience. Through a Jamesian Radical Empiricist method, Borges, it would appear, received confirmation about the persistence of the soul after death that he had read with such attention and for so many years in Swedenborg. Maurice Abramowicz (19011981) was Borges friend from his youth in Geneva with whom he maintained correspondence. In this brief piece (which he describes to Amelia Barili)25 Borges becomes suddenly and delightedly aware that his dead friend is still, in some way, present: Esta noche, no lejos de la cumbre de la colina de Saint Pierre, una valerosa y venturosa msica griega nos acaba de revelar que la muerte es ms inverosmil que la vida y que, por consiguiente, el alma perdura cuando su cuerpo es caos (1989: 467) [Tonight, not far from the top of the hill of Saint Pierre, a courageous and happy Greek music has just revealed to us that death is more implausible than life and that, therefore, the soul survives when its body is chaos].26 Borges intuits not only that his dead friend is still present, but, like Swedenborgs depiction of the communities of discarnate souls, he is surrounded by the souls of the departed: Contigo estaban las
25 It was a beautiful night. Mara Kodama, Maurice Abramowiczs widow and I were at a Greek tavern in Paris, listening to Greek music, which is so full of courage. I remembered the lyrics: While this music lasts, we will deserve Helen of Troys love. While the music lasts, we will know that Ulysses will come back to Ithaca. And I felt that Maurice was not dead, that he was there with us, that nobody really dies, for they all still project their shadow (Burgin 1998: 241). Translation Frank Thomas Smith <http://www.southerncrossreview.org/47/abramowicz.htm>.

26

The Influence of Swedenborg on Borges

223

muchedumbres de las sombras que bebieron en la fosa ante Ulises y tambin Ulises y tambin todos los que fueron o imaginaron los que fueron (1989: 467) [With you were the throngs of shadows who drank before Ulysses in the grave and also Ulysses and also all who were and all those imagined by those who were] (trans. Smith). In tune with much of what we have discussed in this chapter about the relationship between mystical vision and imagination, it is important that neither Borges nor his companions see Abramowicz as a fully present ghost, as some material entity on the same plane of existence as them, but simply imagine him witness to their gathering. This is thus further exploration of the liminal space defined by Corbin as imaginal, neither mere fantasy nor material reality, but a third way in which imagination and reality are in some curious interrelationship. Borges published this volume only months before his own death, and it is therefore of great poetic beauty to read of this wisdom that he gains through his dead friend concerning the future joyous realm of death: Esta noche me has dicho sin palabras, Abramowicz, que debemos entrar en la muerte como quien entra en una fiesta (1989: 467) [Tonight you have told me without words, Abramowicz, that we must enter death like one who enters a party] (trans. Smith). Again and again Borges would have read in his beloved Swedenborg of the persistence of the soul, and of the joyous aspect of the angelic communities. It would appear that sitting at dinner with friends and good wine and evoking the memory of his dead friend, the words of Swedenborg suddenly and rapturously rang true. Estabas ah, silencioso y sin duda sonriente, al percibir que nos asombraba y maravillaba ese hecho tan notorio de que nadie puede morir (1989: 467) [You were there, silent and no doubt smiling when you perceived that we were amazed and marveled at the notorious fact that no one can die] (trans. Smith). If this moment did, indeed, constitute an epiphanic realization of Swedenborgs teachings, then, as readers of Swedenborg and of Borges, we may justifiably intuit that Borges and his friend Abramowicz are now sitting together, conversing, as Borges decribes in Elega, about los dos sueos que se llamaron Laforgue y Baudelaire (1989: 466) [those two dreams called Laforgue and Baudelaire] (my translation) and merrily engaging the angels in theological debates.

Conclusion Confronting the shadow: theherosjourney in El Etngrafo1

Artists are magical helpers. Evoking symbols and motifs that connect us to our deeper selves, they can help us along the heroic journey of our own lives. Joseph Campbell, Pathways to Bliss An art that does not heal is not an art. Alejandro Jodorowsky, The Way of the Tarot Ive always been a great reader of Jung. Borges, Conversations with Jorge Luis Borges

Borges later fictions have received far less critical attention than his wellknown publications of Ficciones (1944) and El Aleph (1949). Bell-Villada (1999: 260), for example, dismisses El Informe de Brodie as rather slight, suggesting that: Because none of the material in Dr. Brodies Report even approaches the level of the Ficciones or the stories in El Aleph, there is little reason to discuss any one piece in detail. The prose pieces of Elogio de la sombra and the tales of El libro de arena and La Memoria de Shakespeare are, with notable exceptions, often overlooked. This can be explained partly by the enigmatic and at times pseudo-realist character of these later fictions, which may fail to evoke the labyrinthine complexity and literary puzzles of his earlier pieces. This to me is a scholarly oversight, as I feel that

An earlier version of this conclusion was published as an article in Journal for Romance Studies: Confronting the Shadow: The Heros Journey in Borges El Etngrafo, 12/2 (summer 2012), 1732. Many thanks to the journal editors for kind permission to reproduce the text here.

226

Chapter Five

Borges later works poetry, fiction, essays and interviews demonstrate a creative mind grappling with equal intensity with the philosophical and metaphysical questions as his earlier work, only with a style that employs fewer devices and strategies to catalyse the particular puzzle-solving detective faculty in the reader. An example of this is the brief (just over 600 words) and deceptively simple tale El Etngrafo of Elogio de la sombra, which has received curiously little scholarly attention. Brevity in Borges generally betrays deep currents, and a close reading of this tale opens many avenues implicit in the text. In particular, the tale embodies crucial elements of the heros journey as extensively examined by C.G. Jung, a journey that analogizes the process of psychic healing expressed by Jung as Individuation. In this final conclusive chapter I appraise El Etngrafo alongside other fictions of Borges that represent aspects of the heros journey. In particular, I evaluate the particular dynamics reflected in the tale of the stages of the journey as articulated by Jung scholar Joseph Campbell as the Monomyth, which he observed in mythological tales across time and cultures: the summons away from home, the confrontation with the shadow, the dialogue with the senex (wise old man) figure, the death and resurrection, the magical knowledge and the return home. Psychopathology, Jung argued, arises commonly through an individuals inability or unwillingness to assess the distinction between ego and persona and to explore the egos relationship with unconscious complexes and archetypal figures. The heros journey thus expresses the egos inner journey into the unconscious to acknowledge and integrate these areas which, through being ignored, block psychic energy (libido), and being contemplated, release this energy. In this sense, Murdock, the protagonist of El Etngrafo, can be analysed as engaging in this process of psychic healing, gaining wisdom and a deeper understanding of his own psyche. He can also be seen as embodying a collective psyche that confronts a collective shadow and gains deeper understanding of unconscious processes. This analysis corresponds to a larger project in which I evaluate the shifting oeuvre of Borges in the light of Jungs process of individuation the journey towards the self, often depicted in literature and mythology as the heros journey. This is not, however, a psychoanalytical appraisal of the tale, rather it follows the amplification analysis customary to Jungs depth psychology which reveals an archetypal mythic pattern

Conclusion Confronting the shadow: the heros journey in El Etngrafo

227

apparent within both El Etngrafo and other tales of Borges. By such an evaluation I hope to depict within the tale an implicit search for psychic wholeness the voyage into the unconscious and the confrontation with the shadow analogized by the heros journey. There is a rich tradition in the Borges scholarship of binding his work to his biography through a psychoanalytical perspective, most notably Freudian, but also, in the case of Rodrguez Monegal (1978), through a Lacanian and Kleinian lens. Characteristic of the psychoanalytical reading are the Oedipal, Narcissicistic and parricidal elements of his life and work, described by Rodrguez Monegal (1990: 129) in a later article: Educated by his father in the writers calling, he had practiced it as a son; in so doing he avoided parricide. But on the death of his father in 1938, and after an accident on Christmas Eve of the same year, Borges committed symbolic suicide in order to conceal the parricide and to be free to begin writing his most important fictions.2 This interpretation, which Woodall described as an obsessively psychoanalytical view of the man (1997: xxi), remains influential, with parallel arguments concerning the failed writer-father, the overbearing mother, the consequent troubled relationships with women and the clues of this dynamic implicit in the literary works, forming the central narrative of Williamsons Borges: A life (2004). There are limitations, however, to the psychoanalytical reading of Borges, as it can limit the artistic creation to a mere cipher ofthis dominant Freudian dynamic of psychological trauma. This is highlighted by Earle (2000: 100) in his review of the starkly Freudian analysis by Woscoboinik (1998): In this psychoportrait our model is cornered by the ghosts of Oedipus and Narcissus the mother-obsession and the self-obsession, that is and never escapes. Furthermore, Borges himself was critical of Freudian psychoanalytical
2 Molloy (1994: 78) questions whether Borges was consciously alluding to Freud in his examination of das unheimlich the uncanny in his review of Beckfords Vathek. Tcherepashenets (2008) approaches Borges interest in dreams in relation to Freuds dream analysis. de Costa (2000: 47) appraises the humour in Death and the Compass in light of Freuds Jokes and their Relation to the Unconscious. A number of articles, such as Portugal M. Saliba (2001), also appraise Borges through a variety of psychoanalytical perspectives.

228

Chapter Five

analyses establishing too rigid a bond between artistic creativity and childhood, family and sexuality. His scathing comments to Burgin about Freuds obsession are well known:
I think of [Freud] as a kind of madman, no? A man laboring over a sexual obsession. Well, perhaps he didnt take it to heart. Perhaps he was just doing it as a kind of game. I tried to read him, and I thought of him either as a charlatan or as a madman, in a sense. After all, the world is far too complex to be boiled down to that all-too-simple scheme. (Burgin 1969: 109)3

His views of Freud chime closely with those that Jung expressed later in his life concerning Freuds obsessive desire to maintain his theories of sexuality,4 and, indeed, in the same interview Borges expressed his respect for Jung: Jung I have read far more widely than Freud, but in Jung you feel a wide and hospitable mind (Burgin 1969: 109). Borges was an engaged reader of Jung, citing his work on numerous occasions.5 However, his
3 Borges jokingly called Freud not my favourite fiction writer (Barnstone 2000: 111), and Jason Wilson reminds us that Borges was as anti-Marxism or anti-pyschoanalysis (merely gossip) as he was anti-Hitler (2006: 119). Kristal remarks on the irony that Borges presented a lecture on Spinoza 1981 at the Freudian School of Buenos Aires, given his skepticism about Freud, and his sometimes disparaging remarks about psychoanalysis (2002: 144). There was no mistaking the fact that Freud was emotionally involved in his sexual theory to an extraordinary degree. When he spoke of it, his tone became urgent, almost anxious, and all signs of his normally critical and skeptical manner vanished. A strange, deeply moved expression came over his face, the cause of which I was at a loss to understand. I had a strong intuition that for him sexuality was a sort of numinosum ( Jung 1989: 150). When, then, Freud announced his intention of identifying theory and method and making them into some kind of dogma, I could no longer collaborate with him; there remained no choice for me but to withdraw ( Jung 1989: 167). Some notable examples of his references to Jung, in particular to Psychologie und Alchemie, are: Nota sobre Walt Whitman (1974: 24953), Nathaniel Hawthorne (1974: 67085), Kafka y sus Precursores (1974: 71012), El Verdugo Piadoso, of Nueve Ensayos Dantescos (1989: 3579), Los Conjurados, of Los Conjurados (1989: 501), William Beckford. Vathek (2005: 533), and El Libro de los Seres Imaginarios. He also refers to Jung in many interviews.

Conclusion Confronting the shadow: the heros journey in El Etngrafo

229

familiarity with Jungs works should not be considered here as grounds for perceiving a necessary Jungian influence on his writings, such as one might find, for example, a conscious influence of Freud upon certain Dadaist artists. Rather I hope to demonstrate that the archetypal narrative of the Hero, as indicated by Jung and illustrated by Campbell, is apparent in Borges art as it is apparent in dreams, myths and art across time and culture.

El Etngrafo6
In a customary fashion, Borges author and Borges narrator are conflated in the opening lines of the tale: El caso me lo refieron (1975a: 46) [This story was told me], and the narrative is located in the temporal and spatial distance. In this way, as with many of the tales of El Informe de Brodie, it is given a mythological, timeless dimension by the implication of anecdote, suggesting that the narrator Borges is not author but mere storyteller recounting a tale that he was told some time ago, the events of which took place even further ago. This is an important aspect of this and other tales, as the narrative assumes a collective nature, becoming the creation not of a lone artist, but of tradition. Pursuing this avenue, one can perceive the protagonist of the tale as everyman, embodying aspects of a collective psyche in addition to that of the author. This is at once visible in El Etngrafo both in the fact that Murdock is also the thousands of characters visibles e invisibles, vivos y muertos (1975a: 46) [seen and unseen, living and dead], and by the fact that Murdock is depicted with only the barest of defining characteristics. He is credulous and nave, unquestioning of authority, harbouring an underdeveloped critical faculty which would prohibit him from engaging in any philosophical, metaphysical or psychological exploration. Murdocks ingenuous character dramatizes the radicality of his transformation during the narrative, positioning the
6 Di Giovanni translates the tale as The Anthropologist.

230

Chapter Five

initial lack of consciousness against the later position of heightened consciousness. Jung depicts this character type as in ignorance of the unconscious and consequently living in peril of neurotic fear of the unknown: A man who is unconscious of himself acts in a blind, instinctive way and is in addition fooled by all the illusions that arise when he sees everything that he is not conscious of in himself coming to meet him from outside as projections (1983: 335). This state of passivity sets the scene for the development of ego-consciousness in relation to the unconscious, a process analogized in the journey of the hero. Whilst numerous passages of Jungs extensive work elucidate this psychic process, it is summarized cogently by Joseph Campbell as the prototypical sequence of steps pursued by mythic heroes across time and cultures, illustrated dramatically in The Hero with a Thousand Faces (1949). Campbell borrowed the term monomyth from Joyces Finnegans Wake to describe this process: A hero ventures forth from the world of common day into a region of supernatural wonder: fabulous forces are there encountered and a decisive victory is won: the hero comes back from this mysterious adventure with the power to bestow boons on his fellow man (1949: 30). Importantly, through his passivity, Murdock embodies a collective ego that is likewise not in tune with the deeper dimensions of the unconscious. This becomes apparent when Murdock leaves the security of home and its nurturing environment and plunges into the unknown represented by the prairie. The narrator reveals that one of Murdocks ancestors had died in hostility with the Indians and that esa antigua discordia de sus estirpes era un vnculo ahora (1975a: 46) [this old family bloodshed was now a link]. A link to what? The relationship here is immediately apparent with Borges and his ancestral heritage (Williamson 2004: 24), and as such Murdock confronts a personal shadow in the guise of ancestral strife, and his trip to the prairie could indicate a step towards redemption or vindication of this historical enmity. Murdock certainly prepares himself for such an encounter, aware that in order to learn the language of los hombres rojos (1975a: 46) [the red men] he would need to be accepted by them: Previ, sin duda, las dificultades que lo aguardaban; tena que lograr que los hombres rojos lo aceptaran como unos de los suyos (1975a: 46) [No doubt he foresaw the difficulties that were in store for him; he would have to do his

Conclusion Confronting the shadow: the heros journey in El Etngrafo

231

best to get the red men to accept him as one of them]. Murdock is also symbolically bound to the Indians by the curious facial description of de perfil de hacha (1975a: 46) [hatchet face], which evokes the mythologized Native American hatchet. Amplifying Murdock to the embodiment of collective psyche, however, his experience expresses a collective confrontation with the traditional other represented by the Indians. Campbell describes this archetypal encounter and its significance:
Theres a lot in you thats neither being carried into this persona system nor into your ego, as part of what you perceive as you. Just opposite to the ego, buried in the unconscious, is what Jung calls the shadow. [] The nature of your shadow is a function of the nature of your ego. It is the backside of your light side. In the myths, the shadow is represented as the monster that has to be overcome, the dragon. It is the dark thing that comes up from the abyss and confronts you the minute you begin moving down into the unconscious. It is the thing that scares you so that you dont want to go down there. (2004: 73)

Two streams are developing together, therefore: Murdock as individual confronting his personal shadow tied to his ancestry; and Murdock as westerner confronting the shadow of the Indian. Jung wrote plentifully about the conflict between westerners and indigenous Americans as a projection of the European shadow content upon the radical other. Projection implies lack of conscious awareness of such a process, and thus the Indian who is labelled savage and barbarous reflects the savage and barbarous nature of the European/American: I have frequently observed in the analysis of Americans that the inferior side of the personality, the shadow, is represented by a Negro or Indian (1956: 183). Jung perceives in individual psyches the centuries-old conflict across the Americas concerning civilization and barbarism, a debate repeatedly reflected in Borges writing. It is important to note that I am not embarking on a fresh evaluation of the matter of civilization and barbarism in Borges, primarily because such a complex issue requires a deep assessment of Borges relationship with his soldier ancestors, his depiction of the caudillo Rosas, his interpretation of Martn Fierro, gauchos, Indians, knife-fighters and hoodlums, Pern and Evita, the Third Reich, communism, hippies (see Guibert in Burgin

232

Chapter Five

1998: 51), and the military junta of the Dirty War. The conflicting polarities of civilization and barbarism are reflected in his appreciation or dislike of novelists and poets, philosophies, theologies and cosmologies, and in his interpretation of such philosophical dialectics as William James tough-minded or tender-minded, Jungs shadow complex, or Nietzsches articulation of the cosmopolitan Apollonian and the barbarian Dionysian. The debate is central to the Argentine national character and is central to Borges and his readership. For wider analysis see: Balderston (1993), Ulla (2002), Williamson (2004), and Orrego Arismendi (2007). Importantly for Borges, however, the time-worn debate evoked in the sixteenth century by Las Casas and Seplveda and rearticulated by Sarmiento cannot be reduced to a simple binary. As indicated by the enumeration above, barbarism is visible in Borges work in many guises beyond the mythical Indian, and indeed constitutes an essential characteristic of the individual psyche. In this way one can see Dahlmanns journey into the unconscious in the tale El Sur [The South] leading him to confrontation with his shadow projection, the gauchos. In this tale the gaucho represents the brutish opposite of Dahlmann uncultured, instinctive, dealing not with abstraction but tangible reality but also, conversely, what Dahlmann most desires. Such an interpretation is reinforced by the idea that Borges himself supported, that Dahlmanns whole adventure into the pampa was a dream, and hence a compensatory vision of unconscious desire.7 The integration of the shadow, in this case through the ritual death with the assistance of the senex figure who throws him the knife, is one of compen-

It [The South] can be read in two ways. You may read it in a straightforward way and you may think that those things happen to a hero. Then, you may think theres a kind of moral behind it the idea that he loved the south and in the end the south destroyed him. But theres another possibility, the possibility of the second half of the story which is hallucination. When the man is killed, hes not really killed. He died in the hospital, and though that was a dream, a kind of wishful thinking, that was the kind of death he would have liked to have in the pampas with a knife in his hand being stabbed to death. That was what he was looking forward to all the time. So Ive written that story in order that it would be read both ways (in Burgin 1998: 8).

Conclusion Confronting the shadow: the heros journey in El Etngrafo

233

sation, and brings about symbolic psychic wholeness. Similarly, in the tale of Brodie El evangelio segn Marcos [The Gospel according to Mark], the protagonist Espinosa and the rustic Gutre family (who themselves are of civilized Scottish ancestry) enact a symbolic union of compensation the civilized embodying the barbarous and vice versa through Espinosas ritual crucifixion. The indio de ojos celestes [Indian with blue eyes] ofEl cautivo [The Captive] is both barbarous and civilized, unable to remain rooted to one polarity. Lastly, as Bell-Villada (1999: 1589) discusses, the tale of Historia del guerrero y de la cautiva [Story of the Warrior and the Captive] concerns the double characterization of the Lombard barbarian warrior who becomes civilized and the civilized Englishwoman who turns savage, but also the pairing of the cautivas the Englishwoman and Borges grandmother, one civilized one savage, both captive; and consequently the double guerrero Droctulf and Colonel Borges. These multiple and subtle pairings in Borges fiction evoke a strongly Jungian alchemical vision of the twin polarities within each individual psyche: light and dark, civilized and barbarous, ego and shadow. It is interesting to note that both Jung and Borges were fascinated by Stevensons tale Strange Case of Dr Jekyll and Mr Hyde (1886), Jung equating Mr Hyde with our shadow (Fordman 1953: 49), Borges acknowledging that his tales Borges y yo, and El otro were adaptations of Stevensons tale (Borges 1982: 166), and that Las ruinas circulares was a retelling of his tale El Golem, which itself follows Wildes Picture of Dorian Gray, which itself was a retelling of Jekyll and Hyde (Barnstone 1982: 82). In brief, therefore, Borges repeatedly evokes the confrontation with the barbarous other, often depicted as fetch, doppelgnger, gaucho, Indian or knife-fighter, who evokes a powerful psychic drive within the civilized protagonists and whose integration is often evoked by a ritual death. Borges position is strikingly akin to Jungs in this perspective, and importantly can be understood within a framework of the process of individuation, the journey towards psychic wholeness. Just as Dahlmann integrates the shadow of the barbarous in his journey south, so Jung writes of the savage or the primitive within us whose integration likewise propels the individual or the collective towards wholeness: Indeed, for a wide-awake person, the primitive contents may often prove to be a source of renewal (1993: 195). And just

234

Chapter Five

as Borges recognized the cult of violence that lay within his psyche hidden beneath layers of language, literature and culture, so Jung recounts in his memoirs a primitive figure who appeared in a dream and who led him to conclude that: The small, brown-skinned savage who accompanied me [] was an embodiment of the primitive shadow (1989: 181). Murdock endures the arduous separation from home, friends, family, customs and even his language over his two-year encampment on the plains. He confronts a deeper aspect of the barbarous shadow, both on a personal and collective level, with the great challenge to the deep-set epistemological certainties that his culture had instilled in him: lleg a pensar de una manera que su lgica rechazaba (1975a: 48) [he came to see things in a way his reason rejected]. This is the result of his many months of apprenticeship, his dialogue with the tribal sacerdote [medicine man], his rigorous moral and physical exercises and his awakening understanding of the language of dreams. It is at this level that the most profound transformation occurs with Murdock, discernible in his realization that en las noches de luna llena soaba con bisontes (1975a: 48) [on nights when the moon was full he dreamed of bison].8 This insight, which he relays to the medicine man, signifies the conclusion of his sojourn on the prairie and he returns home. Importantly, Murdock has engaged on the heros journey a narrative encountered in countless myths (Campbell) and dreams ( Jung) allegorizing the journey inward into the unconscious (Campbell 2004: 11133). Having heeded the herald (his professor) and headed out to the prairie, having undergone trials and training, he encounters in his dreams the tribes totem animal, the bison. The bison represents another shadow projection of Western history, as they were slaughtered en masse during the final decades of the nineteenth century in order to drive the nomadic tribes into the reservations and make way for cattle. Campbell explored the importance of the buffalo in Native American myths, discussing the impact of the slaughter in depth with Bill Moyers: That was a sacramental violation. [] The frontiersmen shot down whole herds, taking only the skins

Di Giovanni mistakenly translates bisontes as mustang. I am unable to determine how that mistake arose.

Conclusion Confronting the shadow: the heros journey in El Etngrafo

235

to sell and leaving the bodies there to rot. That was a sacrilege. It turned the buffalo from a thou to an it (Campbell 1988: 78).9 The slaughter of the bison was not simply a strategy to assist ethnic translocation; it was also, as Campbell observes, an attempt to erase the animal nature from within the Euro-American psyche, concomitant with a refusal to acknowledge the shadow. Jung intuited that such acts of extreme aggression arose from a fear of the unconscious content: When I see a man in a savage rage with something outside himself, I know that he is, in reality, wanting to be savage toward his own unconscious self (1993: 16). Murdock has thus passed through a threshold from one mythic order represented by razn [reason] and ciencia [science] into another represented by dreams, the full moon and the totem animal. Everything has changed for Murdock. He had set out on the adventure at the behest of the professor in order to study indigenous languages and later to present the thesis. After radical separation from home and a new vision of reality, he returns home and, like the captive of the eponymous tale, he feels homesick for the prairie. He returns to the professor and informs him that he will not present the thesis. What has changed? There are many aspects to this question. Firstly, on an individual basis, Murdock has atoned for his ancestor who died in a skirmish with the Indians. This family lineage is symbolic of a collective need to atone for the brutality of colonialism. However, the tale is not a discourse in postcolonialism, and atonement for colonialism is a loose interpretation. Murdock has learned to harken to his dreams. Here the aesthetics of Borges and the psychology of Jung come together in harmony. A central pillar of Jungs entire lifes work rests on the importance of dreams, in brief, as messages from the unconscious:
9 Campbell also quotes the famous 1852 letter Chief Seattle wrote to the US President: Your destiny is a mystery to us. What will happen when the buffalo are all slaughtered? The wild horses tamed? What will happen when the secret corners of the forest are heavy with the scent of many men and the view of the ripe hills is blotted by talking wires? Where will the thicket be? Gone! Where will the eagle be? Gone! And what is it to say goodbye to the swift pony and the hunt? The end of living and the beginning of survival (1988: 34).

236

Chapter Five
In the end, we have to ask what the aim of the dream is from a teleological point of view. Why does this persons unconscious wish to show him an image like that? [] The dream is a product of the imagination, a gallery of images, images of protection from some blow that is threatening; the function of the dream is to compensate the conscious attitude. I believe that what dreams show us in vivid and impressive images are our vulnerable points. (1993: 143)

Dreams are cognate with the epistemological value of active imagination and are the fundamental portal for an exploration of the unconscious; they manifest archetypal images and mythic narratives; are habitual factors of synchronicity and as such can operate outside of ego-consciousness, time and space; are pertinent to the psychic and physiological state of the individual; and consequently are of absolute importance for the process of psychic healing.
It is in our dreams that the body makes itself aware to our mind. The dream is in large part a warning of something to come. The dream is the bodys best expression, in the best possible symbol it can express, that something is going wrong. The dream calls our minds attention to the bodys instinctive feeling. If man doesnt pay attention to these symbolic warnings of his body he pays in other ways. A neurosis is merely the bodys taking control, regardless of the conscious mind. (1993: 49)

Borges, as I argued in Chapter Two, likewise pays attention to dreams, recognizing their importance in his own literary production, observing their perennial importance in artistic creativity across cultures, puzzling over their oblique relationship with linear time, and acknowledging that they reveal much of the psychic state of the individual. Borges refers to Jungs deep analysis into dream symbolism, suggesting in El verdugo piadoso [The Pitying Torturer] (one of the Nueve Ensayos Dantescos) that La segunda [conjetura] equipara, segn la doctrina de Jung, las invenciones literarias a las invenciones onricas (1989: 357) [The second conjecture, following the doctrine of Jung, equates literary and oneiric inventions] (2000: 284). This equation of literary and dream creativity is a constant throughout Borges work, and indeed, like Jung, attention to dreams and nightmares

Conclusion Confronting the shadow: the heros journey in El Etngrafo

237

forms a mainstay of his philosophical discourse.10 Los sueos son una obra esttica, quiz la expresin esttica ms antigua. Toma una forma extraamente dramtica (1989: 231) [Dreams are an aesthetic work, perhaps the most ancient aesthetic expression. They take a strangely dramatic form] (1984: 40). Borges places a strong epistemological value on the dreamworld and the aesthetic, and innumerable passages testify to the power of dreams to grant the dreamer knowledge of deeper aspects of the self and further panoramas of landscapes and times. Dreams are crucial, both for Borges and for Jung, in pursuing the path towards psychic well-being. Murdock has thus travelled deep into the unknown, and has released the powerful psychic energy represented by the dream of the bison. This is the energy of healing, the vital force that is essential to the shaman in tribal societies and was essential for Jung. The medicine man himself would have had to walk the similar path of physical and psychological separation, arduous training and attention to dreams prior to gaining the power to heal. Such a process of trauma is documented in the literature concerning shamanism (Eliade 1972, Halifax 1982, McKenna 1991), encapsulated by Campbell: In primal societies, the shaman provides a living conduit between the local and the transcendent. The shaman is one who has actually gone through a psychological crack-up and recovery (2004: xviii). In this respect, the medicine man acts as psychoanalyst for Murdock, guiding him on his exploration of the unconscious, supporting him in the darkness. So strong is that association between shaman and doctor that Campbells explanation of it deserves quoting in full:
Psychoanalysis, the modern science of reading dreams, has taught us to take heed of these unsubstantial images. Also it has found a way to let them do their work. The dangerous crises of self-development are permitted to come to pass under the protecting eye of an experienced initiate in the lore and language of dreams, who then enacts the role and character of the ancient mystagogue, or guide of souls, the initiating medicine man of the primitive forest sanctuaries of trial and initiation. 10 Borges, whilst recognizing the importance of dreams in psychology, is critical of what he feels is scant attention to nightmares: I have read many books on dreams, volumes of psychology, but I never found anything interesting on nightmares (Barnstone 1982: 7).

238

Chapter Five
The doctor is the modern master of the mythological realm, the knower of all the secret ways and words of potency. His role is precisely that of the Wise Old Man of the myths and fairy tales whose words assist the hero through the trials and terrors of the weird adventure. He is the one who appears and points to the magic shining sword that will kill the dragon-terror, tells of the waiting bride and the castle of many treasures, applies healing balm to the almost fatal wounds, and finally dismisses the conqueror, back into the world of normal life, following the great adventure into the enchanted night. (1949: 910)

Murdock returns home radically transformed from the nave and uncritical student that he was prior to his voyage of discovery, and informs his professor that he intends not to publish. This interchange also a symbolic confrontation is of particular importance for an understanding of the psychological processes of the narrative. Murdock has changed but the academy has not. He has activated a powerful force of psychic energy through his journey, and yet the wisdom gained lies beyond the strict measures of academic discourse. His professor is visibly displeased with this judgement and snidely alludes to the fact that Murdock has abandoned his culture and language, that he has gone native. But Murdock does not intend to return to the prairie; he has integrated the psychic force represented by the shadow figures of the Indian and the bison, and has returned to his cultural home. The westerner, Jung argued, cannot pretend that his roots lie elsewhere and that his psychic constitution is other than its particular cultural formation. Jung, perhaps problematically from our twenty-first century outlook, perceived certain people, such as the Taos Pueblo Indians or the eastern Africans, operating with a more direct, unconscious and less ego-orientated psychic structure than the Europeans ( Jung 1989). He consequently advised against an abandonment of the storm-lantern of the ego (Von Franz 1975: 41), not allowing it to be engulfed in the dark seas of the unconscious. For this reason, as documented in his memoirs, he broke up a festive nocturnal drum and dance ceremony in the Sudan as he felt threatened by the overwhelming forces of unconscious energy: At that time I was obviously all too close to going black (1989: 271);11
11 I was not to recognize the real nature ofthis disturbance until some years later, when I stayed in tropical Africa. It had been, in fact, the first hint of going black under

Conclusion Confronting the shadow: the heros journey in El Etngrafo

239

and, as Schlamm (2010) discusses, he was unwilling to meet Hindu gurus whilst on his trip to India in 1938, erroneously believing them to advocate ego abandonment. This also explains his fears over the use of psychedelic drugs (Von Franz 1971: 41). Murdock has not turned his back on his culture, nor has he abandoned ego-consciousness, but has chosen to return with the shadow energy fully integrated. The hero must always return. Here a further dynamic is established between Murdocks journey and the process of individuation. Borges, as established, was a close reader of William James (as was his father and Macedonio Fernndez). In particular, Borges evaluation of mysticism owes much to the four characteristics of mystical states articulated by James in Varieties (1902: 380): ineffability, noetic quality, transiency and passivity. Borges reading of Angelus Silesius, Meister Eckhart, Emmanuel Swedenborg and Blake (all of whom Jung also read) demonstrates his employment of these four terms in navigating the ontologically challenging texts. His own two mystical experiences, as I analysed in Chapter Two, furthermore, conform to these characteristics. The noetic and the ineffable are of crucial importance in our evaluation of Murdocks experience, as he has acquired wisdom, yet is unable to express it in arid academic prose that lacks the vocabulary of the experience. Murdock, like Borges, experienced something mystical, noetic yet ineffable, instructive yet beyond language. This has a further relationship with Jung, for whom the process of individuation the heros journey will constellate archetypal images which are endowed with numinosity. In a 1945 letter, Jung accredits his work as a medical doctor as healing through the numinous a potent statement that binds him with the shamans and medicine men of tribal cultures:
I know it is exceedingly difficult to write anything definite or descriptive about the progression of psychological states. It always seemed to me as if the real milestones were certain symbolic events characterized by a strong emotional tone. You are quite right, the main interest of my work is not concerned with the treatment of neuroses but rather with the approach to the numinous. But the fact that the approach to the

the skin, a spiritual peril which threatens the uprooted European in Africa to an extent not fully appreciated ( Jung 1989: 245).

240

Chapter Five
numinous is the real therapy and inasmuch as you attain to the numinous experiences you are released from the curse of pathology. Even the very disease takes on a numinous character. ( Jung, in Hollis and Rosen 2003: 120)

Within Jungs dynamic process, therefore, one cannot separate healing from the numinous, or, as Campbell expresses it, healing is made possible by becoming transparent to the transcendent (2004: xvii). Thus Murdocks journey and the revelation it affords him is a voyage of healing. But what was Murdocks (psycho)pathology prior to his journey? Here, as described above, it is important to consider Murdock embodying a collective psyche. In response to his professor, Murdock declares that la ciencia, nuestra ciencia, me parece una mera frivolidad (1975a: 48) [science our science seems not much more than a trifle]. Whilst on the prairie, lleg a pensar de una manera que su lgica rechazaba (1975a: 48) [he came to see things in a way his reason rejected]. Logic and science, the quintessence of the western dream of civilization, led Murdocks ancestor to die fighting the Indians, and led his collective ancestors to slaughter the buffalo and herd the Indians into reservations. Logic and science deny the epistemological value and validity of fantasy, imagination, mythology and the dreamworld, the very lifeblood of the Indian community with whom Murdock resides and the very source of Borges and Jungs aesthetic and psychological project. The numinous is taboo, and nowhere more than the university; and the professor is the stalwart representative of his institution. Murdocks professor advised him to head out to the prairie and to observe the rites and que descubriera el secreto que los brujos revelan al iniciado (1975a: 46) [to uncover the medicine mans secret],12 an eccentric research proposal for one studying lenguas indgenas [aboriginal languages]. He is then irked by Murdocks later decision not to publish. Orrego Arismendi, one ofthe few scholars to have scrutinized El Etngrafo, suggests that the professor is a likely analogue of Borges, ansioso por saber lo que pasa por la mente nativa como solo podra estarlo el mismo Borges (2007: 49) [eager, like Borges himself, to know what goes through the native mind] (my translation), owing primarily to his thirst to know these
12 Di Giovannis translation is here also imprecise.

Conclusion Confronting the shadow: the heros journey in El Etngrafo

241

hidden secrets. This is a possible interpretation, if, for example, we correlate it to Borges desire whilst in Japan to examine his own mystical experiences with Shinto monks. However, another angle would be to view the professor, un hombre entrado en aos (1975a: 46) [a man getting along in years], as one who has failed to engage in the process of individuation, nevertheless knowing that something is missing that he wishes to recover. Like the bride-snatcher depicted by Campbell (2004: 118), he is unwilling to venture on the journey himself; or, like the mythical King Mark, who entrusts Tristan to bring back his bride Iseult, unconsciously willing that Tristan does fall in love with her; or King Arthur, who unwittingly invites Lancelot and Guinevere to love, the professor seeks to seize the treasure by proxy, all the while unconsciously resigned to the understanding that the journey is the treasure. Murdock tells him as much: El secreto, por lo dems, no vale lo que valen los caminos que me condujeron a l. Esos caminos hay que andarlos (1975a: 48) [The secret, I should tell you, is not as valuable as the steps that brought me to it. Those steps have to be taken, not told]. Murdock here acts the same role as Bjarni Thorkelsson in Borges tale Undr, who, when exhorted by the narrator to reveal the secret word, declines, stating that: He jurado no revelarla. Adems, nadie puede ensear nada. Debes buscarla solo (1989: 50) [I have sworn not to divulge it. Besides, nobody can teach anything. You must find it out for yourself ] (1979: 61). The professors psychic state corresponds to that described by Jung as exhibiting critical conflation of ego and persona and a pathological denial of unconscious content (see, for example, his essay Does the World Stand on the Verge of a Spiritual Rebirth? [1993: 6776]). The professor represents the state of psychic disharmony that would be harmonized by the journey of the hero the process of individuation and as such his character is crucial for an understanding of the development of the tale. Murdock is empowered by his experience. He has undergone a physical and spiritual adventure, has encountered the shadow, has learned from the senex, has experienced the numinous, and has returned enriched. And his adventure does not end there; the final words of the tale can be interpreted as his experience of the anima (for explanation of animus/a see Kast 2006) in the figure of his wife; and, as with the shadow figure, he assimilates rather than becomes this figure, symbolized by divorce. He then finds

242

Chapter Five

work in the library, a location depicted symbolically by Borges as the vault of human memory and knowledge, and thus Murdock inhabits a psychic state representing perennial wisdom. Murdocks journey thus constitutes an archetypal voyage of the hero, illustrated in its perennial stages by Campbells Monomyth. In this way this tale and other tales of Borges reveal an unconscious prevailing force towards psychic wholeness, towards the self. It is at this level that Borges as poet/ author can be traced along the pathway of individuation, seeking the elusive centre of the mandala-labyrinth. Importantly for this book, however, is the evocation both by Jung as psychologist and Borges as artist of a dynamic process that underscores an individuals search for selfhood and knowledge, described by Jung as individuation, and depicted by Borges as the search for God, the god in the making (Burgin 1998: 209, 241; Barnstone 1982: 109), his poem Elogio de la sombra: Llego a mi centro, / a mi algebra y mi clave, / a mi espejo (1975a: 126) [I reach my center, / my algebra and my key, / my mirror], or his perennial search for the true identity of Borges. Such a process is portrayed in numerous tales and poems and is reflected in his reading matter, such as Sufi mystics, Swedenborg and Dante. El Etngrafo, an understudied tale, exhibits characteristics germane to the heros journey, a quest for knowledge integral to a process of healing. What Murdock learns out in the desert heals his soul. And what does he learn? We must go to the desert to find out.

Bibliography

Borges, Jorge Luis, Silvina Ocampo & Adolfo Bioy Casares, eds, Antologia de la Literatura Fantstica (Buenos Aires, Sudamericana, 1940). Other Inquisitions, 19371952 (New York: Washington Square Press, 1964). and Margarita Guerrero, El libro de los seres imaginarios (Buenos Aires: Emec, 1967). Dreamtigers, Mildred Boyer and Harold Morland, trans. (New York: E.P. Dutton, 1970). The Aleph and Other Stories, 19331969, Norman Thomas di Giovanni, ed. and trans. (New York: Dutton, 1971a). An Introduction to American Literature (Lexington: University Press of Kentucky, 1971b). Silvina Ocampo & Adolfo Bioy Casares, eds, Extraordinary Tales, Anthony Kerrigan, trans. (New York: Herder & Herder 1971c). Jorge Luis Borges Selected Poems 19231967, Norman Thomas di Giovanni, ed. (London: Allen Lane, The Penguin Press, 1972). and Adolfo Bioy Casares, eds, Cuentos breves y extraordinarios (Buenos Aires: Losada, 1973). Extraordinary Tales, Anthony Kerrigan, trans. (New York: Souvenir Press, 1973). Obras Completas: 19231972 (Buenos Aires: Alianza Emec Editores, 1974). In Praise of Darkness, Norman Thomas di Giovanni, trans. (London: Allen Lane, 1975). Walt Whitman: Man and Myth, Critical Inquiry 1/4 ( Jun., 1975b), 70718. Labyrinths, Donald A. Yates and James E. Irby, eds, various trans. (London: Penguin, 1976). The Book ofSand, Norman Thomas di Giovanni and Alastair Reid, trans. (London: Penguin, 1979). and Adolfo Bioy Casares, eds, Libro del cielo y del infierno (Buenos Aires: Sur, 1983). Seven Nights, trans. Eliot Weinberger (University of Michigan: New Directions, 1984). Atlas, trans. Anthony Kerrigan (New York: E P Dutton, 1985) and Margarita Guerrero, The Book of Imaginary Beings, Norman Thomas di Giovanni, trans. (London: Penguin, 1987).

244 Bibliography
Silvina Ocampo & Adolfo Bioy Casares, eds, The Book of Fantasy (New York: Viking, 1988) Obras Completas: 19751985 (Buenos Aires: Emec Editores, 1989). Prologue to Xul Solar, Catlogo de obras del Museo (Buenos Aires: Fundacin Pan Klub, 1990). Historia universal de la infamia (Buenos Aires: Emec, 1991). Obra Potica 19231977 (Buenos Aires: Emec, 1993). Testimony to the Invisible, in Lawrence, ed., 1995, 316. The Total Library: Non-fiction, 19221986, Esther Allen, Suzanne Jill Levine & Eliot Weinberger, trans., Eliot Weinberger ed. (London: Allen Lane, The Penguin Press, 2000). Borges Profesor, Martn Arias and Martn Hadis, eds (Buenos Aires: Emec, 2002). and Ernesto Sbato, Dilogos (Buenos Aires: Emec, 2002) Obra Completa IV: 19751988 (Buenos Aires: Emec Editores, 2005). Brodies Report, Andrew Hurley, ed. and trans. (London: Penguin, 2006). On Mysticism, Mara Kodama, ed. (London: Penguin, 2010). Alifano, Roberto, ed., Twenty Four Conversations with Borges, N. S Araz, W. Barnstone & N. Escandell, trans. (Massachusetts: Lascaux Publishers, 1984). Alazraki, Jaime, Critical Essays on Jorge Luis Borges (Boston: G.K. Hall, 1987). Alazraki, Jaime, Borges and the Kabbalah and Other Essays on His Fiction and Poetry (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988). Almeida, Ivn, Borges and Peirce, on abduction and maps, Semiotica 1401/4 (2002), 1331. Ankarsj, Magnus, William Blake and religion: a new critical view ( Jefferson, North Carolina: McFarland, 2009). Ayora, Jorge, Gnosticism and Time in El Inmortal Hispania 56/3 (1973), 5936. Baba, Meher, God in a Pill? (California: Sufism Reoriented, 1966). Bez-Rivera, Emilio R. Swedenborg and Borges: from the Mystic of the North to the Mystic in puribus, in McNeilly, ed., 2004, 7191. Bald, Margaret, Banned Books: Literature Suppressed on Religious Grounds (New York: Facts on File Inc., 2006). Balderston, Daniel, Out of context: historical reference and the representation of reality in Borges (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1993). Barili, Amelia, Borges on Life and Death, in Burgin, ed., 1998, 2409. Barili, Amelia, Borges, Buddhism and Cognitive Science. A New Approach to Applied Cognitive Science and Contemplative Studies across Disciplines, Religion East and West. Journal of the Institute for World Religions (Berkeley, Institute for World Religions, 9, 2009), 4758.

Bibliography

245

Barnstone, Willis, ed., Borges at Eighty: Conversations (Indiana University Press, 1982). Barnstone, Willis, With Borges on an ordinary evening in Buenos Aires: a memoir (University of Illinois Press, 2000). Bell-Villada, Gene H., Borges and his fiction: a guide to his mind and art (Texas Pan American series, 1999). Bergquist, Lars, Swedenborg and Heavenly Hermeneutics, in McNeilly ed., 2002, 97110. Bioy Casares, Adolfo, Borges (Barcelona: Ediciones Destino, 2006). Bossart, W.H., Borges and Philosophy: Self, Time and Metaphysics (New York: Peter Lang, 2003). Bosteels, Bruno, Borges as Antiphilosopher, Vanderbilt e-Journal of Luso-Hispanic Studies 3 (2006), 2331. Bosteels, Bruno, The Truth Is In the Making: Borges and Pragmatism, The Romanic Review 98/ 23 (2007), 13551. Bourne, Daniel. A Conversation with Jorge Luis Borges. Artful Dodge (College of Wooster, Ohio) April 25, 1980. < http://www3.wooster.edu/artfuldodge/ interviews/borges.htm>. Brescia, Pablo, A Superior Magic: Literary politics and the rise of the fantastic in Latin American fiction, Forum for Modern Language Studies 44/4 (2008), 37993. Brown, Sir Thomas, Religio Medici (Kessinger Publishing, 2003). Burgin, Richard, ed., Conversations with Jorge Luis Borges (Florida: Holt, Rinehart & Winston, 1969). Burgin, Richard, ed., Jorge Luis Borges: Conversations ( Jackson: University Press of Mississippi, 1998). Campbell, Joseph, The Hero with a Thousand Faces (New York: Bollingen Foundation, Pantheon Books, 1949). Campbell, Joseph, The Power of Myth, with Bill Moyers (New York: Doubleday, 1988). Campbell, Joseph, Pathways to Bliss (California: New World Library, 2004). Canto, Estela, Borges a Contraluz (Barcelona: Espasa Calpe, 1999). Chadwick, John, Swedenborg and his readers Selected Essays, Stephen McNeilly, ed. (London: The Swedenborg Society 2003). Christ, Ronald, Jorge Luis Borges, The Art of Fiction. Interview, The Paris Review 40, WinterSpring, 1967. Christ, Ronald J., The Narrow Act (New York University Press, 1969). Christ, Ronald, et. al., Borges at NYU, in Burgin 1998, 11838. Cohen, J.M., Jorge Luis Borges (Edinburgh: Oliver and Boyd, 1973). Coleman, Alexander, Notes on Borges and American Literature, TriQuarterly 25 (1972), 35677.

246 Bibliography
Conan Doyle, Arthur, The Story of Swedenborg, in McNeilly, ed., 2005, 95111. Cortnez, Carlos, ed., Borges the Poet (Fayettevill: University of Arkansas Press, 1986). de Costa, Ren, Humor in Borges: Humor in Life and Letters (Detroit, MI: Wayne State University Press, 2000). Daniels, Michael, Making Sense of Mysticism, Transpersonal Psychology Review 7/1 (2003), 3955. Deck, Raymond H. Jr., New Light on C.A. Tulk, Studies in Romanticism 16/2 (Spring, 1977), 21736. Doblin, Rick, Pahnkes Good Friday Experiment A Long-Term Follow-Up and Methodological Critique, The Journal of Transpersonal Psychology 23/1 (1991), 128. Dutton, Denis, Merely a Man of Letters: Jorge Luis Borges: an interview, Philosophy and Literature 1/3 (1977), 33741. Ellwood, Robert S., Mysticism and Religion (Seven Bridges Press, 1999). Emerson, Ralph Waldo, Essays And Poems, Peter Norberg ed. (Spark Educational Publishing, 2005) Emerson, Ralph Waldo, Emerson on Swedenborg: Introducing the Mystic, Stephen McNeilly ed. (London: The Swedenborg Society, 2003). Engudanos, Miguel, et. al. A writer is waiting for his own work, in Barnstone 1982, 91101. Engudanos, Miguel, et. al. Now I am more or less who I am, in Burgin 1998, 16476. Earle, Peter G., Review: The Secret of Borges. A Psychoanalytic Inquiry into His Work by Julio Woscoboinik, Hispanic Review 68.1 (2000), 99101. Eliade, Mircea, Shamanism: Archaic Techniques of Ecstasy (New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1972). Erdman, David V., Blakes Early Swedenborgianism: A Twentieth-Century Legend, Comparative Literature 5/3 (Summer, 1953), 24757. Fernandes, Marcel, Borges and Pragmatism: Borges, William James, and the Destruction of Philosophy, PhD Thesis (University of Otago, Dunedin, New Zealand, March 2008). Ferrer, Jorge, Revisioning Transpersonal Theory: A Participatory Vision of Human Spirituality (New York: Suny Press, 2002). Flynn, Annette, The Quest for God in the Work of Borges (London and New York: Continuum International Publishing Group, 2009). Fordman, Frieda, An Introduction to Jungs Psychology (London: Penguin, 1953). De Garayalde, Giovanna, Jorge Luis Borges sources and illumination (London: Octagon Press, 1978).

Bibliography

247

Garca, Humberto, In the Name of the Incestuous Mother: Islam and Excremental Protestantism in De Quinceys Infidel Book, Journal for Early Modern Cultural Studies 7/2 (FallWinter, 2007), 5787. Garrett, Clarke, Swedenborg and the Mystical Enlightenment in Late EighteenthCentury England, Journal of the History of Ideas 45/1 ( JanMar., 1984), 6781. Giskin, Howard, The Mystical Experience in Borges: A Problem of Perception, Hispanfila 98/2 (1990), 7185. Goloboff, Gerardo Mario, Ser Hombre: Exploracin del Tema del Otro en un Soneto de Jorge Luis Borges, Revista Iberoamericana 43/100101 (1977), 57589. Green, Celia Elizabeth, Lucid dreaming: the paradox of consciousness during sleep (London; Routledge, 1994). Grof, Stanislav, The Cosmic Game: Explorations in the Frontiers of Human Consciousness (Dublin: Newleaf, 1998). Guibert, Rita, Interview with Jorge Luis Borges, in Burgin 1998, 4276. Halifax, Joan, Shaman: the wounded healer (London: Thames and Hudson, 1982). Holditch, Kenneth, Borges and Emerson: The Poet as Intellectual, in Cortnez, ed., 1986, 197206. Hollis, James and David Rosen, The Archetypal Imagination (Texas: A&M University Press, 2003). Hurth, Elisabeth, The Poet and the Mystic: Ralph Waldo Emerson and Jakob Bhme ZAA (Zeitschrift fr Anglistik und Amerikanistik) 53/4 (2005), 33352. Huxley Aldous, The Doors of Perception (Chatto and Windus, 1954). Inge, William Ralph, Christian Mysticism (Methuen, 1913). Inge, William Ralph, Mysticism in Religion (London: Hutchinsons University Library 1947). Jaff, Aniela, Was C.G. Jung a Mystic? And Other Essays (Einsiedeln: Daimon Verlag, 1989). James, William, Varieties of Religious Experience (London: Longmans, Green & Co., 1913). James, William, Letters of William James, Henry James, ed. (Kessinger Publishing, 2003). James, William, A Suggestion about Mysticism, The Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods 7/4 (1910), 8592. Jantzen, Grace, Power, Gender and Christian Mysticism (Cambridge University Press, 1995). Jay, Mike, Emperors of Dreams: Drugs in the Nineteenth Century (Cambridgeshire: Dedalus, 2000). Johnson, Gregory R. William James on Swedenborg: A Newly Discovered Letter Studia Swedenborgiana 13: 2 (2003) <http://www.baysidechurch.org/studia>.

248 Bibliography
Jung, C.G., Tipos psicolgicos, Ramn de la Serna, trans. (Buenos Aires: Editorial Sudamericana, 1945). Jung, C.G., Symbols of Transformation: An Analysis of the Prelude to a Case of Schizophrenia (New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1956). Jung, C.G., Flying Saucers: A Modern Myth of Things Seen in the Sky (Collected Works 10: Civilization in Transition, 1958), 307437. Jung, C.G., Alchemical Studies, R.F.C. Hull, ed., Gerhard Adler, trans. (Collected Works 13, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1983). Jung, C.G., Memories, Dreams, Reflections, Aniela Jaff, ed. (New York: Vintage Books, 1989). Jung C.G. C.G. Jung Speaking: Interviews and Encounters, William McGuire and R.F.C. Hull, eds (Princeton University Press, 1993). Jung, C.G., Jung on active imagination: key readings, Joan Chodorow, ed. (London: Routledge, 1997). Jung, C.G., The Red Book, Sonu Shamdasani, ed. (New York: W.W. Norton & Co., 2009). Jung, C.G., C.G. Jung Speaking: Interviews and Encounters, William McGuire and R.F.C. Hull, eds (New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1993). Jurado, Alicia, Genio y figura de Jorge Luis Borges (Editorial Universitaria de Buenos Aires, 1996). Kast, Verena, Anima/animus, in The Handbook of Jungian Psychology: Theory, Practice and Applications, Renos K. Papadopoulos, ed. (London: Routledge, 2006), 94113. Kripal, Jeffrey, Roads of Excess, Palaces of Wisdom: Eroticism & Reflexivity in the Study of Mysticism (University of Chicago Press, 2001). Kristal, Efran, Invisible Work: Borges and Translation (Vanderbilt University Press, 2002). Lachman, Gary, Swedenborg: An Introduction to His Life and Ideas (Penguin Group US, 2012) Lachman, Gary, Jung the Mystic: The Esoteric Dimensions of Carl Jungs Life and Teachings (Tarcher, 2010). Lawrence, James, ed., Testimony to the Invisible: Essays on Swedenborg (Pennsylvania: Chrysalis Books, 1995). Lawrence, James F., Swedenborgs Trail in the Coleridgean Landscape , Studia Swedenborgiana 11/2 (1999): 5566. Lezama Lima, Jos, Diarios 19391949 / 19561958, Ciro Bianchi Ross, ed. (Havana: UNEAC, 2001). Main, Roderick, The Rupture of Time: Synchronicity and Jungs Critique of Modern Western Culture (Hove, East Sussex: Brunner-Routledge, 2004).

Bibliography

249

McDannell, Colleen and Bernhard Lang, Heaven: A History (London: Vintage 1990). McKenna, Terence (1991) The Archaic Revival (San Francisco: Harper). Stephen McNeilly, ed., On the true philosopher and the true philosophy: essays on Swedenborg (London: Swedenborg Society, 2002). Stephen McNeilly, ed., In Search of the Absolute: Essays on Swedenborg and Literature (London: Swedenborg Society, 2004). McNeilly, Stephen, ed., Between Method and Madness: Essays on Swedenborg and Literature (London: The Swedenborg Society, 2005). Milosz, Czeslaw, Dostoevsky and Swedenborg, in Lawrence, ed., 1995, 1951. Molloy, Sylvia, Signs of Borges (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1994). Montaigne, Michel de, The Complete Essays of Michel de Montaigne, 2 Vols (Forgotten Books, 1910). Moss, Robert. Dreamgates: an explorers guide to the worlds of soul, imagination, and life beyond death (New York: Three Rivers Press, 1998). Mualem, Shlomy, The Imminence of Revelation: Aesthetics and Poetic Expression in Early Wittgenstein and Jorge Luis Borges, Variaciones Borges 18 (2004), 197217. Nubiola, Jaime Jorge Luis Borges and WJ, Streams of William James 1/3 (Winter 2000), 7. Nubiola, Jaime, WJ and Borges Again: The Riddle of the Correspondence with Macedonio Fernndez, Streams of William James 3/2 (Fall 2001), 1011. Nubiola, Jaime Jorge Luis Borges y William James: Aproximaciones a la obra de William James: la formulacin del pragmatismo (Biblioteca Nueva, Universidad Complutense de Madrid, 2005), 20118. Nez-Faraco, Humberto, Borges and Dante: Echoes of a Literary Friendship (Oxford and Bern: Peter Lang, 2006). Orrego Arismendi, Juan Carlos, Borges: sus cuentos sobre indios araucanos y el siglo XIX, Variaciones Borges 24 (2007), 3555. Pahnke, Walter, Drugs and Mysticism, The International Journal of Parapsychology, 8/2 (Spring 1966), 295313. Portugal M. Saliba, Ana Maria, Borges y Freud: Conjunciones, Variaciones Borges 12 (2001) 17992. Quinn, Patrick, Emerson and Mysticism, American Literature 21/4 ( Jan 1950), 397414. Raine, Kathleen, Poetry in relation to traditional wisdom Temenos Academy Review, 10 (2007), 2136. Raine, Kathleen, The Human Face of God, in Lawrence, ed., 1995, 5189. Rawlinson, Andrew, The book of enlightened masters: western teachers in eastern traditions (Chicago: Open Court, 1998).

250 Bibliography
Rix, Robert, William Blake and the cultures of radical Christianity (London: Ashgate Publishing, Ltd., 2007). Rodrguez Monegal, Emir, Jorge Luis Borges: A literary Biography (New York: Dutton, 1978). Rodrguez Monegal, Emir, Borges and Derrida: Apothecaries, in Borges and His Successors: The Borgesian Impact on Literature and the Arts, ed. Edna Aizenberg (Columbia, MO: University of Missouri Press, 1990), 12855. Rodrguez Risquete, Francisco, Borges: fervor de Dante, Quaderns dItali 10 (2005), 195218. Romero, Oswaldo, Dios en la Obra de Jorge L. Borges: Su Teologa y su Teodicea, Revista Iberoamericana 43/100101 (1977), 465503. Rowlandson, William Borgess Reading of Dante and Swedenborg: Mysticism and the Real Variaciones Borges 32 (2011), 5987. Rowlandson, William, The Anaesthetic Revelation: Psychedelia and Mysticism, in Cameron Adams, Anna Waldstein, Ben Sessa, David Luke and David King (eds) Breaking Convention: Essays on Psychedelic Consciousness (London: Strange Attractor, 2013, in press) 23442. Rowlandson, William, Reading Lezamas Paradiso (Oxford, Peter Lang, 2007). Russell, Bertrand, Mysticism, in Religion and Science (Oxford University Press, 1961), 17190. Salas, Susana Chica, Conversacin con Borges, Revista Iberoamericana 42/9697 (1976), 58591. Schlamm, Leon, Revisiting Jungs dialogue with yoga: observations from transpersonal psychology, International Journal of Jungian Studies 2/1 (2010), 3244. Schopenhauer, Arthur, The World as Will and Representation, Vol. II (Courier Dover Publications, 1966). Schorer, Mark, Blake and Swedenborg, Modern Philology, 36 (1938), 15778. Schuchard, Marsha Keith, Why Mrs Blake Cried: William Blake and the Erotic Imagination (Century First Edition, 2006). Shenker, Israel, Borges, a Blind Writer with Insight, New York Times (6 April 1971). Smith, Huston, Cleansing the Doors of Perception: the religious significance of entheogenic plants and chemicals (Sentient Publications, 2000). Sorrentino, Fernando, Siete conversaciones con Jorge Luis Borges (Buenos Aires: Editorial El Ateneo, 2001). Soud, Stephen E., Borges the Golem-Maker: Intimations of Presence in The Circular Ruins, MLN 110/4 (1995), 73954. Staal, Frits, Exploring Mysticism (Berkeley, Los Angeles, London: University of California Press, 1975). Stace, W.T., The Teachings of the Mystics (New York: Macmillan, 1960).

Bibliography

251

Stace, W.T., Mysticism and Philosophy (London: Macmillan, 1961). Stephens, Matthew, Borges and WJ Revisited Streams of William James 2/3 (Fall 2000), 12. Suzuki, D.T., Zen Buddhism: Selected Writings of D.T. Suzuki (New York: Anchor Books, 1956). Swedenborg, Emanuel, Heaven and Hell (De Coelo et Ejus Mirabilibus, et de Inferno, ex Auditis et Visis [London 1758]) George F. Dole, trans. (London: Swedenborg Foundation New Century Edition), 2000. Swedenborg, Emanuel, Arcana Coelestia [London 1749], John F. Potts, trans. (1910), <www.sacred-texts.com/swd/ac/index.htm>. Swedenborg, Emanuel, Divine Providence [London 1764], William Frederic Wunsch, trans. (1851), <http://www.sacred-texts.com/swd/dpr/index.htm>. Synnestvedt, Sig, ed., Swedenborg, testigo de lo invisible (Buenos Aires: Marymar, 1982). Synnestvedt, Sig, ed., The Essential Swedenborg (New York, Swedenborg Foundation, 1977). Talbot, Brian, Schuchards Swedenborg, The New Philosophy ( JulyDecember 2007), 165218. Taylor, Eugene I. and Robert H. Wozniak, Pure Experience, the Response to William James: An Introduction, in E.I. Taylor & R.H. Wozniak, eds, Pure Experience: The Response to William James (Bristol: Thoemmes Press, 1996), ixxxxii. Taylor, Eugene, Peirce and Swedenborg Studia Swedenborgiana, 6/1 (1986), 255l. Taylor, Eugene, Have we engaged in a colossal misreading of Jamess Varieties? Streams of William James 5/1 (Spring 2003), 27. Taylor, Eugene, Emerson: The Swedenborgian and Transcendentalist Connection, in Lawrence, ed., 1995, 14173. Taylor, Eugene, A Psychology of Spritual Healing (Chrysalis Books, the Swedenborg Foundation, 1997). Tcherepashenets, Nataly, Place and Displacement in the Narrative Worlds of Jorge Luis Borges and Julio Cortzar (New York: Peter Lang, 2008). Ulla, Noem, Notas sobre El cautivo de Jorge Luis Borges, Variaciones Borges 13 (2002), 22733. Underhill, Evelyn, Mysticism: A Study of the Nature and Development of Mans Spiritual Consciousness (New York: E.P. Dutton & Co., 1912). Van Dusen, Wilson, Swedenborgs Spiritual Method, Studia Swedenborgiana, 7/3 (1991), 319. Van Dusen, Wilson, A mystic looks at Swedenborg, in Lawrence, ed., 1995, 10541. Van Dusen, Wilson, The Presence of Other Worlds (Chrysalis Books, the Swedenborg Foundation, 2004).

252 Bibliography
Vzquez Mara Esther, Borges. Imgenes, memorias, dilogos (Caracas, Monte vila, 1977). Von Franz, Marie-Louise, C.G. Jung: his Myth in our time (New York: G.P. Putnams Sons, 1975). Wallace, David Foster, Borges on the Couch, New York Times (7 November, 2004). Warnes, Christopher, Magical Realism and the Postcolonial Novel: Between Faith and Irreverence (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2009). Watts, Alan, Eastern Wisdom, Modern Life: Collected Talks: 19601969 (Novato, California: New World Library, 2006). Watts, Alan, Beat Zen Square Zen and Zen, in The Portable Beat Reader, Ann Charters, ed. (Penguin Classics, 2006), 60715. Webb, James, The Harmonious Circle: The Lives and Work of G.I. Gurdjieff, P.D. Ouspensky, and Their Followers (Boston: Shambhala, 1987). Wellbeloved, Sophia, Gurdjieff : The Key Concepts (London: Routledge, 2003). Wildner Christian, Entrevista realizada por Christian Wildner con Jorge Luis Borges en prlogo a la traduccin por l mismo realizada de Emanuel Swedenborg, El Cielo y sus Maravillas y el Infierno (Buenos Aires, Editorial Kier, 1991) <http:// www.swedenborg.es/borges/borges_wildner.htm>. Williamson, Edwin, Borges: A Life (London: Viking, 2004). Wilson, Colin, The Reality of the Visionary World, in Lawrence, ed., 1995, 89105. Wilson, Jason, Jorge Luis Borges, Critical Lives (London: Reaktion Books, 2006). Woodall, James, Borges: A Life (New York: Basic Books, 1997). Woolger, Roger, Understanding C.G. Jungs Red Book Network Review Journal of the Scientific and Medical Network Journal (Summer 2011), 38. Woscoboinik, Julio, The Secret of Borges: A Psychoanalytic Inquiry into His Work, Dora Carlisky Pozzi trans. (Lanham, MD: University Press of America 1998). Wulff, David, Mystical Experience, in Etzel Cardea, Steven J. Lynn, and Stanley Krippner, eds, Varieties of Anomalous Experience (Washington: American Psychological Association, 2000), 397441. Yates, Donald. Borges: Philosopher? Poet? Revolutionary? in Burgin 1998, 1929. Zaehner, R.C. Mysticism: Sacred and Profane (New York: Oxford University Press, 1961). Yeats, W.B. Swedenborg, Mediums, and the Desolate Places, in W.B. Yeats and Lady Gregory, Visions and Beliefs in the West of Ireland (New York & London: G.P. Putman, 1920), 295339. Yeats, W.B. William Blake and the Imagination, in W.B. Yeats, Ideas of Good and Evil (London: A.H. Bullen, 1903), 16876.

Index

Abramowicz, Maurice, 2223 Alanus de Insulis (Alain de Lille), 117 anomalous human experience (parapsychology, paraphenomena, the occult, etc.), 6, 2130, 914, 10123, 134, 1569, 195 Aristotle, 136, 169 Augustine, St, 28, 110, 156 Baba, Meher, 149, 185 Barili, Amelia, 15, 29, 3943, 195, 198, 222 Bioy Casares, Adolfo, 6, 238, 589, 76, 195, 203, 217 Blake, William, 45, 18, 22, 33, 43, 45, 556, 63, 84, 98, 107, 115, 120, 123, 129, 135, 138, 140, 1434, 15761, 1701, 1823, 188196, 21012, 239 Borges, Jorge Luis aesthetic value of philosophy, 6, 814 agnosticism, 7, 12 -3, 23, 45, 74, 856 ethics, 198203 Hitler, Nazis, Third Reich, 24, 16, 228 in Japan, 989, 108, 113, 159, 191, 241 psychoanalytical reading of, 2279 teaching Borges, 67, 3943 as Virgil, 436 Borges, Jorge Luis, texts discussed or referred to: Abramowicz (Los Conjurados), 2223 Ajedrez [Chess], 154 El Aleph [The Aleph], 4, 8, 43, 767, 804, 100, 10820, 138, 155, 157

Los ngeles de Swedenborg, 194, 2035 Antologa de la literatura fantstica [Extraordinary Tales], 59, 203 Atlas, 1, 30, 104, 154, 194, 221 Autobiographical Essay, 29 La biblioteca de Babel [The Library of Babel], 7, 13, 176 Borges y yo [Borges and I], 220, 233 El ciervo blanco, 105 El Congreso [The Congress], 21, 57, 149 Los Conjurados, 3, 212, 193, 222, 228 Delia Elena San Marco, 73 Dilogo de muertos [Dead mens dialogue], 22, 20514, 221 Doomsday, 22, 193 Duracin del Infierno, 85, 178, 194, 198, 210 Elogio de la sombra [In Praise of Darkness], 3, 12, 104, 153, 165, 198, 209, 21442 El Encuentro [The Meeting], 113, 157 La escritura del dios [The Gods Script], 4, 8, 43, 834 El Etngrafo [The Anthropologist], 22542 Ficciones, 6, 13, 41, 104, 204, 221, 225 Flor de Coleridge, 142, 166 Fragmentos de un evangelio apcrifo [From an apocryphal gospel], 21423 El General Quiroga va en coche al muere [General Quiroga rides to his death in a carriage], 2067

254 Index
Borges, Jorge Luis (cont.) El Hacedor [Dreamtigers], 3, 9, 105, 205 His end and his beginning, 21821 Historia de la eternidad [A History of Eternity], 212, 80, 109, 113, 129, 194 Historia de los ngeles [History of Angels], 15, 60 El idioma analtico de John Wilkens [The Analytical Language of John Wilkens], 13, 15, 175 El Informe de Brodie [Dr Brodies Report], 3, 72, 204, 225, 229, 233 El jardn de senderos que se bifurcan [The Garden of Forking Paths], 7 Leyenda Legend, 208 El Libro de Arena [The Book of Sand], 3, 15, 57, 113, 225 Libro del cielo y del infierno, 195 Libro de los seres imaginarios [Book of Imaginary Beings], 21, 467, 55, 601, 73, 157, 1934, 203, 228 La Memoria de Shakespeare [Shakespeares Memory], 3, 113, 194 El milagro secreto [The Secret Miracle], 22, 84, 105 La muerte y la brjula [Death and the Compass], 7, 13 El muerto [The Dead Man], 176 La muralla y los libros [The Wall & the Books], 12 La nadera de la personalidad [The Nothingness of Personality], 15, 17, 37, 61, 109, 199, 220 Nueva refutacin del tiempo [New Refutation of Time], 80, 194 Nueve Ensayos Dantescos, 49, 66, 228, 236 Pedro Salvadores, 12, 191, 192 Pierre Menard, autor del Quijote [Pierre Menard, author of the The Quixote], 7, 14 Sentirse en muerte mystical experience, 80, 94, 99100, 10820, 123, 129, 149, 1559, 187 Siete Noches [Seven Nights], 3, 31, 33, 35, 41, 48, 69, 71, 99, 103, 105, 133 Qu es el Budismo?, 41 Quevedo, 34 El remordimiento, 218 La Rosa de Paracelsus, 21 Rosas, 2067 Las Ruinas circulares [The Circular Ruins], 21, 56, 72, 84, 104, 221, 233 Ruiseor de Keats [The Nightingale of Keats], 135, 142, 169 Swedenborg, testigo de lo invisible [Testimony to the Invisible], 36, 38, 505, 63, 75, 912, 110, 117, 125, 134, 139, 1436, 150, 155, 162, 166, 171, 1735, 17880, 1823, 192, 196, 200, 2023, 20712 Un telogo en la muerte, 194, 2047, 213, 21921 Tln, Uqbar, Orbis Tertius, 5, 7, 58 Tres versiones de Judas [Three Versions of Judas], 22 Two English Poems, 30 Undr, 1518, 151, 241 Utopa de un hombre que est cansado [Utopia of a Tired Man], 1518 Veinticinco de agosto, 1983, 113, 157, 194 Una vindicacin del falso Baslides [A Vindication of the False Basilides], 21 Borges, Norah, 60

Index
Bhme, Jakob (Boehme or Behmen), 119, 127, 138, 177, 1867, 1901 Bruno, Giordano, 21 Buddhism, 5, 15, 33, 3943, 83, 99, 119, 133, 150, 195, 220 Zen, 989, 133, 150, 185, 215 Caldern de la Barca, Pedro, 105, 220 Campbell, Joseph, 94, 22542 Canto, Estela, 802, 85, 89, 11819, 127 Castillejo, Cristbal de, 278 Cohen, John Michael, 83, 115, 119, 138, 162 Coleridge, Samuel Taylor, 105, 135, 142, 167, 16970, 1889, 196, 211 Conan Doyle, Arthur, 54, 92, 94, 145, 163, 181, 196, 219 Corbin, Henry, 556, 107, 148, 196, 21011, 214, 223 Daniels, Michael, 94100, 1402 Dante Alighieri, 45, 11, 18, 22, 36, 436, 4777, 10518, 150, 158, 17680, 186, 193, 1956, 202, 210, 212, 228, 236, 242 dreams, 4, 18, 2938, 56, 62, 68, 74, 1026, 123, 150, 158, 188, 198, 213, 219, 221, 223, 227, 229, 2347 lucid dreams, 91, 1024, 123, 212 nightmares, 31, 345, 68, 1036, 3467 Dunne, John William, 22, 105, 152 Eckhart, Meister, 45, 8, 1201, 187, 239 Eliade, Mircea, 148, 237 Emerson, Ralph Waldo, 2, 4, 52, 54, 57, 75, 86, 91, 106, 122, 1267, 1305, 139, 145, 1478, 161, 16592, 196, 208 Transcendentalism, 75, 121, 13940, 1679, 192

255
Fernndez, Macedonio, 137, 188, 239 Ficino, Marsilio, 21 Flaubert, Gustave, 52, 75, 196 Flynn, Annette, 369, 101, 10910, 114, 137, 191 Freud, Sigmund, 19, 2279 Grof, Stanislav, 42, 94 Gurdjieff, George Ivanovich, 223 Huxley, Aldous, 22, 94, 122, 141, 149, 185 Inge, William Ralph (Dean Inge), 5, 878, 95, 107, 121 James, Henry, 196 James, Henry, Sr, 52, 130, 139, 188 James, William, 5, 8, 11, 18, 22, 24, 52, 79, 8291, 95102, 10515, 119, 1214, 12563, 167, 16970, 1848, 196, 222, 232, 239 Varieties of Religious Experience, 79, 8891, 95, 119, 127, 132, 1359, 159, 163, 239 Jodorowsky, Alejandro (Alexandro), 225 Juan de la Cruz, San (St John of the Cross), 5, 645, 72, 77, 84, 115, 11718, 145, 162, 187 Jung, Carl Gustav Answer to Job, 15 the hero 22542 individuation, 226, 233, 239, 2412 Memories Dreams Reflections, 20, 29 as mystic and guru, 201 The Red Book, 18, 201, 104, 212 Septem Sermones ad Mortuos, 1534 the shadow, 22542 synchronicity, 258, 236 transcendental function (active imagination), 212, 236 UFOs, 1819

256 Index
Jurado, Alicia, 82, 89, 127 Kabbalah (Cabala), 45, 17, 39, 64, 79, 145, 148, 162, 195 Kant, Immanuel, 9, 11, 18, 59, 61, 93, 137, 139, 159, 169, 170, 183, 188, 196 Kodama, Mara, 22, 835, 114, 119, 222 Kripal, Jeffrey, 6, 31, 39, 82, 113, 121, 123, 128, 133 Lachman, Gary, 20, 31, 91 Lange, Hayde, 301, 104, 154, 221 Lezama Lima, Jos, 557, 176 Luis de Len, 5, 64, 77, 107, 118, 140, 145, 162 McKenna, Terence, 94, 237 Milosz, Czeslaw, 212 Montaigne, Michel de, 268, 1701 Myers, Frederic, 24 Neoplatonism, 4, 21, 85, 142, 146, 167 Novalis, 4, 25 Ocampo, Victoria, 1718 Ocampo, Silvina, 203 Ouspensky, Peter, 223 Pahnke, Walter, 97, 115 Paracelsus, 18, 21 Parmenides, 59, 169 Pascal, 5, 9, 65, 118, 162, 187, 194 Pedro Pramo, 206 Plato, 9, 13, 34, 37, 59, 73, 83, 90, 110, 133, 1356, 142, 1523, 157, 169, 176 Poe, Edgar Allan, 48, 59, 167, 196 postcolonialism, 6, 235 psychedelic, 94, 115, 122, 149, 239 Quiroga, Facundo, 20614, 220 Raine, Kathleen, 52, 56, 63, 176, 211 Reid, Alastair, 43, 45 Rosas, Juan Manuel de, 20614, 220 Russell, Bertrand, 24, 87, 121, 12930, 132, 159, 196 Scholem, Gershom, 1718, 148 Schopenhauer, Arthur, 9, 18, 55, 88, 99100, 136, 140, 151, 183, 196 Schuchard, Marsha Keith, 1467, 163 Scotus Erigena, 45, 59 Shakespeare, William, 63, 76, 105, 118, 152, 1612, 1701, 179, 220 Shamanism, 201, 94, 237, 239 Shaw, George Bernard, 15, 57, 101, 194, 196, 200, 202 Silesius, Angelus, 4, 5, 18, 22, 43, 64, 126, 159, 179, 187, 239 Cherubinischer Wandersmann, 22 Socrates, 37, 133, 152 Staal, Frits, 42, 86, 889, 107, 122, 126, 1301, 144, 150 Stace, Walter, 5, 86, 901, 967, 1012, 1068, 115, 122, 124, 126, 12930, 135, 141 Steiner, Rudolf, 22, 196 Stevenson, Robert Louis, 5, 7, 57, 196 Brownies, 346, 46, 105 Strange Case of Dr Jekyll and Mr Hyde, 345, 233 Sufi mystical poetry, 4, 22, 44, 53, 83, 116, 1556, 242 Suzuki, Daisetsu Teitaro, 94, 96, 99, 150, 197 Swedenborg, Emanuel Arcana Coelestia, 2, 20310, 217 reception in Catholic countries, 1978 doctrine of correspondences, 94, 145, 1746, 188, 202

Index
Heaven and Hell, 12, 22, 45, 47, 54, 56, 59, 123, 128, 143, 1701, 178, 180, 196, 199221 as heterodox or heretic, 636, 77, 94, 106, 123, 178, 181, 187, 192, 199 Melanchthon, 2047, 213, 21921 Moravian Chapel, 146, 18990 psychic or extra-sensory powers, 914 as Viking or as Eric the Red, 2, 36, 51, 173, 178, 211 Teresa de Jess (Teresa de vila, St Teresa), 5, 8, 62, 97, 120, 126, 145, 162, 187 Thousand and One Nights, 6 Underhill, Evelyn, 82, 86, 901, 956, 1067, 113, 115, 1214, 135, 141 Van Dusen, Wilson, 38, 924, 100, 102, 130, 132, 134, 197, 213

257
Von Franz, Marie-Louise, 20, 115, 2389 Watts, Alan, 79, 86, 101, 107, 185 Weatherhead, Leslie Dixon, 48, 59, 645, 72, 77, 108, 118, 194 Wellbeloved, Sophia, 223 Wells, H. G., 5, 48, 59, 179, 197 Western esotericism, 5, 17, 24, 40, 142 Whitman, Walt, 54, 135, 1667, 196, 228 Wilson, Colin, 63, 172 Woolger, Roger, 20 Xul Solar (Oscar Agustn Alejandro Schulz Solari), 5, 77, 80, 126, 157, 1701, 194 Yeats, W. B., 52, 54, 623, 81, 130, 161, 181, 196 Zaehner, R. C., 86, 96, 101, 1067, 115, 122, 135, 141, 150

Você também pode gostar