Você está na página 1de 14

Modal Arguments for Atheism

1 di 14

http://www.infidels.org/library/modern/ryan_stringer/modal-atheism.html

PAID ADVERTISEMENTS

2012 Internet Infidels Fundraising Drive / $30,000.00 of $40,000.00


By providing information which is nearly impossible to find elsewhere, the Secular Web has sought to level the playing field by offering
arguments and evidence challenging supernatural beliefs. In an ocean of religious confusion, help us maintain a drop of sanity! Donate

75.00%
Mi piace

Tweet

submit

StumbleUpon
+1 Recommend this on Google

Home: Library: Modern: Ryan Stringer: Modal Arguments for Atheism

Modal Arguments for Atheism (2012)


Ryan Stringer
1. Introduction
One can put forth different kinds of arguments to defend atheism. One
kind is an evidential argument, where some contingent fact about the
world is cited as evidence against God's existence. Perhaps the most
popular of such arguments is the evidential argument from evil, which
cites the large amount of severe evil or suffering in the world as strong
evidence against God's existence. Other evidential arguments for
atheism include: the argument from scale[1], which cites the scale of
the universe as evidence against God's existence; the argument from
nonbelief[2], which cites the scope of nonbelief in God as evidence
against his existence; and the argument from physical minds[3], which
cites the overwhelming evidence that minds have a physical basis (or
are physically realized) as evidence against God's existence. These
arguments have the probabilistic conclusion that God does not exist,
and thus do not conclusively demonstrate the truth of atheism.
There are also more ambitious logical arguments for atheism, which
attempt to show that either (a) the proposition that God exists is
logically inconsistent with some contingent fact about the world, or (b)
the concept of God is logically incoherent in some way. The first kind of
logical argument resembles evidential arguments because it is based
on some contingent fact about the world. But unlike evidential
arguments, this kind of logical argument purports to conclusively
demonstrate the truth of atheism based on a logical incompatibility
between the cited contingent fact about the world and the proposition
that God exists. The second kind of logical argument is the most
ambitious of them all. Unlike the first kind of logical argument, which
concludes with the contingent truth of atheism, the second kind
concludes with the necessary truth of atheism.
Home
What's New

In addition to the better-known evidential and logical arguments for


atheism, there is a third kind of argument that will be the focus of this
paper: modal arguments for atheism. Unlike the other two kinds, modal
arguments begin with a possibility claimthat some proposition is

09/11/2012 18.40

Modal Arguments for Atheism

2 di 14

Support Us
Bookstore
Kiosk
Library
News Wire
Products
Blog
E-Resources
About Us
FAQ
Honorary Board
Contact Us
Link to Us
Submissions
Search

http://www.infidels.org/library/modern/ryan_stringer/modal-atheism.html

possibly true. But like the second kind of logical argument, modal
arguments conclude with the necessary truth of atheism. Thus modal
arguments appear to be very strong, for they deliver the necessary
truth of atheism on the basis of a mere possibility claim.
In order to show how they contribute to the philosophical defense of
atheism, in this paper I formulate modal arguments for atheism and
then examine the ways a critic might respond to them. Specifically, I
aim to show that modal arguments for atheism either (a) positively
support atheism or (b) at least undermine modal arguments for theism.

2. The General Structure of Modal Arguments for Atheism


Laying out the general structure of modal arguments for atheism
makes it easier to generate concrete examples. With that in mind, their
general structure is as follows:
A. It is possible that p.
B. Necessarily, if it is possible that God exists, then it is
necessary that God exists.
C. Necessarily, if God exists, then it is not the case that p.
D. Therefore, it is not possible that God exists. (from A, B,
& C)
Premise A is the formula for generating the possibility claims that
underlie the modal arguments. Premise B follows from the conception
of God as a necessary being: if God is a being that, conceptually
speaking, exists necessarily, then it is necessarily true that he will exist
in every possible world if he exists in any possible world. Premise C
asserts a logical incompatibility between God's existence and the
object or state of affairs held to be possible in premise A. With these
premises in place we can deduce our conclusion in the following
manner. First, from C it follows that "if it is necessary that God exists,
then it is necessary that it is not the case that p." Next, since A is
logically equivalent to "it is not necessary that it is not the case that p,"
it follows from A and the above consequence of C, via modus tollens,
that "it is not necessary that God exists." Then from this and B it
follows, again via modus tollens, that "it is not possible that God exists."

3. Generating Modal Arguments for Atheism


With the general structure of these arguments in place, we can now
generate specific arguments by substituting an actual proposition for p.
But how do we determine what proposition to use in place of p? How
do we know if a given proposition will work? Here we must find a
proposition that is logically inconsistent with the proposition "God
exists"that is, a proposition that, when plugged in for p, will give us a
true C-premise. One way to do this is to look at evidential arguments
for atheism. For example, recall that the evidential argument from evil
cites the large amount of severe evil or suffering in the world as
evidence against God's existence. This is cited as evidence for atheism
because it is probably gratuitousthat is, there is probably no morally
sufficient reason for God to permit or create it. And that is precisely the
kind of evil that God, as a morally perfect being, will not permit or
create. Consequently, God and gratuitous evil cannot possibly coexist.
Thus, our first instance of p could be:

09/11/2012 18.40

Modal Arguments for Atheism

3 di 14

http://www.infidels.org/library/modern/ryan_stringer/modal-atheism.html

1. Gratuitous evil exists.


Plugging this proposition in for p would give us the modal argument
from gratuitous evil.[4]
Another evidential argument to look at here is the one from physical
minds. Since God is necessarily a minded, nonphysical being, he could
not exist if all minds were physically realized. And if God did exist, then
it could not be the case that all minds are physically realized. So God's
existence and the physical realization of all minds are logically
incompatible things. Thus, our second instance of p could be:
2. All minds are physically realized.
Plugging this proposition in for p would then give us the modal
argument from physical minds.
Now let's look at the evidential arguments from nonbelief and scale.
Unfortunately, neither will help us to construct more modal arguments
for atheism because there is a crucial difference between them and the
evidential arguments from evil and physical minds. To see this
difference, first note that these arguments each involve (basically) two
claims: an incompatibility claim asserting a logical incompatibility
between God's existence and some state of affairs S, and an evidence
claim asserting that S obtains. Again, all of these arguments have
atheism as their probabilistic conclusion. However, when it comes to the
arguments from evil and physical minds, it is the evidence claim that is
probabilistic, whereas the incompatibility claim is not. But when it
comes to the arguments from nonbelief and scale, it is the
incompatibility claim, and not the evidence claim, that is probabilistic.
Since their incompatibility claims are only probabilistic, these two
arguments do not help us here: they would not provide airtight
C-premises, and thus would not generate airtight modal arguments for
atheism.
Fortunately, other bases for strong modal arguments for atheism can
be found without looking at evidential arguments. For example, since
God is morally perfect, he will not allow a state of affairs to obtain in
which every free person besides himself always does the morally wrong
thing. So our third instance of p could be:
3. Every metaphysically free, non-God person always
does the morally wrong thing.
Plugging this proposition in for p would then give us what I will call the
modal argument from super depravity.[5] Now if (3) is objectionable for
some reason, we could use a similar, more modest claim for our third
instance of p. This is:
3'. The world's metaphysically free, non-God
creatures produce more moral evil than moral
goodness such that their freedom is not worth the
cost.

Plugging this proposition in for p instead of (3) would give us what I will
call the modal argument from depravity.

09/11/2012 18.40

Modal Arguments for Atheism

4 di 14

http://www.infidels.org/library/modern/ryan_stringer/modal-atheism.html

There are at least two other bases for generating good modal
arguments for atheism. Let's say that something is a maltheistic deity if
and only if it has the properties of being omniscient, omnipotent, and
perfectly evil. Any being that qualifies as a maltheistic deity cannot
possibly coexist with God.[6] For suppose that God and such a
maltheistic deity coexist. Since both are omniscient, omnipotent beings,
it is impossible for either to thwart the will of the other, for it is logically
impossible to thwart the will of a being that is omniscient and
omnipotent. Moreover, their wills will be in complete conflict with each
other since God is perfectly good and a maltheistic deity is perfectly
evil. Now let's say that God wills something. Since he is omniscient and
omnipotent, it is impossible for his will to be thwarted; so God will
succeed in his willing. However, since the maltheistic deity is also
omniscient and omnipotent, it is impossible for its will to be thwarted;
so it will succeed in thwarting God's will. Therefore, God will also not
succeed in his willing, which obviously contradicts that God will
succeed in his willing. The same kind of contradiction can be generated
by supposing first that the maltheistic deity wills something. Since the
supposition that both God and a maltheistic deity exist leads to logical
contradictions, these beings cannot possibly coexist. We thus have a
fourth instance of p with:
4. A maltheistic deity exists.
Plugging this in for p would give us the modal argument from a
maltheistic deity. In fact, this argument could actually be a template for
several such arguments since there appears to be more than one
possible being that qualifies as a maltheistic deity. An easy way to
generate multiple possible maltheistic deities is by adding a single
property at a time. For instance, we can get a unique maltheistic deity
by adding the property of necessary existence to omniscience,
omnipotence, and perfect evilness; and a different one by adding the
property of contingent existence instead.
Finally, there is another basis for modal arguments for atheism that is
more like a template for several such argumentsperhaps even an
infinite number of them. First of all, it is necessarily true that if God
exists, then he is the creator of the universe. In other words, God's
existence necessarily precludes any other being from creating the
universe. So we have a fifth instance of p with:
5. Some other being besides God created the universe.
Plugging this in for p would then give us the modal argument from a
different creator. Of course, there are numerous possible beings
besides Godperhaps an infinite number of themthat could have
created the universe. So for each proposition asserting that one
particular non-God being created the universeor that several
particular non-God beings did sowe could generate a good modal
argument for atheism. Thus there are several (if not infinitely many)
modal arguments from a different creator.

4. Responding to Modal Arguments for Atheism


So, what are we to make of arguments that deliver the necessary truth
of atheism from a mere possibility claim? Surely such a strong atheistic

09/11/2012 18.40

Modal Arguments for Atheism

5 di 14

http://www.infidels.org/library/modern/ryan_stringer/modal-atheism.html

conclusion cannot be delivered so easily and cheaplyas well as an


infinite number of times! There must be something fishy going on here.
But what is it about these arguments that stinks? There is no obvious
culprit here. Since the arguments are all deductively valid, the problem
must lie with one or more of the premises themselves. But even then
there is still no obvious culprit. The A-premises are all quite strong:
besides their intuitive plausibility, the objects or states of affairs that
they assert to be possible are all conceivable, coherent things.[7]
Moreover, at least (1) and (2) are very plausible in their own right. For
the horrific evil we face in this world certainly appears, upon
philosophical reflection, to be gratuitousthere is no discernible
justification for God to permit or create it. And it is, of course, very
plausible for this evil to really be how it appears to be. Our best
evidence also suggests that all minds with which we are acquainted are
physically realized, which in turn suggests that all minds are physically
realized. Though this evidence could be deceiving, it is again very
plausible that things really are as they appear here. But since (1) and
(2) are very plausible in their own right, surely the mere possibility of
them being true is as strong as possibilities come.
Then there is B and the C-premises. As mentioned above, the former
follows from the conception of God as a necessary being, which is
popular among philosophers. The latter are all airtight incompatibility
claims; so they are beyond dispute. What, then, are the possible
options for contesting these arguments? Well, one can contest the
A-premises or contest B. Let's begin with the first one. Even though the
A-premises are all quite strong, there are nevertheless two strategies
(that I know of) for contesting them. One is to directly contest them by
trying to show that the objects or states of affairs that they assert to be
possible are really incoherent things. However, this is not a viable
strategy: not only would this be an endless task in virtue of the
countless non-God beings that could have created the universe, but it
is surely false that all of the seemingly possible objects or states of
affairs are really incoherent things. The more promising strategy is to
contest the A-premises indirectly by putting forth some theistic
counterargument that specifically delivers the conclusion that:
Q. It is necessary that God exists.
Armed with this proposition, an imagined critic can deduce the falsity of
the A-premises from Q and the C-premises. But how should one go
about getting Q?
Not just any theistic argument will work here. In order to give our
imagined critic what he or she needs to deduce the falsity of the
A-premises, the argument must specifically conclude with Qthat is, it
must point specifically to a necessarily existing God. However, most
theistic arguments do not do so, such as those that appeal to the
existence, order, complexity, "fine-tuning," or apparent design of the
universe, or to the existence of minds, reason, miracles, religious
experiences, and so on. The bases of these arguments do not even
point specifically towards God, let alone to a necessarily existing one.
And even if they did offer some support for the existence of God (which
I think is false), they would still offer no support for a necessarily
existing God over a contingently existing one.
One exception here is the modal cosmological argument, which invokes

09/11/2012 18.40

Modal Arguments for Atheism

6 di 14

http://www.infidels.org/library/modern/ryan_stringer/modal-atheism.html

a necessarily existing God as the one necessary being needed to


explain why contingent beings exist. But as I have shown elsewhere[8],
this argument is invalid: it does not point specifically to God, or even to
only one necessary being. It is also based on the rather dubious
principle of sufficient reason, and so will not give our imagined critic
what he or she needs to deduce the falsity of the A-premises.
As far as I can tell, the only viable option left is to use an ontological
argument.[9] Now the classic ontological argument will not work
because it is clearly invalid.[10] But a modal version of the ontological
argument will work, and it can be formulated quite simply as:
P. It is possible that God exists.
B. Necessarily, if it is possible that God exists, then it is
necessary that God exists.
Q. Therefore, it is necessary that God exists. (from B & P)
In fact, this argument works very well in the present context. Unlike
most theistic arguments, it is clearly valid (as a straightforward example
of modus ponens) and does not contain any premise that embodies an
invalid inference. Furthermore, it essentially tries to beat modal
arguments for atheism at their own game. For besides using premise B
just as modal arguments for atheism use it, it too rests on a possibility
claim that can be defended on similar grounds as our A-premises: not
only is it intuitively plausible, but God is a conceivable, coherent
thing.[11] Thus, putting forth the modal ontological argument is the
best way for our imagined critic to contest the A-premises.
In response, we could point out that there are numerous arguments
that P is false because the concept of God is actually an incoherent
concept. However, we must ignore such arguments, for although they
cause problems for theism, falling back on them to contest P would
render modal arguments for atheism superfluous. Namely, if we can
provide independent grounds to doubt the coherence of the concept of
God, then we do not need modal arguments for atheism. In fact, if any
incoherence argument works, then atheism is established and theism is
destroyedany other atheistic argument, or demonstration of the
failure of theistic arguments, would be unnecessary. Thus, we must
ignore incoherence arguments in order for modal arguments for
atheism to have the merit that I attribute to them in this paper.
But even if we ignore incoherence arguments, contesting our
A-premises by appealing to the modal ontological argument fails to
defeat modal arguments for atheism. First of all, P and any given
A-premise are, at best, equally plausibleit would be absurd to claim
that P is more plausible than any of the A-premises.[12] For even if P is
intuitively plausible, and God is a conceivable, coherent thing, the
same can be said of the objects or states of affairs said to be possible
in the A-premises. Now the equal plausibility of P and any given
A-premise implies that the modal ontological argument and any given
modal argument for atheism are on an equal footingthat the
soundness of one argument is as plausible as the soundness of the
other. But since the soundness of one argument implies the
unsoundness of the other, the soundness of any given modal argument
for atheism is as plausible as its unsoundness. Therefore, at best the
modal ontological argument undermines any given modal argument for

09/11/2012 18.40

Modal Arguments for Atheism

7 di 14

http://www.infidels.org/library/modern/ryan_stringer/modal-atheism.html

atheism considered by itself.[13]


However, even if the modal ontological argument undermines any given
modal argument for atheism taken alone, the modal ontological
argument certainly does not undermine the entire set of modal
arguments for atheism. To see why, consider first the disjunction of the
A-premises:
(DA) A1 or A2 or A3 or A4 or A5.

Since the truth of this proposition only requires that one of its disjuncts
be true, and since each one is just as plausible as P, it has a much
higher probability of being true than Pespecially if DA has an infinite
number of disjuncts. So DA is more plausible than P. Consequently, it
is more plausible that at least one of the modal arguments for atheism
is sound and that the modal ontological argument is unsound than that
the modal ontological argument is sound while the modal arguments
for atheism are unsound. Thus the modal ontological argument does
not undermine the entire set of modal arguments for atheism.
Suppose that P is somehow more plausible than any given A-premise.
While this would defeat the claim that P and any given A-premise are
equally plausible, it would not necessarily undermine the higher
probability of DA. For suppose that DA does have an infinite number of
disjuncts, and that each one has some chance of being true. If so, then
the probability of DA, regardless of the probability of each individual
disjunct, approaches 1. So no matter how much more plausible P is
than any of DA's disjuncts, DA is still more plausible than P.
Furthermore, even if DA has only a finite number of disjuncts, it is still
more likely to be true than P. For given the conservative assumptions
that (a) either DA or P must be true, (b) each disjunct again has some
chance of being true, and (c) there are only 5 disjuncts, each disjunct
only needs to have a probability of at least .14 in order for DA to have a
higher probability than P.[14] However, an estimated probability of .14
for each A-premise is not only absurdly low in its own right, but results
in P having a probability of .47almost 3.5 times as likely as each
A-premise! This is absurdly generous. We should therefore estimate
the probability of each A-premise to be higher than .14, which means
that we should estimate DA to be more probable than P. So once
again, DA is more plausible than P.
In a final attempt to contest the set of modal arguments for atheism by
contesting their A-premises, our imagined critic could argue that the
modal ontological argument is not the only counterargument to be
considered. In addition to P, there are several other possibility claims
that, when combined with B, entail Q, and thus the falsity of the
A-premises. More specifically, our imagined critic could generate a new
possibility claim, and hence a new theistic counterargument, by
removing the proposition "God exists" from P and replacing it with any
of the following:
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
12.

God created the universe.


Jesus was the son of God.
God spoke to Abraham.
There is eternal communion with God.
The Ten Commandments were given by God.
The Bible is the word of God.

09/11/2012 18.40

Modal Arguments for Atheism

8 di 14

http://www.infidels.org/library/modern/ryan_stringer/modal-atheism.html

13. The Koran is the word of God.


14. Satan rebelled against God.
15. God loves everyone.
There are countless other examples that could work hereperhaps
even an infinite number of them. So in place of a single modal theistic
argument, there is actually a set of such arguments comparable to the
set of modal arguments for atheism. Consequently, even if the modal
ontological argument by itself does not undermine the entire set of
modal arguments for atheism, the set of modal theistic arguments does
undermine it (or so our imagined critic would argue).[15]
As clever as it may be, this response does not work. The problem here
is that taking "God exists" out of P and replacing it with anything like
(7) through (15) above would not really generate a new modal
argument for theism. In fact, the above procedure would not really
involve taking the proposition "God exists" out of P at all, but would
instead involve adding something to this proposition that does not do
any independent work. For instance, consider the possibility claim
generated from (7): it is possible that God created the universe. This
amounts to the claim that "it is possible that God exists and created the
universe." Now it is true that this claim can be substituted in for P in the
modal ontological argument, and that the argument will still remain
valid. However, it is the proposition "God exists" that is still doing all of
the workadding that he created the universe is completely
superfluous. What our imagined critic needs to do is generate modal
arguments for theism in the same way that I generated modal
arguments for atheism. After finding the first instance of p with
"gratuitous evil exists," I did not try to find other instances by tacking on
superfluous additions to gratuitous evil (e.g., specific victims). Since it
is the evil that would be doing all of the work here, such a procedure
would not have delivered truly new instances of p, and thus would not
have delivered new modal arguments for atheism. Instead, this
procedure would have delivered only a single modal argument for
atheism presented in different ways. I therefore found other objects or
states of affairs that are completely independent of gratuitous evil, and
it is because they worked on their own that I was able to use them to
generate new modal arguments for atheism. By following the faulty
tacking-on procedure, our imagined critic has merely found different
ways to present the modal ontological argument; and until he or she
can apply the procedure that I followed to theism, the modal
ontological argument is the only modal theistic argument available to
be pitted against the set of modal arguments for atheism.
Since contesting the A-premises failed to refute modal arguments for
atheism, contesting Bwhich amounts to contesting the conception of
God as a necessary beingis the only option left. Luckily for theists,
this is a good response to such arguments. For starters, B is
suspicious since it is the only premise in these modal arguments (the
ontological argument and those for atheism) that asserts the entailment
of a necessity from a mere possibility. It is ultimately responsible for the
fishiness of deducing the necessary truth of atheism from mere
possibility claims.
There are also grounds for thinking that B is false. For one thing, B
implies that P and the A-premises are logically inconsistent with each
other. But this inconsistency is suspect: as stated above, P and the
A-premises are all intuitively plausible, and their objects or states of

09/11/2012 18.40

Modal Arguments for Atheism

9 di 14

http://www.infidels.org/library/modern/ryan_stringer/modal-atheism.html

affairs are conceivable, coherent things. Since there seems to be no


logical inconsistency between P and the A-premises, B appears to be
false. Furthermore, it is trivially true that if it is necessary that God
exists, then it is possible that God exists. But from this and B it follows
that "it is necessary that God exists" and "it is possible that God exists"
are logically equivalent propositions. However, such a consequence
seems falseclaims of possibility and necessity are on opposite sides
of the modal spectrum. So again, B appears to be false.
Finally, there appears to be no good reason to conceive of God as a
necessary being, and thus no grounds for thinking that B is true. As I
have argued elsewhere[16], neither the need for God to exist
independently of all else, nor the idea that necessary existence is a
perfection, constitute a good reason for conceiving of God as a
necessary being. Instead, God seems to be (conceptually speaking) a
logically contingent beingone that exists in some, though not all,
possible worlds.
On the other hand, Alvin Plantinga offers some very promising grounds
for conceiving of God as a necessary being. While necessary existence
is not itself a perfection, perhaps it is a necessary condition of
perfection.[17] First, consider that the goodness of a being in a world
W may not be a function of the being's properties in that world alone; it
may also depend upon its properties in other worlds. If so, then a truly
perfect being must have the set of traditional, perfect-making divine
attributes (let's call this set T) in the world in which it exists, as well as
in every other possible world. But since existence is a necessary
condition of having properties (things that do not exist do not have
properties, according to Plantinga), a being must exist in order to have
T. So if a perfect being must have T in every possible world, and having
T in every possible world requires existing in every possible world, then
a perfect being must exist in every possible world. And since God is, by
definition, a perfect being, he must be conceived of as a being that
exists in every possible worldthat is, as a necessary being.
Despite its brilliance, I think this attempt to vindicate the necessary
beinghood of God fails. To see why, consider first the following
observation made by Plantinga:
Those who worship God do not think of him as a being that
happens to be of surpassing excellence in this world but
who in some other worlds is powerless or uninformed or of
dubious moral character.[18]

But why do people not think of God in this way? Well, if God had T in
this world and had properties that fell short of T in others, then God
would have T accidentally. But if God had T accidentally, then God
could fail to have T, which in turn implies that God is not perfecthe
would be a better being if he could not fail to have T.[19] However, God
is perfect by definition; so he could not fail to have T, or have T
accidentally. Instead, God must have T essentially, or in every possible
world in which he exists. The upshot here is that God's perfection
requires that he have T essentially and not accidentally, which means
that God's goodness is a function of his having T essentially instead of
accidentally. This can then be generalized: the goodness of any being
is a function of whether it has its properties essentially, or accidentally.
The idea that a being's goodness is a function of whether it has its

09/11/2012 18.40

Modal Arguments for Atheism

10 di 14

http://www.infidels.org/library/modern/ryan_stringer/modal-atheism.html

properties essentially or accidentally seems to be what Plantinga is


driving at when he suggests that the goodness of a being in a world W
depends on its properties in other worlds. If so, then Plantinga seems
to be correct. However, he has not established that a perfect being
must have T in every possible world. Instead, he has established that a
perfect being must have T essentially, which is consistent with this
being's logical contingency. Put another way, Plantinga has established
that a being's perfection requires that it have T in every world it
happens to grace, not that it must instantiate T in every possible world.
On the other hand, isn't the claim that a perfect being must have T in
every possible world still plausible? That depends on whether a
necessary being that has T essentially is a better being than a logically
contingent being that has T essentially. I don't think that such a being
would be better, for if it were, then maximal exemplification of T would
have to contribute to perfect beinghoodhaving T essentially would
not be sufficient for perfect beinghood. But why should we think this?
We would not think, for example, that a soccer player with the best
possible soccer skills is a better soccer player than another with the
same skills just because the former played in every game of the season
while the latter played in only some of them. Here the rate at which a
perfect skill is exemplified is irrelevant to being a perfect soccer
playerall it takes is the possession of certain skills. Likewise, a
necessary God does not seem to be a better being than a logically
contingent God just because the former's essential T-properties are
exemplified in every possible world, while the latter's essential
T-properties are only exemplified in some. All it takes to be a perfect
being is having T essentially, and this is true of both Gods. So it does
not seem to be true that a perfect being must have T in every possible
world. Consequently, Plantinga has not provided good grounds for
conceiving of God as a necessary being.
At this point, then, we seem to have no good reason to conceive of God
as a necessary being, and thus no grounds for thinking that B is true.
On the other hand, we do seem to have good grounds for thinking that
B is false. So until it can be shown otherwise, rejecting B is a viable
wayindeed, the only viable wayto reject modal arguments for
atheism.

5. Modal Arguments for Atheism and the Philosophical Defense of


Atheism
I have shown that premise B is the only viable place to contend modal
arguments for atheism. But no matter what B's epistemic status, modal
arguments for atheism make a contribution to the philosophical
defense of atheism. For suppose that B is true, or at least more
plausible than its negation. If so, then the only threat to modal
arguments for atheism is the modal ontological argument. However, the
set of modal arguments for atheism is stronger than the modal
ontological argument: because DA is more plausible than P, it is more
plausible that at least one of the modal arguments for atheism is sound
and that the modal ontological argument is unsound than that all of the
modal arguments for atheism are unsound and that the modal
ontological argument is sound. So if B is true or more plausible than its
negation, then atheism is positively supported by modal arguments for
atheism.

09/11/2012 18.40

Modal Arguments for Atheism

11 di 14

http://www.infidels.org/library/modern/ryan_stringer/modal-atheism.html

Now suppose that B is false, or at least no more plausible than its


negation. If so, then modal arguments for atheism thereby fail, but the
modal ontological argument and modal cosmological argument also
fail, for they too rely upon the conception of God as a necessary being.
Put another way, even if modal arguments for atheism fail in virtue of
relying on the conception of God as a necessary being, they take the
modal ontological argument and modal cosmological argument down
with them. So even if modal arguments for atheism do not positively
support atheism, they still make a contribution to the philosophical
defense of atheism.

Notes
[1] Nicholas Everitt, The Non-Existence of God (New York, NY:
Routledge, 2004), Chapter 11.
[2] Ted Drange, Nonbelief and Evil: Two Arguments for the
Nonexistence of God (Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books, 1998).
[3] See the argument from physical minds page here on the Secular
Web.
[4] See Richard Gale, "Freedom Versus Unsurpassable Greatness,"
International Journal for the Philosophy of Religion, Vol. 23, No. 2
(1988): 65-75, and Richard Gale, On the Nature and Existence of God
(New York, NY: Cambridge University Press, 1991), Chapter 6. Gale
neither uses the phrase "modal argument from gratuitous evil" nor
formulates such an argument, but "the modal problem of evil" he refers
to (p. 229) in his excellent book is another way to describe the
argument.
[5] Again, see "Freedom Versus Unsurpassable Greatness" and On the
Nature and Existence of God. Here, too, Gale does not use the phrase
"modal argument from super depravity" or formulate such an argument,
but he does provide the basis for this argument.
[6] Michael Tooley, "Plantinga's Defence of the Ontological Argument,"
Mind, Vol. 90 (1981): 422-427.
[7] Of course, the intuitive plausibility of the A-premises, as well as the
conceivability and coherence of their contents, does not guarantee their
truth. But it does provide defeasible justification for them. Perhaps the
objects or states of affairs are not really coherent, the A-premises are
defeated by competing possibility claims, or the A-premises are false
for some other reason. However, until such defeat is forthcoming, the
intuitive plausibility of the A-premises, as well as the conceivability and
coherence of their contents, provides good epistemic grounds for them.
For although intuitions can certainly be mistaken, undefeated ones
carry some epistemic weight. Moreover, a thing could be conceivable
without being possible, but its conceivability at least suggests that it is
possible, insofar as our imaginative and rational powers give us
epistemic access to modal space. Finally, incoherent things are
automatically impossible; so a thing's coherence suggests its possibility
at least in the sense that it is not automatically rendered impossible.
[8] See my "Questions of Existence and the Modal Cosmological
Argument" (2011) on the Secular Web. In that paper I argue that one

09/11/2012 18.40

Modal Arguments for Atheism

12 di 14

http://www.infidels.org/library/modern/ryan_stringer/modal-atheism.html

reason why the modal cosmological argument is not rationally


acceptable is that invoking God as the necessary being that explains
contingent beings has the wildly implausible result that gratuitous evil
is impossible. It is now evident that I could have offered several reasons
perhaps an infinite number of themfor why the modal cosmological
argument is not rationally acceptable: asserting that God is the
necessary being that explains contingent beings results in the
impossibility of every object or state of affairs contained in the instances
of p mentioned above, and each such consequence is an implausible
result.
[9] A not viable option would be a moral argument for theism that is
something like:
1. Necessarily, if God does not exist, then moral realism is
false.
2. Necessarily, moral realism is true.
3. Therefore, necessarily, God exists
This is not a viable option because not only are both premises highly
controversial, but the first seems patently false. In fact, it smacks of
being an article of faith. So no one would be justified in simply putting
forth this argument as something that can be unproblematically relied
upon for another purpose, like blunting the force of modal arguments
for atheism.
[10] Since the invalidity of this argument is old news, I will be brief in
explaining it here. Its first premise is the conceptual claim that "God is
the greatest possible being," and its second premise is that "existence
is a great-making property." Now these premises at best establish what
God is conceptuallythe first premise asserts what the concept of God
amounts to at the most general level, and the second premise allows
us to fill in one of the great-making properties (existence) contained in
this concept. But it does not follow from what God is conceptually that
there is a God. Like the concept of any other concrete being, the
concept of God does not guarantee its own instantiation. So the
argument is invalid.
[11] A bad way to argue for P is the following modus ponens argument:
N. God ought to exist.
O. If God ought to exist, then it is possible that God exists.
P. Therefore, it is possible that God exists.
Since God is a perfect being, it would be very good if he existed. So N
is plausibly true (assuming, of course, that ought-statements can be
true). However, O is probably false because God could be an
incoherent thing even if he ought to exist. For instance, a clean-shaven
man with a beard that is very powerful, knowledgeable, benevolent,
and deeply concerned with the well-being of cats certainly ought to
exist because it would be very good if such a being existed. But this
being is obviously an incoherent one, and thus cannot possibly exist;
so the fact that it ought to exist does not imply that it is possible for it to
exist. Furthermore, it would be misguided to defend O by claiming that
it is an instance of the widely accepted "ought-implies-can" principle;
for the widely accepted version of this principle pertains to action, not
the existence of objects or states of affairs. For example, it is
unreasonable or false to maintain that Jack ought to jump over the

09/11/2012 18.40

Modal Arguments for Atheism

13 di 14

http://www.infidels.org/library/modern/ryan_stringer/modal-atheism.html

moon or bench press his car because Jack cannot do these thingsa
necessary condition of saying that Jack ought to do something is that
he can do it. But even if the ought-implies-can principle is acceptable
with respect to action, this does not generalize to the existence of God
and other things. For as I have already shown, a thing ought to exist in
virtue of it being very good if that thing existed, and this is no guarantee
that it is possible for the thing to exist.
This argument is part of Carl Kordig's ontological argument. See Carl
Kordig, "A Deontic Argument for God's Existence," Nous, Vol. 15
(1981): 207-208.
[12] One could argue that the A-premises (or at least some of them) are
more intuitively plausible, and thus stronger, because they involve
objects or states of affairs that are simpler than God. However, it is
common among theologians and philosophers to maintain that God is a
simple object; so it may not be the case that God is more complex than
the objects or states of affairs that the A-premises assert to be possible.
Though the claim that God is simple seems absurd, considerations of
simplicity are themselves complex and turbid; so I will ignore them in
the present context.
[13] Of course, the reverse also holds: since the soundness of the
modal ontological argument is as plausible as the soundness of any
modal argument for atheism, and the soundness of the latter implies
the unsoundness of the former, the soundness of the modal ontological
argument is as plausible as its unsoundness. Thus any modal
argument for atheism taken alone undermines the modal ontological
argument. Colloquially, the arguments "cancel each other out." This is
an important result for the philosophical defense of atheism since it
shows that the modal ontological argument does not provide rational
justification for theism.
[14] The probability estimates for DA and P when the former has only 5
disjuncts and each disjunct has a probability of .14 are calculated as
follows. Since DA and P are mutually exclusive, the probability of P is
equivalent to the probability of DA's falsity, which in turn is equivalent to
the probability of the conjunction of the negations of the A-premises.
That is, the probability of P is equivalent to the probability of the
following proposition:
(CA) Not-A1 and Not-A2 and Not-A3 and Not-A4 and
Not-A5.

But since the probability of each A-premise is assumed to be .14, the


probability of each negation of an A-premise is .86. So the probability of
CA, and hence P, is given by (.86)5, which is approximately .47. The
probability of DA is then 1 - P, which is approximately .53.
[15] I would like to thank an anonymous reviewer for pointing out this
possible objection.
[16] See my "Questions of Existence and the Modal Cosmological
Argument" on the Secular Web.
[17] Alvin Plantinga, The Nature of Necessity (New York, NY: Oxford
University Press, 1974), p. 214.

09/11/2012 18.40

Modal Arguments for Atheism

14 di 14

http://www.infidels.org/library/modern/ryan_stringer/modal-atheism.html

[18] The Nature of Necessity, p. 214.


[19] Beings seem similar to cars: those that could have less than
maximal value could be better and thus are not perfect. In other words,
a car is not perfect if it could fall short of maximal car value; and a
being is not perfect if it could fall short of maximal being value.
Copyright 2012 Ryan Stringer. The electronic version is copyright 2012 by Internet
Infidels, Inc. with the written permission of Ryan Stringer. All rights reserved.

Top of Page
Share

Copyright Internet Infidels 1995-2012. All rights reserved.


disclaimer

09/11/2012 18.40

Você também pode gostar