Você está na página 1de 193

Humes Skeptical Crisis Z

This page intentionally left blank

Humes Skeptical Crisis Z


A Textual Study

ROBERT J. FOGELIN

1
2009

1
Oxford University Press, Inc., publishes works that further
Oxford Universitys objective of excellence
in research, scholarship, and education.
Oxford New York
Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi
Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi
New Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto
With ofces in
Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece
Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore
South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam

Copyright 2009 by Oxford University Press, Inc.


Published by Oxford University Press, Inc.
198 Madison Avenue, New York, New York 10016
www.oup.com
Oxford is a registered trademark of Oxford University Press
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced,
stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means,
electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise,
without the prior permission of Oxford University Press.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Fogelin, Robert J.
Humes skeptical crisis : a textual study / Robert J. Fogelin.
p. cm.
ISBN 978-0-19-538739-1
1. Hume, David, 17111776. Skepticism in the treatise of human nature.
2. Skepticism. 3. Knowledge, theory of. I. Title.
B1489.F638 2009
128dc22
2008049463
9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
Printed in the United States of America
on acid-free paper

For Jane Lincoln Taylor

This page intentionally left blank

But what have I here said . . . ?

This page intentionally left blank

Preface Z

A few words about the provenance of this work may help explain
the form it takes. It concerns the same material that I examined
in the rst eight chapters of Humes Skepticism in the Treatise of
Human Nature, published in 1985. The primary intention of that
work was to counter the tendency, common at the time, to play
down or simply ignore the skeptical themes in Humes Treatise in
favor of a thoroughgoing naturalistic reading in the style of Norman
Kemp Smith. Since the skeptical themes were being played down,
to provide a suitable counterweight, I played them up. This work
is intended to offer a more balanced account of the relationship
between Humes naturalism and his skepticism.
In 1990 I was given the opportunity to develop the central ideas of
that book as a lecturer in a National Endowment for the Humanities
seminar directed by David Fate Norton and Wade Robison. It consisted of ve lectures on book 1, part 4 of the Treatise, the locus
of Humes deepest skeptical reections. I wrote careful notes and
corrected them in the light of the energetic discussions that greeted
these lectures. My intention at the time was to use these notes as
the basis for a second edition of Humes Skepticism in the Treatise.
I then became involved in other projects and thought no more of
these notes until fteen years later, when I received an invitation
from Livia Guimaraes to give a series of lectures on Hume at the
Universidade Federal de Minas Geraise in Brazil. I dug out the

Preface

NEH notes, reread Hume, and produced an extensive revision of


the original NEH lectures. This work is based on those lectures.
Much has changed as a result of these multiple revisions. I have
corrected what I now take to be misreadings of particular texts.
I have given more prominence to the naturalistic themes in the
Treatise, in particular, to Humes attempts to give a naturalistic
account of the emergence of philosophical positions. On the other
side, I now lay more stress on the claim that Humes pursuit of a
science of human nature itself generates a skeptical challenge that
calls his naturalistic program into question. Hence the title: Humes
Skeptical Crisis. Rather than an analysis of Humes skepticism of
the kind presented in Humes Skepticism in the Treatise of Human
Nature, this work presents a narrative account of how this skeptical crisis arises as Humes investigations penetrate more and more
deeply into the operations of the human understanding.
Over the years a number of books have played an important part
in shaping my thinking about Humes philosophy, both through
agreement and disagreement. These include Thomas Browns Cause
and Effect (1822), J. A. Passmores Humes Intentions, Terrence
Penelhums Hume, Barry Strouds Hume, Annette Baiers Progress of
Sentiments, and Don Garretts Cognition and Commitment in Humes
Philosophy. I also have learned a great deal from an unpublished
paper by David Owen titled Scepticism with regard to reason.
It is available from the departmental website (philosophy.arizona.
edu).
The editorial comments in the Selby-Bigge and Nidditch editions of the Treatise of Human Nature and the two Enquiries have
been of invaluable help, as have the extensive comments in the new
David Norton and Mary Norton critical edition of the Treatise and
the new Thomas Beauchamp critical edition of the rst Enquiry.

Preface

xi

I owe a special debt to the two scholars who served as readers of


the manuscript for Oxford University Press: rst for their generous
support, second for their editorial comments that at times strengthened my reading of the text, while at other times saved me from
embarrassing errors.
Beyond this, there are the articles I have read, talks I have attended,
comments I have received on papers I presented in various venues,
and, not of least importance, conversations that I have had at gatherings around the world with fellow Hume enthusiasts. I cannot name
them all, but some who have been particularly useful, often calling
texts to my attention either in support or in opposition to views I
hold, include: Annette Baier, Lewis White Beck, Simon Blackburn,
Janet Broughton, Thompson Clarke, Willis Doney, Julia Driver,
Harry Frankfurt, Don Garrett, Livia Guimaraes, Ted Honderich,
Christopher Hookway, Gary Mathews, Peter Millican, David
Norton, David Owen, Richard Popkin, Geoffrey Sayer-McCord,
Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, David Stove, Barry Stroud, Meredith
Williams, Michael Williams, and Kenneth Winkler. I have surely
forgotten some, and to them I apologize.
I have received institutional support for this project from the
National Endowment for the Humanities, the Rockefeller Study
Center at Bellagio, The Liguria Study Center for the Arts and
Humanities at Bogliasco, the Faculty Research Fund at Dartmouth
College, and a generous Emeritus Grant from the Mellon
Foundation.
I would also like to thank Peter Ohlin and Linda Donnelly of the
Oxford University press for their support and editorial help, and, as
before, thank Florence Fogelin and Jane Taylor for their patience
and skill in dealing with drafts of my work. In gratitude for her help
over many years, I have dedicated this work to Jane Taylor.

This page intentionally left blank

Contents Z

Texts and Citations

xvii

Introduction: The Interpretive Problem


1

Of Knowledge and Probability 11


A Quick Tour of Part 3, Book 1 11
Section 1. Of knowledge 11
Section 2. Of probability; and of the idea of cause and effect 13
Section 3. Why a cause is always necessary 14
Section 4. Of the component parts of our reasonings
concerning causes and effects 15
Section 5. Of the impressions of the senses and memory 15
Section 6. Of the inference from the impression to the idea 16
Section 7. Of the nature of the idea, or belief 18
Section 8. Of the causes of belief 19
Section 9. Of the effects of other relations, and other habits 20
Section 10. Of the inuence of belief 20
Section 11. Of the probability of chances 21
Section 12. Of the probability of causes 21
Section 13. Of unphilosophical probability 22

xiv

Contents

Section 14. Of the idea of necessary connexion 22


Section 15. Rules by which to judge of causes and effects
Section 16. Of the reason of animals 28

27

2 Hume on Unphilosophical Probabilities 29


Unphilosophical as Opposed to Philosophical Probabilities
Sources of Unphilosophical Probabilities 30
The effect of the remoteness of the event 30
The effect of the remoteness of the observation 31
Reiterative diminution 31
Prejudice based on general rules 35
Conicts within the Imagination and Skepticism 37

29

3 Humes Skepticism with Regard to Reason 39


The Turn to Skepticism 39
The Basic Argument 40
Reducing knowledge to probability 41
The regression argument 43
The principle of reiterative diminution 44
Humes Response to His Skeptical Argument 48
Peritrope 52
4 Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses 55
Humes Turnabout with Regard to the Senses 55
The Organization of Section 2 57
The Causes of Our Belief in the Existence of Bodies 59
The senses not the source of this belief 60
Reason not the source of this belief 63
The Operations of the Imagination in Forming This Belief 65

Contents

Humes informal statement of his position 66


Humes systematic statement of his position 69
The Philosophers Double-Existence. Theory of Perception
The Pyrrhonian Moment 82
A Concluding Note 83

xv

78

5 Of the Ancient and Modern Philosophy 85


Reasons for Examining Ancient and Modern
Philosophical Systems 85
Of the Ancient Philosophy (Section 3) 85
The false belief in the continued identity of changing objects 87
The ction of underlying substance, or original rst matter 89
The false belief in the simplicity of objects 90
The ction of a unifying substance 93
The incomprehensibility of the peripatetic system 93
Skeptical implications 94
Of the Modern Philosophy (Section 4) 96
Against the distinction between primary and secondary qualities 97
Another Pyrrhonian moment 99

6 The Soul and the Self 101


Of the Immateriality of the Soul (Section 5)
Setting the dialectical stage 101
The soul as substance 102
The problem of local conjunction 104
Soulbody interaction 107
On proofs of immortality 108
Of Personal Identity (Section 6) 109

101

xvi

Contents

Basic criticisms 110


Account of the ction of personal identity 112
Disputes about identity as merely verbal 116
The reservations in the appendix 117

7 The Conclusion of Book 1

125

A Gloomy Summation of Skeptical Results 125


What Is to Be Done? 130
Being a Philosopher on Skeptical Principles 132

8 Two Openings and Two Closings

139

The Treatise and the Enquiry on Skepticism 139


The Opening of the Treatise 140
The Opening of the Enquiry 140
The Response to Skepticism in the Enquiry 144
The Science of Human Nature in the Enquiry 146
The Role of Skeptical Arguments in the Enquiry 149
Skepticism concerning the senses 149
Skepticism concerning reason 151
Skepticism concerning moral reasoning 152
Pyrrhonism and Mitigated Skepticism 155

Notes

159

Works Cited or Mentioned


Index 167

165

Texts and Citations Z

For the readers convenience, all citations to A Treatise of Human


Nature and to An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding have
a double entry. The rst is to the editions of these works that have
recently been published by Oxford University Press: the David
Fate Norton and Mary J. Norton critical edition of the Treatise
of Human Nature and Tom L. Beauchamps critical edition of the
Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. The second entry is to
Selby-Bigge/Nidditch editions of the Treatise of Human Nature and
David Humes Enquiries. Citations to the Treatise contain only page
numbers. Citations to the Enquiry concerning Human Understanding
are labeled EHU.

xvii

This page intentionally left blank

Humes Skeptical Crisis Z

This page intentionally left blank

Introduction Z The Interpretive Problem

How does Humes naturalismhis attempt to introduce the experimental method of reasoning into moral subjectssquare with
what seem to be his strong skeptical commitments? On the face of
it, these two aspects of his philosophy appear to be at odds with one
another. For example, in a number of places Hume holds that there
are no rational grounds for believing that the regularities that have
held in the past will continue to hold in the future; that in turn
seems to show that the inductive inferences he employs in pursuit
of his science of human nature are themselves baseless. This conict
is so obvious that even philosophically unsophisticated readers often
recognize it. Hume, however, does not seem particularly concerned
about this apparent conict between his inductive skepticism and his
commitment to a science of human nature. In the Treatise of Human
Nature, a skeptical argument is used to reject reason (in a wide sense)
as the source of causal inferences, so that he can replace it with the
associative operations of the imagination. In the Enquiry Concerning
Human Understanding, Hume celebrates this relocation, telling us
that it is . . . conformable to the ordinary wisdom of nature to secure
so necessary an act of the mind, by some instinct or mechanical tendency (EHU, 45/55). As we shall see, skeptical doubts are the source
of deep disquietudes that emerge in the concluding section of the
rst book of the Treatise, but his inductive skepticismthough it
has troubled many othersseems not to have troubled Hume.
3

Introduction

A dramatic way of presenting the tension between Humes naturalism and his skepticism is to compare two passages: one from the
introduction to the Treatise, the other from the closing section of
book 1. Hume launches the Treatise with swagger:
Tis evident, that all the sciences have a relation, greater or
less, to human nature; and that however wide any of them
may seem to run from it, they still return back by one passage or another. Even Mathematics, Natural Philosophy, and
Natural Religion, are in some measure dependent on the science of MAN; since they lie under the cognizance of men,
and are judgd of by their powers and faculties.
Here then is the only expedient, from which we can hope
for success in our philosophical researches, to leave the tedious
lingring method, which we have hitherto followd, and instead
of taking now and then a castle or village on the frontier, to
march up directly to the capital or center of these sciences,
to human nature itself; which being once masters of, we may
every where else hope for an easy victory. From this station we
may extend our conquests over all those sciences, which more
intimately concern human life, and may afterwards proceed
at leisure to discover more fully those, which are the objects
of pure curiosity. There is no question of importance, whose
decision is not comprizd in the science of man; and there is
none, which can be decided with any certainty, before we
become acquainted with that science. In pretending therefore, to explain the principles of human nature, we in effect
propose a compleat system of the sciences, built on a foundation almost entirely new, and the only one upon which they
can stand with any security. (4/xv)

Introduction

In sharp contrast to this brave beginning, in the closing section


of book 1 of the Treatise we nd the following forlorn skeptical
plaint:
But what have I here said, that reections very rend and
metaphysical have little or no inuence upon us? This opinion I can scarce forbear retracting, and condemning from my
present feeling and experience. The intense view of these manifold contradictions and imperfections in human reason has
so wrought upon me, and heated my brain, that I am ready to
reject all belief and reasoning, and can look upon no opinion
even as more probable or likely than another. Where am I,
or what? From what causes do I derive my existence, and to
what condition shall I return? Whose favour shall I court, and
whose anger must I dread? What beings surround me? and
on whom have I any inuence, or who have any inuence
on me? I am confounded with all these questions, and begin
to fancy myself in the most deplorable condition imaginable,
invirond with the deepest darkness, and utterly deprivd of
the use of every member and faculty. (175/ 26869)
This study is an attempt to answer two questions: First, how did
Humes pursuit of his science of man, so condently begun at the
start of the Treatise, land him in philosophical despair? Second, how
does he attempt to extract himself from this melancholy state?
It is important not to write off Humes expressions of despair as
mere histrionics. As Hume comes to see, his pursuit of a science of
human nature has led him into a skepticism that subverts the entire
enterprise. Furthermorethough this will have to be shownhe
nds himself completely incapable of presenting arguments that
will refute the skeptical challenges he himself has produced. If he

Introduction

is going to nd a way out of his intellectual impasse, it will have to


come from the nonrational side of human nature.
At the close of book 1 of the Treatise, Hume suggests that a reliance on common (vulgar) opinions can provide a way out of his
difculties. As we shall see, his suggestions in the Treatise seem tentative and not obviously up to the job he assigns to them. Perhaps
reecting dissatisfaction with his previous treatment of the threat
of radical skepticism, Hume returns to this topic in the opening
section of the Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, where he
confronts the challenge anew. Then, in the closing section of the
Enquiry, he offers a remarkable response to it: When the destructive
mechanisms of PyrrhonismHumes label for radical skepticism
are counterbalanced by the mechanisms that produce common
(vulgar) belief, then the mind, as a result of a vector of these two
opposing forces, naturally settles into the standpoint of a mitigated
and moderate skepticism. This is Humes nal response to the radical skepticism that seemed to overwhelm him in part 4, book 1 of
the Treatise.
Countering radical skepticism by replacing it with a more moderate or mitigated skepticism is not, however, cost-free. Humes
new modesty carries with it a sharp curtailment in the pretensions
of his science of human nature. Where Hume previously spoke of
producing a compleat system of the sciences, built on a foundation almost entirely new, and the only one upon which they can
stand with any security (4/xv), he now speaks circumspectly of
producing reections of common life, methodized and corrected
(EHU, 121/162)
As this development unfolds, there are four contrasting Humes,
or at least four contrasting voices of Hume, inhabiting Humes writing. The rst is the condent Hume, projector of a complete science
of human nature. The second is the melancholy Hume, wracked

Introduction

with Pyrrhonian doubts he seems incapable of shaking. Third, we


have the chastened Hume, modest in his expectations and reasonably content with his lot. There is also a fourth voice or standpoint
found in Humes writings, important but easily overlooked. This is
the standpoint of the ordinary people engaged in the affairs of daily
life: the standpoint of the vulgar.
Which standpoint represents the real Hume? As I read the text,
all four standpoints are real in representing the way matters strike
Hume when operating at a particular level of reection. At the start
of the Treatise, and well into it, Hume is an enthusiast for the new
science of human nature he is developing. Humes standpoint undergoes a radical skeptical transformation in response to the appalling
things his pursuit of the science of human nature reveals to him.
This is full-throated skepticism. The third standpoint emerges from
Humes recognition that radical skepticism cannot be disposed of
by employing arguments against it. When matters are placed on
an argumentative basis, the Pyrrhonist always wins. For Hume, the
slide into radical skepticism can only be countered by yielding in
some measure to our vulgar propensity to believe things that are not
based on sound arguments and, more deeply, even things that run
counter to sound arguments.
The textual study that follows is intended to show the basis for
the broad claims sketched earlier. It largely takes the form of a narrative. With very few exceptions, I present matters as they actually
unfold in the text. Given Humes shifts in standpoint, a narrative approach seems virtually forced on us. It will operate at two
interrelated levels: one global, the other local. A global interpretation concentrates on major aspects of a philosophical position and
indicates how they are interrelated. Dealing with Humes writings
involves, among other things, keeping track of where Hume is in
the dialecticaldare I use the word?unfolding of his position.

Introduction

Local interpretation involves a close reading of texts in an effort


to provide a check on the global interpretation, while at the same
time enriching its content. Grotesquely bad readings of a text usually arise from violations of the principle of global interpretation
often made in an effort to square a position under examination
with contemporary philosophical fashions. Shallow readings usually result from neglecting the details of the text where, as it is said,
Godsometimes the Devilis said to reside. To borrow phrasing
from Kant, global interpretation without local interpretation is
empty, local interpretation without global interpretation is blind.
Because I will be engaged in a close textual study, I will, for the
most part, stay within the margins of the text and cite it extensively.
I will not be much concerned with the sources of Humes ideas and
only occasionally compare Humes claims with those made by other
philosophers. I will make no effort to show that Humes writings
are relevant to contemporary philosophical debates. I think they
are, but it seems patronizing to Hume to insist on this. I will not
be much involved with the rich and impressive secondary literature on Hume that has appeared in recent decades. In dealing with
the secondary literature, one is again dealing with textstexts that
often refer to other texts and often present interpretive problems
of their own. I have not become deeply involved in the secondary
literature because I do not see how this can be done in a fair and
accurate way without interrupting the ow of the narrative I am
presenting.
I would, however, suggest three works I nd impressive that can
be read protably in conjunction with this work. Barry Strouds
Hume, among its many virtues, will prove very helpful in lling
out my whirlwind account of book 3 of the Treatise that I present in Chapter 1. David Owens essay Scepticism with Regard to
Reason offers a rich and scholarly examination of the subject that

Introduction

is in some ways similar to mine and in some ways different. Finally,


I recommend Don Garretts Cognition and Commitment in Humes
Philosophy for a treatment of Humes skepticism that differs in fundamental ways from my own.
In this work I make no claims for originality on particular points.
Perhaps there is some novelty in the way I tell the overall story.

This page intentionally left blank

Chapter 1 Z Of Knowledge and Probability

The central claim I will attempt to establish in this work is that


the skeptical Hume of part 4 of the Treatise emerges naturally
out of Humes unfettered pursuit of the naturalistic program of
part 3. To this end, I will offer a sketch, a prcis, or a whirlwind
tour of what Hume thinks he has accomplished in part 3. I will
cite Humes conclusions and exert restraintthough not total
restraintin commenting on the strength of the arguments he
presents in their behalf. With this broad sketch in hand, I will
then turn to part 4 and examine the skeptical consequences that
emerge when Hume applies his naturalistic account of beliefformation to philosophical beliefs themselves. Part 3 is titled Of
knowledge and probability. One section is dedicated to a discussion of knowledge, the remaining fteen to probability and
related topics.

Z
A Quick Tour of Part 3, Book 1
Section 1. Of knowledge
At the opening of this section, Hume repeats his list of what he calls
philosophical relations that he had originally presented and briey
discussed in part 1, section 5. They are
11

12

Humes Skeptical Crisis

resemblance, identity, relations of time and place, proportion


in quantity or number, degrees in any quality, contrariety, and
causation. These relations may be divided into two classes;
into such as depend entirely on the ideas, which we compare
together, and such as may be changd without any change in
the ideas. (50/69)
He declares that only four, which depending solely upon ideas,
can be the objects of knowledge and certainty. These four are resemblance, contrariety, degrees in any quality, and proportions in quantity
or number (50/70). The four relations that depend entirely on the
ideas, which we compare together, are the basis for the domain of
knowledge; the remaining three (relations of time and place, identity, and causation), which do not have this feature, are the concern
of the domain of probability.
Hume makes quick work of the domain of knowledge. He says
that three of these relationsresemblance, contrariety, and degrees
in any qualityare matters of intuition rather than demonstration.
Whether they hold or not can be established by merely inspecting the
ideas themselves. Arithmetic contains intuitive truths, but contains
demonstrative truths as well. This is in virtue of what has come to
be known as Humes Law (one-to-one correlation), which provides
a precise standard, by which we can judge . . . equality (51/71). For
want of a similarly precise standard, geometry can provide nothing
better than what we might call damn-near demonstrative truths.
Given its importance for his project as a whole, this discussion
of intuitive and demonstrative knowledge is surprisingly brief and
underdeveloped. It is striking that Hume expresses no dissatisfaction
with it and gives no forewarning of the assault on both intuitive and
demonstrative knowledge that awaits the reader in the opening section of book 1, part 4.

Of Knowledge and Probability

13

Section 2. Of probability; and of the idea


of cause and effect
Humes treatment of knowledge is almost peremptory; his treatment of probability is elaborate and complex. There are, according
to Hume, three kinds of relations that do not generate knowledge,
that is, intuitive and demonstrative truths. They are identity, relations of time and place, and causation. Each gets a part of book 1
dedicated to it. Relations of time and place are examined in part 2;
causation is examined in part 3; and, setting aside its opening and
closing sections, identity is a central topic of part 4.1 I will quickly
run through the basic moves concerning causation and probability
as they unfold in book 1, part 3 of the Treatise.
Section 2 raises a question that will not be answered until section 14: How are we to dene the relationship between a cause and
an effect? This section initiates the quest for an answer and moves
through the following stages:
1. An examination of a particular instance of causation reveals
only two relationships: contiguity and priority.
2. But, according to Hume, these two relations by themselves do not provide an adequate account of causation:
Shall we then rest contented with these two relations of
contiguity and succession, as affording a complete idea of
causation? . . . There is a necessary connexion to be taken
into consideration; and that relation is of much greater
importance, than any of the other two above mentiond
(55/77).
3. But an inspection of the objects themselves reveals nothing
corresponding to the idea of a necessary connection, so
again an impasse has been reached.

14

Humes Skeptical Crisis

4. At this stage of his investigations, Hume seems explicitly


committed to the idea that a necessary connection is an
essential component of a causal relation, but so far he has
been unable to give an adequate account of this idea. In an
attempt to nd another way of approaching this problem,
Hume proposes to beat about in two neighboring elds,
asking:
First, for what reason we pronounce it necessary, that every thing
whose existence has a beginning, shoud also have a cause?
Secondly, why we conclude, that such particular causes must
necessarily have such particular effects; and what is the nature
of that inference we draw from the one to the other, and of the
belief we repose in it? (55/78)
As a result of these two expeditions, Hume will reverse himself,
and instead of holding that the idea of a necessary connection is
an essential component of our idea of a causal relation, he will hold
that the idea of a necessary connection is an attendant product of
causal reasoning.
Section 3. Why a cause is always necessary
To state the question more fully, what is the basis for thinking that
everything whose existence has a beginning should also have a cause
for this beginning? Hume argues that this cannot be justied as either
a demonstrative or an intuitive truth for the following reason:
As all distinct ideas are separable from each other, and as
the ideas of cause and effect are evidently distinct, twill be
easy for us to conceive any object to be non-existent this

Of Knowledge and Probability

15

moment, and existent the next, without conjoining to it the


distinct idea of a cause or productive principle. The separation, therefore, of the idea of a cause from that of a beginning of existence, is plainly possible for the imagination; and
consequently the actual separation of these objects is so far
possible, that it implies no contradiction nor absurdity; and
is therefore incapable of being refuted by any reasoning from
mere ideas; without which tis impossible to demonstrate the
necessity of a cause. (56/79)
With demonstrative and intuitive reasoning eliminated, it seems
that the belief in question must have its basis in experience. But
instead of pursuing this topic directly, Hume turns his attention to
the second neighboring eld and asks why we conclude, that such
particular causes must necessarily have such particular effects.
Section 4. Of the component parts of our reasonings
concerning causes and effects
Hume argues that causal reasoning must have as its rst component
some initial experience, for without an origin in an initial experience causal reasoning would be no more than hypothetical.
Section 5. Of the impressions of the senses
and memory
Hume lays out the component parts of his program:
Here . . . we have three things to explain, viz. rst, The original
impression. Secondly, The transition to the idea of the connected cause or effect. Thirdly, The nature and qualities of
that idea. (59/84)

16

Humes Skeptical Crisis

The remainder of the section discusses the difference between


memory and imagination, with some qualications, drawing the
distinction in terms of vivacity.
Section 6. Of the inference from the impression
to the idea
This section demands special attention because it contains, in a
complex form, a line of reasoning that will later emerge (in the
Abstract and the Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding) as
Humes skeptical argument concerning induction.
Earlier, Hume was stymied in his attempt to discover anything
corresponding to a necessary connection between causally related
events. All he could nd of signicance are the relations of priority
and contiguity. Now, however, when he turns his attention to the
specic assignment of causes and effects, he hits on the further idea
that events that are causally connected are constantly conjoined in
terms of priority and contiguity. This newly discovered notion of
constant conjunction will play a central role in Humes rst denition of cause, but his initial reaction to it is negative.
To tell the truth, this new-discoverd relation of a constant
conjunction seems to advance us but very little in our way.
For it implies no more than this, that like objects have always
been placd in like relations of contiguity and succession; and
it seems evident, at least at rst sight, that by this means we
can never discover any new idea, and can only multiply, but
not enlarge the objects of our mind. . . . From the mere repetition of any past impression, even to innity, there never
will arise any new original idea, such as that of a necessary
connexion; and the number of impressions has in this case
no more effect than if we connd ourselves to one only.
(62/88)

Of Knowledge and Probability

17

The expression at rst sight suggests that Hume is not really


committed to the idea that nothing new can emerge from the mere
repetition of the same ideas, and, in fact, he will reject it. Hume also
drops a hint of even deeper signicance for understanding his ultimate
position concerning the relationship between necessary connections
and causal inferences: Perhaps twill appear in the end, that the
necessary connexion depends on the inference, instead of the inferences
depending on the necessary connexion (62/88). This is just how things
will turn out, but it can only be shown after Hume gives his account of
the transition to the idea of the connected cause or effect, the second
component in the program announced in the previous section.
Hume rst attempts to show that causal inferences are not the
product of our rational faculties. The initial move, and the key
move, is this:
[If reason produced causal inferences] it woud proceed upon
that principle, that instances, of which we have had no experience,
must resemble those, of which we have had experience, and that the
course of nature continues always uniformly the same. (62/89)
The question now becomes: How can the principle that the course of
nature continues always uniformly the same itself be justied? Given
the architecture of Humes position, there are only two options:
In order therefore to clear up this matter, let us consider
all the arguments upon which such a proposition may be
supposd to be founded; and as these must be derivd either
from knowledge or probability, let us cast our eye on each of
these degrees of evidence, and see whether they afford any
just conclusion of this nature. (62/89)
The rst alternative is ruled out by the conceivability argument:
There can be no demonstrative arguments to prove, that those
instances, of which we have had no experience, resemble those,

18

Humes Skeptical Crisis

of which we have had experience. We can at least conceive a


change in the course of nature; which sufciently proves, that
such a change is not absolutely impossible. To form a clear
idea of any thing, is an undeniable argument for its possibility, and is alone a refutation of any pretended demonstration
against it. (62/89)
The second alternative is eliminated by the argument from circularity:
According to this account of things, which is, I think, in
every point unquestionable, probability is founded on the
presumption of a resemblance betwixt those objects, of which
we have had experience, and those, of which we have had
none; and therefore tis impossible this presumption can arise
from probability. (63/90)
What we have, then, is a skeptical argument intended to show
that there can be no justication of the principle that the course of
nature continues always uniformly the same. For Hume, this provides a sufcient basis for saying that causal inferences are not the
product of our rational faculties.
When the mind, therefore, passes from the idea or impression of one object to the idea or belief of another, it is not
determind by reason, but by certain principles, which associate together the ideas of these objects, and unite them in the
imagination. (64/92)
Section 7. Of the nature of the idea, or belief
In section 5, Hume lays out a three-part program. The third component concerns the nature and qualities of that idea that is the product of a causal inference. For his purposes, it is important to draw a

Of Knowledge and Probability

19

distinction between merely entertaining an idea and having a belief.


He does so by invoking the notion of vivacity. Beliefs are distinguished
from mere ideas in virtue of their superior vivacity. With others,
I nd Humes appeal to vivacity, if taken in any reasonably literal sense,
unconvincing, almost unintelligible. I believe that Bismarck is the capital of North Dakota; I can also entertain the idea that Bismarck is the
capital of South Dakota. Is the rst thought more vivacious (lively,
vivid) than the second? Not to me. Degrees of vivacity might better be
taken as a metaphor for degree of belief instead of its basis.
Hume uses the notion of vivacity in an effort to give a causal
account of belief-formation. For Hume, belief-formation is a suitable topic for his science of human natureindeed, it is a central
topic. Beliefs, according to Hume, arise, are strengthened, weakened, augmented, revised, rejected, and so on, all in accordance
with causal laws. This is an important ideamore important than
his use of vivacity to implement it. In what follows, however, I will
simply accede to Humes references to vivacity and treat them as
placeholders for a causal account of belief-formation. Taken as a
metaphor, vivacity is not all that bad.
Section 8. Of the causes of belief
This section presents what we might call Humes theory of vivacity
transfer. It is of central importance to Humes naturalistic account
of operations of the human mind.
I woud willingly establish it as a general maxim in the science
of human nature, that when any impression becomes present to
us, it not only transports the mind to such ideas as are related to
it, but likewise communicates to them a share of its force and
vivacity. (69/98)

20

Humes Skeptical Crisis

In a causal inference there is a twofold movement: When an event is


experienced, the mind immediately envisages another event of the
kind constantly conjoined with it. But the triggered idea does not
simply pop into ones mind; it also inherits a portion of the vivacity
of the triggering event.
In this section, Hume also invokes the notion of custom as an apt way
of referring to the manner in which causal inferences are grounded:
[From observation] I conclude, that the belief, which attends
the present impression, and is producd by a number of past
impressions and conjunctions; that this belief, I say, arises
immediately, without any new operation of the reason or
imagination. Of this I can be certain, because I never am
conscious of any such operation, and nd nothing in the subject, on which it can be founded. Now as we call every thing
custom, which proceeds from a past repetition, without any
new reasoning or conclusion, we may establish it as a certain truth, that all the belief, which follows upon any present
impression, is derivd solely from that origin. (7172/102)
Section 9. Of the effects of other relations,
and other habits
This section examines the lesser inuence of the other two principles of associationresemblance and contiguityin transferring
belief. It provides an account of why causal associations are, in general, stronger than the other two modes of association.
Section 10. Of the inuence of belief
This complex and interesting section contains a series of reections
on the following fact:

Of Knowledge and Probability

21

Pain and pleasure have two ways of making their appearance


in the mind; of which the one has effects very different from
the other. They may either appear in impression to the actual
feeling and experience, or only in idea, as at present when
I mention them. Tis evident the inuence of these upon our
actions is far from being equal. Impressions always actuate
the soul, and that in the highest degree; but tis not every idea
which has the same effect. (81/118)
Though it contains important material, most of what Hume says here
bears more directly on topics discussed in books 2 and 3 of the Treatise
than on our present topic, the character of causal reasoning.
Section 11. Of the probability of chances
In this section Hume uses the notion of dispersed vivacity to explain
a priori probabilities. A crude example: We fully believe that, when
cast, a six-sided die will come to rest on one of its six sidesnot on
an edge. We can say that the vivacity level for this claim is effectively 1.
On the assumption that the die is not loaded, there are six equally
likely outcomes from casting the die, so the vivacity level for each
face of the die coming up on top is 1/6. This is the probability we will
naturally assign to the possibility that the die will come up, say, 4.
This may not sound particularly plausible, but, as I have suggested
elsewhere, the notion of vivacity transfer can be used to underwrite
a standard probability calculus (Fogelin 1985, pp. 5960).2
Section 12. Of the probability of causes
An application of the notion of dispersed vivacity is used to explain
what we would call statistical probabilities. Very roughly, the distribution of vivacity reects the relative frequency of the occurrence

22

Humes Skeptical Crisis

of an event in a given setting. The more often A is followed by B,


the greater the vivacity handed over by A to B, thus generating a
greater degree of subjective probability that B will follow upon an
occurrence of A.
Section 13. Of unphilosophical probability
Having completed his discussion of the probability of chances and
the probability of causes, both of which, Hume tells us, are receivd
by philosophers, and allowd to be reasonable foundations of belief
and opinion (97/143), he turns his attention to other kinds of probability that have not had the good fortune to obtain the same sanction (97/143). This section is important for seeing a fundamental
feature of Humes science of human nature: All beliefs, including
the ill-formed, the ction-ridden, and the just plain nutty, fall
under its purview. Hume takes it to be one of the chief strengths of
his position that it can explain the sources both of beliefs that are
respectable and of those that are not. Included in the second category are many beliefs of philosophersboth ancient and modern.
This, as we will see, is a central theme of part 4 of book 1. Given
the importance of this section to this later part of the Treatise, I will
dedicate a separate chapter to it.
Section 14. Of the idea of necessary connexion
After an eleven-section excursion through neighboring elds,
Hume returns to the problem posed in section 2 concerning the
status of a necessary connection. His line of march, as I understand
it, runs as follows. In section 2 Hume takes it for granted that a
necessary connection is an essential component of a causal relation.
Presumably it serves to connect the cause with its effect and in that

Of Knowledge and Probability

23

way underwrites an inference from one to the other. Having shown


(in section 6) that the inference from cause to effect cannot be the
product of the operations of our rational faculties, the notion of a
necessary connection is no longer burdened with the task of underwriting this inference. Hume is therefore free to treat the idea of a
necessary connection as a product of this inference rather than as its
basis. This is precisely what he concludes in the opening paragraph
of section 14:
After a frequent repetition, I nd, that upon the appearance
of one of the objects, the mind is determind by custom to
consider its usual attendant, and to consider it in a stronger
light upon account of its relation to the rst object. Tis this
impression, then, or determination, which affords me the idea
of necessity. (105/156)
The text exhibits what has come to be known as a Euthyphro choice:
Do we draw inferences from cause to effect because we think they
are necessarily connected, or do we think that they are necessarily
connected because we draw inferences from one to the other? For
what I take to be dialectical reasons, Hume starts out (seemingly)
adopting the rst option, then ends up adopting the second, more
daring, option. In the Treatise, Hume is fond of such reversals. We
will encounter other striking instances of it.
Having settled the status of the idea of a necessary connection,
Hume then expresses his concern that his argument, being so obviously
correct, might not be appreciated for its depth and importance.
This evidence both in the rst principles, and in the deductions, may seduce us unwarily into the conclusion, and make
us imagine it contains nothing extraordinary, nor worthy of
our curiosity. But tho such an inadvertence may facilitate the
reception of this reasoning, twill make it be the more easily

24

Humes Skeptical Crisis

forgot; for which reason I think it proper to give warning,


that I have just now examind one of the most sublime questions in philosophy. (105/156)
Hume therefore allots another thirteen pages to an expansion of
his basic argument concerning our idea of a necessary connection.
There is some interesting material in these pages, including:
Thus as the necessity, which makes two times two equal to
four, or three angles of a triangle equal to two right ones,
lies only in the act of the understanding, by which we consider and compare these ideas; in like manner the necessity or
power, which unites causes and effects, lies in the determination of the mind to pass from the one to the other. (112/166)
For Hume, the feeling of necessity that one has in thinking that
2 2 = 4 is the same feeling that one has that a heavy object will
fall if it is released from a height. By modern standardsperhaps
by the standards of Humes timethis is a curious notion of
necessity, but the text shows unambiguously that he is committed to it.
Humes additional remarks on necessary connections also contain an important summary passage that conrms the interpretation
of the text I have presented:
Tis now time to collect all the different parts of this reasoning, and by joining them together form an exact denition of
the relation of cause and effect, which makes the subject of
the present enquiry. This order woud not have been excusable, of rst examining our inference from the relation before
we had explaind the relation itself, had it been possible to
proceed in a different method. But as the nature of the relation depends so much on that of the inference, we have been

Of Knowledge and Probability

25

obligd to advance in this seemingly preposterous manner,


and make use of terms before we were able exactly to dene
them, or x their meaning. We shall now correct this fault by
giving a precise denition of cause and effect. (114/169)
With the idea of a necessary connection now properly put in its
place, Hume next proceeds to offer two denitions of cause, one
treating causation as a philosophical relation, the other treating it as
a natural relation.
There may two denitions be given of this relation, which are
only different, by their presenting a different view of the same
object, and making us consider it either as a philosophical or as
a natural relation; either as a comparison of two ideas, or as an
association betwixt them. We may dene a cause to be [a]n
object precedent and contiguous to another, and where all
the objects resembling the former are placd in like relations
of precedency and contiguity to those objects that resemble
the latter. If this denition be esteemd defective, because
drawn from objects foreign to the cause, we may substitute
this other denition in its place, viz. [a] cause is an object
precedent and contiguous to another, and so united with it,
that the idea of the one determines the mind to form the idea
of the other, and the impression of the one to form a more
lively idea of the other. (114/16970)
In case the reader has somehow missed it, Hume adds a paragraph
driving home the point that neither denition makes reference to a
necessary connectionthus reversing his original claim that a necessary connection is an essential element of a causal relation.
If we dene a cause to be, an object precedent and contiguous
to another, and where all the objects resembling the former are

26

Humes Skeptical Crisis

placd in a like relation of priority and contiguity to those objects,


that resemble the latter; we may easily conceive, that there is no
absolute nor metaphysical necessity, that every beginning of
existence shoud be attended with such an object. If we dene
a cause to be, an object precedent and contiguous to another, and
so united with it in the imagination, that the idea of the one determines the mind to form the idea of the other, and the impression
of the one to form a more lively idea of the other; we shall make
still less difculty of assenting to this opinion. (11516/172)
These two denitions are not without difculties. The second,
which treats causation as a natural relation, seems circular in
employing the transparently causal term determines as part of the
denition of a cause. This criticism can be avoided by treating the
second denition (so-called) as a causal statement concerning causal
belief-formation. There is nothing circular in that.
The rst denition, where causation is treated as a philosophical
relation, faces a more serious challenge. Some, and not merely a few,
have taken Hume to be presenting a regularity denition of a causal
law. On this readingIll call it the causal law readingHumes
rst denition is taken to mean:
If every event of type B is uniquely paired with an event of
type A that is prior to it and contiguous with it, then events
of type A cause events of type B.
Thomas Reid interpreted Hume in this manner and produced the
following counterexample to it:
It follows from this denition of cause, that night is the cause
of day, and day the cause of night. For no two things have
more constantly followed each other since the beginning of
the world. (Reid 334)

Of Knowledge and Probability

27

In fact, Humes rst denition is not correctly represented by the


causal law reading and does not imply it. Humes rst denition
concerns a singular causal statement of the form a is the cause of
b, and can be represented as follows:
a is the cause of b if and only if a is contiguous and prior to b,
and any object resembling a is similarly paired with an object
resembling b, and any object resembling b is paired with an
object resembling a that is contiguous and prior to it.
Humes rst denition, taken in this, the correct, way, is not subject to Reids criticism. The point is this: Predicates used to pick
out the cause and to pick out the effect need not x the appropriate resemblance classes.3 The denition may be subject to other
criticismsin particular, concerning the specication of the proper
resemblance classesbut I will not go into this matter here.
Section 15. Rules by which to judge of causes
and effects
Proponents of a naturalistic reading of Humes Treatise point to this
section as conrmation of their approach. They are right to do so. It
opens with the following declaration:
According to the precedent doctrine, there are no objects,
which by the mere survey, without consulting experience, we
can determine to be the causes of any other; and no objects,
which we can certainly determine in the same manner not
to be the causes. Any thing may produce any thing. . . . Since
therefore tis possible for all objects to become causes or effects
to each other, it may be proper to x some general rules, by
which we may know when they really are so. (116/173)

28

Humes Skeptical Crisis

He then lays down eight rules that will serve as guides to empirical
inquiry, telling his reader that they are of much more use than the
elaborate systems put forward by our scholastic head-pieces and
logicians [who] show no such superiority above the mere vulgar in
their reason and ability (117/175). It is hard to see, as naturalistic
interpreters point out, why Hume would nd it useful to present
such a system of rules for empirical inquiry if he harbored serious
doubts about the very possibility of such inquiry.
Section 16. Of the reason of animals
Hume holds that higher animals are capable of reasoning of the
same kind employed by human beings. The dog that avoids re
and precipices, that shuns strangers, and caresses his master, he
tells us, proceeds from a reasoning, that is not in itself different, nor
founded on different principles, from that which appears in human
nature (119/177). He thus claims that his theory can account for
both human and animal reasoning and challenges those who reject
it to attempt to do likewise:
Let any philosopher make a trial, and endeavour to explain that
act of the mind, which we call belief, and give an account of the
principles, from which it is derivd, independent of the inuence of custom on the imagination, and let his hypothesis be
equally applicable to beasts as to the human species; and after
he has done this, I promise to embrace his opinion. (119/178)
Passages like this, and many others of the same kind, seem to
settle the interpretive dispute in favor of naturalismunless, that
is, we turn pages and enter the skeptical realm of part 4. In fact, as
briey noted, the skepticism that emerges in part 4 is anticipated in
part 3 itself, in section 13, under the heading Of unphilosophical
probability. This is the subject of the next chapter.

Chapter 2 Z Hume on Unphilosophical


Probabilities

Z
Unphilosophical as Opposed to Philosophical
Probabilities
In sections 11 and 12 of part 3, Hume examines what he calls the
probability of chances and the probability of causes. At the start of
section 13, he tells us that both are receivd by philosophers, and
allowd to be reasonable foundations of belief and opinion. He then
continues: But there are [other kinds of probability], that are derivd
from the same principles, tho they have not had the good fortune to
obtain the same sanction (97/143). Hume dubs these other kinds of
probabilitythose not sanctioned by philosophersunphilosophical
probabilities. In sections 11 and 12, Hume argues that philosophical
probabilities are grounded in the operations of the imagination. In
section 13, he makes the same claim with respect to unphilosophical
probabilities. The upshot is that both philosophical and unphilosophical probabilities spring from the same principles: the operations of the imagination. Furthermore, philosophical probabilities
and unphilosophical probabilities can come into conict with one
another, and that, on Humes theory, amounts to saying that the
imagination can come into conict with itself. As we shall see, exposing conicts within the imagination is a central theme of part 4, and
their discovery is the primary source of Humes skeptical jitters.
29

30

Humes Skeptical Crisis

Z
Sources of Unphilosophical Probabilities
Hume examines four sources, or kinds, of unphilosophical probability: the effect of the remoteness of an event, the effect of the
remoteness of an observation, reiterative diminution, and prejudice
based on general rules.
The effect of the remoteness of the event
Humes discussion of this kind of unphilosophical probability provides his rst example of how a clash can arise between the deliverances of philosophical and unphilosophical probabilities.
The argument, which we found on any matter of fact we
remember, is more or less convincing, according as the fact is
recent or remote; and tho the difference in these degrees of
evidence be not receivd by philosophy as solid and legitimate;
because in that case an argument must have a different force today, from what it shall have a month hence; yet notwithstanding the opposition of philosophy, tis certain, this circumstance
has a considerable inuence on the understanding, and secretly
changes the authority of the same argument, according to the
different times, in which it is proposd to us. (9798/143)
Here Hume speaks of an argument that appeals to events remote in
time and claims that, as a matter of fact, the more remote an event
is, the less authority it will carry. This psychological fact cannot be
explained by appealing to principles of received philosophy, since it
runs counter to them. It can, Hume thinks, be explained by the
fact that, in general, events remote in time have less impact on the
imagination than those that have occurred more recently.

Hume on Unphilosophical Probabilities

31

It is worth asking why Hume should be interested in what seems


to be an unsound, actually quite stupid, mode of probabilistic reasoning. Part of the answer is that this phenomenon provides an
opportunity for him to show off the power of his own position. He
thinks that on his principles he can give an explanation of why such
a mode of reasoning takes place, whereas other theories cannot.
More deeply, in his science of human nature, Hume is attempting
to give a causal account of the ways in which human beings actually
think and act. Beliefs as they are actually formed will play a central
role in this project. Humes scientic investigations will be governed
by philosophical rules of probabilistic reasoning (see part 3, section 15),
but, as he sees, it would be a mistake to suppose that common
human belief-formation is equally governed by such rules.
The effect of the remoteness of the observation
The second kind of unphilosophical probability Hume examines is
similar to the rst, except that now it is the remoteness of the observation, and not of the event, that diminishes vivacity. An experiment, that is recent and fresh in the memory, he tells us, affects us
more than one that is in some measure obliterated (98/143).
Reiterative diminution
Because of its close connection with Humes skepticism with regard
to reason, Humes discussion of his third kind of unphilosophical
probability is worth careful examination.
I add, as a third instance of this kind, that tho our reasonings
from proofs and from probabilities be considerably different
from each other, yet the former species of reasoning often
degenerates insensibly into the latter, by nothing but the

32

Humes Skeptical Crisis

multitude of connected arguments. Tis certain, that when an


inference is drawn immediately from an object, without any
intermediate cause or effect, the conviction is much stronger,
and the perswasion more lively, than when the imagination
is carryd thro a long chain of connected arguments, however infallible the connexion of each link may be esteemd.
(98/144)
The point Hume is making is clear: Long chains of reasoning can
lose their force simply in virtue of their length. The reason for this
is that vivacity must gradually decay in proportion to the distance,
and must lose somewhat in each transition. Here various analogies
spring to mind: The friction involved in each transition rubs off
some of the vivacitys luster, or, here, as elsewhere, entropy takes its
toll. None of these analogies seems adequate. Then again, Humes
talk about vivacity is not without problems of its own. In any case,
the important idea here is that re-iterated diminutions, to use
Humes phrase (99/145), will reduce the doxastic force of a series of
inferences in direct proportion to its length.
At this point, Hume goes off into a neighboring eld to respond
to the criticism that the principle of reiterated diminutions, if true,
would have the effect of destroying our knowledge of the ancient
past.
Tis evident there is no point of antient history, of which
we can have any assurance, but by passing thro many millions of causes and effects, and thro a chain of arguments
of almost an immeasurable length. Before the knowledge of
the fact coud come to the rst historian, it must be conveyd
thro many mouths; and after it is committed to writing,
each new copy is a new object, of which the connexion with
the foregoing is known only by experience and observation.

Hume on Unphilosophical Probabilities

33

Perhaps, therefore, it may be concluded from the precedent


reasoning, that the evidence of all antient history must
now be lost; or at least, will be lost in time, as the chain of
causes encreases, and runs on to a greater length. . . . This
may be considerd as an objection to the present system.
If belief consisted only in a certain vivacity, conveyd from
an original impression, it woud decay by the length of the
transition, and must at last be utterly extinguishd: And vice
versa, if belief on some occasions be not capable of such an
extinction; it must be something different from that vivacity.
(98/14445)
Humes response to this criticism is quite remarkable. In essence
it comes to this: Whether reiterative diminution will destroy our
beliefs concerning the ancient past depends on the manner in which
we view the sequence of transitionsan idea of central importance
in part 4. Looked at in one way, reiterative diminution would
indeed have the effect of destroying all beliefs handed down to us
from the past:
If all the long chain of causes and effects, which connect any
past event with any volume of history, were composd of parts
different from each other, and which twere necessary for the
mind distinctly to conceive, tis impossible we shoud preserve
to the end any belief or evidence. (99/146)
That is, if we look at the matter sequentially, we would recognize
that each time information about the remote past is transmitted,
some vivacity (hence assurance) is lost.1 With a sufcient number of
reiterations, belief in the past events would be annihilated. But we
do have strong beliefs concerning the remote past. How, on Humes
theory, is this possible?

34

Humes Skeptical Crisis

Humes answer is that, in fact, and fortunately, we do not view


the matter sequentially:
Let us consider, that tho the links are innumerable, that connect any original fact with the present impression, which is
the foundation of belief; yet they are all of the same kind, and
depend on the delity of printers and copists. One edition
passes into another, and that into a third, and so on, till we
come to that volume we peruse at present. There is no variation in the steps. After we know one, we know all of them;
and after we have made one, we can have no scruple as to
the rest. This circumstance alone preserves the evidence of
history. (99/146)
Then this crucial move:
But as most of these proofs [that make up the long chain
of inferences] are perfectly resembling, the mind runs easily
along them, jumps from one part to another with facility, and
forms but a confusd and general notion of each link. (99/146,
emphasis added)
What are we to make of Humes claim that we have a confused
notion of each link in the chain of inferences? For Hume, having
a confused notion of these links contrasts with having a distinct
notion of them, that is, recognizing them as distinct entities. This
may seem a bit shifty in its use of the notion of being distinct, but
it is just what Hume says:
By this means a long chain of argument, has as little effect in
diminishing the original vivacity, as a much shorter woud have,
if composd of parts, which were different from each other, and
of which each requird a distinct consideration. (99/146)

Hume on Unphilosophical Probabilities

35

It seems, then, that beliefs in remote past events are preserved only
because we become fuddled when we think of how they have been
handed down to us. This idea that a limitation or weakness in the
human intellect can protect us from an unanswerable skeptical challenge will reappear in part 4, section 1.
Prejudice based on general rules
Hume calls his fourth species of unphilosophical probability
prejudice:
A fourth unphilosophical species of probability is that derivd
from general rules, which we rashly form to ourselves, and
which are the source of what we properly call prejudice.
An Irishman cannot have wit, and a Frenchman cannot have
solidity; for which reason, tho the conversation of the former
in any instance be visibly very agreeable, and of the latter very
judicious, we have entertaind such a prejudice against them,
that they must be dunces or fops in spite of sense and reason.
Human nature is very subject to errors of this kind; and perhaps this nation as much as any other. (99100/14647)
With respect to prejudice, the general rules that govern our judgment
are rashly formed and stand in contrast to those that proceed from
more general and authentic operations of the understanding.
Following the pattern found in his discussion of the rst three
forms of unphilosophical probability, Hume proceeds to offer an
account of why human beings reason in this unreasonable way:
Shoud it be demanded why men form general rules, and
allow them to inuence their judgment, even contrary to
present observation and experience, I shoud reply, that in my

36

Humes Skeptical Crisis

opinion it proceeds from those very principles, on which all


judgments concerning causes and effects depend. Our judgments concerning cause and effect are derivd from habit and
experience; and when we have been accustomd to see one
object united to another, our imagination passes from the
rst to the second, by a natural transition, which precedes
reection, and which cannot be prevented by it. (100/147)
The text here is not altogether transparent. It seems that Hume is
attributing a double capacity to the imagination. After experiencing
a customary union of objects of type A with objects of type B, on the
appearance of A we are disposed to infer the forthcoming presence
of B, but not only that, we are also disposed to accept a general rule
to the effect that As are sure indicators of the associated Bs. Suppose,
for example, that Nigel believes that a Frenchman cannot have solidity. He might have absorbed this belief from his cultural heritage,
but let us suppose that his belief is based on his own encounters
with the French. Having encountered a series of Frenchmen lacking
in solidity, his imagination performs two operations. First, on again
encountering a Frenchman he will immediately take it for granted
that he is dealing with someone lacking solidity. Along with this,
under the inuence of the imagination, he will also adopt a general
rule to the effect that all Frenchmen lack solidity. Now suppose he
encounters a Frenchman of unquestionable depth and probity. If he
recognizes this, then, from the standpoint of philosophical probability, he should resist automatically assuming that this particular
person lacks solidity. Similarly, he should relax his general rule that
all Frenchmen lack solidity. However, the grip of the general rule
can be tenacious, preventing Nigel from recognizing the depth and
probity of the Frenchman before him. General rules, tenaciously
held, can blind Nigel to contrary evidence. He may even see the

Hume on Unphilosophical Probabilities

37

Frenchmans actions as foppish when they are not. All in all, not a
bad start for an account of the nature of prejudice.

Z
Conicts within the Imagination
and Skepticism
It is easy to read this examination of the nature and sources of prejudice as no more than a cautionary tale concerning the dangers of
rash generalizations as opposed to the security provided by generalizations that are broader and more authentic. That, however, is not
how Hume proceeds. Instead, he treats the conict between general
rules that are grounded in philosophical probabilities and those that
are grounded in unphilosophical probabilities as a challenge to his
theory:
According to my system, all reasonings are nothing but the
effects of custom; and custom has no inuence, but by enlivening the imagination, and giving us a strong conception of
any object. It may, therefore, be concluded, that our judgment and imagination can never be contrary, and that custom cannot operate on the latter faculty after such a manner,
as to render it opposite to the former. (101/149)
The fact is, however, that general rules derived from unphilosophical probabilities sometimes do clash with those having a philosophically more proper heritage.
Thus our general rules are in a manner set in opposition to
each other. When an object appears, that resembles any cause
in very considerable circumstances, the imagination naturally
carries us to a lively conception of the usual effect, tho the

38

Humes Skeptical Crisis

object be different in the most material and most efcacious


circumstances from that cause. Here is the rst inuence of
general rules. But when we take a review of this act of the
mind, and compare it with the more general and authentic operations of the understanding, we nd it to be of an
irregular nature, and destructive of all the most establishd
principles of reasoning; which is the cause of our rejecting it.
This is a second inuence of general rules, and implies the
condemnation of the former. Sometimes the one, sometimes
the other prevails, according to the disposition and character
of the person. The vulgar are commonly guided by the rst,
and wise men by the second. (1012/14950)
It seems, then, that the operations of the associative principles of
the imagination are not highly discriminate in the beliefs that they
entrench.
These reections lead Hume to make his rst reference to skepticism in the Treatise:
Meanwhile the sceptics may here have the pleasure of observing a new and signal contradiction in our reason, and of seeing
all philosophy ready to be subverted by a principle of human
nature, and again savd by a new direction of the very same
principle. The following of general rules is a very unphilosophical species of probability; and yet tis only by following
them that we can correct this, and all other unphilosophical
probabilities. (102/150)
This passage is a harbinger of things to come in part 4, where conicts within the operations of the mindand the skeptical consequences that ow from thembecome a central concern.

Chapter 3 Z Humes Skepticism with


Regard to Reason

Z
The Turn to Skepticism
Part 4 of book 1 of the Treatise represents the outer limit of Humes
critical reections on the philosophical enterprise. To borrow a
phrase from Immanuel Kant, it represents Humes attempt to delineate the fate of reason when its demands are pursued in an unrestricted manner. The result, as both Hume and Kant portray it, is
intellectual disaster. There is, however, an important difference in
the scope of their critiques. Kants primary target is the attempt
to produce substantive (synthetic) a priori knowledge that reaches
beyond the phenomenal world. Roughly speaking, his critique concerns metaphysics as traditionally pursued. Humes critique is more
radical and more far-reaching, for it calls into question both the
understanding and the senses in their modest and natural employments, not just their misemployment in a priori metaphysics. The
opening sections (1 and 2) of part 4 taken together yield the sweeping negative conclusion that
[t]is impossible upon any system to defend either our understanding or senses; and we but expose them farther when we
endeavour to justify them in that manner. As the sceptical
doubt arises naturally from a profound and intense reection
39

40

Humes Skeptical Crisis

on those subjects, it always encreases, the farther we carry


our reections, whether in opposition or conformity to it.
(144/218)
Hume seems to leave no areas protected from radical doubt except,
perhaps, immediate subjective reports.
I think this result comes as a shock to the reader after the condent development of Humes science of human nature in the rst
three parts of book 1. Earlier, in Humes discussion of unphilosophical probabilities, there were some indications that the operations of
the imagination can have problematic results, but nothing prepares
the reader for the radical change of direction that seems to occur
when we pass from part 3 to part 4.

Z
The Basic Argument
This much is clear from the text: Section 1, part 4, book 1 of the
Treatise opens with a skeptical examination of the demonstrative
sciences (Humes words), that is, of beliefs based on demonstration
and intuition. Given his own nomenclature, both intuitive and
demonstrative truths are in the domain of knowledge as opposed
to the domain of probability. It is also clear that Humes skepticism is not limited to the domain of knowledge, but includes
the domain of probability as well. The moral that Hume draws
from his skeptical reections is that our intellectual faculties, when
allowed to follow their own principles without restraint, are wholly
destructive of beliefs based on reasoning. So the scope of Humes
argument is unrestricted: It is not limited to those beliefs that are
the product of demonstrative and intuitive reasoning, though it
includes them.

Humes Skepticism with Regard to Reason

41

It is also clear from the text that Humes skepticism concerning


demonstrative reasoning is based on probabilistic reasoning. This
contrasts with traditional skeptical attacks on demonstrative reasoning that usually point to such things as the circularity of demonstrative proofs, the threat of an innite regress, the lack of probity, the
appearance of paradoxes, and the like. Humes challenge is quite
different and, to the best of my knowledge, without precedent. In
effect, he starts by raising the question: How do we establish the
appropriate level of assurance that we should assign to any piece of
demonstrative reasoning? That, for Hume, is a matter of assessing
the probability of error.
Reducing knowledge to probability
The rst step in Humes skeptical argument is an attempt to show
that, under the critical eye of proper reasoning, knowledge degenerates into probability. The key move involves what Hume will later
refer to as a reex act of the mind (122/182).
In all demonstrative sciences the rules are certain and infallible; but when we apply them, our fallible and uncertain faculties are very apt to depart from them, and fall into error.
We must, therefore, in every reasoning form a new judgment,
as a check or controul on our rst judgment or belief; and
must enlarge our view to comprehend a kind of history of
all the instances, wherein our understanding has deceivd us,
compard with those, wherein its testimony [emphasis added]
was just and true. Our reason must be considerd as a kind of
cause, of which truth is the natural effect; but such-a-one as
by the irruption of other causes, and by the inconstancy of our
mental powers, may frequently be prevented. By this means

42

Humes Skeptical Crisis

all knowledge degenerates into probability; and this probability is greater or less, according to our experience of the veracity or deceitfulness of our understanding, and according to
the simplicity or intricacy of the question. (121/180)
Before getting into details of the skeptical argument concerning
reason, we should note that Hume presents his argument using the
metaphor of testimony. Our reason, he tells us, provides us with
testimony that is sometimes just and true; at other times it deceives
us. In order to assess the reliability of this testimony, we should
shift our attention away from the immediate object of our judgment
and examine the reliability of our faculties in dealing with the matter at hand. We should consider the ratio of the testimony that has
deceived us relative to the testimony that is just and true. Ideally, the
veracity should fully outweigh the deceitfulness, leaving us fully (or
at least highly) condent. If not, our level of condence should be
adjusted accordingly. This sounds quite sensible and in line with the
discussion in section 12, Of the probability of causes.1
Hume may be wrong in saying knowledge degenerates into
probabilitywe will look at his arguments for this shortlybut at
least he is saying this: Establishing a claim to demonstrative knowledge always involves establishing a prior claim of probability. That
is an arresting idea in itself, and not altogether implausible.2
Hume adds another reason for holding that the evaluation of
demonstrative reasoning reduces to or is at least dependent on probabilistic reasoning.
There is no algebraist nor mathematician so expert in his
science, as to place entire condence in any truth immediately upon his discovery of it, or regard it as any thing but
a mere probability. Every time he runs over his proofs, his
condence increases; but still more by the approbation of his

Humes Skepticism with Regard to Reason

43

friends; and is raisd to its utmost perfection by the universal


assent and applauses of the learned world. Now, tis evident,
that this gradual increase of assurance is nothing but the addition of new probabilities, and is derived from the constant
union of causes and effects, according to past experience and
observation. (121/18081)
Here it will help to contrast a horizontal with a vertical perspective
for evaluating the soundness of a proof. The wise algebraist runs
over his proofs a number of times to make sure they are free of error.
Similarly, in adding up a long column of gures, it is prudent to
check the result a number of times, perhaps adding from top to bottom one time, from bottom to top the next. One can also ask others
to check the resultor use a calculator. If the sums consistently
come out the same, this increases ones condence that the sum is
correct. On the horizontal approach, justication, as we might put
it, remains on the same level: We check a computation relative to
further computations. If a general agreement results, even if counterbalanced by a few disagreements, this can place the correctness of
the computation beyond doubt.
The regression argument
Instead of resting content with a horizontal perspective for the assessment of arguments, Hume insists that the canons of reason demand
that arguments be evaluated from a vertical perspective as well:
In every judgment, which we can form concerning probability, as well as concerning knowledge, we ought always to correct the rst judgment, derivd from the nature of the object,
by another judgment, derivd from the nature of the understanding. (122/18182)

44

Humes Skeptical Crisis

Here we are not concerned with nding further conrming evidence, but, instead, we step up a level and reect on our ability to
carry out conformational procedures correctly. As Hume points out,
this principle applies not only to the assessment of demonstrative
arguments, but also to the assessment of probabilities themselves:
As demonstration is subject to the controul of probability,
so is probability liable to a new correction by a reex act of
the mind, wherein the nature of our understanding, and
our reasoning from the rst probability become our objects.
(122/182)
This claim has two important implications. The rst is that an argument that began with demonstrative reasoning as its target is now,
as Hume explicitly states, made equally applicable to probabilistic
reasoning. Secondand this is crucial to Humes argumentthe
reex act of judging our own capacities will, of itself, add a new
uncertainty into our considerations.
Having thus found in every probability, beside the original
uncertainty inherent in the subject, a new uncertainty derivd
from the weakness of that faculty, which judges, and having
adjusted these two together, we are obligd by our reason to
add a new doubt derivd from the possibility of error in the
estimation we make of the truth and delity of our faculties.
(122/182)
The principle of reiterative diminution
Humes regression argument yields the traditional skeptical trope
of innite regress, and that, it would seem, would be sufcient to
achieve Humes skeptical purposes. However, an innite-regress

Humes Skepticism with Regard to Reason

45

argument is usually intended to show that some claim cannot be


justied because the demand for justication keeps repeating itself.
Humes central focus is on beliefs: how they are formed, how they
can be strengthened, and here, how they can be extinguished by
the relentless application of what he takes to be a canon of proper
reasoning. It is, I think, for this reason that he appeals to the notion
of reiterated diminutionsan idea that, as we saw, made its rst
appearance in his discussion of unphilosophical probabilities. Here
is how Hume exploits this principle in the present context:
No nite object can subsist under a decrease repeated in innitum; and even the vastest quantity, which can enter into
human imagination, must in this manner be reducd to nothing.
(122/182)
[Thus] all the rules of logic require a continual diminution, and at last a total extinction of belief and evidence.
(122/183)
In order to show that Humes reasoning is not wholly articial, it
will be helpful to consider an example of a situation where human
beings would actually engage in such reasoning, at least up to a
point. A cognitive psychologist is conducting the following experiment: Computations are ashed fairly briey on a screen. (We will
assume that there is no difculty in reading them correctly.) Subjects
viewing them are asked to record whether the computation is correct or not. If they answer correctly, they are awarded one point; if
they answer incorrectly, they lose two points. They can also take a
bye and not win or lose any points. A handsome prize is awarded to
the subject who accumulates the most points.
This game reects the structure of Humes argument reasonably
well. The players willingness to bet reects the level of their condence. There are two factors at work: The chance of being wrong is

46

Humes Skeptical Crisis

a function of the complexity of the computation presented but also


a function of the players ability to do arithmetic in their heads. In
this situation, the players could, in fact, begin an ascent of the kind
that Hume speaks of. Faced with a long division that strikes her
as correct, a particular player rst thinks she should bet that it is.
That is level one. She might, however, recall that she has often lost
bets on long divisions that struck her as right. Because of this, her
condence in her original decision is shaken and she now thinks she
should take a bye instead. That is level two. But the regress can be
pursued a step higher, for here again, she is relying on the testimony
of her fallible understanding, which, if she is judicious, should
become the subject of a new correction by a reex act of the mind,
wherein the nature of our understanding, and our reasoning from
the rst probability become our objects. And so on indenitely.
What are we to say about Humes argument and its counterpart game? They both depend on the endless nesting of condence
assessments inside condence assessments. The stack of assessments
of assessments goes endlessly high and in the process the nesting
becomes endlessly complex. That is a bad thing, but does not, in
itself, yield the diminution in condence that Hume insists on. All
sorts of patterns might emerge. Suppose that the subjects are told
whether their answers are correct immediately after they record
each decision. In this setting, another subject may be struck by her
uncanny ability to get things right. She therefore sees (and has) no
good reason to correct her original rst-level decisions and no diminution of assurance takes place. What this shows is that a reex act
of the mind, wherein the nature of our understanding, and our reasoning from the rst probability become our objects need not, of
itself, produce the diminution in condence required, as Hume puts
it, by all the rules of logic. Whether such a correction is necessary
depends on a contingent matter of fact.3

Humes Skepticism with Regard to Reason

47

So I think that Hume is simply wrong in thinking that the application of the reex principle automatically introduces a diminution in assurance demanded by the laws of logic or rationality. We
might better consider the reex act of self-examination a useful aid
for epistemic (or doxastic) prudence. There are occasions where it
is prudent to take into consideration our mental abilities for dealing with a complex or unfamiliar matter. One way to do this is to
take the vertical approach and consider how well we have done in
the past in dealing with matters of the kind at hand. The reexive move has, however, a fundamental shortcoming: As we ascend
higher and higher in levels of probability assessments of probability assessments, we almost immediately run out of data concerning
how well we have performed tasks of this kind. We have no idea, for
example, how well we do in making fourth-level assessments since,
in all likelihood, we have never attempted to perform one. Isnt this
lack of adequate data enough to yield Humes skeptical conclusion?
No. What it shows is that the vertical method has a use, but a very
limited use, in evaluating ones own cognitive capacities. This result
would carry skeptical consequences only if there were no alternative
way of guarding against cognitive errors.
What I have called the horizontal method provides an alternative to the vertical method. To repeat an example, if the result that
I get in adding up a column of gures coincides with the results
that others get, that increases my condence that my result is correct. Beyond thisand this is importantit also increases my condence that I am reliable in performing tasks of this particular kind.
Doesnt this ignore the possibility that something everyone agrees
on might be wrong? It does ignore this possibility. Relying on this
point would, however, subvert Humes attempt to show that canons of rationality, pursued without constraint, ultimately destroy
all beliefs. Transforming Humes skeptical argument into a general

48

Humes Skeptical Crisis

worry about human fallibility misses the specic point Hume is trying to establish.
If I am right, Humes skepticism with regard to reason suffers
from two serious shortcomings. The rst is that he has not shown
that making the reexive move will, in virtue of principles of logic
or rationality, diminish levels of assurance. The second is that he
has not shown that the vertical approach is the sole and demanded
method for establishing the reliability of ones cognitive faculties. In
sum, neither epistemic nor doxastic prudence forces us to adopt the
vertical approach, and even if we do, principles of logic or rationality do not, of themselves, yield diminution of assurance.4

Z
Humes Response to His Skeptical Argument
It seems, then, that Humes skeptical argument with regard to reason
does not work. Hume, however, thought it did, and his response to
this skeptical argument is worth examining. The skeptical argument
has three central components:
1. The Reexive Principle
2. An Innite Regress
3. The Principle of Reiterative Diminution
All three principles are, for him, demands of rationality. Intellectually,
he embraces them without reservation. Hume also holds that, taken
together, these demands of reason lead to the annihilation of both
knowledge and probability. Given this, is Hume a skeptic or not?
Hume poses this question himself:
Shoud it here be askd me, whether I sincerely assent to this
argument, which I seem to take such pains to inculcate, and
whether I be really one of those sceptics, who hold that all

Humes Skepticism with Regard to Reason

49

is uncertain, and that our judgment is not in any thing possessed of any measures of truth and falsehood; I shoud reply,
that this question is entirely superuous, and that neither I,
nor any other person was ever sincerely and constantly of that
opinion. Nature, by an absolute and uncontroulable necessity, has determind us to judge as well as to breathe and feel.
(123/183)
Hume asks two questions, not one: Do I assent to the argument?
and Am I one of those skeptics who holds that all is uncertain?
He does not answer the rst question directly, but instead calls it
superuous. Why is it superuous? Because he, like everyone else in
the world, is incapablepsychologically incapableof total skepticism or total suspension of belief. But still, does he accept the argument or not? The answer to this question is yes, he does accept it,
for he thinks that he has presented an argument that is theoretically
irrefutable. What may seem odd is that he accepts an argument that
establishes the groundlessness of our believing, yet he cannot cease
believing. In Fogelin (1985) I tried to capture these dual aspects of
Humes position by drawing a distinction between theoretical skepticism and belief or doxastic skepticism. A theoretical skeptic puts
forward arguments intended to show that beliefs of a certain kind
(perhaps all beliefs) lack adequate warrant. Hume, as I read him, is
a radical, if not quite unmitigated, theoretical skeptic.5 The notion
of a doxastic skeptic comes closer to the common understanding of
a skeptic: The doxastic skeptic suspends judgments concerning various kinds of beliefs or perhaps all beliefs. She may do so on the basis
of theoretical skepticism, or she may not. Using this terminology,
Hume is a mitigated doxastic skeptic, though, as we shall see, the
degree of mitigation varies with context. The upshot of this discussion is that Hume actually has two reasons for thinking that attacks
on his skeptical argument will fail: From a theoretical perspective,

50

Humes Skeptical Crisis

the argument is irrefutable; from the doxastic perspective, there is


no one to attack.
A further question remains for Hume to answer:
But here, perhaps, it may be demanded, how it happens, even
upon my hypothesis, that these arguments above-explaind
produce not a total suspense of judgment, and after what
manner the mind ever retains a degree of assurance in any
subject? (123/184)
Of course, most people have never heard of Humes argument, but
Hume has and so have we. How, on the face of it, can any of us in
the know (as it were) sustain any of our beliefs?
I answer, that after the rst and second decision; as the action
of the mind becomes forcd and unnatural, and the ideas faint
and obscure; tho the principles of judgment, and the ballancing of opposite causes be the same as at the very beginning; yet their inuence on the imagination, and the vigour
they add to, or diminish from the thought, is by no means
equal. . . . The posture of the mind is uneasy; and the spirits
being diverted from their natural course, are not governd in
their movements by the same laws, at least not to the same
degree, as when they ow in their usual channel. (124/185)
I think that this aptly describes what happens in the game introduced
above. We can ascend the ladder of reexive evaluations a few rungs,
but soon things go fuzzy, then blank.6 It seems that if we could sustain
our commitments to the three principles of rationality, or maintain our
stance in the reective mode, then all our beliefs would be destroyed.
Fortunately a nonrational principlethat we enter with difculty
into remote views of thingsoverrides these rational principles and
thereby stays the hand of the principle of reiterated diminutions.

Humes Skepticism with Regard to Reason

51

I think it is important to note that in section 1, Hume exhibits


no jitters as a result of his skepticism with regard to reasonthat
will come later. His purpose in presenting this skeptical argument,
he tells us, is to illustrate the correctness of his own account of cause
and effect and, more deeply, his account of belief-formation.
My intention then in displaying so carefully the arguments
of that fantastic sect, is only to make the reader sensible of
the truth of my hypothesis, that all our reasonings concerning
causes and effects are derivd from nothing but custom; and that
belief is more properly an act of the sensitive, than of the cogitative part of our natures. (123/183)
In contrast:
If belief, therefore, were a simple act of the thought, without
any peculiar manner of conception, or the addition of a force
and vivacity, it must infallibly destroy itself, and in every case
terminate in a total suspense of judgment. (123/184)
These passages clearly support a naturalistic reading of the text.
Hume has, to his satisfaction, eliminated a rival intellectualist theory
by presenting a skeptical argument that refutes it, and, beyond this,
has shown, again to his satisfaction, that the intellectualist standards
are the source of this skeptical argument. Using his own theory, he
has given an explanation to how this skeptical impasse necessarily
arises when rational principles are relentlessly pursued, and has further shown how the operations of our nonrational faculties provide
the only way of avoiding this disaster.
This reading is borne out by the structure of the text itself. Part 3
of book 1 is titled Of knowledge and probability. There Hume
argues that an adequate account of probability can be derived from
the nonrational faculty of the imagination. In the opening section

52

Humes Skeptical Crisis

of part 4, book 1, Hume argues that, under governance of rational


(as opposed to natural) principles, knowledge reduces to probability, and probability, under reiterative diminution, reduces to nothing. That, for Hume, is where we wind up if we take reason to be
the foundation for the xation of belief. It is hard to nd a stronger
basis for a naturalistic reading of the text than this. There is, however, more to come.

Z
Peritrope
It is important to keep in mind that, for Humes purposes, it is
essential that the skeptical argument he has propounded be theoretically irrefutable. For this reason he is called upon to defend it. A
standard ploy, dating back to antiquity, is to argue that skepticism
can be shown to be self-refuting by turning skeptical arguments
back upon themselves (peritrope). How, it is asked, can rational
arguments be used to undercut rationality itself without thereby
undercutting themselves? Hume offers the following response to
this challenge.
This argument is not just; because the sceptical reasonings . . . woud be successively both strong and weak, according
to the successive dispositions of the mind. . . . The sceptical
and dogmatical reasons are of the same kind, tho contrary
in their operation and tendency; so that where the latter
is strong, it has an enemy of equal force in the former to
encounter; and as their forces were at rst equal, they still
continue so, as long as either of them subsists; nor does one
of them lose any force in the contest, without taking as much
from its antagonist. Tis happy, therefore, that nature breaks

Humes Skepticism with Regard to Reason

53

the force of all sceptical arguments in time, and keeps them


from having any considerable inuence on the understanding. Were we to trust entirely to their self-destruction, that
can never take place, till they have rst subverted all conviction, and have totally destroyd human reason. (125/18687)
This is certainly ingenious, but it is not responsive to a primitive
uneasiness. Hume, if his reasoning is correct, has produced an argument using probabilistic considerations that shows that probabilistic reasoning, systematically pursued, will be destructive of all
beliefs. Turning the table on this reasoning, we apply it to Humes
probabilistic reasoning and ask whether it undercuts itself. Humes
answerand as far as I can see, his only possible answerwould
have to go something like this: Not to worry, human beings are
incapable of pursuing this probabilistic reasoning far enough down
(actually up) this path of reiterative evaluations to reach skepticism. This hardly provides solace, for, thanks to Humes argument,
we know in advance where the successive applications of probability
assessments will lead: to total skepticism. We do not actually have
to perform these assessments to see this.
It seems then that Humes position is dialectically unstable. His
skeptical argument has to be sound in order to promote his skepticism with regard to reason. Yet when applied to itself, the argument
does seem self-defeating. Hume can explain why this skeptical argument causes no difculties for the vulgar. They know nothing of it,
and if, for some reason, they set out on the path of making higherorder probability assessments, they will quickly tire and give up.
The combination of ignorance and weakness of the intellect shields
them from danger. The learnedat least those among them who are
familiar with Humes skeptical argumenthave no like protection.
If they accept Humes argument, as Hume thinks they must, they

54

Humes Skeptical Crisis

will agree that the successive application of the reexive method will
lead to a total destruction of beliefand they will agree without so
much as making a serious try at applying this method. The ignorance and weakness of mind that protects the vulgar provides no
protection to the learned, including Hume himself.
In his section concerning skepticism with regard to reason,
Hume shows no signs of recognizing the precarious character of his
own position relative to his own skeptical argument. Hume seems
to see himself as standing above the fray while the skeptic and the
dogmatist engage in mortal combat that inevitably leads to their
mutual destruction. It doesnt seem to cross his mind that he himself could be swept up in the combat with a similar outcome. Later
he will confront this possibilitywith dramatic results.

Chapter 4 Z Of Skepticism with Regard


to the Senses

Z
Humes Turnabout with Regard to the Senses
The transition from skepticism with regard to reason to skepticism
with regard to the senses is made in these words:
Thus the sceptic still continues to reason and believe, even
tho he asserts, that he cannot defend his reason by reason; and by the same rule he must assent to the principle
concerning the existence of body, tho he cannot pretend
by any arguments of philosophy to maintain its veracity.
Nature has not left this to his choice, and has doubtless,
esteemd it an affair of too great importance to be trusted
to our uncertain reasonings and speculations. We may well
ask, What causes induce us to believe in the existence of body?
but tis in vain to ask, Whether there be body or not? That is
a point, which we must take for granted in all our reasonings. (124/187)
Thirty pages later, quite a different voice is heard:
Having thus given an account of all the systems both popular
and philosophical, with regard to external existences, I cannot
forbear giving vent to a certain sentiment, which arises upon
55

56

Humes Skeptical Crisis

reviewing those systems. I begun this subject with premising,


that we ought to have an implicit faith in our senses, and that
this woud be the conclusion, I shoud draw from the whole
of my reasoning. But to be ingenuous, I feel myself at present
of a quite contrary sentiment, and am more inclind to repose
no faith at all in my senses, or rather imagination [emphasis added], than to place in it such an implicit condence.
(14344/217)
The closing sentence of the second passage represents a fundamental shift in Humes attitude concerning the relationship between
our rational faculties and the nonrational operations of the imagination. Previously, for the most part, Hume has held that the operations of the imagination dominate the operations of the intellect,
so that on those occasions when our intellect leads us into skeptical
doubt, the imagination steps in and saves our beliefs. We have seen
two instances of this. In part 3 we saw that reason can provide no
justication for our causal inferences because it cannot provide a
proof that nature is uniformthe principle on which our causal
inferences rest. Happily for us, a bountiful nature has implanted in
us an instinct that compels us to make these inferences even so. The
opening passage of section 2 is written in much the same spirit.
The imagination saves the day with respect to skepticism with
regard to reason in a different, indeed negative, way. As we saw, it
is the inability of the imagination to preserve vivacity that saves us
from a total loss of belief. As Hume puts it: The Attention is on
the stretch; the posture of the mind is uneasy (124/185). This is not
nature being bountiful in her gifts, but being prudent in distributing them.
We have also examined one case where the mechanisms of the
imagination bequeathed to us are themselves the source of a skeptical

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses

57

crisis. That was in the discussion of prejudice in the section on


unphilosophical probability, where Hume tells us:
Sceptics may here have the pleasure of . . . seeing all philosophy ready to be subverted by a principle of human nature,
and again saved by a new direction of the very same principle.
(102/150)
The beleaguered tone of this passage is strikingly similar to the one
adopted by Hume in the closing paragraphs of section 2.
Given their past service in Humes science of human nature, the
principles of the imagination could be expected to play an important role in the explanation of the formation of our beliefs concerning external objects. In fact they do. Furthermore, I do not think
Hume has any serious reservations concerning the correctness of his
explanation. What he attempted to accomplish he thought he had
accomplished: to give a causal account of the implicit faith that the
vulgar repose in our senses, and further to give an account of the
mechanism that generates philosophers commitment to a so-called
double-existence theory of perception. The upshot of this investigation, however, is that Hume nds his own faith in his senses
slipping away, and slipping away as a natural consequence of applying his science of human nature to the formation of our perceptual
beliefs. The text is, I think, quite straightforward on this matter,
something I will try to show in detail.

Z
The Organization of Section 2
The organization of section 2 may seem peculiar, for it takes some
time before we can see why Hume speaks of skepticism with regard to

58

Humes Skeptical Crisis

the senses. In the rst twenty-plus pages of the section, he attempts


to provide a descriptive account of how the vulgarall of us most of
the timecome to believe that the objects of perception have a continued and distinct existence, even when not perceived. Throughout
this discussion, Hume largely takes it for granted that the vulgar
view is simply false. Earlier in the Treatise Hume remarks, almost
in passing, that it is allowd by philosophers, and besides pretty
obvious of itself, that nothing is ever really present with the mind but
its perceptions or impressions and ideas (49/67, emphasis added).
Humes challenge, then, is to give a causal account of the emergence
of a deeply engrained and almost universally accepted falsehood.
Though a commitment to what is commonly called the way of ideas
shapes Humes discussion, he does not get around to defending it until
near the close of section 2, and there very casually. Here it is in toto:
Twill rst be proper to observe a few of those experiments,
which convince us, that our perceptions are not possest of any
independent existence. When we press one eye with a nger,
we immediately perceive all the objects to become double,
and one half of them to be removd from their common and
natural position. But as we do not attribute a continud existence to both these perceptions, and as they are both of the
same nature, we clearly perceive, that all our perceptions are
dependent on our organs, and the disposition of our nerves
and animal spirits. This opinion is conrmd by the seeming encrease and diminution of objects, according to their
distance; by the apparent alterations in their gure; by the
changes in their colour and other qualities from our sickness
and distempers; and by an innite number of other experiments of the same kind; from all which we learn, that our
sensible perceptions are not possest of any distinct or independent existence. (140/21011)

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses

59

Far from being an argument showing that our sensible perceptions


are not possessed of any distinct or independent existence, this is little
more than a gesture in the direction of an argument. Humes casualness in presenting it can be taken as a sign of his complacency in
thinking that it will not meet with serious objections.1 I think, however, that there is a good and dialectically subtle reason why Hume
proceeds as he does. The presentation of this argument appears precisely at the point where Hume completes his examination of the
beliefs of the vulgar and turns his attention to the alternative views of
the learned. It is at this point, and not before, that his radical skepticism emerges.

Z
The Causes of Our Belief in the Existence of Bodies
Hume tells us that the subject, then, of our present enquiry is
concerning . . . the causes which induce us to believe in the existence
of body (125/18788). This question is transposed into two
questions:
Why we attribute a continud existence to objects, even
when they are not present to the senses; and why we suppose
them to have an existence distinct from the mind and perception? (12526/188)
Hume holds that continued and distinct existences are intimately
connected, indeed mutually imply each another. It does seem right
that something that continues to exist unobserved must have a distinct existence. But distinctness does not seem to imply continued
existence. Perhaps things distinct from the mind pop in and out of
existence on their own, but I will ignore this possibility.
Having presented these two (interrelated) questions, Hume goes
on to make a very strong claim concerning them:

60

Humes Skeptical Crisis

These are the only questions, that are intelligible on the present subject. For as to the notion of external existence, when
taken for something specically different from our perceptions, we have already shown its absurdity. (126/188)
In defense of this claim, Hume refers the reader to a passage earlier
in the Treatise:
Now since nothing is ever present to the mind but perceptions, and since all ideas are derivd from something antecedently present to the mind; it follows, that tis impossible for us
so much as to conceive or form an idea of any thing specically different from ideas and impressions. . . .
The furthest we can go towards a conception of external
objects, when supposd specically different from our perceptions, is to form a relative idea of them, without pretending to comprehend the related objects. Generally speaking
we do not suppose them specically different; but only attribute to them different relations, connexions and durations.
(49/6768)
Humes point, I take it, is this: To have merely a relative notion
perhaps relational notion would be betterof an external object
would be to understand it only as the cause of our perception without attributing any other properties to it. The entity would amount
to an x that is the cause of a perception, where this x is not characterized in any other way.
The senses not the source of this belief
Hume is now in a position to raise his basic question. It mimics
his previous treatment of causality. Which faculty, he asks, leads us

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses

61

to believe in the continued and distinct existence of objects: sense,


reason, or imagination (126/188)?
The possibility that the senses give us the idea of the continued
existence of an unsensed object is eliminated out of hand.
For that is a contradiction in terms, and supposes that the
senses continue to operate, even after they have ceasd all
manner of operation. (126/188)
If continued existence and distinct existence, as Hume suggests,
mutually imply each other, then the dismissal of the senses giving
us an idea of a distinct existence should be equally brisk. In fact,
Humes treatment of the topic is more elaborate:
That our senses offer not their impressions as the images of
something distinct, or independent, and external, is evident;
because they convey to us nothing but a single perception,
and never give us the least intimation of any thing beyond.
A single perception can never produce the idea of a double
existence, but by some inference either of the reason or imagination. (126/189)
The reference to double existence anticipates Humes discussion of
a philosophical view commonly called representational realism,
examined toward the end of the section. The plain man, according
to Hume, entertains no such idea. The point here is that the senses
are not capable of generating the illusion of something, so to speak,
in back of what is sensed.
Since all actions and sensations of the mind are known to
us by consciousness, they must necessarily appear in every
particular what they are, and be what they appear. Every
thing that enters the mind, being in reality a perception, Tis

62

Humes Skeptical Crisis

impossible any thing shoud to feeling appear different. This


were to suppose, that even where we are most intimately conscious, we might be mistaken. (127/190)
After making some cursory remarks about personal identity,
Hume turns his attention to what we can call the naive view of
external existence, or the outness of the things we perceive.
In casting my eye towards the window, I perceive a great extent
of elds and buildings beyond my chamber. From all this it may
be inferd, that no other faculty is requird, beside the senses, to
convince us of the external existence of body. (127/19091)
Hume offers three responses to this claim. The rst is that, properly speaking, [t]is not our body we perceive, when we regard our
limbs and members, but certain impressions, which enter by the
senses, [etc.] (127/191). This claim, however, is something Hume
has yet to establish. Humes second consideration is genuinely
arcane: Sounds, and tastes, and smells, tho commonly regarded
by the mind as continud independent qualities, appear not to have
any existence in extension, and consequently cannot appear to the
senses as situated externally to the body (127/191). Here, Hume
refers his reader to his later defense of the claim that something can
exist, but exist nowhere, presented in part 4, section 5. In his third
consideration Hume tells us that even our sight informs us not of
distance or outness (so to speak) immediately and without a certain
reasoning and experience, as is acknowledgd by the most rational
philosophers (12728/191). Given the doctrine itself and given the
use of the curious Berkelean word outness, Hume is almost certainly referring to Berkeleys problematic New Theory of Vision.2
In what seems to be an exercise in overkill, Hume adds a number
of other considerations intended to show that sense cannot be the

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses

63

source of our belief in external existents, including a brief discussion


of primary, secondary, and what we might call, just to keep the number sequence going, tertiary properties. Showing the inadequacies of
these notions does not, however, show the inadequacies of representational realism, even if it does embarrass particular versions of it.
I will not go into this here,3 but instead proceed directly to Humes
summary passage:
Thus to resume what I have said concerning the senses; they
give us no notion of continud existence, because they cannot
operate beyond the extent, in which they really operate. They
as little produce the opinion of a distinct existence, because
they neither can offer it to the mind as represented, nor as
original. To offer it as represented, they must present both an
object and an image. To make it appear as original, they must
convey a falsehood. (128/19192)

Reason not the source of this belief


To his satisfaction, Hume has eliminated the senses as the source
of the plain mans belief in the continued and distinct existence of
perceptions. He turns next to reason as a possible source of these
beliefs and says:
We can attribute a distinct continud existence to objects
without ever consulting reason, or weighing our opinions
by any philosophical principles. And indeed, whatever convincing arguments philosophers may fancy they can produce
to establish the belief of objects independent of the mind, tis
obvious these arguments are known but to very few, and that
Tis not by them, that children, peasants, and the greatest

64

Humes Skeptical Crisis

part of mankind are inducd to attribute objects to some


impressions, and deny them to others. (129/193)
While true enough, isnt this irrelevant? Suppose savants could produce an argument showing that the plain mans belief that objects
of perception have a continued and distinct existence is true.
Wouldnt that vindicate the plain mans belief, even if the proof
was wholly unknown to him? Actually, as we shall see, the savants
are united in rejecting the view of the vulgar. That, however, is
not the main point to stress. Humes project is to explain how the
vulgar acquire a belief in the external existence of bodies, and he
will spend considerable time trying to explain how the imagination
accomplishes this feat. It is a plain matter of fact that the vulgar do
not arrive at this belief by a process of ratiocination. Hume might
have left it at that.
Hume, however, does not rest his case on this plain matter of
fact but, as is his wont, adds further considerations to his argument.
He argues in addition that our belief in the distinct and continued
existence of unperceived objects cannot come from reason because
the belief is itself unreasonable.
For philosophy informs us, that every thing, which appears
to the mind, is nothing but a perception, and is interrupted,
and dependent on the mind; whereas the vulgar confound
perceptions and objects, and attribute a distinct continud
existence to the very things they feel or see. This sentiment,
then, as it is entirely unreasonable, must proceed from some
other faculty than the understanding. (129/193)
Once more, Hume simply invokes the way of ideas as grounds for
rejecting the view of the vulgar who confound, Hume says, perceptions and objects.

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses

65

Hume completes his rejection of the idea that reason can serve as
the basis of the vulgar belief in the continued and distinct existence
of perceptions by appealing to his analysis of causal relations:
To which we may add, that as long as we take our perceptions
and objects to be the same, we can never infer the existence of
the one from that of the other, nor form any argument from
the relation of cause and effect; which is the only one that
can assure us of matter of fact. Even after we distinguish our
perceptions from our objects, twill appear presently, that we
are still incapable of reasoning from the existence of one to
that of the other. (129/193)
It seems that if we take our perceptions and objects to be the
same, as the vulgar do, then there is no place for a causal relation
to apply, for no object can be the cause of itself. If we distinguish
the perceptions from the objects, as the double-existence theorists
do, we would then have two things that could enter into causal
relations, but, as we shall see, an unanswerable skeptical argument
then arises.

Z
The Operations of the Imagination in Forming
This Belief
With both sense and reason eliminated, we are left with the imagination as the source of the belief that the objects we are aware of can
enjoy a continued and distinct existence.
So that upon the whole our reason neither does, nor is it possible it ever shoud, upon any supposition, give us an assurance of the continud and distinct existence of body. That

66

Humes Skeptical Crisis

opinion must be entirely owing to the imagination; which


must now be the subject of our enquiry. (129/193)
Humes task is to show how the imagination generates the false
belief in the continued distinct existence of perceptions implicitly
held by the vulgar. Furthermore, he has to do this without endowing the vulgar with capacities that would allow them to recognize
the error involved in their naive beliefs. What follows is an extraordinarily complex explanation of how the imagination can accomplish this. Perhaps recognizing the demands his theory will make on
the reader, Hume begins by offering a broad, informal sketch of his
position before going into technical details.
Humes informal statement of his position
Hume rst argues that the belief in the continued and distinct existence of bodies cannot be based on either involuntariness or on
force and violence. (Feelings of pain can be used as counterexamples
to both suggestions.) He then considers constancy and coherence in
our train of ideas as the basis of our belief in the existence of body.
He gives homey examples of each. With respect to constancy, Hume
sees before him a desk with books and other objects on it. He closes
his eyes for a few moments, opens them again, and nds things just
as they were before he closed his eyes. With respect to coherence, he
leaves his room where a re is blazing. Returning sometime later, he
nds that the re has burned down an amount appropriate to the
time he has been absent.
Hume examines coherence, rst comparing it with everyday
causal reasoning.
[Seated in my study] I hear on a sudden a noise as of a door
turning upon its hinges; and a little after see a porter, who

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses

67

advances towards me. This gives occasion to many new reections and reasonings. First, I never have observd, that this
noise coud proceed from any thing but the motion of a door;
and therefore conclude, that the present phaenomenon is a
contradiction to all past experience, unless the door, which I
remember on the other side of the chamber, be still in being.
(13031/196)
In this passage, Hume employs what has now come to be known as
an inference to the best explanation. The existence of a door (now
unperceived) is the most reasonable way of making sense of the
sound heard and of the porters appearance before him. Hume then
adds:
There is scarce a moment of my life, wherein there is not a
similar instance presented to me, and I have not occasion to
suppose the continud existence of objects, in order to connect their past and present appearances, and give them such
an union with each other, as I have found by experience to be
suitable to their particular natures and circumstances. Here
then I am naturally led to regard the world, as something real
and durable, and as preserving its existence, even when it is
no longer present to my perception. (131/197)
What are we to make of this passage? Is Hume actually presenting
a proof of the existence of the external world? That cannot be right,
so we have to assume that the passage is written from the vulgar perspective where we often make inferences to the existence of things
that we are not perceiving in order to make sense of things that we
are perceiving. Hume is suggesting that a parallel pattern of reasoning takes place when we infer continued existence from coherence.
He notes, however, an important difference between the two cases:

68

Humes Skeptical Crisis

But tis evident, that, whenever we infer the continud existence of the objects of sense from their coherence, and the
frequency of their union, tis in order to bestow on the objects
a greater regularity than what is observd in our mere perceptions. (131/197)
That is, taken at face value, our actual experience is interrupted
(fragmented, eeting, etc.), yet imagination somehow contrives to
disguise this gappiness.
Having shown how the maintenance of coherence can be a factor
supporting the vulgar view concerning the status of objects of perception, Hume largely sets it aside in favor of the inuence of constancy of all external bodies; and that we must join the constancy
of their appearance to the coherence, in order to give a satisfactory
account of that opinion (132/19899).
Humes homey example of the inuence of constancy concerned,
as we saw, his looking at his desk, closing his eyes for a bit, and upon
opening them nding the objects on his desk arranged in the same
way as they were before he closed his eyes. The constancy in this
experience naturally leads him to believe that the objects he observes
after reopening his eyes are the selfsame things that he saw before he
closed them. Now speaking of the reappearance of the perception
of the sun or ocean, Hume provides a more elaborate sketch of the
mechanisms that bring about the belief that we are experiencing the
very same thing again, when, in fact, we are not.
When we have been accustomd to observe a constancy in certain impressions, and have found, that the perception of the
sun or ocean, for instance, returns upon us after an absence
or annihilation with like parts and in a like order, as at its rst
appearance, we are not apt to regard these interrupted perceptions as different, (which they really are) but on the contrary

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses

69

consider them as individually the same, upon account of their


resemblance. But as this interruption of their existence is contrary to their perfect identity, and makes us regard the rst
impression as annihilated, and the second as newly created,
we nd ourselves somewhat at a loss, and are involvd in a
kind of contradiction. In order to free ourselves from this difculty, we disguise, as much as possible, the interruption, or
rather remove it entirely, by supposing that these interrupted
perceptions are connected by a real existence, of which we are
insensible. (13233/199)
As Hume makes clear, his broad, informal sketch of his position is
of a piece with his earlier accounts of mental phenomena:
This supposition, or idea of continud existence, acquires a
force and vivacity from the memory of these broken impressions, and from that propensity, which they give us to suppose
them the same; and according to the precedent reasoning, the
very essence of belief consists in the force and vivacity of the
conception. (133/199)
So far there are no signs of danger. Things change, however, when
Hume attempts to go deeper in an effort to justify what he calls his
system.
Humes systematic statement of his position
Hume provides a road map for his more difcult systematic elaboration of his position:
In order to justify this system, there are four things requisite.
First, To explain the principium individuationis, or principle of
identity. Secondly, Give a reason, why the resemblance of our

70

Humes Skeptical Crisis

broken and interrupted perceptions induces us to attribute an


identity to them. Thirdly, Account for that propensity, which this
illusion gives, to unite these broken appearances by a continud
existence. Fourthly and lastly, Explain that force and vivacity of
conception, which arises from the propensity. (133/199200)
The principle of identity
It is clear, though still worth stating, that Hume is concerned with
identity over timea concept that will play a central role in subsequent sections of part 4. This notion of identity over time is different from what we might call the bare self-identity that a single
object bears to itself at a particular time. Nor can identity over time
be explained in terms of self-identity at a given time. This is what
Hume is sayingor at least what I think he is sayingin the following, not altogether transparent, passage:
As to the principle of individuation; we may observe, that the
view of any one object is not sufcient to convey the idea of
identity. For in that proposition, an object is the same with itself, if
the idea expressd by the word, object, were no ways distinguishd
from that meant by itself; we really shoud mean nothing, nor
woud the proposition contain a predicate and a subject, which
however are implyd in this afrmation. One single object conveys the idea of unity, not that of identity. (133/200)
Appealing to a multiplicity of objects will not give us the notion of
identity over time either, for
a multiplicity of objects can never convey this idea, however
resembling they may be supposd. The mind always pronounces
the one not to be the other, and considers them as forming

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses

71

two, three, or any determinate number of objects, whose existences are entirely distinct and independent. (133/200)
Hence a dilemma:
Since then both number and unity are incompatible with the
relation of identity, it must lie in something that is neither
of them. But to tell the truth, at rst sight this seems utterly
impossible. (133/200)
Hume attempts to show how the imagination solvesor rather
submergesthis dilemma, using time as the vehicle. There is, however, a difculty with invoking time to deal with the problem of
identity. In part 2, section 3, Hume states that time cannot make
its appearance to the mind, either alone or attended with a steady
unchangeable object, but is always discovered by some perceivable
succession of changeable objects (28/35). If that is true, then an
attribution of duration to an unchanging object is a falsehooda
falsehood, Hume adds, that is the common opinion of philosophers as well of the vulgar (29/37).
In part 4, section 2, Hume repeats this account of the ctitious
temporality of unchanging objects. Specically citing part 2, section 5,
he tells us:
I have already observd, that time, in a strict sense, implies
succession, and that when we apply its idea to any unchangeable object, tis only by a ction of the imagination, by which
the unchangeable object is supposd to participate of the
changes of the co-existent objects, and in particular of that of
our perceptions. (133/200201)
Hume attempts to explain this ction of an unchanging object
existing in time by using one of his favorite devices: placing things
in different lights, or viewing them from different perspectives.

72

Humes Skeptical Crisis

For when we consider any two points of this time, we may


place them in different lights: We may either survey them at
the very same instant; in which case they give us the idea of
number, both by themselves and by the object; which must
be multiplyd, in order to be conceivd at once, as existent in
these two different points of time: Or on the other hand, we
may trace the succession of time by a like succession of ideas,
and conceiving rst one moment, along with the object then
existent, imagine afterwards a change in the time without any
variation or interruption in the object; in which case it gives
us the idea of unity. Here then is an idea, which is a medium
betwixt unity and number; or more properly speaking, is
either of them, according to the view, in which we take it:
And this idea we call that of identity. (13334/201)
To see how this works, consider the following changing sequence
of six events:
JKLMNO
Such a sequence involves multiple changes. On Humes theory, this
gives us the notion of time. Next, consider a sequence that does not
involve change:
AAAAAA
This gives us the notion of unity. Now juxtapose the two:
J K L M N O (Number)
A A A A A A (Unity)
There are, as I read Hume, two ways that we can view this juxtaposition. We can view the second (unchanging) sequence in the

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses

73

light of the transition from J to O. Taken that way, the unchanging sequence seems to share the temporality exhibited in the rst
sequence. On the other hand, we can view the second sequence
stepwise in terms of single moments and in that way preserve the
unity of the unchanging sequence. The ction of identity over
time is the result of ip-opping back and forth between these two
perspectives.
It is worth noting that Hume qualies his account of the ction
of identity over time in an important way:
Here then is an idea, which is a medium betwixt unity and
number; or more properly speaking, is either of them, according
to the view, in which we take it: And this idea we call that of
identity. (134/201, emphasis added)
In this passage Hume says something quite remarkable: Speaking
properly he is not offering an account of how a ctitious idea of
identity emerges; instead, he is offering an account of how the ction that we have such an idea arises. To put the matter another way,
he has not offered an account of how a ctitious complex idealike
that of grifnis formed. Hume is saying something stronger and
more interesting: We think that we have an idea of identity, but are
wrong in this. We are conceptually addled.4
Gap lling
The second task that Hume sets for himself is to explain why the
resemblance of our broken and interrupted perceptions induces us
to attribute an identity to them.
I now proceed to explain the second part of my system, and
show why the constancy of our perceptions makes us ascribe

74

Humes Skeptical Crisis

to them a perfect numerical identity, tho there be very


long intervals betwixt their appearance, and they have only
one of the essential qualities of identity, viz. invariableness.
(134/2012)
Hume begins this discussion by reminding his reader that his
rst concern is to explain how the vulgar, who, unlike philosophers,
do not distinguish between perceptions and objects can come to
believe in the continued existence of objects when the objects are
unperceived. In fact, their experience of what they take to be a single unchanging object may actually have the form:
(a) A_ A_A_A_A
Yet they ascribe to the object of their perception a career of the following kind:
(b) AAAAAAAAA
Because of the similarity between these two series, we are inclined to
assimilate them, but because of the gaps in (a) we also are inclined
to distinguish them. Hume attempts to explain the assimilation by
using the notion of the association of dispositions:
Nothing is more apt to make us mistake one idea for another,
than any relation betwixt them, which associates them together
in the imagination, and makes it pass with facility from one to
the other. Of all relations, that of resemblance is in this respect
the most efcacious; and that because it not only causes an
association of ideas, but also of dispositions, and makes us
conceive the one idea by an act or operation of the mind, similar to that by which we conceive the other. This circumstance
I have observd to be of great moment; and we may establish
it for a general rule, that whatever ideas place the mind in the

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses

75

same disposition or in similar ones, are very apt to be confounded. The mind readily passes from one to the other, and
perceives not the change without a strict attention, of which,
generally speaking, tis wholly incapable. (135/2034)
Hume spends a number of pages elaborating and illustrating the
contents of this passage. I will not go into the details of this discussion except to note that Humes appeal to dispositions working (as it
were) behind the scenes does seem to compromise the assumption,
cited earlier, that all actions and sensations of the mind are known
to us by consciousness, [and] must necessarily appear in every particular what they are, and be what they appear (127/190). Mental
dispositions need not be transparent to us.
The idea of continued existence
In virtue of the association of dispositions, we have a strong tendency
to take gappy sequences as non-gappy. At times, however, interruptions are too long to make this possible; despite this, we continue
to attribute an identity over time to the entities in the interrupted
sequence. This brings Hume to his third task: to account for that
propensity, which this illusion [i.e., the illusion of identity] gives, to
unite these broken appearances by a continud existence (133/200).
His answer is this:
The smooth passage of the imagination along the ideas of the
resembling perceptions makes us ascribe to them a perfect
identity. The interrupted manner of their appearance makes
us consider them as so many resembling, but still distinct
beings, which appear after certain intervals. The perplexity
arising from this contradiction produces a propension to

76

Humes Skeptical Crisis

unite these broken appearances by the ction of a continud


existence, which is the third part of that hypothesis I proposd
to explain. (136/206)
According to Hume:
Almost all mankind, and even philosophers themselves, for
the greatest part of their lives, take their perceptions to be
their only objects, and suppose, that the very being, which is
intimately present to the mind, is the real body or material
existence. Tis also certain, that this very perception or object
is supposd to have a continud uninterrupted being, and neither to be annihilated by our absence, nor to be brought into
existence by our presence. (137/2067)
To return to the familiar example, a person looking at his table
thinks that it is the very table he is perceiving, not an image or
representation of a table. He further thinks that the very thing he
perceives continues to exist when he closes his eyes, and does not
spring back into existence only on the occasion of his opening his
eyes. However deeply engrained this belief may be, as philosophers
tell us, it is false. But now a new problem confronts Hume: The
point of view of the vulgar seems worse than being simply false;
it seems atly self-contradictory. It may be doubted, Hume tells
us, whether we can ever assent to so palpable a contradiction, and
suppose a perception to exist without being present to the mind
(137/206, emphasis added). Here is Humes quite remarkable
response to this deep difculty:
What we call a mind, is nothing but a heap or collection of
different perceptions, united together by certain relations, and
supposd, tho falsely, to be endowd with a perfect simplicity

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses

77

and identity. Now as every perception is distinguishable from


another, and may be considerd as separately existent; it evidently follows, that there is no absurdity in separating any
particular perception from the mind; that is, in breaking off
all its relations, with that connected mass of perceptions,
which constitute a thinking being. (13738/207)
Analogically, let apples in a heap stand for perceptions in the mind.
Just as there is no contradiction in thinking that an apple can remain
in existence when separated from the heap, there is no contradiction in
thinking of a perception remaining in existence when separated from
the heap of perceptions that constitute a mind. Similarly, just as there
is no contradiction involved in putting the apple back in the heap,
there is no contradiction in a perception rejoining the heap of perceptions. Is this analogy apt for describing Humes position? I think it is.
In passing, we can note that Hume might have tried to extract
himself from his difculties with unperceived perceptions by
drawing a distinction between believing that a perception can
exist unperceived and believing of something that is a perception
that it can exist unperceived. The second option best characterizes the beliefs of the vulgar as Hume himself describes them.5
The belief in continued existence
The fourth and nal part of Humes program is to explain why
the vulgar not only feign but believe (138/208) that an object can
continue to exist even when it is no longer perceived. Here Hume
invokes his familiar doctrine of vivacity transfer. Not only does the
imagination create the ction of continued and distinct existence,
it also transfers vivacity to this ction, thus giving it the status of a
belief.

78

Humes Skeptical Crisis

Hume concludes his examination of the vulgar view of perception with an elegant summary passage that he believes the intelligent reader will nd wholly convincing:
Tis indeed evident, that as the vulgar suppose their perceptions
to be their only objects, and at the same time believe the
continud existence of matter, we must account for the origin of
the belief upon that supposition. Now upon that supposition,
tis a false opinion that any of our objects, or perceptions, are
identically the same after an interruption; and consequently
the opinion of their identity can never arise from reason, but
must arise from the imagination. The imagination is seducd
into such an opinion only by means of the resemblance of
certain perceptions; since we nd they are only our resembling perceptions, which we have a propension to suppose the
same. This propension to bestow an identity on our resembling perceptions, produces the ction of a continud existence; since that ction, as well as the identity, is really false,
as is acknowledgd by all philosophers, and has no other effect
than to remedy the interruption of our perceptions, which is
the only circumstance that is contrary to their identity. In the
last place this propension causes belief by means of the present
impressions of the memory; since without the remembrance
of former sensations, tis plain we never shoud have any belief
of the continud existence of body. (139/20910)

Z
The Philosophers Double-Existence
Theory of Perception
Having completed his account of the origins of the vulgar view of
perception, Hume turns his attention to the views of philosophers

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses

79

on the topic. Philosophers have been led to reject the views of the
vulgar because they think there are convincing grounds for holding
that our perceptions are not possest of any independent existence.
Hume then thinks it proper to observe a few of those experiments,
which convince us, that our perceptions are not possest of any independent existence (140/210). As I noted at the start of this chapter, given the importance of these argumentsor experiments, as
Hume calls themit is surprising how brief and underdeveloped
they are. It never seems to cross his mind to view them critically,
not to say skeptically.
Humes leading idea is that adopting the way of ideas rst
drives philosophers out of the common standpoint, but, under
the inuence of everyday beliefs that they cannot fully shake, they
are naturally led to adopt what Hume calls a double-existence theory of perception. This theory, which has come to be known as
representational realism, can come in a variety of forms, but the
primitive idea is to draw a distinction between ideas (perceptions,
and the like) that are mind-dependent and material objects that
exist independently of minds. An idea is said to be true of a material object if it properly represents it. This is merely a prototheorya mere sketch that demands elaboration and defensebut
I will not develop it further because I think it is this prototheory,
not simply some specic realization of it, that Hume targets for
investigation.
Hume holds, in the rst place, that this theory seems to provide
a way of accommodating our previous natural (though false) belief
in the continued and distinct existence of what we perceive with a
philosophical commitment to the way of ideas. We might think of
it as a vector of these two inuences. But, according to Hume, far
from making things better, this new, double-existence theory makes
them worse. The theory is, he tells us, only a palliative remedy,
[that] contains all the difculties of the vulgar system, with some

80

Humes Skeptical Crisis

others, that are peculiar to itself (140/211). To establish this, Hume


attempts to show that the double-existence theory has no primary
recommendation either to reason or the imagination, but acquires all its
inuence on the imagination from the former [i.e., the vulgar system]
(140/211).
The argument intended to show that the double-existence theory has no primary appeal to reason is a standard skeptical argument that takes Hume only a paragraph to state.
The only conclusion we can draw from the existence of one
thing to that of another, is by means of the relation of cause
and effect, which shows, that there is a connexion betwixt
them, and that the existence of one is dependent on that of the
other. The idea of this relation is derivd from past experience,
by which we nd, that two beings are constantly conjoind
together, and are always present at once to the mind. But as
no beings are ever present to the mind but perceptions; it
follows that we may observe a conjunction or a relation of
cause and effect betwixt different perceptions, but can never
observe it betwixt perceptions and objects. Tis impossible,
therefore, that from the existence or any of the qualities of
the former, we can ever form any conclusion concerning the
existence of the latter, or ever satisfy our reason in this particular. (14041/212)
Hume then sets aside the idea that the double-existence theory
could be the direct product of the imagination, because he cannot think of any plausible argument that might be produced along
these lines. He is content to leave the matter as a challenge to anyone who would ground the belief in double existence on the operations of imagination to provide a satisfactory account of how it is
able to do so.

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses

81

Humes refutation of the double-existence theory is brief. He


spends considerably more time giving a naturalistic account of how
the acceptance of the double-existence theory (despite its inherent
difculties) naturally emerges from the predicament in which the
philosopher nds himself. In the study, the philosopher adopts the
way of ideas, but in the street he returns to the standpoint of the
vulgar. However, and this is important, the inuence of nature cannot be fully curbed, even in the study:
Nay she has sometimes such an inuence, that she can stop
our progress, even in the midst of our most profound reections, and keep us from running on with all the consequences
of any philosophical opinion. Thus though we clearly perceive the dependence and interruption of our perceptions, we
stop short in our career, and never upon that account reject
the notion of an independent and continud existence. That
opinion has taken such deep root in the imagination, that tis
impossible ever to eradicate it, nor will any straind metaphysical conviction of the dependence of our perceptions be sufcient for that purpose. (142/214, emphasis added)
This important passage offers a partial explanation of the staying
powerthe perennial attractionof variants of representational
realism: It has deep roots in the imagination. That, however, is only
half the story:
This hypothesis . . . of the double existence of perceptions
and objects; . . . pleases our reason, in allowing, that our
dependent perceptions are interrupted and different; and at
the same time is agreeable to the imagination, in attributing a continud existence to something else, which we call
objects. This philosophical system, therefore, is the monstrous

82

Humes Skeptical Crisis

offspring of two principles, which are contrary to each other,


which are both at once embracd by the mind, and which are
unable mutually to destroy each other. (142/215)
We thus arrive at the deeply paradoxical result that a philosophical
position can gain support, indeed robust support, from an irreconcilable conict within the operations of the human mind itself.

Z
The Pyrrhonian Moment
This brings us to the second passage cited at the start of this chapter:
I begun this subject with premising, that we ought to have an
implicit faith in our senses, and that this woud be the conclusion, I shoud draw from the whole of my reasoning. But
to be ingenuous, I feel myself at present of a quite contrary
sentiment, and am more inclind to repose no faith at all in
my senses, or rather imagination, than to place in it such an
implicit condence. I cannot conceive how such trivial qualities of the fancy, conducted by such false suppositions, can
ever lead to any solid and rational system. . . . What then can
we look for from this confusion of groundless and extraordinary opinions but error and falsehood? And how can we justify
to ourselves any belief we repose in them? (14344/21718)
Hume goes further, and retroactively includes the operations of reason in his gloomy assessment:
This sceptical doubt, both with respect to reason and the
senses, is a malady which can never be radically curd, but
must return upon us every moment, however we may chase

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses

83

it away, and sometimes may seem entirely free from it. Tis
impossible upon any system to defend either our understanding or senses; and we but expose them farther when we
endeavour to justify them in that manner. As the sceptical
doubt arises naturally from a profound and intense reection
on those subjects, it always encreases, the further we carry
our reections, whether in opposition or conformity to it.
(144/218)
It should be clear what is troubling Hume. He recognizes with full
force that his account of the operations of the human mind applies
to the operations of his own minda mind incapable of leading us
to any solid and rational system, including, it seems, the development of his own science of man. It doesnt help to suggest that
Humes science of man is not intended to be a rational system,
but an empirical system instead. Hume is not restricting his claims
to the systems of rationalist philosophers. The passage just cited
makes it clear that his skeptical worries are a consequence of his own
philosophizing and that his own philosophizing falls under their
scope. We will revisit this self-referential crisis as it appears in the
nal section of book 1.

Z
A Concluding Note
Humes readers may, perhaps should, nd the development of section 2 perplexing. Hume starts out expressing an implicit faith in
the senses. He then proceeds to give an account of how this faith
in the senses emerges. His tacit assumption seems to be that this
faith is built into us as a gift of a provident nature who doubtless esteemd it an affair of too great importance to be trusted to

84

Humes Skeptical Crisis

our uncertain reasonings and speculations (125/187). Hume tells an


upbeat story along these lines with respect to our causal reasoning.
By the end of the section, however, his own reections have thoroughly shaken this implicit faith. Did he realize where he was going
to end up from the start? Who knows, but when he completed the
section he understood exactly what had taken place. Why, then,
didnt he revise the section in a way that would bring the opening
passages into conformity with the closing passages? The answer
and I think this is importantis that the section reenacts the mental processes that take us from one standpoint to another. Hume is
engaged in something like a phenomenology of mind with, however, a downward trajectory.

Chapter 5 Z Of the Ancient and Modern


Philosophy

Z
Reasons for Examining the Ancient and Modern
Philosophical Systems
At the close of section 2, Hume tells his readers that he will examine some general systems both ancient and modern that have been
proposed concerning the external and internal worlds. This will
not, he tells us, in the end be found foreign to our present purpose (144/218). What we will get, in fact, is a further demonstration
of how Humes science of man can be used to give an account
of how philosophical systems arise naturally at various stages of
philosophical inquiry. We have already seen such an investigation
with respect to the double-existence theory of perception. We will
now see how Humes science of human nature can similarly be used
with respect to both ancient and modern (i.e., seventeenth- and
eighteenth-century) notions of substance.

Z
Of the Ancient Philosophy (Section 3)
Reecting the spirit of his times, Humes attitude toward the ancient
notion of substance and the concepts related to it is patronizing
throughout.
85

86

Humes Skeptical Crisis

I am perswaded, there might be several useful discoveries made


from a criticism of the ctions of the antient philosophy, concerning substances, and substantial forms, and accidents, and
occult qualities; which, however unreasonable and capricious,
have a very intimate connexion with the principles of human
nature. (145/219)
Presumably, the study of the unreasonable and capricious employment of our mental faculties will be useful by exhibiting these faculties in a setting where they go haywire. Asking the question How
could presumably intelligent people come to believe such incredible
things? can, in its own way, shed light on the actualas opposed
to the idealizedway that human beings form concepts and acquire
beliefs.
We saw in the previous chapter how Hume used the ction
involved in ascribing duration to an unchanging object to explain
the further ction of identity over time. The ction of identity over
time was then used to give an account of the vulgar belief in the
continued and distinct existence of perceptions despite the existence
of interruptions or gaps in experience. In section 3, Of the antient
philosophy, Hume tells a parallel story concerning identity over
time, but this time in the face of change rather than interruption. He
also tells an interestingly different story about our belief in the simplicity of objects in the face of their evident complexity. Mirroring
the structure of the previous section, the discussion moves at two
levels: First, an account is given of the common opinion; then an
account is given of a philosophical opinion that naturally evolves
in an effort to save as much of the common opinion as possible,
even after philosophy discovers its untenability. Hume begins by
contrasting the views of the most judicious philosophers with those
of the common lot of mankind.

Of the Ancient and Modern Philosophy

87

Tis confest by the most judicious philosophers, that our ideas


of bodies are nothing but collections formd by the mind of
the ideas of the several distinct sensible qualities, of which
objects are composd, and which we nd to have a constant
union with each other. But however these qualities may in
themselves be entirely distinct, tis certain we commonly
regard the compound, which they form, as ONE thing, and
as continuing the SAME under very considerable alterations.
The acknowledgd composition is evidently contrary to this
supposd simplicity, and the variation to the identity. It may,
therefore, be worth while to consider the causes, which make
us almost universally fall into such evident contradictions, as
well as the means by which we endeavour to conceal them.
(145/219)1

The false belief in the continued identity


of changing objects
Given Humes strict understanding of identity, objects that differ in any qualities cannot be the same objects, and for this reason it makes no sense to speak of an object undergoing change.
In fact, however, provided that a sufcient degree of similarity is
maintained, the mind will treat a sequence of qualitatively differing
perceptions in the same way that it treats a sequence of qualitatively
unchanging perceptions. By association, it will attribute identity
over time not only to unchanging sequence, but also to a slightly
changing sequence.
The smooth and uninterrupted progress of the thought, being
alike in both cases, readily deceives the mind, and makes us

88

Humes Skeptical Crisis

ascribe an identity to the changeable succession of connected


qualities. (145/220)
But a shift in perspective can overthrow this:
But when we alter our method of considering the succession,
and instead of tracing it gradually thro the successive points
of time, survey at once any two distinct periods of its duration, and compare the different conditions of the successive
qualities; in that case the variations, which were insensible
when they arose gradually, do now appear of consequence,
and seem entirely to destroy the identity. (145/220)
Here, as before, Hume invokes the notion of two different
ways of viewing a sequence. We can represent the situation with a
diagram rather like one used before, this time, however, reecting
gradual change. Column I represents, as a foil, an unchanging
object. Column II represents a four-propertied object undergoing
gradual change.

II

ABCD
ABCD
ABCD
ABCD
ABCD

BCDE
CDEF
DEFG
EFGH
FGHI

Here each step in column II preserves three qualities, so, taken stepby-step, a strong degree of resemblance is preserved, and because
of this it maintains some degree of resemblance to the unchanging sequence in column I as well. Yet, if we shift our perspective
and compare the initial step in column II with its nal step, we
nd ourselves comparing BCDE with FGHI where no similarity

Of the Ancient and Modern Philosophy

89

remains. Admittedly this diagrammatic representation looks articial, even simpleminded, but it does, I think, capture the essence of
what Hume has in mind when he speaks of a contradiction arising
from competing perspectives.
The ction of underlying substance, or original
rst matter
The scholastic rule was: When one encounters a contradiction, draw
a distinction! The imagination, according to Hume, follows a different rule: When one encounters a contradiction, create a ction!
In order to reconcile which contradictions the imagination
is apt to feign something unknown and invisible, which it
supposes to continue the same under all these variations; and
this unintelligible something it calls a substance, or original
and rst matter. (146/220)
So, despite surface appearance, the imagination posits something
that remains constant in sequence II. It is not, however, some other
property that has hitherto gone unnoticed. It is something of a
wholly different orderas Hume tendentiously puts it, something
that is unknown, invisible, and unintelligible. Taken this way, the
imagination does not provide us with a ctitious idea of substance
or original rst matter but, instead, creates the ction that we have
such an idea. As with the notion of identity over time, it is a misunderstanding to think that Hume is speaking of a ction in the
sense that a centaur or a grifn is a ctitious being. The idea of
substance, unlike the idea of a grifn, is not an idea at all. It is,
we might say, an empty placeholder for a solution to a problem
masquerading as a solution. If that is right, then Humes treatment
of substance is of a piece with his previous treatment of the ction

90

Humes Skeptical Crisis

involved in attributing duration to an unchanging object. There too


we encountered an attribution of a contentless ction.
The false belief in the simplicity of objects
Humes examination of simplicity also involves a double perspective, but in an interestingly different way. In daily life we treat, say,
a peach as a single thing possessing various qualities.
The colour, taste, gure, solidity, and other qualities, combind
in a peach or melon, are conceivd to form one thing; and
that on account of their close relation, which makes them
affect the thought in the same manner, as if perfectly uncompounded. (146/221)
Im not sure, as Hume suggests, that we treat such objects as perfectly
uncompounded, since for various practical purposes we do distinguish parts of such objects (peels, pits, and so on). Yet, there is a
general cohesiveness in the characteristics of this object that leads us
to think of it as a single object. When I push the peach away from
me, its colors do not become detached and trail behind.
In a remarkable passage, Hume challenges even this level of
togetherness.
But the mind rests not here. Whenever it views the object
in another light, it nds that all these qualities are different,
and distinguishable, and separable from each other; which
view of things [is] destructive of its primary and more natural
notions. (146/221)
I have broken the passage here to call attention to this notion of
viewing the object in another light. Hume explains what he
means on the next page:

Of the Ancient and Modern Philosophy

91

But philosophers, who abstract from the effects of custom,


and compare the ideas of objects, immediately perceive the
falsehood of these vulgar sentiments, and discover that there
is no known connexion among objects. Every different object
appears to them entirely distinct and separate; and they perceive, that tis not from a view of the nature and qualities of
objects we infer one from another, but only when in several
instances we observe them to have been constantly conjoind.
(147/223)
When we adopt this philosophical perspective, we push aside all
connections imposed on our perceptions by our associative mechanisms and absorb ourselves in the immediate content of experience.
Here we can speak of adopting a phenomenalist stance. From the
phenomenalist stance things strike us as entirely distinct and separate. They also strike us as eeting and perishing (130/195), or as
Hume puts it in the Enquiry, loose and separate (EHU 144/74).
Things fall apart; the center cannot hold. Furthermore, a commitment to the way of ideas can be an immediate product of adopting
the phenomenalist stance, for from that perspective, it is universally allowed by philosophers, and is besides pretty obvious of itself,
that nothing is ever really present with the mind but its perceptions
or impressions and ideas (49/67, emphasis added).2
For Hume, what I am calling the phenomenalist stance is the
privileged perspective, the perspective that reveals how things really
are when all articial impositions are suppressed. It is a realm of perceptions (impressions and ideas) and nothing more. It is also a radically fractured and pluralistic world where perceptions are entirely
distinct and separate, eeting and perishing, and loose and separate.
Hume could have added, following Berkeley, that these perceptions
are visibly inactive, for, in effect, Hume holds this too.3 This is

92

Humes Skeptical Crisis

not the perspective from which the vulgar view the world. Indeed,
the two perspectives are radically opposed to one another. For the
most part, this is not the perspective of past philosophers either. For
Hume, however, any departure from this standpoint will generate
falsehoods, ctions, or plain nonsense.
The situation now becomes dialectically complex. The previous
clashes between viewpoints took place within our commonas
opposed to philosophicalunderstanding. To repeat a previous
example, our belief in the identity of an object changing over time
arises when the changes preserve a suitable level of resemblance and
are viewed sequentially. We are jolted out of this belief when we
note the lack of resemblance between an object as it appears to us
now and how it appeared to us in the distant past. Two common
ways of viewing matters come into conict: how they seemed living through them, and how they seem looking back. The present
case is quite different: Here we have a global clash between frameworks for viewing the world. From the philosophical standpoint,
the common standpoint is challenged in toto. This is precisely how
Hume proceeds in pursuing his philosophical program. Adopting
the standpoint of those he calls the most judicious philosophers, he
dismisses as errors the beliefs of the vulgar. He then attempts to provide a naturalistic account of how these errors arise. He next offers
an account of how those who operate from within the philosophical
standpoint go on to introduce a philosophical ctionsomething
plain folks know nothing ofin an effort to provide a surrogate
for the common beliefs they have demolished, yet still hanker after.
For Hume, piling a philosophical ction on the prior ctions of the
vulgar only makes matters worse.
Where is Hume himself in all this? He is a member of the philosophical party in rejecting the beliefs of the vulgar. He never, so far as
I know, rejects the standpoint of the most judicious philosophers,

Of the Ancient and Modern Philosophy

93

even if he does reject the palliatives they offer under the lingering
inuence of their vulgar upbringing.
The ction of a unifying substance
Returning to Humes treatment of simplicity, having invoked the
philosophical perspective to reject the standpoint of the vulgar,
Hume nishes off the philosophical position in the same way he
dealt with the philosophical account of the identity of an object
changing over time. Here, in full, is the passage interrupted above:
Whenever [the mind] views the object in another light, it
nds that all these qualities are different, and distinguishable,
and separable from each other; which view of things being
destructive of its primary and more natural notions, obliges
the imagination to feign an unknown something, or original substance and matter, as a principle of union or cohesion
among these qualities, and as what may give the compound
object a title to be calld one thing, notwithstanding its diversity and composition. (146/221)

The incomprehensibility of the peripatetic system


Humes summary conclusion is that the whole [peripatetic] system,
therefore, is entirely incomprehensible, and yet is derivd from principles as natural as any of those above-explaind (147/222). But how
can discourse that is entirely incomprehensible be of any service to
anyone? Humes answer, though ironic, is important:
But as nature seems to have observd a kind of justice and compensation in every thing, she has not neglected philosophers

94

Humes Skeptical Crisis

more than the rest of the creation; but has reservd them a consolation amidst all their disappointments and afictions. This
consolation principally consists in their invention of the words
faculty and occult quality. For it being usual, after the frequent
use of terms, which are really signicant and intelligible, to
omit the idea, which we woud express by them, and to preserve
only the custom, by which we recal the idea at pleasure; so it
naturally happens, that after the frequent use of terms, which
are wholly insignicant and unintelligible, we fancy them to be
on the same footing with the precedent, and to have a secret
meaning, which we might discover by reection. (14748/224)
Words such as incomprehensible, insignicant, and unintelligible have both a broad and a narrow use. Used broadly, they
indicate foolishness or unsupportability. We say, for example, that
it is incomprehensible that some people still object to uoridating
drinking water. Taking incomprehensibility this way, Humes passage amounts to a broad, abusive condemnation of the peripatetic
position. Taken more narrowly, it can indicate that the peripatetic
vocabulary lacks meaning or semantic content. Hume, I think,
would have no reservations about using this expression in both
ways, but I am inclined to take his criticism in the second way, for
that squares with the notion I have pressed that the ctions Hume
attributes to philosophers are not ideas with a ctitious content but,
instead, the ction that a term is being used with a content.
Skeptical implications
Before closing the discussion of this section, I wish to return to the
question raised above, What is Humes standpoint in this discus-

Of the Ancient and Modern Philosophy

95

sion? In two places Hume hints at an answer. Both appear in a


specic context, but have a more general signicance.
In considering this subject [occult qualities and related matters], we may observe a gradation of three opinions, that rise
above each other, according as the persons, who form them,
acquire new degrees of reason and knowledge. These opinions are that of the vulgar, that of a false philosophy, and that
of the true; where we shall nd upon enquiry, that the true
philosophy approaches nearer to the sentiments of the vulgar,
than to those of a mistaken knowledge. (147/22223)
The second passage is slightly more forthcoming in introducing the
notion of moderate skepticism.
By this means [i.e., by employing terms that are wholly insignicant and unintelligible] these philosophers set themselves at ease, and arrive at last, by an illusion, at the same
indifference, which the people attain by their stupidity,
and true philosophers by their moderate scepticism.
(148/224)
Hume concludes this section with a sally:
There is a very remarkable inclination in human nature,
to bestow on external objects the same emotions, which it
observes in itself; and to nd every where those ideas, which
are most present to it. . . . We must pardon children, because
of their age; poets, because they profess to follow implicitly the suggestions of their fancy: But what excuse shall
we nd to justify our philosophers in so signal a weakness?
(148/22425)

96

Humes Skeptical Crisis

Z
Of the Modern Philosophy (Section 4)
Before examining the modern notion of material substance, Hume
makes some prefatory remarks that are worth close attention.
He opens section 4 with a response to someone who might object
to his selectively rough treatment of the ancient philosophers.
But here it may be objected, that the imagination, according
to my own confession, being the ultimate judge of all systems
of philosophy, I am unjust in blaming the antient philosophers, for making use of that faculty, and allowing themselves
to be entirely guided by it in their reasonings. In order to justify myself, I must distinguish in the imagination betwixt the
principles which are permanent, irresistible, and universal;
such as the customary transition from causes to effects, and
from effects to causes: And the principles, which are changeable, weak, and irregular; such as those I have just now taken
notice of. The former are the foundation of all our thoughts
and actions, so that upon their removal human nature must
immediately perish and go to ruin. The latter are neither
unavoidable to mankind, nor necessary, or so much as useful
in the conduct of life; but on the contrary, are observd only
to take place in weak minds, and being opposite to the other
principles of custom and reasoning, may easily be subverted
by a due contrast and opposition. For this reason, the former
are receivd by philosophy, and the latter rejected. (148/225)
It is essential to take this paragraph in the specic context in which it
appears. Obviously, it is aimed at what Hume takes to be the extravagances of the ancient philosophersextravagances that would not
have occurred if the philosophers had constrained their thought by

Of the Ancient and Modern Philosophy

97

using only principles that are permanent, irresistible, and universal;


such as the customary transition from causes to effects, and from
effects to causes: and the principles. There is, I think, a temptation
to think that Hume is saying something much stronger, namely,
that principles of the imagination that are permanent, irresistible,
and universal will not yield skeptical consequences. That reading
of the text will not hold up, for Humes skepticism with regard to
reason and his skepticism with regard to the senses are products
of reasoning governed by just those principles that are permanent,
irresistible, and universal. It is this fact that generates Humes deep
skeptical crisis. Humes skeptical attack on the modern conception
of material substance has the same status.
A second feature of this opening paragraph is that it sets the
stage for a rhetorical ploy. After contemptuously dismissing the
ancient philosophers views on substance and related matters, we
might expect Hume to treat the supposedly more enlightened views
of modern philosophers more generously. He does not. For Hume,
the views of ancient philosophers on these topics are ridiculous; the
views of modern philosophers, no better.
Against the distinction between primary
and secondary qualities
Echoingperhaps appropriating is a better wordarguments
presented by Berkeley, Hume calls into question the modern notion
of material substance by attacking one of its central components:
the distinction between primary and secondary qualities. In brief,
Humes core argument runs as follows:
The fundamental principle of that philosophy is the opinion concerning colours, sounds, tastes, smells, heat and cold;

98

Humes Skeptical Crisis

which it asserts to be nothing but impressions in the mind,


derivd from the operation of external objects, and without
any resemblance to the qualities of the objects. (149/225)
From which it follows that
[u]pon the removal of sounds, colours, heat, cold, and other
sensible qualities, from the rank of continud independent
existences, we are reducd merely to what are calld primary
qualities, as the only real ones. (150/227)
This, according to Hume, leads to disaster.
I believe many objections might be made to this system: But
at present I shall conne myself to one, which is in my opinion very decisive. I assert, that instead of explaining the operations of external objects by its means, we utterly annihilate
all these objects, and reduce ourselves to the opinions of the
most extravagant scepticism concerning them. (150/22728)
Canvassing various possibilities, Hume comes to the conclusion
that solidity is a primary feature of material objects. Then, after
going through an elaborate argument, he comes to the further conclusion that we cannot attribute solidity to an object possessing no
secondary qualities. If that is right, it makes no senseit is unintelligibleto speak of material objects possessing primary qualities
without their also possessing some secondary qualities. We are thus
forced to the conclusion that
[o]ur modern philosophy, therefore, leaves us no just nor satisfactory idea of solidity; nor consequently of matter. (151/229)
Berkeley arrived at the same conclusion more expeditiously.

Of the Ancient and Modern Philosophy

99

I desire any one to reect and try, whether he can by any


abstraction of thought, conceive the extension and motion
of a body, without all other sensible qualities. For my own
part, I see evidently that it is not in my power to frame an
idea of a body extended and moved, but I must withal give it
some colour or other sensible quality which is acknowledged
to exist only in the mind. In short, extension, gure, and
motion, abstracted from all other qualities, are inconceivable.
(Principles, part 1, section 10)
Another Pyrrhonian moment
Section 4 ends on a Pyrrhonian note of the same tenor as the conclusion of section 2.
Thus there is a direct and total opposition betwixt our reason and our senses; or more properly speaking, betwixt those
conclusions we form from cause and effect, and those that
perswade us of the continud and independent existence of
body. When we reason from cause and effect, we conclude,
that neither colour, sound, taste, nor smell have a continud
and independent existence. When we exclude these sensible
qualities there remains nothing in the universe, which has
such an existence. (152/231)
The opening paragraphs of section 4 should be read in the light of
this, its closing paragraph, for once again we encounter a reversal.
Hume begins by comparing ancient philosophywhich was thoroughly abused in the preceding sectionwith modern philosophy.
Of the former, he tells us that

100

Humes Skeptical Crisis

the opinions of the antient philosophers, their ctions of


substance and accident, and their reasonings concerning substantial forms and occult qualities, are like the spectres in the
dark, and are derivd from principles, which, however common, are neither universal nor unavoidable in human nature.
(149/226)
In contrast:
The modern philosophy pretends to be entirely free from this
defect, and to arise only from the solid, permanent, and consistent principles of the imagination. Upon what grounds
this pretension is founded must now be the subject of our
enquiry. (149/226)
What Humes further enquiry yields is the discovery that modern
philosophy, relying on principles of the imagination that are permanent, irresistible, and universal, is no more intelligible than the
doctrines of the ancients.

Chapter 6 Z The Soul and the Self

Z
Of the Immateriality of the Soul (Section 5)
This is the second-longest section of part 4 of the Treatise. Only
Humes Of skepticism with regard to the senses is longer. It is
irreligious, in places ironic and smart-alecky, sometimes obscure. It
also contains material that is, I believe, important for understanding Humes problematic and difcult discussion of personal identity
that follows it.
Setting the dialectical stage
Hume begins by telling us that the examination of our internal perceptions will be free of the sorts of contradictions that arose when
dealing with external objects.
The intellectual world, tho involvd in innite obscurities, is
not perplexd with any such contradictions, as those we have
discoverd in the natural. What is known concerning it, agrees
with itself; and what is unknown, we must be contented to
leave so. (152/232)
Hume lays full blame for the contradictions that do emerge in the
examination of the intellectual world at the feet of philosophers.
101

102

Humes Skeptical Crisis

Tis true, woud we hearken to certain philosophers, they


promise to diminish our ignorance; but I am afraid tis at the
hazard of running us into contradictions, from which the subject is of itself exempted. These philosophers are the curious
reasoners concerning the material or immaterial substances, in
which they suppose our perceptions to inhere. (15253/232)
The soul as substance
Given what Hume has said about our (supposed) idea of substance
in sections 3 and 4 of part 4, it should be clear in advance what he
is going to say about the dispute between those who treat the soul
as an immaterial substance and those who treat it as a material substance. He will dismiss both views as nonsensical.
Neither by considering the rst origin of ideas, nor by means
of a denition are we able to arrive at any satisfactory notion
of substance; which seems to me a sufcient reason for abandoning utterly that dispute concerning the materiality and
immateriality of the soul, and makes me absolutely condemn
even the question itself. (153/234)
This passage invokes two objections to any theory that treats
the soul as a substance, be it immaterial or material. One concerns
the origin of the idea of substance, the other, the denition of substance. His opening move combines them:
As every idea is derivd from a precedent impression, had we
any idea of the substance of our minds, we must also have
an impression of it; which is very difcult, if not impossible, to be conceivd. For how can an impression represent
a substance, otherwise than by resembling it? And how can

The Soul and the Self

103

an impression resemble a substance, since, according to this


philosophy, it is not a substance, and has none of the peculiar
qualities or characteristics of a substance? (153/23233)
After this ingenious move, Hume raises his familiar challenge concerning the supposed origin of an idea.
I desire those philosophers, who pretend that we have an idea
of the substance of our minds, to point out the impression
that produces it, and tell distinctly after what manner that
impression operates, and from what object it is derivd. Is it
an impression of sensation or of reection? Is it pleasant, or
painful, or indifferent? (153/233)
The strength of this argument depends on the adequacy of Humes
theory of the origin of ideassomething that I do not wish to consider here.
The argument based on the denition of substance is more interesting and will, I think, have important repercussions for the later
discussion of personal identity. Hume imagines someone attempting to evade the demand to point out the impression that gives rise
to our idea of substance by offering a denition instead: A substance
is something that may exist by itself. To this Hume replies:
Shoud this be said, I shoud observe, that this denition agrees
to every thing, that can possibly be conceivd; and never will
serve to distinguish substance from accident, or the soul from
its perceptions. For thus I reason. Whatever is clearly conceivd
may exist; and whatever is clearly conceivd, after any manner, may exist after the same manner. This is one principle,
which has been already acknowledged. Again, every thing,
which is different, is distinguishable, and every thing which
is distinguishable, is separable by the imagination. This is

104

Humes Skeptical Crisis

another principle. My conclusion from both is, that since all


our perceptions are different from each other, and from every
thing else in the universe, they are also distinct and separable,
and may be considerd as separately existent, and may exist
separately, and have no need of any thing else to support their
existence. They are, therefore, substances, as far as this denition explains a substance. (153/233)
Humes point here is that under the proposed denition, the concept of a substance carries no explanatory power because it comprehends every thing that can possibly be conceived, including
perceptions.
If we rely on this denition of substance, we get a picture of
the mind, not simply as a bundle of perceptions, butstrictly
speakingas a bundle of substances. But what could constitute
the unity of such a bundle at one time, or its identity over time?
On the traditional view of substance, the members of a collection
of substances cannot be unied either through inherence in one
another or through causal connections. Is it possible that Hume
came to recognize that his ingenious argument against treating the
soul as a substance raised a parallel difculty with his own account
of personal identity? Ill come back to this in the second half of this
chapter.
The problem of local conjunction
Having produced what seems to be a complete argument establishing the unintelligibility of any account of the soul that treats it as a
substance, Hume goes on, as is his normal practice, to add further
considerations to the topic. They concern the possibility of the local
conjunction of the extended entities with nonextended entities. The

The Soul and the Self

105

rst argument he considers is supposed to favor the immateriality


of the soul.
Whatever is extended consists of parts; and whatever consists
of parts is divisible, if not in reality, at least in the imagination. But tis impossible any thing divisible can be conjoind to
a thought or perception, which is a being altogether inseparable and indivisible. For supposing such a conjunction, woud
the indivisible thought exist on the left or on the right hand
of this extended divisible body? (154/234)
Hume continues in this vein, and then concludes:
Thought, therefore, and extension are qualities wholly incompatible, and never can incorporate together into one subject.
(154/23435)
Hume is so taken with the idea of local conjunction that he enters a
ve-page digression, considering in general what objects are, or are not
susceptible of a local conjunction (154/235). There is some interesting
material in this digression, including a discussion of the relationship of
a g to its taste. Is the taste coextensive with the g? If so, does the taste
itself have a shapein particular, the shape of the g, or at least the
shape of its tasty parts? Since assigning a shape to a taste seems absurd,
we seem to be forced to say that though the taste exists, it must exist
nowhere. Hume then offers an account of how the mechanisms of the
imagination lead us (falsely) to locate the taste in the g itself.
After his long discussion of the problem of locally conjoining
something that exists, but exists nowhere with that which is extended
the supposed problem for the materialistHume notices that the
materialist, now referred to as the free-thinker, can run a reverse argument against the immaterialist. This argument depends on the claim
that some of our perceptions are themselves extended:

106

Humes Skeptical Crisis

That table, which just now appears to me, is only a perception, and all its qualities are qualities of a perception. Now
the most obvious of all its qualities is extension. . . . And to cut
short all disputes, the very idea of extension is copyd from
nothing but an impression, and consequently must perfectly
agree to it. To say the idea of extension agrees to any thing, is
to say it is extended. (157/23940)
Does this mean that our idea of a table has a certain lengthsay,
ve feet? I do not think so, but I must confess that I nd this discussion bafing. In any case, for Hume the local conjunction of
the extended with the nonextended now raises the problem of local
conjunction for the immaterialist as well.
The free-thinker may now triumph in his turn; and having
found there are impressions and ideas really extended, may
ask his antagonists, how they can incorporate a simple and
indivisible subject with an extended perception? (157/240)
Thus, with respect to the problem of local conjunction, we wind up
precisely where Hume wants us to wind up: with a standoff of an
absurdity facing an equal (but opposite) absurdity.
So far, Hume has been evenhanded in his treatment of materialist and immaterialist conceptions of the soul, but now, showing
where his true animus lies, he singles out the immaterialist for an
extraordinary ad hominem attack.
I assert, that the doctrine of the immateriality, simplicity, and
indivisibility of a thinking substance is a true atheism, and
will serve to justify all those sentiments, for which Spinoza is
so universally infamous. (157/240)
Hume claims to see a clear analogy between the doctrine of the
immateriality, simplicity, and indivisibility of a thinking substance

The Soul and the Self

107

and the materiality, simplicity, and indivisibility of Spinozas single,


all-encompassing substance. Hume, perhaps tactically, adopts the
common view that Spinozas system amounts to materialism and
hence atheism. He then attempts to show that any arguments that
theologians can bring against Spinozism can be transposed into an
equally powerful argument against their own doctrine of the immateriality of the soul. I will not go into this.
Soulbody interaction
Hume offers a further consideration that he thinks also favors materialism. The materialist has been challenged to explain how matter
can effect thought.
Tis absurd to imagine, that motion in a circle, for instance,
shoud be nothing but merely motion in a circle; while motion
in another direction, as in an ellipse, shoud also be a passion or
moral reection: That the shocking of two globular particles
shoud become a sensation of pain, and that the meeting of two
triangular ones shoud afford a pleasure. Now as these different
shocks, and variations, and mixtures are the only changes, of
which matter is susceptible, and as these never afford us any
idea of thought or perception, tis concluded to be impossible,
that thought can ever be causd by matter. (161/246)
This passage as stated looks more like a mindbody identity theory
than like a causal-interaction theory. Nonetheless, Hume treats it as a
matter of causal interaction, sketches his own account of causal relations, and then dismisses the objection to materialism as follows:
Now as all objects, which are not contrary, are susceptible of
a constant conjunction, and as no real objects are contrary; it

108

Humes Skeptical Crisis

follows, that for aught we can determine by the mere ideas,


any thing may be the cause or effect of any thing; which
evidently gives the advantage to the materialists above their
antagonists. (163/24950)
Hume does not seem to notice that his account of causality could
also help the immaterialists (if they chose to use it) explain the
reverse causal operations from mind to body. It is not likely that an
immaterialist would feel comfortable accepting Humes account of
causal relations, but that is a different matter.
On proofs of immortality
Hume seemingly concludes his discussion in these words:
To pronounce, then, the nal decision upon the whole; the
question concerning the substance of the soul is absolutely
unintelligible. (163/250)
Hume cannot, however, resist one nal sally aimed at religion. He
is wonderfully outrageous:
There is only one occasion, when philosophy will think it
necessary and even honourable to justify herself, and that is,
when religion may seem to be in the least offended; whose
rights are as dear to her as her own, and are indeed the same.
If any one, therefore, should imagine that the foregoing arguments are any ways dangerous to religion, I hope the following apology will remove his apprehensions. (16364/250)
One of the reasons theologians have been attracted to the idea that
the soul is a spiritual substance is that this seems to provide the
basis for establishing the immortality of the soul. Again appealing

The Soul and the Self

109

to his own account of causality, Hume dismisses this suggestion out


of hand:
There is no foundation for any conclusion a priori, either
concerning the operations or duration of any object, of which
tis possible for the human mind to form a conception. Any
object may be imagind to become entirely inactive, or to be
annihilated in a moment; and tis an evident principle, that
whatever we can imagine, is possible. Now this is no more true
of matter, than of spirit; of an extended compounded substance, than of a simple and unextended. In both cases the
metaphysical arguments for the immortality of the soul are
equally inconclusive. (164/250)
I will let the nal sentence of the section speak for itself:
If my philosophy, therefore, makes no addition to the arguments for religion, I have at least the satisfaction to think it
takes nothing from them, but that every thing remains precisely as before. (164/25051)

Z
Of Personal Identity (Section 6)
Though the topic is different, to a large extent Humes examination of personal identity is a replay of arguments that he previously employed in his treatment of the immateriality of the soul.
He begins by giving a vigorous statement of the position he will
attack:
There are some philosophers, who imagine we are every
moment intimately conscious of what we call our self;

110

Humes Skeptical Crisis

that we feel its existence and its continuance in existence;


and are certain, beyond the evidence of a demonstration,
both of its perfect identity and simplicity. The strongest
sensation, the most violent passion, say they, instead of distracting us from this view, only x it the more intensely,
and make us consider their inuence on self either by their
pain or pleasure. To attempt a further proof of this were to
weaken its evidence; since no proof can be derivd from any
fact, of which we are so intimately conscious; nor is there
any thing, of which we can be certain, if we doubt of this.
(164/251)

Basic criticisms
It takes Hume only a few pages to dispose of this position. His rst
response goes by so quickly that it may be easy to miss.
From what impression coud this idea be derivd? This question tis impossible to answer without a manifest contradiction
and absurdity; and yet tis a question, which must necessarily
be answerd, if we woud have the idea of self pass for clear and
intelligible. It must be some one impression, that gives rise
to every real idea. But self or person is not any one impression, but that to which our several impressions and ideas are
supposd to have a reference. (164/251)
It is not entirely clear what Hume has in mind in saying that the
self is not any one impression to which our several impressions
are supposed to have a reference, but the claim seems similar to the
denitional move Hume made near the start of his discussion of the
immateriality of the soul, where he asked:

The Soul and the Self

111

How can an impression resemble a substance, since, according


to this philosophy, it is not a substance, and has none of the
peculiar qualities or characteristics of a substance? (153/233)
Hume then interpolates a straightforward introspective claim:
If any impression gives rise to the idea of self, that impression
must continue invariably the same, thro the whole course of
our lives; since self is supposd to exist after that manner. But
there is no impression constant and invariable. (164/251)
He concludes his criticisms by repeating, almost verbatim, a claim
made in the previous section (see 153/233):
All these are different, and distinguishable, and separable
from each other, and may be separately considerd, and may
exist separately, and have no need of any thing to support
their existence. (164/252)
Hume gives the discussion a vivid Epicurean turn by declaring:
Were all my perceptions removd by death, and coud I neither
think, nor feel, nor see, nor love, nor hate, after the dissolution of my body, I shoud be entirely annihilated, nor do I
conceive what is farther requisite to make me a perfect nonentity. (165/252)
He closes his criticism of the view of the mind sketched at the opening
of the section with a strikingactually, strikingly inaptmetaphor:
The mind is a kind of theatre, where several perceptions successively make their appearance; pass, re-pass, glide away, and
mingle in an innite variety of postures and situations. There
is properly no simplicity in it at one time, nor identity in different; whatever natural propension we may have to imagine

112

Humes Skeptical Crisis

that simplicity and identity. The comparison of the theatre


must not mislead us. They are the successive perceptions
only, that constitute the mind; nor have we the most distant
notion of the place, where these scenes are represented, or of
the materials, of which it is composd. (165/252)
I originally thought that Humes theater metaphor is intended to
invoke an audience as perceivers of the perceptions in the mind,
and then go on to reject it. But as one of the readers for Oxford
University Press pointed out, this is not what Hume says. Hume is
not here denying the existence of a perceiver of perceptions; he is
denying that we have a notion of the place where our perceptions
exist. His target is substantival conceptions of the self.
Account of the ction of personal identity
Following his standard practice, Hume goes on to give an account
of how the ctions of personal identity and personal unity come
about. The basic explanation is a further development of the dominant theme of the four previous sections. The imagination has a
strong tendency to confound two distinct kinds of sequences: identity over time and the diversity exhibited by several different objects
existing in succession, and connected together by a close relation
(165/253). When we focus on (or are struck by) the close relationships between the diverse objects, we tend to assimilate the two
kinds of sequences. When we are struck by the diversity exhibited in
the second sort of sequence, we separate them.
Our propensity to this mistake [of assimilation] is so great
from the resemblance above-mentiond, that we fall into it
before we are aware; and tho we incessantly correct ourselves by reection, and return to a more accurate method

The Soul and the Self

113

of thinking, yet we cannot long sustain our philosophy, or


take off this biass from the imagination. Our last resource
is to yield to it, and boldly assert that these different related
objects are in effect the same, however interrupted and variable. In order to justify to ourselves this absurdity, we often
feign some new and unintelligible principle, that connects
the objects together, and prevents their interruption or variation. Thus we feign the continud existence of the perceptions
of our senses, to remove the interruption; and run into the
notion of a soul, and self, and substance, to disguise the variation. (166/254)
Humes task, then, is to provide an account of how relatedness
in a sequence of diverse objects can be transmuted into the ction
of identity over time.
Our chief business, then, must be to prove, that all objects,
to which we [falsely] ascribe identity, without observing their
invariableness and uninterruptedness, are such as consist of a
succession of related objects. (167/255)
Adopting a tactic employed previously by Locke, Hume sneaks up
on the problem of personal identity by examining the notion of
identity as it concerns other types of entities, including material
objects, artifacts, plants, and animals. Ill run through this quickly.
For Hume, strictly speaking, a mass of matter becomes a new and
distinct entity with the loss or addition of a single atom, yet we continue to think of it as the selfsame thing if the matter lost or gained
is small or, more precisely, proportionally small. We also have a tendency to think that identity is preserved if the changes are gradual
or insensible. Artifacts can undergo total material change and still
be thought to remain the same thing in virtue of a common end or

114

Humes Skeptical Crisis

purpose, for examplenot Humes examplethe axe that has been


in the family for three generations, having had eight handles and
three heads. We think that animals and vegetables can preserve their
identity through total material change in virtue of the sympathy
of [their] parts to their common end, and suppose that they bear
to each other, the reciprocal relation of cause and effect in all their
actions and operations (168/257).
Hume thinks that his discussion of these various ways in which
the ction of identity gets ascribed to objects undergoing change
creates a strong presumption in favor of offering a similar account
of personal identity.
Here tis evident, the same method of reasoning must be
continud, which has so successfully explaind the identity
of plants, and animals, and ships, and houses, and of all the
compounded and changeable productions either of art or
nature. The identity, which we ascribe to the mind of man,
is only a ctitious one, and of a like kind with that which we
ascribe to vegetables and animal bodies. It cannot, therefore,
have a different origin, but must proceed from a like operation of the imagination upon like objects. (169/259)
Having declared the matter settled, Hume adds more. He recurs
to rst principles and poses the problem of personal identity in the
most fundamental form. Tis evident, he tells us, that the identity, which we attribute to the human mind, however perfect we
may imagine it to be, is not able to run the several different perceptions into one, and make them lose their characters of distinction
and difference, which are essential to them (169/259). Humes next
argument is of central importance for understanding the deep reservations that he expresses in an appendix concerning his treatment of
personal identity. I will set it aside until I turn to that topic.

The Soul and the Self

115

Having shown to his satisfaction that personal identity has to


be treated as a ction, Hume is surprisingly brief in his account
of how this ction arises. With others, Locke for example, Hume
holds that memory plays a fundamental role in generating the belief
in personal identity. Memory, after all, provides the main access to
our previous livesthough, with age, CVs can help as well. One
difculty with memory, however, is that it supplies us with only a
gappy past.
Who can tell me, for instance, what were his thoughts and
actions on the rst of January 1715, the 11th of March 1719,
and the 3d of August 1733? Or will he afrm, because he has
entirely forgot the incidents of these days, that the present
self is not the same person with the self of that time; and by
that means overturn all the most establised notions of personal identity? In this view, therefore, memory does not so
much produce as discover personal identity, by showing us the
relation of cause and effect among our different perceptions.
(171/262)
When Hume speaks of the most established notions of personal
identity, he is, if speaking strictly, referring to the established ction
of personal identity.
Hume, however, is not always punctilious in adhering to the
strict way of expressing things and often mixes it with expressions
drawn from the vulgar perspective. This is true of the following
extraordinary passage, where Hume gives a metaphorical account of
the origins of the ction of personal identity:
As to causation; we may observe that the true idea of the human
mind, is to consider it as a system of different perceptions or
different existences, which are linkd together by the relation

116

Humes Skeptical Crisis

of cause and effect, and mutually produce, destroy, inuence,


and modify each other. Our impressions give rise to their correspondent ideas; and these ideas in their turn produce other
impressions. One thought chaces another, and draws after
it a third, by which it is expelld in its turn. In this respect,
I cannot compare the soul more properly to any thing than to
a republic or commonwealth, in which the several members
are united by the reciprocal ties of government and subordination, and give rise to other persons, who propagate the same
republic in the incessant changes of its parts. And as the same
individual republic may not only change its members, but also
its laws and constitutions; in like manner the same person may
vary his character and disposition, as well as his impressions
and ideas, without losing his identity. (170/261)
Throughout this passage, causation is taken as the vulgar take it, as
a connecting link, nexus, productive principle, and so on. We know
from part 3 that this is the view of causation that Hume attempted to
undermine. In fact, Hume had explicitly rejected it a few pages earlier
when he reminded us of what has been already provd at large, that
the understanding never observes any real connexion among objects,
and that even the union of cause and effect, when strictly examind,
resolves itself into a customary association of ideas (169/25960).
He will reject it again in the discussion of personal identity in the
appendix. By his own lights, the political metaphor in this passage is
badas bad as the earlier metaphor of the mind as a theater.
Disputes about identity as merely verbal
Hume concludes his discussion of personal identity by declaring
all disputes concerning identitynot simply disputes concerning
personal identitymerely grammatical or verbal.

The Soul and the Self

117

All the nice and subtile questions, concerning personal identity


can never possibly be decided, and are to be regarded rather as
grammatical than as philosophical difculties. Identity depends
on the relations of ideas; and these relations produce identity,
by means of that easy transition they occasion. But as the relations, and the easiness of the transition may diminish by insensible degrees, we have no just standard, by which we can decide
any dispute concerning the time, when they acquire or lose a
title to the name of identity. All the disputes concerning the
identity of connected objects are merely verbal, except so far
as the relation of parts gives rise to some ction or imaginary
principle of union, as we have already observd. (171/262)
For Hume, as we have seen, strictly speaking, any alteration in an
object from one moment to the next is sufcient to destroy its identity over time. A tree, in losing a single leaf, is no longer the same
tree. For that matter, the slightest utter of a leaf is sufcient to have
this effect. Of course, as Hume recognizes, in daily life we (including
Hume) do not employ the notion of identity in this strict manner.
But once we abandon a strict notion of identity, there is no way,
according to Hume, to objectively settle the question whether the
object remains the same object under change or not. A difference of
opinion here is nothing more than a disagreement on how we will
decide to use a word, and hence is purely grammatical, that is, verbal.
On the other hand, an attempt to give an account of the mechanisms
that give rise to the ction of identity over time is a substantive matter that Hume, to his present satisfaction, has been able to resolve.
The reservations in the appendix
As we read the text of section 6, Hume seems much at his ease
in disposing of both the vulgar and the learned understandings of

118

Humes Skeptical Crisis

personal identity, and putting his own account in their place. It


should thus come as a surprise when we turn to the appendix and
encounter the following passage:
I had entertaind some hopes, that however decient our theory of the intellectual world might be, it woud be free from
those contradictions, and absurdities, which seem to attend
every explication, that human reason can give of the material
world. But upon a more strict review of the section concerning personal identity, I nd myself involvd in such a labyrinth,
that, I must confess, I neither know how to correct my former
opinions, nor how to render them consistent. (3989/633)
The hopes that Hume refers to were expressed in the opening passage of section 5, Of the immateriality of the soul. So once more
we have an example of a brave and promising beginning ending in
disappointment. As before, Hume gives vent to the skeptical feelings that this reversal calls forth.
If this be not a good general reason for scepticism, tis at least a
sufcient one (if I were not already abundantly supplid) for me to
entertain a difdence and modesty in all my decisions. (399/633)
Humes sardonic if I were not already abundantly supplied should
be taken at face value. As if things were not bad enough already
recall the strong skeptical conclusions found in sections 1, 2, and
4his account of personal identity, which he plainly viewed as a
triumph, has, under strict review, fallen apart.
Humes picture of the mind
Hume rst lays out the original reasons that induced him to deny
the strict and proper identity and simplicity of a self or thinking

The Soul and the Self

119

being. They fall into two categories: those that concern substance
and those that concern necessary connections.
Hume quickly summarizes his reasons for rejecting the idea that
personal identity can be explained by treating the mind as a mental
substance. The simplest involves a direct appeal to introspection:
When I turn my reection on myself, I never can perceive this
self without some one or more perceptions; nor can I ever
perceive any thing but the perceptions. Tis the composition
of these, therefore, which forms the self. (399/634)
Another argument turns on the intelligibility of something existing
without inhering in a substance.
But tis intelligible and consistent to say, that objects exist
distinct and independent, without any common simple substance or subject of inhesion. This proposition, therefore, can
never be absurd with regard to perceptions. (399/634)
Then, in a remarkable passage, Hume goes beyond the suggestion
that an individual perception satises the denition of an individual
substance to claim that an individual perception can, by itself, constitute an individual mind:
We can conceive a thinking being to have either many or
few perceptions. Suppose the mind to be reducd even below
the life of an oyster. Suppose it to have only one perception,
as of thirst or hunger. Consider it in that situation. Do you
conceive any thing but merely that perception? Have you any
notion of self or substance? If not, the addition of other perceptions can never give you that notion. (399/634)
Turning next to necessary connections, if perceptions are not unied at a given time and do not preserve identity over time through

120

Humes Skeptical Crisis

inhesion in a substance, they must, it seems, be grounded through


connections among the perceptions themselves. Hume explicitly
closes off this option in a passage in section 6 not previously cited:
A question naturally arises concerning this relation of identity; whether it be something that really binds our several
perceptions together, or only associates their ideas in the
imagination? That is, in other words, whether, in pronouncing concerning the identity of a person, we observe some
real bond among his perceptions, or only feel one among the
ideas we form of them? This question we might easily decide,
if we woud recollect what has been already provd at large,
that the understanding never observes any real connexion
among objects, and that even the union of cause and effect,
when strictly examind resolves itself into a customary association of ideas. For from thence it evidently follows, that identity is nothing really belonging to these different perceptions,
and uniting them together; but is merely a quality, which we
attribute to them, because of the union of their ideas in the
imagination, when we reect upon them. (169/25960)
In the appendix he puts it this way:
If perceptions are distinct existences, they form a whole only
by being connected together. But no connexions among distinct existences are ever discoverable by human understanding. (400/635)
This claim, of course, reects the central development of part 3.
There Hume begins with the notion that a causal relation contains
as an essential element the idea of a necessary connection. As we
have seen, in the end, he rejects this notion and treats necessary
connectedness as a feeling that is the product of drawing a causal

The Soul and the Self

121

inference rather than as a connecting link that validates the inference. As he puts it: We only feel a connexion or a determination to
pass from one object to another (400/635). That feeling, like any
perception, is simply another member of the heap of perceptions.
Here, then, is the picture of the mind that has emerged. The mind
is a bundle of perceptions with no contents other than perceptions.
These perceptions are not related to one another by inhering in a common substance. In fact, strictly speaking, each perception is itself an
individual substance. In this respect, the mind is a bundle of substances.
Beyond this, each perception may be viewed as an individual mind, so
the mind is not simply a bundle of perceptions, it is a bundle of minds.
Finally, there can be no real connections among individual perceptions,
so no perception can apprehend other perceptions. In Humes audience-free theater, nothing exists that can apprehend the bundle, so the
bundle of perceptions exhibits no mechanism for bundling. For that
matter, it does not seem to contain any mechanism that accounts for
the feeling of connectedness of perceptions within the bundle. If this is
what Humes theory of the human mind comes to, it is not altogether
remarkable that he came to have misgivings concerning it.
Humes declaration of failure
Most philosophers seem inclind to think, that personal identity arises from consciousness; and consciousness is nothing
but a reected thought or perception. The present philosophy, therefore, has so far a promising aspect. All my hopes
vanish, when I come to explain the principles, that unite our
successive perceptions in our thought or consciousness. I cannot discover any theory, which gives me satisfaction on this
head. (400/63536)

122

Humes Skeptical Crisis

It is, I think, important to see that Humes concerns go beyond his


disappointment with his account of personal identity. What particularly disturbs him is that his difculties seem to ow directly
from two principles central to his philosophical position:
In short there are two principles, which I cannot render
consistent; nor is it in my power to renounce either of them
(emphasis added), viz. that all our distinct perceptions are distinct existences, and that the mind never perceives any real connexion among distinct existences. Did our perceptions either
inhere in something simple and individual, or did the mind
perceive some real connexion among them, there woud be no
difculty in the case. (400/636)
Hume cannot be saying that his two principles are inconsistent with
each another. They are not. What I think he is saying is that accepting these two principlesprinciples that he has relied on throughout the Treatiseforecloses the possibility of giving an account of
the ction of personal identity. Why is this? Commentators have
made all sorts of suggestions concerning what must be bothering
Hume. Some of these suggestions point to difculties that should
have concerned him. It is difcult, however, to nd textual evidence
supporting these suggestions, because Hume does not point to a
specic problem in his treatment of personal identity. Instead, he
speaks of being involved in a labyrinth (399/633).
To get a sense of this labyrinth, we can consider what it would
be like to give an account of the ction of personal identity under
the following constraints. The rst two concern the two principles
Hume nds impossible to renounce:
1. Allow no reference to relations of interdependence among
perceptions. Taken in itself, the presence or absence of any

The Soul and the Self

123

one perception has no bearing on the presence or absence


of any other.
2. Allow no reference to substance as an underlying substrate
or as a principle of unity.
The third constraint ows from his account of perceptions.
3. Allow no reference, including tacit reference, to a spectator.
For Berkeley, the being of a perception is to be perceived
and, correlated with this, the being of a mind is to be a
perceiver. Hume specically denies the existence of any
such perceiving mind, and, by implication, he must deny
that the being of a perception is to be perceived. Reference
to perceptions cannot be used as a cover for sneaking in a
perceiver.
I believe that these are constraints Hume accepts in attempting to
offer an account of the ction of personal identity. I think he came
to see that every attempt he made to carry out his program within
them failed. But if that is Humes problem, why didnt he say so?
Well, I think he pretty much did say so when he described himself
as being involved in a labyrinth. He doesnt say anything more specic than this.
One last question: If they are raising profound difculties,
why doesnt Hume abandon at least one of the constraints that
has trapped him in his labyrinth? Doing so would, in fact, entail
a wholesale revision of central arguments of the Treatise, including his prized treatment of causation. With respect to the rst two
constraints, Hume tells us that it is not in [his] power to renounce
either of them. I think that the third constraint has a similar hold
on him. The vulgar seem to reject these constraints, as do many philosophers. Why is Hume seemingly locked into them? The answer,

124

Humes Skeptical Crisis

I believe, is that Humes commitment to these principles ows from


his acceptance of what I have called the phenomenalist stance as the
proper, ction-free perspective for developing his science of human
nature. Given his commitment to this perspective, Hume nds
these constraints forced upon him.

Chapter 7 Z The Conclusion of Book 1

Z
A Gloomy Summation of Skeptical Results
At the start of the seventh, and concluding, section of part 4, Hume
pauses to take stock of where his reections have led him.
Before I launch out into those immense depths of philosophy, which lie before me, I nd myself inclind to stop a
moment in my present station, and to ponder that voyage,
which I have undertaken, and which undoubtedly requires
the utmost art and industry to be brought to a happy conclusion. . . . My memory of past errors and perplexities,
makes me difdent for the future. The wretched condition,
weakness, and disorder of the faculties, I must employ in
my enquiries, encrease my apprehensions. And the impossibility of amending or correcting these faculties, reduces
me almost to despair, and makes me resolve to perish on
the barren rock, on which I am at present. (17172/26364,
emphasis added)
I take this passage to be an unfeigned expression of the melancholy
generated by a series of disasters unanticipated in the brave opening pages of the Treatise. Others have found it overdone, John
Passmore, for example:
125

126

Humes Skeptical Crisis

The bewilderment that Hume displays at the end of Book I


of the Treatise is genuine enough, although, unable to resist
the opportunity skepticism offers him for self-dramatization,
he lapses into a stagey melodramatic tone. . . . By the time he
came to write the Enquires and the Dialogues on Natural
Religion, his feelings, his ideas, and his literary impulses
were under better control.
To this he adds:
We shall understand his skeptical intentions more clearly if
we make these later writings our point of departure, referring
back, as the need arises, to the more detailed arguments of the
Treatise. (Passmore 1952, p. 133)
In this work I have been proceeding in the opposite direction, taking the Treatise as the central text for understanding Humes relationship to skepticism. The skeptical intentions (as Passmore calls
them) of the Enquiry and the Dialogues on Natural Religion grow
naturally out of the skeptical crisis found in the Treatise and cannot
be fully understood without recognizing this relationship.
In any case, in the passage cited above, Hume reviews the development of his thought from what he calls his present station. He
refers to his own past errors and perplexities, but his central concern
is the wretched condition, weakness, and disorder of the human
mental faculties that his pursuit of the science of human nature has
laid bare. Hume is quite precise in locating the primary source of
his difculties: his doctrine that all beliefs are (at least ultimately)
grounded in the operations of the imagination.
For with what condence can I venture upon . . . bold enterprizes, when beside those numberless inrmities peculiar to
myself, I nd so many which are common to human nature?

The Conclusion of Book 1

127

Can I be sure, that in leaving all establishd opinions, I am


following truth; and by what criterion shall I distinguish
her, even if fortune shoud at last guide me on her foot-steps?
After the most accurate and exact of my reasonings, I can
give no reason why I should assent to it; and feel nothing but
a strong propensity to consider objects strongly in that view,
under which they appear to me (emphasis added). . . . Without
this quality, by which the mind enlivens some ideas beyond
others (which seemingly is so trivial, and so little founded
on reason) we coud never assent to any argument, nor carry
our view beyond those few objects, which are present to our
senses. . . . The memory, senses, and understanding are . . . all
of them founded on the imagination, or the vivacity of our
ideas. (17273/265)
Hume goes on to catalog the various ways in which reliance on
the imagination can generate profound difculties. One is that the
imagination in its operations can yield beliefs incompatible with
one another. Humes rst recognition of the imaginations capacity to come into conict with itself occurs in section 13 of part 3
(Of unphilosophical probability). This, as we saw, is also the rst
place that Hume explicitly recognizes the skeptical consequences
that emerge from the operations of the imagination.1 Hume does
not refer to this discussion in section 7, but he does explicitly cite a
parallel line of reasoning in the concluding paragraph of section 4 of
part 4 (Of the modern philosophy). He paraphrases it as follows:
No wonder a principle so inconstant and fallacious shoud
lead us into errors, when implicitly followd (as it must be)
in all its variations. Tis this principle, which makes us reason
from causes and effects; and tis the same principle, which
convinces us of the continud existence of external objects,

128

Humes Skeptical Crisis

when absent from the senses. But tho these two operations
be equally natural and necessary in the human mind, yet in
some circumstances they are directly contrary [here Hume
refers the reader to section 4 of part 4], nor is it possible for
us to reason justly and regularly from causes and effects, and
at the same time believe the continud existence of matter.
(173/26566)
The specic circumstance that Hume refers to in this passage concerns the skeptical consequences that follow from his critique of the
distinction between primary and secondary qualities. It is worth
repeating.
There is a direct and total opposition betwixt our reason and
our senses; or more properly speaking, betwixt those conclusions we form from cause and effect, and those that perswade us
of the continud and independent existence of body. When we
reason from cause and effect, we conclude, that neither colour,
sound, taste, nor smell have a continud and independent existence. When we exclude these sensible qualities there remains
nothing in the universe, which has such an existence. (152/231)
Humes rst cause for concern, then, is that an implicit reliance on the imagination can yield irreconcilable conicts generated
within the imagination itself. His second concernand this seems
to affect him at least as deeplyis that enquiring into the operations of this faculty has brought to light its arbitrary, weak, and
capricious character.
When we trace up the human understanding to its rst principles, we nd it to lead us into such sentiments, as seem
to turn into ridicule all our past pains and industry, and to
discourage us from future enquiries. (173/266)2

The Conclusion of Book 1

129

These difculties with the products of the imagination suggest that


the careful reasoner should abandon all reliance on so weak a faculty. This, however, is not an option open to Hume, for it would
leave him with no way of dealing with the skepticism with regard
to reason presented in the opening section of part 4. His task there
was not to nd a way of refuting his skeptical argument concerning
reasoncorrectly or not, he thought it irrefutable. His task was
to give an account of the undeniable fact that people continue to
believe a great many things even when apprised of this argument.
Looking back on this previous discussion, Hume described the situation this way:
I have already shown [in section 1 of part 4], that the understanding, when it acts alone, and according to its most general
principles, entirely subverts itself, and leaves not the lowest
degree of evidence in any proposition, either in philosophy
or common life. We save ourselves from this total scepticism
only by means of that singular and seemingly trivial property
of the fancy, by which we enter with difculty into remote
views of things, and are not able to accompany them with so
sensible an impression, as we do those, which are more easy
and natural. (174/26768)
If we are suitably struck by the arbitrariness of the nonrational
mechanism that saves understanding from destroying itself, we may
be tempted to abandon reason altogether and place full reliance on
the imagination, obediently accepting whatever it sends our way.
That, however, yields a deep dilemma of its own.
Shall we, then, establish it for a general maxim, that no rend
or elaborate reasoning is ever to be receivd? Consider well the
consequences of such a principle. By this means you cut off

130

Humes Skeptical Crisis

entirely all science and philosophy: You proceed upon one


singular quality of the imagination, and by a parity of reason must embrace all of them: And you expressly contradict
yourself; since this maxim must be built on the preceding
reasoning, which will be allowd to be sufciently rend and
metaphysical. What party, then, shall we choose among these
difculties? If we embrace this principle, and condemn all
rend reasoning, we run into the most manifest absurdities.
If we reject it in favour of these reasonings, we subvert entirely
the human understanding. We have, therefore, no choice left
but betwixt a false reason and none at all. (174/268)
In this passage Hume reects on the position that he nds himself in
and provides a narrative describing how he got there. The intense
view of these manifold contradictions and imperfections in human
reason, Hume tells us, has so wrought upon me, and heated my
brain, that I am ready to reject all belief and reasoning, and can look
upon no opinion even as more probable or likely than another
(175/26869). Isnt this all, as Passmore suggests, a bit overdramatic,
overwrought? No. From the perspective that Hume has reached, the
crisis is genuine, unavoidable, and destructive of the entire project
of developing his science of human nature.

Z
What Is to Be Done?
Hume needs a way of exiting from his dismal situation, but for him
there is no way of thinking his way out of his crisis. Reason, he
tells us, is incapable of dispelling these clouds (175/269). One has
to abandon the study and reenter the affairs of daily life. In doing
so, he tells us,

The Conclusion of Book 1

131

I nd myself absolutely and necessarily determind to live,


and talk, and act like other people in the common affairs of
life. But notwithstanding that my natural propensity, and the
course of my animal spirits and passions reduce me to this
indolent belief in the general maxims of the world, I still feel
such remains of my former disposition, that I am ready to
throw all my books and papers into the re, and resolve never
more to renounce the pleasures of life for the sake of reasoning and philosophy. For these are my sentiments in that splenetic humour, which governs me at present. I may, nay I must
yield to the current of nature, in submitting to my senses
and understanding; and in this blind submission I show most
perfectly my sceptical disposition and principles. (175/269,
emphasis added)
So Hume, when he returns to daily occupations, yields to the current of nature and blindly submits to the deliverances of sense and
understandingthe very faculties he was forced to reject in his
study. It is the blindness of the submissionaccepting something
without having, or even seeking, justicatory groundsthat shows
most perfectly his skeptical dispositions and principles.
Even if, for the moment at least, this maneuver frees Hume of
philosophical melancholy, doesnt he still stand under the obligation
to stop frittering away his time in agreeable company and get back
to work in his study? When in agreeable company, he is inclined to
say no.
[Must I] strive against the current of nature, which leads
me to indolence and pleasure; that I must seclude myself, in
some measure, from the commerce and society of men, which
is so agreeable; and that I must torture my brain with subtilities and sophistries, at the very time that I cannot satisfy

132

Humes Skeptical Crisis

myself concerning the reasonableness of so painful an application. . . . No: If I must be a fool, as all those who reason
or believe any thing certainly are, my follies shall at least be
natural and agreeable. (175/26970)

Z
Being a Philosopher on Skeptical Principles
Hume nds, however, that he is not fully content with this way out
of his difculties. Despite the trouble it has brought him, Hume
nds that he has not completely lost his desire to lead the life of the
mind. His ingenious answer is that we should pursue philosophy in
the same skeptical manner that, in daily life, we accept the deliverances of understanding, namely, blindly.
If we are philosophers, it ought only to be upon sceptical
principles, and from an inclination, which we feel to the
employing ourselves after that manner. Where reason is lively,
and mixes itself with some propensity, it ought to be assented
to. (176/270)
These two sentences, I take it, specify the skeptical principles Hume
thinks we should abide by in philosophizing. Skeptics, in this sense,
restrict their reections to matters that naturally attract their attention, and assent to things that they nd naturally compelling.
Skeptics, in this sense, live in accordance with how things strike
them in the situation they are inand nothing more.
With respect to our motive for pursuing philosophy, on this
approach, it is the same as our motive for playing backgammon or
conversing with merry friends: In appropriate circumstances and
carried out in the appropriate way, it can be fun. In Humes more
dignied language:

The Conclusion of Book 1

133

At the time, therefore, that I am tird with amusement and


company, and have indulgd a reverie in my chamber, or in
a solitary walk by a river-side, I feel my mind all collected
within itself. . . . I [then] feel an ambition to arise in me of
contributing to the instruction of mankind, and of acquiring a name by my inventions and discoveries. These sentiments spring up naturally in my present disposition; and
shoud I endeavour to banish them, by attaching myself to
any other business or diversion, I feel I shoud be a loser in
point of pleasure; and this is the origin of my philosophy.
(176/27071)
Here we have Humes skeptical grounds for reentering his study,
but with his previous skeptical calamity still echoing in his brain,
and still chastened, he returns to the philosophical arena difdently. In what might rst seem no more than a passing remark
he tells us:
There are in England, in particular, many honest gentlemen, who being always employd in their domestic affairs,
or amusing themselves in common recreations, have carryd
their thoughts very little beyond those objects, which are
every day exposd to their senses. And indeed, of such as
these I pretend not to make philosophers, nor do I expect
them either to be associates in these researches or auditors
of these discoveries. They do well to keep themselves in their
present situation; and instead of rening them into philosophers, I wish we coud communicate to our founders of systems, a share of this gross earthy mixture, as an ingredient,
which they commonly stand much in need of, and which
woud serve to temper those ery particles, of which they are
composd. (177/272)3

134

Humes Skeptical Crisis

This may seem like a pro forma tip-of-the-hat to Englands honest


gentlemen, but, in fact, Hume goes on to give their earthy opinions special philosophical entitlement.
While a warm imagination is allowd to enter into philosophy, and hypotheses embracd merely for being specious and
agreeable, we can never have any steady principles, nor any
sentiments, which will suit with common practice and experience. But were these hypotheses once removd, we might
hope to establish a system or set of opinions, which if not true
(for that, perhaps, is too much to be hopd for) might at least
be satisfactory to the human mind, and might stand the test
of the most critical examination. (177/272)
In this passage, the word specious has the meaning of attractive, not falsely attractive. What Hume seems to be saying is this:
When engaged in philosophizing, we should not accept a hypothesis simply because it is attractive and agreeable from within the
philosophical perspective. It must meet another criterionactually
two other criteria. The rst is that it must suit with common practice and experience, and by this I take Hume to mean that the
hypotheses cannot clash with common practice and experience. The
second criterion is that the hypothesis must stand up under the
critical examination of the learned. The rst criterion protects us
from drowning in skepticism by barring us from deep waters; the
second criterion provides intellectual respectability.
By the end of book 1, the swagger of Humes introduction is
gone, and his science of human nature has been transformed into a
modest, difdent, and piecemeal activity:
For my part, my only hope is, that I may contribute a little to
the advancement of knowledge, by giving in some particulars

The Conclusion of Book 1

135

a different turn to the speculations of philosophers, and


pointing out to them more distinctly those subjects, where
alone they can expect assurance and conviction. (177/273)
Hume recommends pursuing philosophy in what he calls this careless manner because it is more truly skeptical:
The conduct of a man, who studies philosophy in this careless manner, is more truly sceptical than that of one, who
feeling in himself an inclination to it, is yet so over-whelmd
with doubts and scruples, as totally to reject it. A true sceptic
will be difdent of his philosophical doubts, as well as of his
philosophical convictions; and will never refuse any innocent
satisfaction, which offers itself, upon account of either of
them. (177/273)
By careless, Hume does not mean not giving sufcient attention or thought to avoid error. The expression free of care
comes closer to Humes eighteenth-century use of the term. One
pursues a philosophical topic for the intrinsic pleasure it gives.
One accepts things and perhaps reports them to others when they
strike one as right and lets it go at that.
True skeptics, as Hume portrays them, are not barred from
engaging in philosophical activity, provided they pursue it with
proper modesty and difdence. In light of this proviso, a further
dispensation seems surprising indeed: In expressing the results of
their investigations, the true skeptics are not barred from making
strong, unqualied epistemic claims. For Hume, employing such
language need not be indicative of a dogmatic spirit.
We [as skeptics] should yield to that propensity, which inclines
us to be positive and certain in particular points, according to
the light, in which we survey them in any particular instant.

136

Humes Skeptical Crisis

On such an occasion we are apt not only to forget our


scepticism, but even our modesty too; and make use of such
terms as these, tis evident, tis certain, tis undeniable; which
a due deference to the public ought, perhaps, to prevent.
I may have fallen into this fault after the example of others;
but I here enter a caveat against any objections which may
be offerd on that head; and declare that such expressions were
extorted from me by the present view of the object, and imply
no dogmatical spirit, nor conceited idea of my own judgment,
which are sentiments that I am sensible can become nobody,
and a sceptic still less than any other (some emphasis added).
(178/27374)
In this passage, the opposite of skepticism is dogmatism, and the
point Hume is making is that one can speak like a dogmatist without thereby becoming one. We might think of these natural and
spontaneous uses of tis evident, tis certain, tis undeniable as emotive or expressive in charactercousins of Eureka, aha, bingo,
I get it, and now I can go on. In fact, it might be possible to
develop an epistemic-sense theory to give an account of epistemic
normativity in a way that parallels Humes moral-sense account of
moral normativity. In a Humean spirit, we could treat the objective
certainty that we ascribe, say, to a demonstration as a projection
of our subjective certitude regarding it. Hume says something very
like this in his claim that the necessity we ascribe to causal relations is the same in kind as that which we nd in mathematics (see
112/166).
Book 1 of the Treatise closes with the passage just cited. Yet
Humes situation still seems fragile. His appeal to the gross earthy
mixture of attitudes and beliefs of honest gentlemen bears a
heavy burden in protecting Hume from radical skepticism, and it

The Conclusion of Book 1

137

is not clear how (or if ) it can bear this burden. It is also unclear
how human faculties can be disciplined to stay within the modest
bounds that Hume, in his calmer moments, prescribes. Given the
seriousness of the skeptical challenges Hume has raised against his
own system, his responses to them seem, to borrow one of his own
phrases, little more than palliative remedies.
All the same, when we turn the page to the beginning of book 2,
Of the Passions, we nd Hume in ne fettle. As one of the readers
for the Press puts it, we nd Hume presenting a long and steady
and boring account of the passions, resuming the science of man as
though there was never a crisis about it. I agree that the transition
from part 4 of book 1 to the opening part of book 2 is at least as
surprising as the transition from part 3 to part 4 in book 1. The sudden appearance of radical skepticism and its sudden disappearance
are equally perplexing.
What are we to make of this? Perhaps when Hume reined in his
ambitions, his good spirits returned and he found that he could
again conduct his philosophical studies in a careless (i.e., carefree)
manner with the reasonable hope that he could at least contribute
a little to the advancement of knowledge. The closing remarks of
book 1, part 4, section 7 of the Treatise are not, however, Humes
nal words on the relationship between skepticism and the legitimacy of his philosophical enterprise. Hume addresses the problem anew in the Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding and
attempts to resolve it in an interestingly different manner. We can
look at this next.

This page intentionally left blank

Chapter 8 Z Two Openings and Two


Closings

Z
The Treatise and the Enquiry on Skepticism
Hume placed the following advertisement in the front matter of
his Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding:
most of the principles, and reasonings, contained in this
volume, were published in a work in three volumes, called
A Treatise of Human Nature: A work which the Author had
projected before he left College, and which he wrote and
published not long after. But not nding it successful, he was
sensible of his error in going to the press too early, and he
cast the whole anew in the following pieces, where some negligences in his former reasoning and more in the expression,
are, he hopes, corrected. . . . Henceforth, the Author desires,
that the following Pieces may alone be regarded as containing
his philosophical sentiments and principles. (EHU 1/2)
In this work I have willfully disregarded Humes injunction by
making only passing references to the Enquiry Concerning Human
Understanding and concentrating almost exclusively on Humes
Treatise. Nor do I propose to examine the Enquiry in detail here.
I will, however, spend some time comparing the opening and closing parts of book 1 of the Treatise with the opening and closing
139

140

Humes Skeptical Crisis

sections of the Enquiry. The relationship is interestingly complex


and sheds light, I believe, on how Hume came to see the relationship between his philosophical work and skepticism.

Z
The Opening of the Treatise
As we have seen, in the introduction to the Treatise Hume presents a
prospectus extolling the new science of man that he is about to pursue.
His claims in its behalf are hardly modest. His ambition is to produce
an account of human nature with the scope and power achieved by
Newton and others with respect to the physical world. In fact, he claims
to outdo Newton by proposing a complete system of the sciences.
There is no question of importance, whose decision is not
comprisd in the science of man; and there is none, which can
be decided with any certainty, before we become acquainted
with that science. In pretending therefore to explain the
principles of human nature, we in effect propose a compleat
system of the sciences, built on a foundation almost entirely
new, and the only one upon which they can stand with any
security. (4/xvi)
At the end of book 1, Hume came to the disappointing conclusion that he had not fullled this systematic project and seemed to
despair of the possibility of doing so.

Z
The Opening of the Enquiry
The rst section of the Enquiry is titled Of the different species of
philosophy. Hume begins by distinguishing two perspectives that

Two Openings and Two Closings

141

we can adopt with respect to the study of human nature. One, the
popular or easy approach, considers man chiey as born for action;
and as inuenced in his measures by taste and sentiment (EHU 5/5).
The other, abstruse, approach considers man in the light of a reasonable rather than an active being, and endeavours to form his understanding more than cultivate his manners (EHU 5/6). The popular
approach to human nature, which both entertains and elevates its
readers, needs no apology, but why, Hume asks, should anyone
engage in abstruse philosophy? This question is motivated, in part at
least, by the poor reception the Treatise received. That, however, is
not the whole storyand, to my mind, not the most important part
of the story. The developments in the Treatisea work in abstruse
philosophyseem to undercut the possibility of abstruse philosophy, so if Hume is going to salvage any of the principles and reasonings of that work, a defense, if only limited defense, of abstruse
reasoning is in order. What we get at the start of the Enquiry is a
popular essay in defense of engaging in abstruse philosophy.
Hume begins by presenting what amounts to a balance sheet of
reasons for and against engaging in abstruse philosophy. He rst
presents the reasons against doing so:
1. Abstruse philosophy seems to have little inuence on daily
life.
Abstruse philosophy, being founded on a turn of mind, which
cannot enter into business and action, vanishes when the philosopher leaves the shade, and comes into open day; nor can
its principles easily retain any inuence over our conduct and
behaviour. (EHU 6/7)
2. The enterprise is inherently prone to error.
It is easy for a profound philosopher to commit a mistake in
his subtile reasonings; and one mistake is the necessary parent

142

Humes Skeptical Crisis

of another, while he pushes on his consequences, and is not


deterred from embracing any conclusion, by its unusual appearance, or its contradiction to popular opinion. (EHU 6/7)
3. The human mind is unsuited for this activity.
Man is a reasonable being; and as such, receives from science his proper food and nourishment: But so narrow are
the bounds of human understanding, that little satisfaction
can be hoped for in this particular, either from the extent or
security of his acquisitions. (EHU 7/8)
4. Nature personied warns us that engaging in abstruse philosophizing can, as Hume will testify, make one feel miserable.
Abstruse thought and profound researches I prohibit, and
will severely punish, by the pensive melancholy which they
introduce, by the endless uncertainty in which they involve
you, and by the cold reception which your pretended discoveries will meet with, when communicated. Be a philosopher;
but, amidst all your philosophy, be still a man. (EHU 7/9)
Hume next turns his attention to the reasons for engaging in
abstruse philosophy.
1. With respect to the claimed uselessness of abstruse philosophy, Hume responds that the spirit of accuracy it engenders benets
every art and profession.
We may observe, in every art or profession, even those which
most concern life or action, that a spirit of accuracy, however
acquired, carries all of them nearer their perfection, and renders
them more subservient to the interests of society. And though
a philosopher may live remote from business, the genius of

Two Openings and Two Closings

143

philosophy, if carefully cultivated by several, must gradually


diffuse itself throughout the whole society, and bestow a similar correctness on every art and calling. (EHU 8/10)
2. In response to Natures warning that the pursuit of abstruse
philosophy will make one miserable, Hume takes the same line that
he took in the Treatise: Sometimesat least when rightly pursued
examining abstruse questions can bring pleasure.
Were there no advantage to be reaped from these studies,
beyond the gratication of an innocent curiosity, yet ought
not even this to be despised; as being one accession to those
few safe and harmless pleasures, which are bestowed on human
race. . . . Obscurity, indeed, is painful to the mind as well as to
the eye; but to bring light from obscurity, by whatever labour,
must needs be delightful and rejoicing. (EHU 89/11)1
3. More deeply, a study of our mental faculties, though abstruse,
provides us with the only way of freeing ourselves from the delusions of false metaphysics.
The only method of freeing learning, at once, from these
abstruse questions, is to enquire seriously into the nature of
human understanding, and show, from an exact analysis of
its powers and capacity, that it is by no means tted for such
remote and abstruse subjects. We must submit to this fatigue,
in order to live at ease ever after. . . . Accurate and just reasoning
is the only catholic remedy, tted for all persons and all dispositions; and is alone able to subvert that abstruse philosophy and metaphysical jargon, which, being mixed up with
popular superstition, renders it in a manner impenetrable to
careless reasoners, and gives it the air of science and wisdom.
(EHU 910/1213, emphasis added)

144

Humes Skeptical Crisis

We can think of this as the therapeutic (even cathartic) employment


of Humes science of human nature.
On the wholethough the victory is by no means overwhelmingfor Hume, the reasons in favor of pursuing abstruse philosophy outweigh the reasons for rejecting it. The task of the Enquiry is
to make good on this assessment.

Z
The Response to Skepticism in the Enquiry
Turning to the concluding section of the Enquiry, we can compare
the way Hume attempts to meet the challenge of skepticism there
with his response in the closing section of book 1 of the Treatise. In
the Enquiry Hume understands skepticism in much the same way
that he understood it in the Treatise:
The Sceptic . . . provokes the indignation of all divines and
graver philosophers; though it is certain, that no man ever met
with any such absurd creature, or conversed with a man, who
had no opinion or principle concerning any subject, either
of action or speculation. This begets a very natural question;
What is meant by a sceptic? And how far it is possible to
push these philosophical principles of doubt and uncertainty?
(EHU 112/149)
To understand this passage and others like it, it is important to
keep in mind the distinction drawn earlier between two senses of
skepticism. In one sense, a person is skeptical concerning a particular matter if he doubts its truth or suspends judgment concerning it. I have labeled this form of skepticism doxastic skepticism.
We can also speak of arguments as being skeptical. An argument is
skeptical if it calls into question the justication or basis of beliefs

Two Openings and Two Closings

145

or systems of beliefs. I have called this theoretical skepticism. The


skeptic whom Hume alludes to, who has no opinion or principle
concerning any subject, is an example of an extreme doxastic skeptic. Hume associates this kind of skepticismin fact, incorrectly
with Pyrrhonism.2
In the Enquiry, Hume himself draws a distinction between kinds
of skepticism along quite different lines: antecedent versus consequent
skepticism. Hume associates antecedent skepticism with Descartes:
It recommends an universal doubt, not only of all our former opinions and principles, but also of our very faculties; of
whose veracity, say they, we must assure ourselves, by a chain
of reasoning, deduced from some original principle, which
cannot possibly be fallacious or deceitful. But neither is there
any such original principle . . . that [is] self-evident and convincing: Or if there were, could we advance a step beyond
it, but by the use of those very faculties, of which we are
supposed to be already difdent. The CARTESIAN doubt,
therefore, were it ever possible to be attained by any human
creature (as it plainly is not) would be entirely incurable; and
no reasoning could ever bring us to a state of assurance and
conviction upon any subject. (EHU 112/150)
Hume also speaks of a skepticism that is consequent to science and
enquiry:
There is another species of scepticism, consequent to science
and enquiry, when men are supposed to have discovered,
either the absolute fallaciousness of their mental faculties, or
their untness to reach any xed determination in all those
curious subjects of speculation, about which they are commonly employed. (EHU 113/150)

146

Humes Skeptical Crisis

Though Hume does not explicitly say so, this is the kind of skepticism that emerges in part 4 of book 1 of the Treatise.
Notice that consequent skepticism, as I will awkwardly call it,
may yield two quite different results: It can reveal the absolute fallaciousness of our mental faculties, or it can show their untness for
curious subjects of speculation. These options determine Humes
strategy in the Enquiry for dealing with skepticism. The rst result,
a specter that haunts the Treatise, must be avoided because it
destroys all motives for pursuing philosophical enquiry. The second outcome will be embraced because it fences off just those areas
where skeptical disasters occuror so it is hoped.

Z
The Science of Human Nature in the Enquiry
In the opening sentence of the Enquiry, Hume speaks of the science of human nature. If the science of human nature is taken to
be the presentation of detailed associationalist accounts of mental
phenomena, then it is striking how little of this activity, central to
the Treatise, is found in the Enquiry. In the Treatise Hume has an
insatiable lust for producing elaborate associationalist accounts of
mental phenomena, often going off on digressions in order to pursue this passion. He almost seems to be saying: Throw any problem
concerning the operations of the human mind my way, and I will
take care of it. Not only is this aspect of the Treatise reduced in the
Enquiry, there is a wholesale deletionpurge might be a better
wordof the most elaborate and important applications of associationalist methods found in the Treatise. Consider section 2, part 4,
Of skepticism with regard to the senses. The primary task of this
section is to accomplish two things: rst, to offer an account of how
the vulgar come to accept the false belief that objects of perception

Two Openings and Two Closings

147

can have a continued and distinct existence when unperceived; and


second, to offer an account of how the learned arrive at the unintelligible theory of double existence. In the Treatise, a skeptical argument is aimed at the double-existence theory of perception as one
component in a larger project in the science of human nature. In the
Enquiry, only the skeptical argument remains (EHU 11316/15055),
and the accounts of the origins of the vulgar and learned views of
perception are simply gone. Sections 36 of part 4, with their own
elaborate causal accounts of the formation of philosophical beliefs,
suffer a worse fate: They are deleted altogether.3 These deletions
take with them Humes previous discussion of philosophical ctions, that is, the ctions of seeming to refer to something where no
referent is picked out.
How are we to explain this extraordinary shift in emphasis from
the Treatise to the Enquiry? In his autobiographical work, My Own
Life, Hume suggests that it may have been the style of the Treatise
that accounted for its poor reception:
I had always entertained a notion, that my want of success
in publishing the Treatise of Human Nature, had proceeded
more from the manner than the matter, and that I had been
guilty of a very usual indiscretion, in going to the press too
early. I, therefore, cast the rst part of that work anew in the
Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. (Letters 3)
When Hume speaks of the manner, not the matter, of the Treatise,
he may have had these complexoften hard to followassociationalist explanations in mind.
There is, I think, a better explanation for the removal or severe
shortening of these sections: Each contributes to the consequent
skepticism that emerges in part 4 of book 1. There we discover that
the capacity of the imagination to vivify ideas on the basis of its

148

Humes Skeptical Crisis

associationalist principles is responsible for a wide range of false


beliefs shared almost universally by the vulgar. It is responsible for
the empty ctions of philosophers. It is responsible for internal
clashes within the understanding, Finally, when the true character
of its operations is revealed by the science of human nature, all condence in them disappears.
Through erasure, things become much sunnier in the Enquiry,
as, for example, in this famous celebratory passage:
Though the powers and forces, by which [the course of nature]
is governed, be wholly unknown to us; yet our thoughts and
conceptions have still, we nd, gone on in the same train with
the other works of nature. Custom is that principle, by which
this correspondence has been effected; so necessary to the subsistence of our species, and the regulation of our conduct, in
every circumstance and occurrence of human life. Had not the
presence of an object instantly excited the idea of those objects,
commonly conjoined with it, all our knowledge must have been
limited to the narrow sphere of our memory and senses. . . .
As this operation of the mind, by which we infer like effects
from like causes, and vice versa, is so essential to the subsistence of all human creatures, it is not probable, that it could
be trusted to the fallacious deductions of our reason, which is
slow in its operations; appears not, in any degree, during the
rst years of infancy; and at best is, in every age and period of
human life, extremely liable to error and mistake. It is more
conformable to the ordinary wisdom of nature to secure so
necessary an act of the mind, by some instinct or mechanical
tendency. . . . (EHU 4445/5455)
I take this radical shift in the treatment of the imagination from the
Treatise to the Enquiry to be the most basic difference between them.

Two Openings and Two Closings

149

Z
The Role of Skeptical Arguments in the Enquiry
In the Enquiry Hume presents a series of skeptical arguments that
deal, in turn, with the senses, reason, and what he calls moral
reasoning.
Skepticism concerning the senses
Hume begins his skeptical arguments directed against the senses
by dismissing as trite some common reasons for impugning the
senses: perceptual variability, illusions (bent oars in water, double
images), and so on:
These sceptical topics, indeed, are only sufcient to prove,
that the senses alone are not implicitly to be depended on;
but that we must correct their evidence by reason, and by
considerations, derived from the nature of the medium, the
distance of the object, and the disposition of the organ, in
order to render them, within their sphere, the proper criteria
of truth and falsehood. (EHU 113/151)
Hume actually underestimates the force of these supposedly trite arguments. Their point is this: The appearance of things varies with settings
and circumstances, and we have no reasoned grounds for favoring any
one of these perspectives over any other.
Having brushed aside supposedly trite arguments, Hume
replaces them with one he considers both profound and unanswerable. Though perceptual variability of itself does not yield skeptical consequences, its recognition does lead a thoughtful person to
adopt the way of ideas:

150

Humes Skeptical Crisis

It seems . . . evident, that, when men follow this blind and


powerful instinct of nature, they always suppose the very
images, presented by the senses, to be the external objects,
and never entertain any suspicion, that the one are nothing
but representations of the other. . . .
But this universal and primary opinion of all men is soon
destroyed by the slightest philosophy, which teaches us, that
nothing can ever be present to the mind but an image or perception, and that the senses are only the inlets, through which
these images are conveyed, without being able to produce any
immediate intercourse between the mind and the object. The
table, which we see, seems to diminish, as we remove farther
from it: But the real table, which exists independent of us,
suffers no alteration: It was, therefore, nothing but its image,
which was present to the mind. These are the obvious dictates of reason; and no man, who reects, ever doubted, that
the existences, which we consider, when we say, this house
and that tree, are nothing but perceptions in the mind, and
eeting copies or representations of other existences, which
remain uniform and independent. (EHU 11314/152)
This argument is no better than its counterpart found in the
Treatise, and, as before, I will not pause to rehearse the standard
criticism that has been brought against it.
Given his commitment to the way of ideas, it takes only a short
paragraph for Hume to dismiss this representationalist (or doubleexistence) account of perception.
It is a question of fact, whether the perceptions of the senses
be produced by external objects, resembling them: How shall
this question be determined? By experience surely; as all other
questions of a like nature. But here experience is, and must be

Two Openings and Two Closings

151

entirely silent. The mind has never any thing present to it but
the perceptions, and cannot possibly reach any experience of
their connexion with objects. The supposition of such a connexion is, therefore, without any foundation in reasoning.
(EHU 115/153)
On the basis of this argument, Hume draws a conclusion as robust
as any found in the Treatise: This is a topic, therefore, in which
the profounder and more philosophical sceptics will always triumph, when they endeavour to introduce an universal doubt into
all subjects of human knowledge and enquiry (EHU 115/153).
For good measure, Hume throws in an argument against the
modern notion of primary and secondary qualities along the lines
he employed in book 1, part 4, section 4 of the Treatise. I will not
repeat that argument here, but simply note the strong skeptical conclusion that he draws from it.
Bereave matter of all its intelligible qualities, both primary and secondary, you in a manner annihilate it, and
leave only a certain unknown, inexplicable something, as
the cause of our perceptions; a notion so imperfect, that
no sceptic will think it worth while to contend against it.
(EHU 116/155)
In a footnote, Hume explicitly attributes this argument to Berkeley.
Skepticism concerning reason
Hume presents a vigorous restatement of skepticism with regard to
the senses. The same cannot be said for his presentation of skepticism with regard to reason. The argument in the Treatise is not
repeated. Perhaps Hume had second thoughts concerning it. He

152

Humes Skeptical Crisis

may have found its results too much to contend with. In any case,
this argument that deeply troubled him in the Treatise is simply
gone. What we get instead is a curious discussion of the paradoxes
that seem to arise from the mathematical notion of innite divisibility. In order to present a skeptical challenge to reason, Hume would
have to produce an argument of the following form:
Reason commits one to the doctrine of innite divisibility.
The doctrine of innite divisibility leads to absurdities and
contradictions.
Therefore, reason commits one to absurdities and contradictions.
Hume accepts the second premise but in a footnote seems to reject
the rst premise:
It seems to me not impossible to avoid these absurdities and
contradictions, if it be admitted, that there is no such thing as
abstract or general ideas, properly speaking. (118n./158n.)
Hume goes on to sketch a Berkeleyan critique of innite divisibility.
But if Hume is right in saying that the doctrine of innite divisibility is avoidable, then the rst premise of the above argument is false
and no general skepticism with regard to reason is forthcoming.
Skepticism concerning moral reasoning
Hume turns next to moral reasoning, not in the sense of ethical reasoning, but rather nondemonstrative or probabilistic reasoning concerning
matters of fact.4 He tells us that the skeptical objections to reasoning
concerning matters of fact are either popular or philosophical. He dismisses the popular objections to moral reason in the same way that he
dismissed the popular skeptical arguments directed at the senses:

Two Openings and Two Closings

153

The popular objections are derived from the natural weakness of


human understanding; the contradictory opinions, which have
been entertained in different ages and nations; the variations of
our judgment in sickness and health, youth and old age, prosperity and adversity; the perpetual contradiction of each particular
mans opinions and sentiments; with many other topics of that
kind. It is needless to insist farther on this head. These objections
are but weak. For as, in common life, we reason every moment
concerning fact and existence, and cannot possibly subsist, without continually employing this species of argument, any popular
objections, derived from thence, must be insufcient to destroy
that evidence. The great subverter of pyrrhonism or the excessive principles of scepticism, is action, and employment, and the
occupations of common life. (EHU 118/15859)
This is the rst explicit reference to Pyrrhonism in the Enquiry and
is somewhat perplexing. Hume starts out by giving a list of what he
calls popular skeptical objections to reasoning concerning matters
of fact. He seems to identify Pyrrhonists as purveyors of such popular objections. He dismisses these objections as weak. Later, however, Hume insists on the strength of the Pyrrhonists arguments:
Nothing can be more serviceable, than to be once thoroughly
convinced of the force of the pyrrhonian doubt, and of the
impossibility, that any thing, but the strong power of natural
instinct, could free us from it. (EHU 121/162)
There is also the following remark, directed at Berkeley:
That all his arguments, though otherwise intended, are, in
reality, merely sceptical, appears from this, that they admit of
no answer and produce no conviction. (EHU 116n/155n)

154

Humes Skeptical Crisis

These two passages indicate the senses in which, for Hume,


Pyrrhonian arguments can be successively strong and weak. Taken
theoretically, they are strongindeed, unanswerably strong; taken
doxastically, that is, with respect to their power to produce and maintain suspension of belief, their only effect is to cause . . . momentary
amazement and irresolution and confusion (EHU 116n/155n).
Hume turns next to what he calls the philosophical arguments
concerning moral reasoning. Here in the concluding section of the
Enquiry, he offers a brief, elegant, and uncluttered summary of his
own skeptical argument concerning the operations of the understanding, presented earlier in section 4 of the Enquiry:
Here [the sceptic] seems to have ample matter of triumph; while
he justly insists, that all our evidence for any matter of fact,
which lies beyond the testimony of sense or memory, is derived
entirely from the relation of cause and effect; that we have no
other idea of this relation than that of two objects, which have
been frequently conjoined together; that we have no argument
to convince us, that objects, which have, in our experience,
been frequently conjoined, will likewise, in other instances, be
conjoined in the same manner. (EHU 11819/159)
Having completed the skeptical argument, Hume then shifts to
a discussion of the weakness of human faculties:
Nothing leads us to this inference but custom or a certain
instinct of our nature; which is indeed difcult to resist, but
which, like other instincts, may be fallacious and deceitful.
While the sceptic insists upon these topics, he shows his force,
or rather, indeed, his own and our weakness; and seems, for
the time at least, to destroy all assurance and conviction.
(EHU 119/159)

Two Openings and Two Closings

155

The claim that the skeptical argument shows the weakness of our,
and not just the skeptics, mental faculties is reminiscent of claims
made in the Treatise. But there is a puzzle here. Humes reference
to the weakness of our faculties suggests that stronger mental faculties might not face like difculties. Humes skeptical argument is,
however, intended to establish that no reasoning can show that
objects, which have, in our experience, been frequently conjoined,
will likewise, in other instances, be conjoined in the same manner.
The weakness or strength of our faculties does not bear on this matter. Hume does not seem to be altogether clear about this.
To return to a point already made, there is a fundamental difference between the employment of skeptical arguments in the Treatise
and Enquiry. In the Treatise, having presented a skeptical argument,
Hume goes on to ask questions of the following kind: How it happens, that even after all we retain a degree of belief, which is sufcient
for our purpose, either in philosophy or common life (124/185). It is
the pursuit of such questions that leads Hume into a skeptical crisis. In the Enquiry he largely avoids questions of this kind and thus
avoids the consequent skepticism that attempts to answer them can
generate.

Z
Pyrrhonism and Mitigated Skepticism
Rightly or wronglyI think wronglyHume identies Pyrrhonism
with an extreme form of doxastic skepticism, and on this basis produces a number of standard arguments against it:
For here is the chief and most confounding objection to excessive scepticism, that no durable good can ever result from it;
while it remains in its full force and vigour. (EHU 119/159)

156

Humes Skeptical Crisis

And this:
And though a pyrrhonian may throw himself or others into
a momentary amazement and confusion by his profound
reasonings; the rst and most trivial event in life will put to
ight all his doubts and scruples, and leave him the same, in
every point of action and speculation, with the philosophers
of every other sect, or with those who never concerned themselves in any philosophical researches. (EHU 119/160)
This may be comforting, but it provides no answer to the question Hume raised in the opening section of the Enquiry: Given the
multitude of dangers involved and the small rewards to be expected,
why pursue philosophical inquiry at all? How, that is, can philosophy be pursued in a manner that minimizes its dangers and gives
at least some prospect of reasonable reward? Humes answer at the
close of book 1 of the Treatise is, as we have seen, that we keep
ourselves out of trouble by keeping our heads low and doing our
philosophizing within the boundaries of gentlemanly constraints.
In the Enquiry, Hume makes a more remarkable and systematically
more interesting suggestion: We should use Pyrrhonian doubt to
police our philosophical efforts. It is in this way that we arrive at
what Hume calls a mitigated skepticism.
The rst form of mitigated skepticism generates modesty and
reserve. Hume associates it with the probabilism of ancient academic skepticism. His exact wording is important:
There is, indeed, a more mitigated skepticism, or academical
philosophy, which may be both durable and useful, and which
may, in part, be the result of this pyrrhonism, or excessive scepticism, when its undistinguished doubts are, in some measure,
corrected by common sense and reection. (EHU 120/161)

Two Openings and Two Closings

157

Hume really has in mind mutual correction. Human beings, both


the learned and the vulgar, have a strong tendency to become dogmatic in their beliefs. Pyrrhonism can serve as a check on this tendency. Pyrrhonism, as Hume understands it, left to itself, destroys
all belief. Common sense and reection, in their turn, can serve to
curb Pyrrhonisms destructive tendencies. We thus reencounter one
of the central themes of the Treatise: A durable philosophical position can emerge when competing forces are brought into balance.
In this case, the competition between Pyrrhonism on one side and
common sense and reection on the other yields a durable and useful state of mitigated skepticism with respect to the degree of our
assent.
The second form of mitigated skepticism concerns the scope of
our inquires:
Another species of mitigated scepticism, which may be
of advantage to mankind, and which may be the natural
result of the pyrrhonian doubts and scruples, is the limitation of our enquiries to such subjects as are best adapted
to the narrow capacity of human understanding. . . . A correct Judgment . . . connes itself to common life, and to such
subjects as fall under daily practice and experience; leaving
the more sublime topics to the embellishment of poets and
orators, or to the arts of priests and politicians. To bring us
to so salutary a determination, nothing can be more serviceable, than to be once thoroughly convinced of the force of the
pyrrhonian doubt, and of the impossibility, that any thing,
but the strong power of natural instinct, could free us from it.
Those who have a propensity to philosophy, will still continue
their researches; because they reect, that, besides the immediate pleasure, attending such an occupation, philosophical

158

Humes Skeptical Crisis

decisions are nothing but the reections of common life,


methodized and corrected. (EHU 12021/162)
Humes declaration at the start of the Treatise that he would produce
a compleat system of the sciences, built on a foundation almost
entirely new, and the only one upon which they can stand with any
security (4/xv) is now a distant memory.
It is important to recognize that the mitigated skepticism of the
Enquiry is not the result of reasoning. Reason, left to itself, provides no response to Pyrrhonian arguments. Mitigated skepticism
results from the interaction of two forces: a departure from common
instinctive belief, counteracted by the persistence of common instinctive belief. Taken this way, the emergence of mitigated skepticism
is like the emergence of other philosophical positions, for example,
the double-existence theory of perception involves an equilibrium
between competing forces. The double-existence theory, in its various incarnations, has exhibited remarkable durability because, if
Hume is right, of the balancing of the persistent forces that generate it. Humes mitigated skepticism has a similar status. Whereas the
double-existence theory arises from an interplay between the way of
ideas and the vulgar view of perception, Humes mitigated skepticism is the product of an interaction between Pyrrhonian doubt on
one side and the persistence of our common modes of believing on
the other. Viewed this way, the emergence of mitigated skepticism is
an explicable event in the natural history of philosophy.5

Z Notes

Chapter 1
1. Im not thinking just of section 6 of part 4, Of personal identity.
The notion of identity also plays a central role in Humes discussion
of skepticism with regard to the senses and in his discussion of the
metaphysical notion of substance.
2. Hume is particularly proud of his treatment of probability in the Treatise.
He brags about it (in a feigned third person) in his anonymously published Abstract of a Treatise of Human Nature (408/64647).
3. I rst encountered a defense of Hume against Reids criticism along
these lines in a work published by the late-eighteenth-century/earlynineteenth-century Scottish philosopher Thomas Brown:
That darkness and light mutually produce each other, they [i.e.,
common people] do not believe: and if they did believe it, their
belief, instead of conrming the truth of Mr. Humes theory,
would prove it to be false; since it would prove the relation of
Cause and Effect to be supposed where there is no customary
connection. How often, during a long and sleepless night, does
the sensation of darkness exist, without being followed by the
sensation of light? (Brown 1822, 170ff.).

Donald Davidson adopts a similar line in Causal Relations


(Davidson 1967).

159

160

Notes to Pages 3342

Chapter 2
1. Notice that Hume does not seem to be talking about the degradation
of the content of the information transmitted, but rather its vivacity.
Chapter 3
1. It also corresponds to Humes treatment of miracles in section 10 of
the Enquiry Concerning the Human Understanding, where, in effect,
he uses causal principles to evaluate the trustworthiness of eyewitness
testimony. For more on this, see Fogelin (2003).
2. In an attempt to show that intuitive knowledge also degenerates into probability, Hume argues that some probability of error exists in the addition
of even very small numbers. Hume does not employ the reexive move
central to this treatment of demonstrative reasoning, but instead engages
in two slippery-slope arguments I have labeled [1] and [2].
[1] For tis easily possible, by gradually diminishing the numbers,
to reduce the longest series of addition to the most simple question, which can be formd, to an addition of two single numbers;
and upon this supposition we shall nd it impracticable to show
the precise limits of knowledge and of probability, or discover
that particular number, at which the one ends and the other
begins. But knowledge and probability are of such contrary
and disagreeing natures, that they cannot well run insensibly
into each other, and that because they will not divide, but must
be either entirely present, or entirely absent. [2] Besides, if any
single addition were certain, every one woud be so, and consequently the whole or total sum; unless the whole can be different
from all its parts. I had almost said, that this was certain; but
I reect, that it must reduce itself, as well as every other reasoning,
and from knowledge degenerate into probability. (12122/181)

Neither of these arguments is persuasive. With respect to [1], we can


note that, even if it is impracticable to shew the precise limits of
knowledge and of probability, this does not show there is no precise
limit. More simply, even if there is no precise limit, that does not rule

Notes to Pages 4662

3.

4.

5.
6.

161

out the possibility that some simple arithmetic sums fall paradigmatically into the category of intuitive truths. 1 + 1 = 2 can be counted as
an intuitive truth even if we cannot specify the precise place where
ones intuitive powers dim. Argument [2] is no better. We can make
errors in adding a long column of numbers without at some point
mistakenly believing that, say, 2 + 3 = 7. We know that 2 + 3 = 5
but, distracted, write down the wrong number, or read a number
incorrectly.
Here is a more exotic example. Suppose one of the subjects just happens to be omniscient, something, being omniscient, she, he, or it
would know. No diminution of assurance would take place in this
case. It is, however, not clear to me whether it makes sense to speak
of a being who (or that) just happens to be omniscient. Perhaps omniscient beings must be necessarily omniscient, but I dont see why.
Previously I have argued that Humes skeptical argument fails because
he has not ruled out the possibility that the series of diminutions may
approximate a limitperhaps a high limit (Fogelin 1985, note 4,
p. 174). That criticism, though fair enough, now strikes me as shallow
in conceding too much to Humes argument.
As already noted, Hume seems to exempt reports of subjective states
from his skepticism.
Hume used quite a different tactic in dealing with the threat of the
loss of all belief in the remote past through reiterative diminutions
in part 3, section 13. There he says that the imagination avoids this
result by forming a confused and general notion of each link that
disguises the multiplicity of transitions. In both cases, however,
the day is saved by what seems to be a defect in our intellectual
apparatus.

Chapter 4
1. There are objections aplenty that can be brought against it, but I will
not rehearse them here.
2. Incidentally, in the Principles of Human Knowledge, Berkeley deals
with the phenomenon of outnessthe fact that we seem to perceive

162

Notes to Pages 6391

things at a distance from ourselvesmuch more simply by noting


that this phenomenon also occurs in dreams (part 1, section 42).
3. I will examine Humes treatment of primary and secondary properties
in Chapter 5.
4. Humes discussion of identity in some ways parallels his earlier discussion of how beliefs concerning the remote past go through multiple
transitions without being destroyed by the inuence of reiterative
diminution. There, as we saw, Hume invoked the notion of a confused and general notion of each link as a way of explaining how
beliefs in the remote past are preserved. To work, it is essential that
this general notion be confused.
5. It is worth noting that this is the rst occurrence in Humes writings
of the notion that the mind is nothing but a heap, collection, [or,
later, a bundle] of perceptions. In Fogelin (1985) I suggested that
this passage provides the key to understanding Humes reservations,
expressed in his appendix to the Treatise, concerning his treatment
of personal identity. I later thought better of this. Now I am again
inclined to think that there might be something to the idea. In any
case, I will postpone further discussion of Humes notion of separating a particular perception from the bundle of perceptions until
I examine his discussion of personal identity.
Chapter 5
1. There does seem to be an element of historical displacement in this
passage. The topic of the section is ancient philosophy, but the views
of the judicious philosophers that Hume refers to are characteristic
of early-modern philosophy.
2. We nd a number of similar direct appeals to intuition in Berkeleys
writings:
Some truths there are so near and obvious to the mind, that
a man need only open his eyes to see them. Such I take this
important one to be, to wit, that all the choir of heaven and
furniture of the earth, in a word all those bodies which compose

Notes to Pages 91145

163

the mighty frame of the world, have not any subsistence without
a mind. (Principles, part 1, section 6)

3. All our ideas, sensations, or the things which we perceive, by whatsoever


names they may be distinguished, are visibly inactive, there is nothing of
power or agency included in them (Principles, part 1, section 25).
Chapter 7
1. See the discussion of this topic in Chapter 2.
2. In book 3, part 2, section 10 of the Treatise, Hume makes a parallel
claim concerning the dangers involved in inquiring too curiously
into the origins of governments.
No maxim is more conformable, both to prudence and morals, than to submit quietly to the government, which we nd
establishd in the country where we happen to live, without
enquiring too curiously into its origin and rst establishment. Few
governments will bear being examind so rigorously. (357/558)

3. I should confess to having some difculty appreciating Humes appeal


to eighteenth-century English gentlemen, since my own understanding of them largely comes from the plays of Sir John Vanbrugh and
the novels of Henry Fielding.
Chapter 8
1. In the Treatise Hume cited this as his sole reason for pursuing philosophy (see 176/271).
2. For Hume, Pyrrhonism seems be no more than a code word for radical doxastic skepticism. In fact, Humes references to the Pyrrhonists
nowhere reveal an informed understanding of their position. This is surprising for someone who was surely a reader of Bayles Dictionary. Among
other things he could have learned from Bayle is that the Pyrrhonists did
not call for the suspension of everyday, non-dogmatically held beliefs.
For more on the character of Pyrrhonism, see the rst chapter of Fogelin
(1993).

164

Notes to Pages 147158

3. So is the discussion of unphilosophical probability in part 3, where, as


we saw, the threat of radical skepticism makes its rst appearance in
the Treatise.
4. The use of moral survives in the expression moral certainty, which
indicates a degree of probability so great as to admit of no reasonable
doubt.
5. Because it is one of the most famous passages in Humes writings, I
should say something about the closing paragraph of the Enquiry. In
effect, Hume invents the central argument of Language, Truth, and
Logic not quite 200 years before A. J. Ayer produced it. Though he does
not employ the exact terminology, Humes denunciation of divinity
and school metaphysics depends on the distinction between relations
of ideas and matters of fact introduced in section 4 of the Enquiry.
When we run over libraries, persuaded of these principles, what
havoc must we make? If we take in our hand any volume; of
divinity or school metaphysics, for instance; let us ask, Does it
contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number? No.
Does it contain any experimental reasoning concerning matter of
fact and existence? No. Commit it then to the ames: For it can
contain nothing but sophistry and illusion. (EHU 123/165)

This is too heady and swift. The distinction between relations of ideas
and matters of fact as drawn in section 4 of the Enquiry is too underdeveloped and too prone to objections to bear so heavy a burden. In
anticipating Ayers positivism, Hume also buys futures in many of its
problems. This is not the place to go into such matters in detail, but
it is worth inquiring into the status of Humes distinction itself. How
should we treat the following passage?
All the objects of human reason or enquiry may naturally be
divided into two kinds, to wit, Relations of Ideas, and Matters of
Fact. (EHU 24/25)

Should it be committed to the ames?

Z Works Cited or Mentioned

Baier, Annette. 1991. Progress of Sentiments. Cambridge: Harvard University


Press.
Berkeley, George. 1949. Principles of Human Knowledge. In The Works of
George Berkeley, Vol. II. Edited by A. A. Luce and T. E. Jessop. London:
Thomas Nelson & Sons.
Brown, Thomas. 1822. Cause and Effect. 3rd ed. Andover, MA: Mark
Newman.
Davidson, Donald. 1967. Causal Relations. Journal of Philosophy lxiv:
691703.
Fogelin, Robert J. 1985. Humes Skepticism in the Treatise of Human Nature.
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
. 1993. Humes Skepticism. In The Cambridge Companion to
Hume. Edited by D. F. Norton. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge
University Press.
. 2003. A Defense of Hume on Miracles. Princeton, NJ and Oxford:
Princeton University Press.
Garrett, Don. 1997. Cognition and Commitment in Humes Philosophy.
New York, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hume, David. 1932. The Letters of David Hume, Vol. 1. Edited by J. Y. T. Greig.
2 vols. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
. 1975. Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding and Concerning
the Principles of Morals. Edited by L. A. Selby-Bigge and P. H. Nidditch,
3rd ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
. 1978. A Treatise of Human Nature, 2nd ed. Edited by L. A. SelbyBigge and P. H. Nidditch. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
165

166

Works Cited or Mentioned

. 2000. An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding:


A Critical Edition. Edited by T. L. Beauchamp. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
. 2007. A Treatise of Human Nature: A Critical Edition, Vol. 1.
Edited by D. F. Norton and M. J. Norton. 2 vols. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Owen, David. Unpublished. Scepticism with Regard to Reason.
Available from the departmental Web site (philosophy.arizona.edu) at
the University of Arizona.
Passmore, John Arthur. 1952. Humes Intentions. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Penelhum, Terence. 1975. Hume. New York: St. Martins.
Reid, Thomas. 1969. Essays on the Active Powers of the Human Mind.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Z Index

abstruse philosophy, reasons for and


against engaging in, 141144
academical philosophy, 156157
ancient philosophy, 8587, 9495,
9596, 99100
antecedent skepticism, 145
a priori probabilities, dispersed vivacity
and, 21
association, principles of, in
transferring belief, 20
association of dispositions, and
assimilation, 7475
association of dispositions, and idea of
continued existence, 7577
associationalist principles, capacity of
the imagination to vivify ideas
based on, 147148
Ayer, A. J., 164 n.5
beliefs
ability to sustain, 50
causes of, 1920
in external existence, causes of, 5965
imagination and formation of,
concerning external objects, 57
in object simplicity, 86, 9093

as products of causal inferences, 1819


threat of the loss of all, 161 n.6
vulgar, 6364, 65, 7677, 92
See also continued and distinct
existence: belief in
Berkeley, George, 62, 9799, 123,
153154, 162163 n.2
body, existence of, as a given, 55
Brown, Thomas, 159 n.3
Cartesian doubt, 145
causal inferences
associative operations of the
imagination as source of, 3
feeling of necessary connection as
product of, 120121
grounding of, and notion
of custom, 20
ideas and beliefs as products of, 1819
as not the product of rational
faculties, 1718
reason rejected as source of, 3
relationship between necessary
connections and, 17
causal laws, beliefs and, 19
causal reasoning, origins of, 15

167

168

Index

causal relations
and idea of necessary
connection, 120121
necessary connection as attendant
product of, 1314
necessary connection as essential
component of, 2223
necessary connection as not an
essential element of, 2526
causation
as natural relation, 26
as philosophical relation, 12, 26
and philosophical relations of
contiguity and priority, 1314
vulgar perspective on, 115116
cause, denition of, 1617, 2527
cause, necessity of, 1415
circularity argument, 18
Cognition and Commitment in Humes
Philosophy (Garrett), 9
coherence, as basis of belief in external
existence, 6668
common sense and reection, as
curb to Pyrrhonisms destructive
tendencies, 157
conceivability argument, 1718
conjunction, constant, in denition of
cause, 1617
conjunction, local, and immateriality of
the soul, 104107
consequent skepticism, 145146
constancy, as basis of belief in external
existence, 66, 68
constant conjunction, in denition of
cause, 1617
contiguity, and transfer of beliefs, 20
continued and distinct existence

belief in, 6578: gap lling, 7375;


imagination as source of, 6566;
informal statement of Humes
position, 6669; reason as
not the source of, 6364; senses
as not the source of, 6162;
systematic statement of Humes
position, 6970
idea of, 7577
custom, notion of, 20, 51
Davidson, Donald, 159 n.3
demonstrative knowledge, 12
demonstrative reasoning, 41, 4243
Descartes, 145
dispositions, association of, 7477
dogmatism, 136
double-existence theory of perception,
7882, 147, 150151, 158
double perspective, in
Humes examination of
simplicity, 9091
doxastic skepticism, 49, 144145
earthy opinions of honest gentlemen,
133134, 136137
empirical inquiry, rules for, 28
Enquiry Concerning Human
Understanding (Hume)
associative operations of the
imagination as source of causal
inferences, 3
concluding section of, 144146,
164 n.5
imagination in, compared to
Treatise, 148149
science of human nature in, 146148

Index
shift in emphasis from the Treatise, 147
skeptical arguments: concerning
moral reasoning, 152155;
concerning reason, 151152;
concerning the senses, 149151;
in Treatise compared to, 154
on skepticism, 139140
Euthyphro choice, 23
existence. See continued and distinct
existence; double-existence
theory of perception;
external existence
experience, initial, in origins of causal
reasoning, 15
external existence, 5965, 6668
See also continued and distinct
existence
external objects, 57, 60
faculties
human, weakness of, 154155
free-thinkers. See materialists
gap lling, in operations of the
imagination, 7375
Garrett, Don, 9
governments, examination of origins
of, 163 n.2 (chap. 7)
horizontal method, in evaluating
soundness of proof, 43, 47
human mind. See mind, the
human nature, approaches to
study of, 140141
Hume
defense of, against Reids
criticism, 159 n.3

169

exit from his dismal situation,


130132
expressions of despair, 56
expressions of melancholy, 125126
as mitigated doxastic skeptic, 49
self-referential crisis of, 83
skeptical crisis, source of, 5657
skeptical doubts as source of deep
disquietudes, 3
standpoints of, regarding radical
skepticism, 67
turn to skepticism by, 3940
voices of, contrasting, 67
Humes Law, 12
Hume (Stroud), 8
ideas
capacity of the imagination to vivify,
147148
and denition of substance,
102103
inferences from impressions and,
1618
as products of causal inferences, 1819
See also way of ideas, the
identity
attribution of, and idea of continued
existence, 7577
disputes about, as merely verbal,
116117
false belief in continued, of changing
objects, 8789
ction of, over time, 73, 86,
112113
Humes denial of, 118121
as it concerns non-human
entities, 113114

170

Index

ideas (continued)
and perceptions of constancy,
7374
principle of, in operations of the
imagination, 69, 7073
self-identity compared to, 70
See also personal identity
imagination
associative operations of, as source
of causal inferences, 3
capacity of, to vivify ideas based
on associationalist principles,
147148
difculties in implicit reliance on,
126129
and the ction of personal identity,
112113
mechanisms of, as source of Humes
skeptical crisis, 5657
as source of belief in continued
and distinct existence, 6566
treatment of, in the Enquiry compared
to in the Treatise, 148149
undiscriminating operations
of the associative principles
of, 38
immateriality of the soul, 101102,
104107
immortality, proofs of, 108109
impressions, 1516, 1618
incomprehensibility, broad and narrow
meanings of, 94
inductive skepticism, 3
innite divisibility, paradoxes arising
from notion of, 152
innite regress, 4445, 48
intuitive knowledge, 12, 160161 n.2

Kant, Immanuel, 39
knowledge
degeneration of, into probability, 4142
domain of, 1112
intuitive, 160161 n.2
reason, and annihilation of, 48
local conjunction, and immateriality
of the soul, 104107
materialists, and argument against
immaterialist, 105
material substance, modern
notion of, 9798
memory, and belief in personal
identity, 115
memory, impressions of, 1516
mind, the
as bundle of minds, 121
as bundle of perceptions, 121
Humes picture of, 118121
as mental substance, 119
perceptions, exclusive presence in, 60
reex acts of, 41, 44, 46, 4748
theater metaphor and, 111112
See also imagination
miracles, Humes treatment of, 160 n.1
mitigated skepticism, 6, 155158
moderate skepticism, 95
modern philosophy, 85, 9697, 9799,
99100
moral certainty, 164 n.4
moral reasoning, 152155
naturalism, tension between skepticism
and, 4
natural relation, and denition of cause, 25

Index
necessary connection
as attendant product of causal
relation, 1314
as essential component of causal
relation, 2223
feeling of, as product of causal
inference, 120121
as not an essential element of causal
relation, 2526
as product of inference from cause
to effect, 23
New Theory of Vision (Berkeley), 62
objects
changing, false belief in continued
identity of, 8789
external, 60
false belief in simplicity of, 86,
9093
imagination, role in formation of
beliefs concerning, 57
solidity as primary feature of, 98
occult qualities, 94, 95
operations of the imagination
gap lling, 7377
grounding of beliefs in,
as source of Humes
difculties, 126127
and identity, principle of, 7073
philosophical and unphilosophical
probability and, 29
skeptical consequences that emerge
from, 127128
as source of causal inferences, 3
See also continued and distinct
existence: belief in
original rst matter, 8990

171

outness, the phenomenon of, 62,


161162 n.2
Owen, David, 89
Passmore, John, 125126
perception
double-existence theory of, 7882,
147, 150151, 158
individual, as individual
substance, 119
representationalist account of, 7882,
147, 150151, 158
perceptions
the mind as bundle of, 121
reappearance of, 6869
visibly inactive, 9192
perceptual variability, recognition of,
and adoption of the way of ideas,
149150
peripatetic system, incomprehensibility
of, 9394
peritrope, dened, 52
personal identity
basic criticisms, 110112
disputes about, as merely
verbal, 116117
ction of, 112116
Humes declaration of failure
regarding his account of, 121124
Humes examination of, 109112
Humes reservations on, 117118
memory, and belief in, 115
See also identity
phenomenalist stance, 9192
philosophical and unphilosophical
probability, 29, 3738
See also unphilosophical probability

172

Index

philosophical arguments concerning


moral reasoning, 154
philosophical ction, 92
philosophical inquiry, approaches to
pursuit of, 132137, 156
philosophical opinion, common
opinion compared to, 8687
philosophical positions, durable, 157
philosophical relations, 1112,
1314, 25
philosophy
abstruse, 141144
academical, 156157
ancient, 8587, 9495, 9596,
99100
modern, 85, 9697, 9799, 99100
prejudice based on general rules,
as source of unphilosophical
probabilties, 3537
primary and secondary qualities,
distinction between, 9799, 128, 151
privileged perspective, phenomenalist
stance as, 9192
probabilistic reasoning, 152
probability
of causes, 2122
of chances, 21
degeneration of knowledge
into, 4142
and the idea of cause and effect,
1314, 5759, 71
knowledge and, 11
and operations of the
imagination, 29
reason, and annihilation of, 48
and vivacity, distribution of, 2122
See also unphilosophical probability

Pyrrhonian moments, 8283, 99100


Pyrrhonism, 6, 153, 154155, 155158,
163 n.2 (chap. 8)
See also radical skepticism
radical doxastic skepticism, 163 n.2
(chap. 8)
radical skepticism, 67, 59, 137
See also Pyrrhonism
rational arguments, used to undercut
rationality, 5253
reason
regression argument with
regard to, 4344
rejection of, as basis of vulgar
belief, 65
rejection of, as source of causal
inferences, 3
skeptical arguments in Enquiry
concerning, 151152
See also skeptical arguments with
regard to reason
reasoning
capacity for, in humans
and animals, 28
long chains of, and diminution of
vivacity, 3233
long chains of, and nondiminution
of vivacity, 3435
moral, skeptical arguments
concerning, 152155
and transformation of inferences into
general rule, 3637
in unreasonable ways, 3536
reex acts of the mind, 41, 44, 46, 4748
reexive principle, as demand of
rationality, 48

Index
regression argument, and skepticism
with regard to reason, 4344
Reid, Thomas, 2627, 159 n.3
reiterative diminution, principle
of, 3135, 4448
relations
causal, 1314, 2223, 2526, 108,
120121
natural, 25
philosophical, 1112, 1314, 25
remoteness of the event, effect
of, 3031
remoteness of the observation,
effect of, 31
representational realism, staying
power of, 81
representationalist account of perception,
7882, 147, 150151, 158
resemblance, 12, 20, 27
Scepticism with Regard to Reason
(Owen), 89
science of human nature
in the Enquiry, 146148
transformation of, into modest
activity, 134135
senses, the
faith in, 5557
Humes turnabout with regard
to, 5557
implicit faith in, 82
implicit faith shaken, 8384
as not the source of belief in
continued and distinct
existence, 6162
skeptical doubts about, 8283
of skepticism, distinctions between, 144

173

See also skeptical arguments with


regard to the senses
sensory impressions, 1516
sequence of perceptions, the minds
treatment of, 8789
simplicity of objects, false belief
in, 9093
skeptical arguments
and ability to sustain beliefs, 50
central components of, 48
dialectical instability of, 5354
purpose of presentation, 51
skeptical arguments in the Enquiry
concerning moral reasoning, 152155
concerning reason, 151152
concerning the senses, 149151
differences between Treatise
and, 154
skeptical arguments with regard to
reason, 3954
Humes response to his own, 4852
peritrope, 5254
regression argument, 4344
reiterative diminution, principle
of, 4448
skeptical arguments with regard to the
senses, 5584
belief in continued existence, 7778
a concluding note, 8384
introduction, 5960
primary task of, 146147
reason not the source of belief in the
existence of bodies, 6365
the senses not the source of belief in
the existence of bodies, 6063
skeptical principles for philosophizing,
132137

174

Index

skepticism
antecedent, 145
consequent, 145146
distinctions between senses of, 144
doxastic, 49, 144145
in the Enquiry, 139140, 144146
rst reference to, in the Treatise, 38
Humes turn to, 3940
inductive, 3
mitigated, 6, 155158
moderate, 95
radical, 67, 59, 137 (see also
Pyrrhonism)
results of, a gloomy summation, 125130
tension between naturalism and, 4
theoretical, 49, 145
and universal doubt, 151
solidity, as primary feature of material
objects, 98
soul, the
immateriality of, 101102, 104107
spiritual substance of, as basis for
immortality of the soul, 108109
as substance, 102104
soul-body interaction, 107108
standpoints of Hume regarding radical
skepticism, 67
Stroud, Barry, 8
substance, notion of, 8586, 8990,
102103, 103104

time, and the problem of


identity, 71
Treatise of Human Nature (Hume)
naturalistic reading of, 27, 5152
opening of, 140
underlying substance, the ction
of, 8990
unifying substance, the ction of, 93
unphilosophical probability
general rules derived from, 3738
philosophical probability as
opposed to, 29
sources of: prejudice based on
general rules, 3537; remoteness
of the event, effect of, 3031;
remoteness of the observation,
effect of, 31

testimony, metaphor of, 42


theoretical skepticism, 49, 145

way of ideas, the, 58, 64, 79, 81, 9192,


149150

vertical method in evaluating soundness


of proof, 4344, 47
visibly inactive perceptions, 9192
vivacity
distribution of, and probability, 2122
inability of imagination to preserve, 56
long chains of reasoning: and
diminution of, 3233; and
nondiminution of, 3435
voices of Hume, contrasting, 67
vulgar system, 58, 7677,
78, 7981

Você também pode gostar