Você está na página 1de 18

586992

research-article2015

RRPXXX10.1177/0486613415586992Review of Radical Political EconomicsZhou

Article

The Tragedy of the Anticommons


in Knowledge

Review of Radical Political Economics


2016, Vol. 48(1) 158175
2015 Union for Radical
Political Economics
Reprints and permissions:
sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav
DOI: 10.1177/0486613415586992
rrpe.sagepub.com

Yi Zhou1

Abstract
The anticommons in knowledge is distinct from the anticommons in physical objects. The former
is always tragic, the latter not necessarily so. For society at large, the tragedy of the anticommons
is more serious when it involves knowledge than when it involves physical resources. Buchanan
and Yoons (2000) formal model of the anticommons is incorrect even within the neoclassical
context, and their neoliberal suggestion that single ownership is the socially optimal solution
to the tragedy of the knowledge anticommons is misleading. This article argues that the only,
epistemically and socially beneficial solution to the tragedy of the knowledge anticommons is
to create, expand, and protect the knowledge commons. The article also constructs a simple
formal model based on Bessen and Maskins (2006) sequential model, as a metaphor for how the
comedy of the knowledge commons works. The analysis supports the worldwide movement
for free knowledge, and dissents from the evolving political and academic consensus in China in
favor of more restrictive intellectual property regimes.
JEL classification: B59, D23, O34
Keywords
knowledge, anticommons tragedy, knowledge commons

1. Introduction
The overexploitation of common-pool resources has occupied social thinkers for at least two millennia and probably even longer.1 Early literature for formal analyses of this problem included an
1For

example, as Michael Heller mentioned, Pericles, in Thucydidess The History of the Peloponnesian War,
argued that the Peloponnesians devote a very small fraction of the time to the consideration of any public
object, most of it to the prosecution of their own objects. Meanwhile each fancies that no harm will come of
his neglect, that it is the business of somebody else to look after this or that for him; and so, by the same notion
being entertained by all separately, the common cause imperceptibly decays (Thucydides n.d.: book 1, chapter 5; Heller 2008: 208). Aristotle, in his Politics, noted that that which is common to the greatest number has
the least care bestowed upon it. Every one thinks chiefly of his own, hardly at all of the common interest; and
only when he is himself concerned as an individual (Aristotle n.d.: book 2; Heller 2008: 16, 208).

1Department

of Economics, Fudan University, Shanghai, China

Date received: April 17, 2013


Date accepted: October 8, 2013
Corresponding Author:
Yi Zhou, Department of Economics, Fudan University, 600 Guoquan Road, Shanghai, 200433, China.
Email: zhou-yi@fudan.edu.cn, or yizhou@post.harvard.edu

Downloaded from rrp.sagepub.com at Glasgow University Library on May 4, 2016

159

Zhou

article in Danish published by Jens Warming, a Danish economist, in 19112 and an article published by H. Scott Gordon in 1954 (RSAS 2009; Gordon 1954). Katharine Comans Some
Unsettled Problems of Irrigation, published in the first issue of the American Economic Review
in 1911, also addressed the problem (Coman 1911; Ostrom 2011; Libecap 2011). In 1968, the
ecologist Garrett James Hardin popularized concerns about the misuse of common property
resources with a widely referenced article entitled The Tragedy of the Commons in the journal
Science (Hardin 1968; RSAS 2009).
Dual to the concept commons3 is the concept anticommons. The idea was popularized in
a 1998 article by Michael Heller published in the Harvard Law Review entitled The Tragedy of
the Anticommons: Property in the Transition from Marx to Markets. According to the article,
Frank Michelman appeared to have coined the term anticommons by introducing the equivalent of an anticommons through his speculative definition of a regulatory regime in his 1982
article challenging the presumptive efficiency of private property,4 where he defined a regulatory regime to be a type of property in which everyone always has rights respecting the objects
in the regime, and no one, consequently, is ever privileged to use any of them except as particularly authorized by the others. This definition is based upon a kind of logical duality: [i]f a
regime exists in which all are privileged to use whatever objects they wish and in which no one
holds exclusionary rights (that is, a commons), then, as a matter of logic, an anticommons also
could exist where no one is privileged to use objects and everyone has the right to exclude
(Heller 1998).
According to Heller (1998) there are only a few hypothetical examples for which an anticommons under Michelmans definition, which precludes use of the property by anyone, is the most
efficient property regime. Heller (1998) finds that for most resources that people care about,
some level of use is preferable to non-use, and an anticommons regime is a threat to, rather than
the epitome of, optimal use. He concludes that [a]nticommons property is prone to the tragedy
of underuse. It is Heller who coined the term tragedy of the anticommons (Heller 2008: 18, 21).
As a practical matter Epstein (2009) noted that the holdout problem, one of the potential outcomes in an anticommons, has long been a concern of public policy makers.5 Epstein (2009) also
noted that the ability to link this problem up with the issue of overconsumption of shared
resourcesor commonsopens up previously unappreciated avenues for research. Buchanan
and Yoon (2000) tried to unite the concepts of a commons and anticommons mathematically.
Some reviewers may have been attracted to the mathematical beauty in Buchanan and Yoons
(2000) formal model, in which the anticommons and commons problems are shown to be
2As

cited by RSAS (2009), the article is Jens Warming (1911). Om grundrente av fiskegrunde.
Nationalkonomisk Tidsskrift 49: 499-505. English translation Peder Andersen (1983). On rent of fishing
grounds: A translation of Jens Warmings 1911 article, with an introduction, trans. Peder Andersen and
Kirsten Stentoft. History of Political Economy 15 (3) (Fall): 391-396.
3Hess and Ostrom (2006) noted that the word commons is used for both the singular and plural forms.
They (2006) also noted that for the general term commons there is differentiation between a commons as a
shared resource or resource system which is called common-pool resources and independent of particular
property rights, and a commons as a property-rights regime which is called common property and is a legal
regime, a jointly owned legal set of rights.
4As cited by Heller (1998), Michelmans 1982 article is Frank I. Michelman (1982). Ethics, economics,
and the law of property. In Ethics, economics, and the law (NOMOS series - 24), ed. J. Roland Pennock
and John W. Chapman. New York University Press.
5For example, Adam Smith in his The Wealth of Nations noted that the commerce which any nation can
carry on by means of a river which does not break itself into any great number of branches or canals, and
which runs into another territory before it reaches the sea, can never be very considerable; because it is
always in the power of the nations who possess that other territory to obstruct the communication between
the upper country and the sea (Smith 1789: book 1, chapter 3, paragraph 8).

Downloaded from rrp.sagepub.com at Glasgow University Library on May 4, 2016

160

Review of Radical Political Economics 48(1)

symmetrical in several respects. However, on the one hand, their formulation is incorrect even
within the neoclassical context, because they mistook some basic concepts that are at least as old
as what was considered by Jules Dupuit (Coloma 2003)6; on the other hand, even if it were correct
within the neoclassical context, their formal model should be still ideological rather than universally true, as is the case with most other neoclassical economic models. For example, the model
ignores several dimensions of intellectual property issues explored in heterodox economics.7
This article discusses the tragedy of the anticommons with respect to a special category,
knowledge, which is distinct from physical objects. While Heller and Eisenberg (1998) and
Heller (2008: 76-78) warned that the privatization of biomedical research risks creating a tragedy of the anticommons through a proliferation of fragmented and overlapping intellectual property rights, they did not generalize their criticism of intellectual property rights. Instead they
claimed that the tragedy of underuse arising out of the biomedical anticommons is distinct from
the routine underuse inherent in any well-functioning patent system. This article challenges that
delimitation, and argues that intellectual property per se is the very source of the tragedy of the
anticommons in knowledge and that the tragedy is unavoidable so long as an intellectual property
regime exists.
The rest of this article is organized as follows. The second section analyzes both the anticommons in knowledge, which is distinct from the anticommons in physical objects, and the tragedy
of the anticommons in knowledge. This is followed by a third section that refutes the neoliberal
argument that single ownership is the socially optimal solution to the tragedy of the knowledge
anticommons. The fourth section argues that the only epistemically and socially beneficial solution to the tragedy of the knowledge anticommons is to create, expand, and protect the knowledge commons. In the fifth section, a simple model based on Bessen and Maskins (2006)
sequential model is constructed as a metaphor for how the comedy of the knowledge commons
works. The last section is the conclusion.

2. The Anticommons Tragedy in Knowledge


The concept of the anticommons can be traced back to at least as early as 1838. In that year
Antoine Augustin Cournot published his Researches into the Mathematical Principles of the
Theory of Wealth, which included his complementary monopoly theory (Sonnenschein 1968;
Heller 2008: 42). Hugo Sonnenschein in a 1968 article demonstrated a formal duality between
Cournots theory of duopoly and his theory of complementary monopoly (Sonnenschein 1968;
Feinberg and Kamien 2001; Gardner, Gaston, and Masson 2002). Nirvikar Singh and Xavier
Vives in a 1984 article provided a general treatment of the duality between Cournot competition
and Bertrand competition, showing that oligopolists selling complementary products will choose
to compete over price rather than output (Singh and Vives 1984; Gardner, Gaston, and Masson
2002). The methodology these and other researches provided has been adopted by some scholars
for investigating the regime of anticommons and for economic modeling of the anticommons.
These formal economic models for analyzing anticommons and the tragedy of the anticommons in physical objects may also give clues about anticommons and the tragedy of the anticommons in knowledge. For example, the simultaneous anticommons problem illustrated in Colomas
(2003) model, which corrected and reformulated Buchanan and Yoons (2000) formal model
within the neoclassical context, may be also used as a metaphor for one of the two mechanisms
by which an anticommons might be created in biomedical researchby creating too many concurrent fragments of intellectual property rights in potential future products (e.g. the existence of
6Coloma

(2003) identified the mistake and reformulated the model.


example, the profit maximization principle in neoclassical economics, which is adopted by the model,
is not universally true, especially for human knowledge creation.
7For

Downloaded from rrp.sagepub.com at Glasgow University Library on May 4, 2016

161

Zhou

separate patents on complementary gene fragments) (Heller and Eisenberg 1998; Landes and
Posner 2003: 316), and the sequential anticommons problem illustrated in the model in Parisi,
Schulz, and Depoorter (2004) and Schulz, Parisi, and Depoorter (2002) may be also used as a
metaphor for the other mechanismby permitting too many upstream patent owners to stack
licenses on top of the future discoveries of downstream users (Heller and Eisenberg 1998).
Despite some insights, the existing formal economic models for analyzing the anticommons
have limited explanatory power. They fail to address the full scope of anticommons problems in
physical objects. Furthermore, the models are basically designed for explaining an anticommons
in physical objects and therefore miss some of the distinctive problems related to an anticommons in knowledge.
First, the tragedy of the anticommons in knowledge is much more severe than in physical
objects, because of the idiosyncratic nature of knowledge: the existence of substantial, widespread, and even ubiquitous positive knowledge externalities, which will be significantly inhibited by the regime of anticommons.
The essence of knowledge creation is a course of systematic, indivisible, continuous, and
dynamic development. An intellectual property regime, however, tries to break up such a course
into fragments of intellectual monopolies. In the words of Michael Polanyi, [i]t tries to parcel up
a stream of creative thought into a series of distinct claims, each of which is to constitute the basis
of a separately owned monopoly, and tries to divide up the growth of human knowledge. . .into
such sharply circumscribed phases (Polanyi 1944; Machlup 1958). In that case, each owner, i.e.
the monopolist of each fragment of knowledge, has the right to exclude others from using that
fragment, and thus no one will have the freedom to use the whole stream of that knowledge.
The anticommons in knowledge so created poses a dire threat to the growth of human knowledge. For example, as Heller and Eisenberg (1998) mentioned, [p]rivatization of upstream biomedical research in the United States may create anticommons property that is less visible than
empty storefronts but even more economically and socially costly.
Second, when there are significant pervasive negative externalities of use of physical
resources, an anticommons in physical objects may be a better regime for social welfare because
of less use of the resources, whereas with an anticommons in knowledge that is not the case. The
loss of positive externalities from an anticommons in knowledge creation is unlikely to be offset
by reductions in the negative externalities accompanying knowledge creation.
As neoliberals always ignore or downplay externalities,8 Buchanan and Yoon (2000) did not
consider externalities in their model for commons and anticommons. Coloma (2003) corrected
and improved Buchanan and Yoons (2000) model within the neoclassical context, taking externalities into account for the problem of the commons by introducing a specific cost function. But
his model only considered a so-called reciprocal externality, which is a localized negative externality. He did not consider negative externalities on environments outside the commons property,
which are pervasive negative externalities. For the problem of the anticommons, his model considered neither the localized negative externalities nor the pervasive negative externalities. When
negative externalities are pervasive and significant, as is often the case, less use of the resources
as a result of the anticommons regime than the efficient quantity determined in either Buchanan
and Yoons (2000) or Colomas (2003) model may be better for social welfare. In some circumstances, even no use of resources as a result of an anticommons regime under Michelmans

8For

example, Epstein (2009) wrote: The NIMBY movement gets off to the wrong start when it claims
ownership interests in propertymy backyardthat is owned by others there is no way to fix the gridlock problem unless we narrow the definition of externality to exclude all of the various ills that now count
as protectable harm.

Downloaded from rrp.sagepub.com at Glasgow University Library on May 4, 2016

162

Review of Radical Political Economics 48(1)

definition9 may be the best use. Two examples of the latter are Robert Ellicksons hypothetical
wilderness preserve, which any person has standing to enforce, and James Kriers hypothetical nuclear-waste dump, which is so dangerous that everyone has standing to exclude (Heller
1998: 667, 668, note 214, note 215, and note 216).
For knowledge, however, there are never any of the above-mentioned pervasive negative
externalities. For an anticommons in physical objects, less use is not necessarily underuse
and in some circumstances even no use may be the best use, which may be called the comedy
of the anticommons (Heller 2008: 46, 47). For an anticommons in knowledge, less use is
necessarily the underuse, thus becoming tragic.
Finally, when pervasive negative externalities of use of physical resources are minor, possible
coordination and cooperation between multiple owners (excluders) in an anticommons in physical objects may reduce the extent of underuse, but the underuse will not be eliminated; for an
anticommons in knowledge, on the other hand, not only is there the underuse that such coordination and cooperation will not be able to eliminate, but much more importantly, such cooperation will inhibit the positive knowledge externalities to a greater extent.
Both Buchanan and Yoons (2000) and Colomas (2003) model only applied non-cooperative
games in analyzing the commons and anticommons problems, without considering the cases of
cooperative games. In reality, however, there exists the potential for coordination and cooperation between multiple owners (excluders) in an anticommons, with success more likely within
close-knit communities than among hostile strangers (Heller and Eisenberg 1998; Heller 1998:
625, and note 17).10 When pervasive negative externalities are minor, such cooperation, if successful, will improve social welfare by reducing the extent of underuse. The result of the successful cooperation may be an equilibrium where these owners (excluders) total surplus is
maximized, the same as the equilibrium under the single ownership, where the single owners
total surplus is maximized, as shown by Buchanan and Yoon (2000). Buchanan and Yoons
(2000) analysis suggested that the equilibrium under either the single ownership or efficient collective management is socially optimal, but the suggestion is incorrect even according to neoclassical standards. The equilibrium point, with less quantity supplied and higher price, actually
deviates from the true, socially optimal point, where the average revenue given by the demand
function is equal to the social marginal cost, as shown in Colomas (2003) model, which corrected and reformulated Buchanan and Yoons (2000) model within the neoclassical context.11
The deviation derives from the market power that the single owner has or the multiple owners
9Heller

(1998) defined anticommons property as a property regime in which multiple owners hold effective rights of exclusion in a scarce resource. The distinction between Michelmans and Hellers (1998)
definition is important. The former can be understood as an open-access anticommons, which Robert C.
Ellickson argued may be rare and for which a threshold requirement of near simultaneous unanimous
consent, which will be nearly impossible to achieve, ensures that the property will not be used by anyone
(Heller 1998). The latter can be understood as a limited-access anticommons, in which a limited group of
owners have rights of exclusion and which Ellickson argued appears more often (See Heller 1998: 667, 668,
669, and note 218). In the commons/anticommons duality, it is obvious that an open-access anticommons
and a limited-access anticommons correspond to an open-access commons and a limited-access commons
respectively. RSAS (2009), for example, mentioned the cases of open access and a fixed number of
users for a commons.
10Obviously, an anticommons in a close-knit community is a limited-access anticommons.
11Coloma (2003) pointed out that in fact the tragedy of the commons does not exist in Buchanan and Yoons
(2000) model aimed at illustrating both the commons tragedy and the anticommons tragedy, because their
model does not include any cost function. Instead, Colomas (2003) model introduces a cost function for
each owner (user) such that each owners (users) private marginal cost is lower than the social marginal
cost, which represents the reciprocal externality among the owners (users) that creates the tragedy of the
commons.

Downloaded from rrp.sagepub.com at Glasgow University Library on May 4, 2016

163

Zhou

(excluders) under the cooperation in the anticommons collectively have by virtue of monopolizing the physical resources. That is to say, when the pervasive negative externalities are modest,
cooperation between the multiple owners (excluders) in the anticommons in physical objects,
even if successful, will not eliminate the tragedy of underuse.12
This point is also true of the anticommons in knowledge. For example, when patents are
blocking, efficiency would be improved by their joint use, which could be brought about either
by the sale of all the patents to a single firm (whether one of the patentees or a different firm
altogether) or by a cross-licensing agreement that would permit each of the firms to use all the
patents (Landes and Posner 2003: 383). Such joint use, however, would not be socially optimal,
because the single firm would have very strong market power or the result of the cross-licensing
agreement may be to disguise a cartel as a lawful patent monopoly (Landes and Posner 2003:
383). This is the reason why patent pooling and cross-licensing on the patent side or the blanket
licensing on the copyright side have been targets of careful antitrust scrutiny (Landes and Posner
2003: 382, 383; Heller and Eisenberg 1998; Heller 2008: 72, 73, 196). Furthermore, it is particularly noteworthy that the result of the insiders cooperation through these voluntary agreements
is that access to and the free use and distribution of the knowledge by outside competitors and
society at large will be restricted or blocked to a greater extent and therefore the positive knowledge externalities will be inhibited more significantly.
To sum up, the anticommons in knowledge is always tragic, while the anticommons in physical objects is not necessarily so. For society at large, the tragedy of the anticommons in knowledge will be much more tragic than that in physical objects.

3. Single Ownership Is Not the Way Out


Heller (2008: 21, 41, 42) notes that after he (1998) proposed the possibility of an anticommons
tragedy, Buchanan and Yoon (2000) demonstrated my anticommons hypothesis mathematically and [a]ccording to their model, society gets the highest total value from a resource . . .
when a single decision maker controls its use. Actually, however, Buchanan and Yoons mathematical model fails to address the full range of anticommons problems identified in Heller
(1998), and the authors suggestion that the equilibrium under either the single ownership or
efficient collective management is socially optimal is misleading.
As mentioned in the second section of this article, Buchanan and Yoon (2000) considered
neither localized negative externalities nor pervasive negative externalities in their model for
commons and anticommons. Even when pervasive externalities are minor, their suggestion is
still wrong, because the single owner has the market power, [u]nderuse can also arise in the
monopoly context, when a single owner blocks access to a resource, and this situation will also
be tragic (Heller 2008: 45; Coloma 2003). The problem of underuse may disappear when there is
perfect price discrimination (Coloma 2003), but [i]n practice, perfect first-degree price discrimination is almost never possible (Pindyck and Rubinfeld 2001: 373, 407). Even if perfect
price discrimination is possible in practice, all of the consumer surplus will be captured by the
monopolist as a result and it will most likely do much harm to social welfare in the long run,
which is generally considered undesirable.
It seems that although in the commons/anticommons context there is still underuse under
single ownership when pervasive externalities are minor, in the anticommons context alone collecting rights into single ownership may eliminate the tragedy of the anticommons and therefore
improve the situation if pervasive externalities are minor. However, even if concerns about the
12Therefore, Hellers (1998) argument that one of the reasons why the anticommons is not necessarily tragic
is that efficient cooperation among multiple owners (excluders) in an anticommons could develop over time
is not exactly tenable.

Downloaded from rrp.sagepub.com at Glasgow University Library on May 4, 2016

164

Review of Radical Political Economics 48(1)

adequacy of collecting rights into single ownership as a response to the underuse problems
caused by an anticommons could be overcome, other problems remain. In practice it is easier to
fragment than to reconvene fragmented property (Parisi, Schulz, and Depoorter 2004; Heller
2008: 213). As Heller pointed out, collecting rights from an anticommons into usable private
property bundles is often brutal and slow, and both markets and governments may fail to do so
(Heller 1998; Heller and Eisenberg 1998). For example, [l]and is much easier to break up than
to put back together. Eminent domain is one way to unlock the value frozen in gridlocked land,
but its a crude solution (Heller 2008: 110, 111).13 Obviously, it is even harder to solve the
cross-border anticommons tragedy at the international level resulting from fragmented sovereignty, as Adam Smith observed in 1776 in The Wealth of Nations: The navigation of the Danube
is of very little use to the different states of Bavaria, Austria and Hungary, in comparison of what
it would be if any of them possessed the whole of its course till it falls into the Black Sea(Smith
1789: book 1, chapter 3, paragraph 8; Buchanan and Yoon 2000; Heller 2008: 182, 183).14
The above points seem also true of the anticommons in knowledge. Both markets and governments may find it difficult to dissolve barriers to knowledge production assembled under privatization. For example, one program can infringe many different software patents at once. Linux,
the kernel of the GNU/Linux operating system, may have infringed as many as 283 different U.S.
software patents (Stallman 2005). A company that developed a treatment for Alzheimers disease
found it could not bring it to market unless it bought access to dozens of patents and [a]ny single
patent owner could demand a huge payoff; some blocked the whole deal (Heller 2008: xiii). A
final point to remember is that in this emerging new era of technocapitalism,15 even if these formidable obstacles to consolidation can be overcome, the intellectual monopoly created will likely
be detrimental to the diversity and dynamics of knowledge development, replacing the tragedy
of the anticommons with the Sargasso Sea of monopoly.

4. How to Solve the Anticommons Tragedy in Knowledge


Intellectual property rights are the source of the tragedy of the anticommons in knowledge. It is
impossible to find a socially beneficial way to overcome the tragedy within the legal framework
of intellectual property. As discussed above, neither cooperation between multiple right holders (excluders) nor collecting rights into single ownership, if possible, is a socially beneficial way
to overcome the anticommons tragedy in knowledge. On the contrary, these partial solutions
risk blocking the free use and distribution of knowledge to an even greater extent. This is because
of the negative meta-externalities of a well-established intellectual property regime.
13Figure 5.2 in Hellers 2008 book, which comprises two pictures showing [a] lone holdout in a Chinese
project, March 2007 and [t]he holdout, bulldozed, April 2007 respectively, is missing in the Chinese edition of the book (Heller 2008: 113, 234, 235; Heller 2009: 98-100). The holdout story in Chongqing, China
behind the pictures was in the media spotlight in 2007.
14In the commons context, on the one hand, single ownership will not eliminate underuse, if pervasive
externalities are minor; on the other hand, even to the extent that in some circumstances single ownership
may mitigate overuse of resources, the problem is that most common property resources are vast and it is
not practical to privatize them (Pindyck and Rubinfeld 2001: 643). It may be practical to privatize the parking lot discussed in Buchanan and Yoons (2000) model and assign usage and exclusion rights to a single
owner, but the air and waters surrounding us cannot readily be fenced and therefore single ownership is
by no means a way of solving such commons tragedies as a massive extinction of species in the oceans of
the world, water and air pollution, and overpopulation (or what Hardin called the tragedy of the commons
in breeding) (Hardin 1968).
15I thank two of the reviewers of this article for their suggestion that I pay attention to this new version of
capitalism. Douglas Kellner appeared to have coined the term technocapitalism in 1989 (Kellner 2003:
31; Shaw 2008: 26). According to Luis Suarez-Villa, technocapitalism is a new form of capitalism that is
heavily grounded on corporate power and its exploitation of technological creativity (Suarez-Villa 2001,
2009).
Downloaded from rrp.sagepub.com at Glasgow University Library on May 4, 2016

165

Zhou

Meta-externalities refer to the unintended consequences of legal and economic activities


that can affect the broad contours of society and culture. Heterodox economists attend to them,
while neoclassical economists usually ignore them (Cohn 2007: 17, 49, 335). Many heterodox
economists are uneasy about the cultural and social implications of inhibiting free access to
knowledge and information by society at large. Many philosophers find that privatizing and commercializing the results of scientific researchparticularly patenting the results of researchis
both epistemically and socially detrimental due to similar concerns (Biddle 2012).
The only epistemically and socially beneficial solution to the tragedy of the anticommons in
knowledge lies in a return to a tradition of the commons. Historically in the United States the
commons has most often referred to shared spaces that allow for free speech and the democratic
process, most notably the New England town commons (Hess and Ostrom 2006). This is the
focus of Benklers commons-based production of open science, open libraries, and collaboratories (Hess and Ostrom 2006; Benkler 2004). In other words, the solution to the tragedy of the
knowledge anticommons lies in its dual concept, the knowledge commons, that is the effort to
create, expand, and protect knowledge commons.
At present, the term knowledge commons is only loosely defined, ranging from jointly
owned intellectual property to public property and the public domain. The mainstream argues
that the term, when used within the intellectual arena to frequently refer to the knowledge environment for free speech, universal open access, and self-governance, is only a battle cry (Hess
and Ostrom 2006). Research on how to create and nurture a knowledge commons, however, is
well underway in the United States.16 Regretfully, in China almost no attention has been paid to
the knowledge-commons movement in the United States. As I pointed out in Zhou (2011), [v]
ery few people in China have the courage to doubt or oppose the accepted doctrine of intellectual
property rights and the legal system of intellectual property rights as a whole from the philosophical, political, economic, and jurisprudence angles. Unfortunately, the dogma of intellectual property rights prevalent in the United States is now in an even more dominant position
within the intellectual arena in China than in the United States.
In this article, I use the term knowledge commons to refer to a knowledge environment of
freedom in knowledge development and universal open access, and argue that development of the
knowledge commons thus defined is the epistemically and socially beneficial solution to the tragedy of the knowledge anticommons. The knowledge commons is essentially distinct from naturalresource commons in that, as many scholars mentioned, knowledge in the knowledge commons,
as a universal public good, is both nonexclusionary and nonrivalrous, while resources in naturalresource commons are more or less nonexclusionary but rivalrous (Hess and Ostrom 2006).
It is both nonexcludability and rivalrousness that together cause a natural-resource commons to
be prone to the tragedy of overuse. According to Hardin (1998), there are either unmanaged commons or managed commons. For an unmanaged commons, [a]s overuse of resources reduces carrying capacity, ruin is inevitable. For a managed commons, it describes either socialism or the
privatism of free enterprise. Either one may work; either one may fail: The devil is in the details.
Actually, however, the privatism of free enterprise will almost never work. This is because
the equilibrium under either the single ownership or the fragmented ownership in an anticommons as a result of privatization of a commons, or under the cooperation between
16Hess and Ostrom (2006) wrote that [t]he exploration of information and knowledge as commons is still
in its early infancy. Nevertheless, the connection between information in its various forms and commons in its various forms has caught the attention of a wide range of scholars, artists, and activists. The
information-commons movement emerged with striking suddenness. Before 1995, few thinkers saw the
connection. It was around that time that we began to see a new usage of the concept of the commons.
They (2006) also wrote that [i]n the mid-1990s, articles suddenly started appearing in various disciplines
addressing some aspect of this new knowledge commons and that [t]he largest wave of new-commons
exploration appeared in the legal reviews.

Downloaded from rrp.sagepub.com at Glasgow University Library on May 4, 2016

166

Review of Radical Political Economics 48(1)

multiple rational, self-interested owners (users) in a commons, will almost always deviate from
the efficient point, as shown in Figure 1 (without considering the pervasive externalities) in
Coloma (2003).
As for socialism, Hardin may be right: it may work; it may fail. It will be what Hess and
Ostrom (2006) called the tragicomedy of the commons. Retaining the resource as common
property and locking multiple users together may reinforce communitarian and non-utilitarian
values, which are hard to quantify in monetary terms (RSAS 2009; Heller 1998: note 17; Heller
2008: 46). Carol Rose, Elinor Ostrom, and others have shown how the users sometimes create
their own system of governance to manage common property efficiently, which Rose called the
comedy of the commons (Heller 1998: note 17; RSAS 2009; Heller 2008: 46, 214).17 However,
there are still many situations in which collective actions are virtually ineffective.18 Likewise,
whether or not state-owned enterprises (SOEs) could play an important role in avoiding or overcoming the tragedy of the natural-resource commons is also a difficult, unresolved problem,
though it is worth exploring.19 All in all, there is no one solution to all commons dilemmas
(Hess and Ostrom 2006).
By contrast, there is one solution to all knowledge anticommons dilemmas: provision of an
environment called knowledge commons. It is both nonexcludability and nonrivalrousness of
knowledge in the knowledge commons that make it impossible to cause the tragedy of overuse.
On the contrary, the more people who share useful knowledge, the greater the common good
(Hess and Ostrom 2006).
The utilitarian dogma of an incentive-access tradeoff is not true. Free access to knowledge
will not be a disincentive to the creation of inventions and literary and artistic works. The real
incentives for human knowledge creation are not financial as assumed in an intellectual property
regime. The quest for knowledge is rooted in human nature. Ultimately, people produce knowledge for the same reason that a silk worm produces silk (Marx 1862-1863: addenda to part I).
Natural incentives and passions for knowledge creation exist among pure (basic) researchers,
artists, and numerous others conducting applied research in academic communities and elsewhere. A striking instance is the flourishing free software/open source movements, which have
spread into the direct production process (See Zhou 2010, 2011).
In this emerging new era of technocapitalism, technocapitalist corporations are heavily dependent on the appropriation of intellectual creativity as intellectual property (Suarez-Villa 2009).
Actually, the current intellectual property regimes may impede both sustainability-enhancing
innovations and knowledge dissemination (Henry and Stiglitz 2010) and distort research toward
17By

contrast, Ostrom pointed out many cases in which governmentally imposed restrictions were counterproductive and central government intervention had created more chaos than order (RSAS 2009).
18Particularly, locally evolved institutional arrangements governed by stable communities often fail when
rapid change occurs (Dietz, Ostrom, and Stern 2003), and the cooperative mechanisms which have been
proven successful in small-scale, local commons may break down if they are employed to solve the problems of larger and even global commons, such as critical problems of transboundary pollution, tropical
deforestation, and climate change (Heller 2008: 25; RSAS 2009; Dietz, Ostrom, and Stern, 2003; Stavins
2011).
19For citizens of a particular country, SOEs are something like what Aristotle described as property belonging to them, not severally but collectively, and the mainstream economists seem to consider the SOE
dilemma as similar to the situation in which, as Aristotle described, [e]ach citizen will have a thousand
sons who will not be his sons individually but anybody will be equally the son of anybody, and will therefore be neglected by all alike (Aristotle n.d.: book 2). Heller (2008: 34) argued that [i]n recent years, state
property has become less central as a theoretical category and that [i]n a sense, state property has lost its
special character. But, so far as I know, that is not the case at least in China, the worlds most populous
country and second largest economy, and outside China, at least the World Bank has not become less interested in the state property in China (for example, Wei 2012; Flanagan 2012; Back 2012). For my opinion on
the SOEs in China, see Zhou (2009).
Downloaded from rrp.sagepub.com at Glasgow University Library on May 4, 2016

167

Zhou

unsustainable projects. The commodification of intellectual creativity entails wholesale dispossessions (Harvey 2003).20
According to Henry and Stiglitz (2010), experience with genetically modified organisms
shows that an open source model of research and production markedly different from the more
traditional models based on protection of intellectual property is more likely to bring wider social
benefits, both in the short and the long run. Williamss (2013) empirical study also suggested that
the private firm Celeras short-term gene-level IP had persistent negative effects on subsequent
innovation relative to a counterfactual of Celera genes having always been in the public domain.
While Williams (2013) claimed that as Celeras gene-level IP did not depend on patent protection, . . . [t]o the best of my knowledge, there exists no direct evidence on how gene patents
have affected subsequent product development, Bessen and Maskins (2006) sequential model
showed that patents may inhibit sequential and complementary innovation while imitators can
provide benefit to both the original inventor and to society more generally. They (2006) noted
that it is in industries like software or computers that innovation is both sequential and complementary. Actually, however, sequentiality and complementarity is the very essence of almost all
activities of knowledge creation.21 Therefore, patents will be counterproductive in almost all
industries, in which innovation is always sequential and complementary (Bessen and Maskin
2006; Landes and Posner 2003: 326, 327, 366).
Bessen and Maskins (2006) sequential model showed that in a regime with patent protection,
the threshold at which a firm with a higher cost does R&D when it has no patent is less than that
at which the firm with a patent does R&D.22 In the United States, the firms that obtained the most
software patents actually reduced their R&D spending relative to sales after patent protection
was strengthened. In Japan, there was no concomitant increase in R&D or innovation after the
Japanese patent system was significantly strengthened starting in the late 1980s. These results are
quite consistent with the sequential model of innovation, but are difficult to reconcile with the
orthodox incentive theory of patents (Bessen and Hunt 2004; Bessen and Maskin 2006). Bessen
and Maskins (2006) sequential model also showed that expected net social welfare will most

20Once again, I thank two of the reviewers of this article for their respective suggestions that I pay attention
to the related works of Joseph Stiglitz and David Harvey.
21In Bessen and Maskins (2006) sequential model, in which there is an industry consisting of two (ex ante
symmetric) firms, and for each invention a firms cost of R&D is either C = c (with probability q) or C =
0 (with probability 1 q) (here the smaller realization was chosen by them to be zero merely for analytic
convenience and they noted that all the results hold with a positive lower cost), the sequentiality of innovation is represented by assuming that there is an infinite sequence of potential inventions (indexed by t = 1,
2, ...), each of which has direct social value v drawn from c, d, f, F(v), and that if invention t has not yet
been discovered, then there is no chance that innovation t + 1 will be developed, and the complementarity of innovation is represented by assuming that p1, the probability that innovation t + 1 is discovered
conditional on the current invention t having already been discovered, if just one firm undertakes R&D, is
smaller than p2, the corresponding conditional probability that at least one firm will discover innovation t +
1, if both firms undertake R&D.
22Bessen and Maskins (2006) sequential model showed that in a regime with patent protection, v00 {= [1
.5
2q(1 q)p1 (1 q)2 p2]c / [qp1 + 12 (1 q)p2]}, which represents that if neither firm yet has a patent,
the aggressive firm 1 will invest in R&D if its cost is c and v > v00.5, is less than v00.75 {= [1 2q(1 q)p1
(1 q)2 p2]c / ( 12 p2)}, which represents that if neither firm yet has a patent, the passive firm 2 will also invest
in R&D if its cost is c and v > v00.75, and the model also showed that v00.75 is less than v00
{= [1 2q(1 q)p1
1.5
(1 q)2 p2]c / [qp1 + (1 q)(p2 p1)]}, which represents that a firm with a patent will invest in R&D with
a cost of c if v > v00
, provided that q is sufficiently small.
1.5

Downloaded from rrp.sagepub.com at Glasgow University Library on May 4, 2016

168

Review of Radical Political Economics 48(1)

likely be higher in equilibrium without patent protection than in equilibrium with such protection
and that this result holds even with substantial dissipation of rents in the no-patent case.23
These heterodox results with respect to patents in Bessen and Maskin (2006) have been corroborated by similar results on the copyright side in Zhou (2013). A sensible modification by
Zhou (2013) to Landes and Posners (2003) copyright model comes to the conclusion: an
increase in the level of copyright protection reduces the total number of copies of a single work
sold, reduces the net economic welfare generated by a single work, and reduces the total welfare
generated by equivalent works.24
These and some other heterodox research results are contributing to a theoretical foundation
for the creation, expansion, and protection of knowledge commons as the solution to the tragedy
of the anticommons in knowledge, taking into consideration the dynamic nature of knowledge
and the effects of knowledge spillover.

5. The Comedy of the Knowledge Commons: A Simple Model


In this section, I will construct a simple model based on Bessen and Maskins (2006) sequential
model, as a metaphor for how the comedy of the knowledge commons, the ideal solution to the
tragedy of the anticommons in knowledge works. The comedy seems romantic in a society today
where even an unrecognizable one-and-a-half-second sound clip is copyright-protected (Heller
2008: 14, 207), but it can be realistic. Just think: sharing of software is as old as computers, just as
sharing of recipes is as old as cooking, the software-sharing communities existed for many years
until the early 1980s (Stallman 2007), and [u]ntil the 1970s, much biomedical research followed a
commons model, under which anyone could use research results freely (Heller 2008: 58).
Bessen and Maskins (2006) sequential model focuses on comparison between social welfare
with and without patent protection. The simple model I will construct in this section is about how
social welfare could be further improved within the knowledge commons (i.e. a regime without
patent protection), or the maximization of social welfare within the knowledge commons.
Here I denote the social welfare resulting from a spillover and diffusion of inventive and technological knowledge generated by at least one firm into the knowledge commons by F, so that
F = F [d , v2000 ( s )],

(1)
000

where d denotes the extent of such spillover and diffusion, v 2 (s) is the threshold at which the
passive firm 2 does R&D in the dynamic model with no patent protection in Bessen and Maskin
000
(2006), that is, the threshold such that firm 2 will undertake R&D with a cost of c if v > v 2 (s),
and
v2000 ( s ) =

c[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )]
s ( p2 p1 )

(2)
_

23Bessen

and Maskin (2006) proved Proposition 7 that_ [i]f the Upper Tail Condition holds for v sufficiently big and k sufficiently small, then there exists q > 0 such that expected net social welfare in the
dynamic model is _higher in equilibrium without patent protection than in equilibrium with such protection
provided that q < q and particularly noted that this result holds even for small, but positive values of s, the
proportion of a firms gross revenue in the total value v when the firm is successful in making the discovery
and there is no patent protection.
24Zhou (2013) emphasized that the concept of copyright connected with these heterodox conclusions
refers to copyright sensu stricto, which comprises a bundle of economic rights in the artistic or literary
work as focused on by the common law tradition and basically does not include moral rights of the author.

Downloaded from rrp.sagepub.com at Glasgow University Library on May 4, 2016

169

Zhou
I assume for convenience that d = 1 2s, and that equation (1) can be rewritten as
F = af ( d ) bg[v2000 ( s )] = af (1 2s ) bg{

c[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )]
},
s ( p2 p1 )

(3)

where a > 0, b > 0, f(d) 0, f / d > 0, 2 f / d 2 0, and g[v 2 (s)] 0.


In the dynamic model with no patent protection in Bessen and Maskin (2006),
000

W2000 =

sp2 v2000 qc
1 p2

(4)

000

000

where W 2 is firm 2s expected long-run payoff corresponding to v 2 , the threshold at which


000
firm 2 does R&D. Logically, the corresponding investment threshold v 2 is higher and more
000
investment in R&D will then be abandoned the larger W 2 is. The long-term welfare loss to
000
society will accelerate as a result of underinvestment in R&D therefrom, that is g/ W 2 > 0
2
000
and 2 g/W 2 > 0, because of a lost opportunity to generate positive externalities (spillover
effects) by the innovative and technological knowledge25 that will otherwise be created. Therefore,
sp2
g
g W2000
g
=
.
=
> 0,
000
v2
W2000 v2000 W2000 1 p2

2 g
v2000

(5)

sp2
sp2
sp2
2 g
2 g W2000
=
> 0.
2
2
000
1 p2 W2000 v2
1 p2 W2000 1 p2
(6)

From equations (1)-(6), the change in F, the social welfare resulting from knowledge spillover
and diffusion, with respect to a change in s, the proportion of a firms gross revenue in the total
value v when the firm is successful in making the discovery and there is no patent protection in
Bessen and Maskin (2006), which is larger the smaller d is, equals
F
f bc[1 p2 + q( p2 p1 )] g
= 2a
+
,
s
d
s 2 ( p2 p1 )
v2000

(7)26

and the second-order partial derivative of F with respect to s equals

25As Hess and Ostrom (2006) pointed out, knowledge in a knowledge commons is a universal public
good: the more quality information, the greater the public good.
26

F
f
g c[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )]
1
f bc[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )] g
=a
( 2 ) b 000
( 1) 2 = 2a +
d
s 2 ( p2 p1 )
v2000 .
s
d
v2
p2 p1
s

Downloaded from rrp.sagepub.com at Glasgow University Library on May 4, 2016

170

Review of Radical Political Economics 48(1)


2 F
2 f bc 2 [1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )]2 2 g
=
4
a

2
s 2
d 2
s 4 ( p2 p1 ) 2
v2000

2bc[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )] g
< 0.
s 3 ( p2 p1 )
v2000
_

(8)27
_

Equations (7) and (8) indicate that there exists s = s such that F( s ) is its maximum; that is, when
there is no patent protection, at some level of knowledge spillover and diffusion, the social welfare resulting from such spillover and diffusion will be maximized.
I further assume for convenience that equation (3) can be reduced to
F = a (1 2s )

bc[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )]
.
s ( p2 p1 )

(9)

Then
bc[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )]
F
= 2a +
s
s 2 ( p2 p1 )

(10)28

2bc[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )]
2 F
=
< 0.
2
s 3 ( p2 p1 )
s

(11)29

Maximization of F requires that s satisfy


bc[1 p2 + q( p2 p1 )]
F
= 2a +
= 0.
s
s 2 ( p2 p1 )

(12)

This yields
_

s=

27

1 bc[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )]
1 g
2 f bc 2 [1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )]2
+
( 2 ) 3 000 = 4a 2
2
s
( p2 p1 )
s v2
s 4 ( p2 p1 ) 2
d

2 g
v2000

29

(13)

2F
2 f
bc[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )] 2 g c[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )]
= 2a 2 ( 2 ) +
2
2
s
d
s 2 ( p2 p1 )
p2 p1
v2000

( 1)

28

bc[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )]
2a ( p2 p1 )

2bc[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )] g
< 0.
s 3 ( p2 p1 )
v2000

F
bc[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )]
1
bc[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )]
= 2a
.
( 1) 2 = 2a +
s
p2 p1
s
s 2 ( p2 p1 )
2 F bc[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )]
1
2bc[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )]
=
< 0.
( 2 ) 3 =
s 2
p2 p1
s
s 3 ( p2 p1 )

Downloaded from rrp.sagepub.com at Glasgow University Library on May 4, 2016

171

Zhou
Hence, the maximum of F is given by
F max = F ( s )
=a

2abc[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )]
p2 p1

bc[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )]
p2 p1
2a ( p2 p1 )
.
bc[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )]

(14)30

bc[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )]

2a ( p2 p1 )
In a knowledge commons, where there is no patent protection, if s < s =
,
then this indicates that though it gains from a larger rate of knowledge spillover and diffusion,
society loses to a greater extent from underinvestment in R&D by firms. For pure research (basic
research), this problem had been and can be solved by what Heller (2008: 58) referred to as a
commons model, under which the government, universities, and philanthropies pay for much
basic research and give away the results to the public. For applied research and technology innovations in the direct production process in the economy, the flourishing free software/open source
movements, which embody passions for knowledge creation, altruism, and volunteering for free
knowledge, and a new system of governance other than the market or the firm, the traditional
system of governance, are providing spiritual direction (See Zhou 2010, 2011).31
_

bc[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )]

2a ( p2 p1 )
On the other hand, if s > s =
, then this indicates that though it gains from
more investment in R&D by firms, society loses to a greater extent from a lower rate of knowledge spillover and diffusion. This situation may arise from some extent of natural monopoly in
knowledge by the firms, which is different from and usually weaker than intellectual monopoly
in the form of intellectual property. To solve this problem, establishment of alternative and competitive platforms, such as the free software platforms in the free software/open source movements, may be needed (Zhou 2010, 2011), and philanthropies such as the Bill & Melinda Gates

30

F max = F ( s ) = F (
= a{1 2

bc[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )]
)
2a ( p2 p1 )

bc[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )]
}
2a ( p2 p1 )

bc[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )]
2abc[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )]
=a
p2 p1
bc[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )]
( p2 p1 )
2a ( p2 p1 )

2a ( p2 p1 )
bc[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )]
.
bc[1 p2 + q ( p2 p1 )]
p2 p1

31Benkler wrote that production is commons-based when no one uses exclusive rights to organize effort
or capture its value, and when cooperation is achieved through social mechanisms other than price signals
or managerial directions, that [l]arge-scale instances of such cooperation are peer production, and that
[f]ree software is the paradigm of commons-based production, as is the Linux kernel for peer production
(Benkler 2004; Hess and Ostrom 2006: note 12).

Downloaded from rrp.sagepub.com at Glasgow University Library on May 4, 2016

172

Review of Radical Political Economics 48(1)

Foundation may play a crucial role in stimulating knowledge spillover and diffusion (Heller
2008: 69, 197).

6. Conclusion
The anticommons in knowledge is distinct from the anticommons in physical objects. The former
is always tragic, while the latter is not necessarily so. For society at large, the tragedy of the former will be much more tragic than the tragedy of the latter.
The neoliberal argument that single ownership is the socially optimal solution to the tragedy
of the knowledge anticommons is misleading. Actually, intellectual property per se is the very
source of the tragedy of the knowledge anticommons, and the tragedy is unavoidable so long as
the intellectual property regime exists. The only epistemically and socially beneficial solution to
the tragedy of the knowledge anticommons is to create, expand, and protect the knowledge commons. The comedy of the knowledge commons comes from the positive meta-externalities of
performance of the knowledge commons. Some heterodox formal models can be constructed as
metaphors for how the comedy works.
Hopefully, this article with heterodox results would be a piece of writing in support of the
worldwide movement for free knowledge, a new wave of which includes the Academic Spring
movement starting in 2012, the Cost of Knowledge project, and the Access2Research initiative,32
and it would also be a dissenting voice in China.
Acknowledgments
I thank the reviewers and Prof. Steve Cohn for their helpful comments and suggestions.

Declaration of Conflicting Interests


The author declared no potential conflicts of interest with respect to the research, authorship, and/or publication of this article.

Funding
The author received no financial support for the research, authorship, and/or publication of this article.

References
Aristotle. n.d. Politics. Trans. B. Jowett. A digital edition transcribed from an unknown print edition of
Benjamin Jowetts translation: http://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/a8po/ (accessed on May 29,
2012). (1st edtion of Benjamin Jowetts translation: 1885.)
Back, A. 2012. Citing 99%, protester interrupts World Banks Zoellick in China. The Wall Street Journal
Website February 28, available at: http://blogs.wsj.com/chinarealtime/2012/02/28/citing-99-protesterinterrupts-world-banks-zoellick-in-china/ (accessed on January 11, 2013).
Benkler, Y. 2004. Commons-based strategies and the problems of patents. Science (new series) 305 (5,687)
(20 August): 1,110-1,111.
Bessen, J., and R. M. Hunt. 2004. An empirical look at software patents. Federal Reserve Bank of
Philadelphia Working Paper No. 03-17/R.
Bessen, J., and E. Maskin. 2006. Sequential innovation, patents, and imitation. November 1999, revised
March 2006, available at: http://www.sss.ias.edu/files/papers/econpaper25.pdf (accessed on May 7,
2007).
Biddle, J. B. 2012. Tragedy of the anticommons? Intellectual property and the sharing of scientific information. Philosophy of Science 79 (5): 821-832.
32See http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Academic_Spring (accessed on March 10, 2013), http://thecostofknowledge.com/ (accessed on March 10, 2013), and http://access2research.org/ (accessed on March 10, 2013).

Downloaded from rrp.sagepub.com at Glasgow University Library on May 4, 2016

173

Zhou

Buchanan, J. M., and Y. J. Yoon. 2000. Symmetric tragedies: Commons and anticommons. The Journal of
Law and Economics 43 (1): 1-13.
Cohn, S. M. 2007. Reintroducing macroeconomics: A critical approach. Armonk, NY: M. E. Sharpe.
Coloma, G. 2003. Symmetric tragedies: A different approach. March 2003, available at SSRN (posted on
March 26, 2004): http://ssrn.com/abstract=520945 (accessed on August 9, 2012).
Coman, K. 1911. Some unsettled problems of irrigation. American Economic Review 1 (1): 1-19; also
American Economic Review 101 (1): 36-48, February 2011.
Dietz, T., E. Ostrom, and P. C. Stern. 2003. The struggle to govern the commons. Science 302 (5,652)
(December 12): 1,907-1,912.
Epstein, R. A. 2009. Hellers gridlock economy in perspective: Why there is too little, not too much, private property. John M. Olin Law & Economics Working Paper (2nd series) No. 495, the University
of Chicago Law School, November, available at: http://www.law.uchicago.edu/files/file/495-rae-gridlock.pdf (accessed on March 18, 2012).
Feinberg, Y., and M. I. Kamien. 2001. Highway robbery: Complementary monopoly and the hold-up problem. International Journal of Industrial Organization 19 (10): 1,603-1,621.
Flanagan, E. 2012. Chinese protester: World Bank will ruin China. NBCNews.com February 28, available at:
http://behindthewall.nbcnews.com/_news/2012/02/28/10529717-chinese-protester-world-bank-willruin-china?lite (accessed on January 11, 2013).
Gardner, R., N. Gaston, and R. T. Masson. 2002. Tolling the Rhine in 1254: Complementary monopoly
revisited. August, available at: http://www.econ.ucsb.edu/~tedb/Courses/Ec100C/Readings/gardnerTollingtheRhine.pdf (accessed on November 9, 2010).
Gordon, H. S. 1954. The economic theory of a common-property resource: The fishery. Journal of Political
Economy 62 (2): 124-142.
Hardin, G. 1968. The tragedy of the commons. Science 162 (3,859) (December 13): 1,243-1,248.
. 1998. Extensions of The tragedy of the commons. Science (new series) 280 (5,364) (May 1):
682-683.
Harvey, D. 2003. The new imperialism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Heller, M. A. 1998. The tragedy of the anticommons: Property in the transition from Marx to markets.
Harvard Law Review 111 (3): 621-688.
. 2008. The gridlock economy: How too much ownership wrecks markets, stops innovation, and
costs lives, 1st English ed. New York: Basic Books.
. 2009. The gridlock economy, 1st Chinese ed., trans. J. Lv. Beijing: China Machine Press. Trans.
from M. A. Heller, 2008. The gridlock economy: How too much ownership wrecks markets, stops innovation, and costs lives, 1st English ed. New York: Basic Books.
Heller, M. A., and R. S. Eisenberg. 1998. Can patents deter innovation? The anticommons in biomedical
research. Science (new series) 280 (5,364) (May 1): 698-701.
Henry, C., and J. E. Stiglitz. 2010. Intellectual property, dissemination of innovation and sustainable development. Global Policy 1 (3): 237-251.
Hess, C., and E. Ostrom. 2006. Introduction: An overview of the knowledge commons. In Understanding
knowledge as a commons: From theory to practice, ed. C. Hess and E. Ostrom. Cambridge, MA: The
MIT Press. Available at: http://mitpress.mit.edu/catalog/item/default.asp?ttype=2&tid=11012, http://
mitpress.mit.edu/catalog/item/default.asp?ttype=2&tid=11012&mode=toc, & http://mitpress.mit.edu/
books/chapters/0262083574intro1.pdf (accessed on January 9, 2010).
Kellner, D. 2003. Media spectacle. London and New York: Routledge.
Landes, W. M., and R. A. Posner. 2003. The economic structure of intellectual property law. Cambridge,
MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
Libecap, G. D. 2011. Institutional path dependence in climate adaptation: Comans Some unsettled problems of irrigation. American Economic Review 101 (1): 64-80.
Machlup, F. 1958. An economic review of the patent system. Study No. 15, U.S. Senate Committee on the
Judiciary, Subcommittee on Patents, Trademarks and Copyrights. Washington, DC: U.S. Government
Printing Office.
Marx, K. 1862-1863. Theories of surplus-value (vol. IV of Capital) (Part I, part II & part III), English
ed. Moscow: Progress Publishers. Available at: http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1863/
theories-surplus-value/ (accessed on January 15, 2013). (1st Progress Publishers English ed. 1963.)

Downloaded from rrp.sagepub.com at Glasgow University Library on May 4, 2016

174

Review of Radical Political Economics 48(1)

Ostrom, E. 2011. Reflections on Some unsettled problems of irrigation. American Economic Review 101
(1): 49-63.
Parisi, F., N. Schulz, and B. Depoorter. 2004. Simultaneous and sequential anticommons. European Journal
of Law and Economics 17 (2); George Mason Law & Economics Research Paper No. 03-11; Yale Law
& Economics Research Paper No. 279. Available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=388880 (accessed on
August 4, 2009).
Pindyck, R. S., and D. L. Rubinfeld. 2001. Microeconomics, 5th ed. English reprint ed. published by
Tsinghua University Press by arrangement with the original publisher, Pearson Education, Inc., publishing as Prentice Hall. (1st English ed. 1989.)
Polanyi, M. 1944. Patent reform. The Review of Economic Studies 11 (2): 61-76.
The Royal Swedish Academy of Sciences (RSAS). 2009. Economic governance. Scientific background
on the Sveriges Riksbank Prize in Economic Sciences in Memory of Alfred Nobel 2009, compiled
by the Economic Sciences Prize Committee of the Royal Swedish Academy of Sciences, 12 October,
available at: http://nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/economics/laureates/2009/ecoadv09.pdf (accessed on
October 12, 2009).
Schulz, N., F. Parisi, and B. Depoorter. 2002. Fragmentation in property: Towards a general model. Journal
of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 158 (4): 594-613; George Mason Law & Economics
Research Paper No. 02-03. Available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=300681 (accessed on August 4, 2009).
Shaw, D. B. 2008. Technoculture: The key concepts. Oxford and New York: Berg.
Singh, N., and X. Vives. 1984. Price and quantity competition in a differentiated duopoly. RAND Journal
of Economics 15 (4): 546-554.
Smith, A. 1789. An inquiry into the nature and causes of the wealth of nations, ed. E. Cannan, compilation of Smiths 5th ed. of the book (1789) (including extensive footnotes, detailing the changes undergone by the book over its five editions during Smiths lifetime, and annotated references to the book).
London: Methuen and Co., Ltd., 1904. Digital ed. based on E. Cannans 1904 edition, The Library of
Economics and Liberty, uploaded circa 2000 (only Cannans marginal notes, indexes, and contents
are not included; internal references by page numbers have been replaced by linked paragraph reference numbers): http://www.econlib.org/library/Smith/smWNCover.html (accessed on May 27, 2012).
(There were five editions in Smiths lifetime: 1776, 1778, 1784, 1786, and 1789.)
Sonnenschein, H. 1968. The dual of duopoly is complementary monopoly: Or, two of Cournots theories
are one. The Journal of Political Economy 76 (2): 316-318.
Stallman, R. 2005. Software patents and literary patents. The Guardian June 20. Available at: http://www.
gnu.org/philosophy/software-literary-patents.html (accessed on October 3, 2008).
. 2007. The GNU project. Originally published in the book Open sources, updated December 25,
2007, available at: http://www.gnu.org/gnu/thegnuproject.html (accessed on December 30, 2007).
Stavins, R. N. 2011. The problem of the commons: Still unsettled after 100 years. American Economic
Review 101 (1): 81-108.
Suarez-Villa, L. 2001. The rise of technocapitalism. Science Studies 14 (2): 4-20.
Suarez-Villa, L. 2009. Technocapitalism: A critical perspective on technological innovation and corporatism. Philadelphia: Temple University Press. Introduction: http://www.temple.edu/tempress/chapters_1800/2039_ch1.pdf (accessed on September 19, 2013).
Thucydides. n.d. The history of the Peloponnesian War, trans. R. Crawley. A digital ed. transcribed from
an unknown print ed. of R. Crawleys translation: http://www.gutenberg.org/files/7142/7142-h/7142-h.
htm (accessed on May 28, 2012). (1st ed. of R. Crawleys translation 1874.)
Wei, T. 2012. SOE reform not easy, says World Bank report. China Daily March 1. Available at: http://
www.chinadaily.com.cn/cndy/2012-03/01/content_14726598.htm (accessed on January 9, 2013).
Williams, H. L. 2013. Intellectual property rights and innovation: Evidence from the human genome.
Journal of Political Economy 121 (1): 1-27.
Zhou, Y. 2009. The state-owned economy: Hope & fear. (In Chinese.) Fudan Journal (Social Sciences)
supplement: 93-97.
. 2010. A challenge to the intellectual property rights: An economic study of the free software movement. (In Chinese.) Shanghai: Truth & Wisdom Press.
. 2011. Against intellectual monopoly: Free software in China. World Review of Political Economy
2 (2): 290-306.

Downloaded from rrp.sagepub.com at Glasgow University Library on May 4, 2016

175

Zhou

. 2013. A modification to Landes and Posners copyright model and economic implications. The first
version (in Chinese), November 7, 2010, published in Research on Financial and Economic Issues, (in
Chinese,) Number 5, supplement, 2013 (May 2013): 26-30; the second version (in English), March 12,
2012; the third version (in English), May 5, 2013.

Author Biography
Yi Zhou is an associate professor of Political Economy in the Department of Economics at Fudan University,
Shanghai, China. He received his PhD in Economics at Fudan University. He was a Visiting Fellow in the
Department of Economics at Harvard University, September 2003-July 2004. He has written or published
many heterodox economics articles and essays (mostly in Chinese), and a heterodox book, including The
state-owned economy: Hope & fear (in Chinese, 2009), A challenge to the intellectual property rights: An
economic study of the free software movement (book, in Chinese, 2010), and Against intellectual monopoly: Free software in China (in English, 2011).

Downloaded from rrp.sagepub.com at Glasgow University Library on May 4, 2016

Você também pode gostar