Você está na página 1de 34

HART AND RAZ ON THE NON-INSTRUMENTAL MORAL VALUE OF THE RULE OF LAW: A

RECONSIDERATION
Author(s): MARK J. BENNETT
Source: Law and Philosophy, Vol. 30, No. 5 (September 2011), pp. 603-635
Published by: Springer
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/41487002
Accessed: 15-08-2016 15:17 UTC
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Law and Philosophy

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Law and Philosophy (2011) 30:603-635 Springer 2011

DOI 10.1007/S10982-01 1-9106-1

MARK J. BENNETT

HART AND RAZ ON THE NON-INSTRUMENTAL MORAL


VALUE OF THE RULE OF LAW: A RECONSIDERATION

(Accepted 5 May 2011)

ABSTRACT. HLA Hart and Joseph Raz are usually interpreted as being

mentally opposed to Lon Fuller's argument in The Morality of Law

principles of the rule of law are of moral value. Hart and Raz are though

the 'instrumental objection', which says that these principles are of no m


because they are actually principles derived from reflection on how to

the law to guide behaviour. Recently, many theorists have come t


defence against Hart and Raz, refuting the 'instrumental objection' and

the non-instrumental moral value of conformity to the principles of leg

article argues that although this moral value should be affirmed, the

view is incorrect, because Hart and Raz never understood their argume

the instrumental or 'purposive' value of the principles of legality as denial

moral value, as a close reading of their work shows.


I. INTRODUCTION

Is conformity to the principles of the rule of law of moral valu

L. Fuller is famous for arguing that it is. His discussion

'internal morality of law' has received much attention recent


a number of prominent legal theorists using it as the basis f

claim that law has a necessary connection with morality

certain legal positivists acknowledge that some conformity t

1 See TRS Allan, Constitutional jusmcE: A Liberal Theory Of The Rule Of Law (200

University Press, Oxford, 2003); David Dyzenhaus The Legitimacy of Legality, in A Simpl
Lawyer: Essays in Honour of Michael Taggart (David Dyzenhaus et al. eds., 2009); N.E Simm
as a Moral Idea (2007).

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

604 MARK J. BENNETT

law principles is necessary if law is to exist,2 a

fulfilment of these principles by a legal sys


Despite this, it is often said that there is a
against Fuller's claims about the moral value

nutshell, that argument states that conformit

the rule of law is not in itself morally valu


ciples merely allow the law to more effect
ultimate goals the law-maker is aiming at. H

identified as having provided the canon

'instrumental objection', thereby showing th


rule of law is of no moral value.4

This article shows that the orthodox inter


Raz's view of the moral value of conformit

incorrect and cannot withstand a close reading

fact, Hart and Raz substantially agree with Fu

moral value, both in terms of the existence

in terms of its basis in human autonomy. Th


be challenged because it is incorrect and mis

both suggestions of controversy where none e

the important differences that remain betw

tion. I begin by briefly setting out Fuller's vie

its moral value in order to show the basic


are engaging with. Next I describe the orth
Hart and Raz's critique of Fuller in greater d
arguments are generally understood in the
that while Hart's critique of Fuller's idea of
law' was trenchant, he never argued that co

ples of the rule of law was of no moral

discussed conformity with the rule of law, he

2 Matthew Kramer, Objectivity aND tHE Rule of Law ch. 2 (200


of Pluralism ch. 1 (2007).

3 Marmor, supra note 2, at ch.l & Andrei Marmor, The Ideal of


Southern California Legal Studies Research Paper No. 09-6, 2008), a
sol3 /papers.cfm?abstract_id= 1 106243 .

4 By 'no moral value' I mean 'no non-instrumental moral valu


mentators have accepted that Hart and Raz think that conform

instrumental moral value where it helps to make more efficacious


substantive goals of the law. As I explain below, instrumental mor
conformity with the rule of law because it depends on the law h
goals. The moral value that Fuller identified and Hart and Raz are
because it exists wherever there is conformity with the rule of la
mental' to distinguish it from 'instrumental' moral value, but I pr
to use 'instrumental' to signal the difference.

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

HART AND RAZ ON THE RULE OF LAW 605

morally valuable results. Finally, I show that even thou

commonly understood as taking up and clarifying the 'ins


objection', he too never argues that the rule of law is of

value. When his famous article on the topic is read car


becomes clear that Raz saw the rule of law as a moral ideal that

secures human dignity through respecting human autonomy, and


that the arguments in the latter parts of his article are not meant to
deny this. Unfortunately, none of this is appreciated by the orthodox
interpretation of Hart and Raz's arguments, and therefore this article

seeks to put an end to this pervasive misinterpretation.


II. FULLER'S INTERNAL MORALITY OF LAW

Fuller's famous argument is familiar to all students of legal phil

ophy, and it cannot be set out here in more than an outline. Full

identifies an 'internal morality of law', a set of principles that must

fulfilled before law can be said to exist. These principles are generall

referred to today as principles of 'legality' or 'the rule of law'.


recounts the story of King Rex, who, because of his failure to co
form to the internal morality, failed to make law.5 For exampl
Rex's enforcement of his 'law' does not conform to the rules he has

laid down, and he makes his commands extremely ambiguously or


inaudibly.6 This is not just bad law, or bad lawmaking. It is not
lawmaking at all:7
Law, considered merely as order, contains, then, its own implicit morality. This
morality of order must be respected if we are to create anything that can be called
law, even bad law.

the internal morality of law itself.

If we recognize this we can ask, for example,


degree a legal system existed in Nazi Germany

Lon L Fuller, Positivism and Fidelity to Law - A Reply to Professor H

(1958); Lon L Fuller, The Morality of Law 214 (Rev.ed, 1969) at 3

6 Lon L Fuller, Positivism and Fidelity to Law - A Reply to Professor H


(1958).
7 Fuller, Positivism and Fidelity to Law, supra note 5, at 645; Fuller, The Morality of Law, supra note
5, at 38-41.

8 Fuller, Positivism and Fidelity to Law, supra note 5, at 646.

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

606 MARK J. BENNETT

How much of a legal system survived the general de

all forms of social order that occurred under Nazi ru


tions this mutilated system had for the conscientiou
under it.

Hart's mistake, Fuller argues, is to think tha


status of Nazi law as law must be Gustav Ra
unjust law is not law.9 Radbruch, a German ju

the Nazi rule, argued that law that reach


injustice was not law. Hart directed his ar

position, which in Fuller's view resulted in H


idea that law that disregards the internal m

really be said to be law.10 The Nazis' resor

secret laws, to the disregard of the law by th

the perversion of the law by those interpret


down in the internal morality of law.11 Such
merely mean that the law is extremely bad

at all:12

To me there is nothing shocking in saying that a dictatorship which clothes itself


with a tinsel of legal form can so far depart from the morality of order, from the
inner morality of law itself, that it ceases to be a legal system ... [I]t is not hard for

me, at least, to deny it the name of law.

Conformity with the principles of the rule of law is a condition of the

existence of legal system.


Fuller elaborated on these principles in The Morality of Law, noting

that they require that laws should be: '(1) general; (2) [promulgated];
(3) prospective, not retroactive; (4) clear and understandable; (5) free

from contradictions; and they should not (6) require what is


impossible; (7) be too frequently changed; finally (8) there should be
congruence between the law and official action'.13 Failure to conform to these principles 'does not simply result in a bad system of
law; it results in something that is not properly called a legal system

9 Gustav Radbruch, Statutory Lawlessness and Supra-Statutory Law (1946) 26 Oxford J. Legal Stud. 1
(2006V

10 Fuller, Positivism and Fidelity to Law, supra note 5, at 650.


11 Id. at 650-655.
12 Id. at 660.

13 As concisely stated by Hart: HLA Hart, Essays n Jurisprudence aND Philosophy 347 (1983).

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

HART AND RAZ ON THE RULE OF LAW 607

at all'.14 In Fuller's view, total disregard for the intern


incompatible with the existence of law.

Fuller also further explained why these principles a


valuable: they maintain 'a kind of reciprocity between

and the citizen. . . Government says to the citizen in effec

the rules we expect you to follow. If you follow them,


assurance that they are the rules that will be applied
duct'".15 Reciprocity therefore means that the governm

the rule of law and, in return, citizens obey the law.16 Fu

that this reciprocity was the basis of the social practic

actions that were necessary to create a flourishing, w


order. The principles of the rule of law are the found
relationship of reciprocity, and they are built on an 'im

man': 'man is, or can become, a responsible agen

understanding and following rules, and answerable for his

Law is an enterprise that respects people's dignity as self-

agents, not a 'one-way projection of authority'.18 Ful

standing of the ideas of reciprocity and autonomy is comp

the purposes of this article we can sum it up by saying

of law is morally valuable because it allows people

advance what behaviour the government demands of


make plans secure in the knowledge that those rules w

to their conduct.

III. THE ORTHODOX INTERPRETATION OF HART

AND RAZ'S CRITIQUE OF FULLER

Fuller's view is often challenged by saying that his idea of

internal morality identifies principles of effective law-making, rat

than principles that are of any moral value. As Marmor pu

'Some prominent legal philosophers . . . maintain that the value


associate with the rule of law are not moral values; they do not

14 Fuller, The Morality of Law, supra note 5, at 39.


5 Id. at 39-40.

16 For further discussion of Fuller's ideas of reciprocity and autonomy and application to a real s
situation, see Colleen Murphy, Loti Fuller and the Moral Value of the Ride of Law 24 Law & Phi

17 Fuller, The Morality of Law, supra note 5, at 162.


18 Id. at 207.

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

608 MARK J. BENNETT

the law good in any moral-political sense,


good'.19 This argument that the rule of law

value, but only functional or instrumental valu

rejected, with many commentators now sid


his critics on this point. For example, MacC
vious view that conformity with the rule o

tral':20

At one time, I was inclined to agree with H.L.A. Hart that Fuller's principles, even
if in some measure essential to the existence of legal systems as systems of rules,
are merely technical requirements of legal efficiency, not any sort of 'morality'.
For they appear to be in themselves morally neutral. . . . [However, a] claim (such
as Hart makes) that legality is mere efficiency could very properly be disputed[.]

Similarly, Waldron has recently argued that Hart's response to


Fuller's views on the rule of law evaded a proper examination of the
connections between the rule of law and the concept of law, and of
the moral value of the rule of law.21 Waldron argues that Hart was
not completely mistaken in his understanding of the moral value of

the rule of law, but that he was equivocal and intellectually dishonest: Hart sometimes acknowledged the rule of law's moral value,
but sought to downplay or deny it elsewhere because of the threat
that it posed to his legal positivism.22 The argument is that Fuller got

something right that legal positiviste ought to recognise rather than


deny for the sake of some dogmatic version of the thesis that law has

no necessary moral value.23 Alongside Hart, Joseph Raz is supposed

19 Andrei Marmor, The Ideal of the Rule of Law 5 (University of Southern California Legal Studies
Research Paper No. 09-6, 2008), available at http:/ /papers.ssrn.com/sol3 /papers.cfm?abstract_id=
1106243.

20 Neil MacCormick, Natural Law and the Separation of Law and Morals, in Natural Law T
Contemporary Essays 122-124 (Robert P George ed., 1995).

21 Jeremy Waldron, Positivism and Legality: Hart's Equivocal Response to Fuller 83 N. Y. U. L. Re

(2008).
22 Waldron is self-admittedly 'hard' on Hart, accusing him of having 'honest' intellectual inclinations
to agree with Fuller on the morality of legality, but deliberately (and intellectually dishonestly) seeking
to hide this: Id. at 1159. He also argues that 'Hart's treatment of Fuller gives standards of analytic clarity

in legal philosophy a bad name'. Id. at 1157.


Jeremy Waldron Hart and the Principles of Legality, in The Legacy of HLA Hart 60 (Matthew
Kramer et al, eds. 2008): 'For [Hart] the issue was a defensive one, to block a real or imagined assault

upon the Maginot line of positivist jurisprudence - the separation of law and morality'. See also
Simmonds, supra note 1, at 70-71. Some legal positiviste deny their allegiance to a complete denial of
any connection between law and morality - Joseph Raz, Practical Reason aND Norms 165-70 (2d ed.
1990); John Gardner, Legal Positivism: 5 Vz Myths 46 Am. J. Juris. 199 (2001); Leslie Green, Positivism and

the Inseparability of Law and Morals 83 N. Y. U. L. REV. 1035 (2008).

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

HART AND RAZ ON THE RULE OF LAW 609

to offer an equally powerful denial of the moral value of the rule


law in his noted essay on 'The Rule of Law and Its Virtue'.24

The argument that Hart and Raz are commonly said to mak

runs as follows. The rule of law is not, in itself, of any moral value: it

is a set of 'instrumental' or 'functional' principles that allows law


more effectively and efficiently perform its function, that function

being the guidance of behaviour through general norms. All

instruments or tools are used to achieve certain ultimate ends. A

instrument's function is the specific means by which it achieves i


end. An instrument's instrumental or functional virtue is that set

attributes or principles that best allows it to perform its function. Fo

example, a knife is an instrument that has the function to cut. Th


ultimate end to which it is put is to separate some physical matte

Therefore, the instrumental virtue of knives is sharpness, for that is

what allows the knife to separate matter effectively.25 We u

instruments such as knives and law to pursue certain ultimate aim

through particular means or ways related to the function of the


instrument. In other words, the instrument furnishes us with a w

of achieving a goal, and its instrumental virtue tells us what the


instrument should be like if it is to achieve that goal effectively

through the use of that instrument. If you want to rule through law,
you look for different instrumental virtues than if you want to rule
through terror.

On this instrumental view, law's function is to guide huma


behaviour by general norms or rules. The virtue that allows law

best achieve its function is 'formal legality', the principles of the rule

of law - in Fuller's terms, conformity to the principles of the intern

morality of law. The internal morality identifies those principles that

make law best perform its function as an instrument, so as

effectively and efficiently achieve whatever substantive end or go

to which it is directed.26 What Fuller identifies, on this view, are the

principles that make law best achieve its function of guiding hum
24 Joseph Raz, The Rule of Law and its Virtue, in The Authority of Law (1979).

25 The choice of which instrument to use and its instrumental virtue all depends on one's ultim

ends: if one is ultimately trying to separate a tree from its stump, a sharp knife is not effective.
should use an axe or a saw, which have their own particular way of 'cutting' and some additional
distinct virtues - heaviness and rigidity for the axe, lightness and flexibility for the saw - beyon
sharpness: Jeremy Waldron Why Law - Efficacy, Freedom, or Fidelity? 13 Law C Phil. 259, 261-262 (19

HLA Hart, Essays n Jurisprudence aND Philosophy 347 (1983); Ronald Dworkin, Philosoph
Morality and Law - Observations Prompted by Professor Fuller's Novel Claim 113 U. Pa. L. Rev. 668,
(1965).

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

610 MARK J. BENNETT

behaviour by rules, and therefore allow law

whatever ends that the lawmaker is aimi


morality should be avoided except at the

ultimate ends that are being pursued. There


cutting vegetables and cutting people,27 and
conduct to achieve benevolent goals and ma

conformity to the rule of law is of any moral

the substantive aims being pursued, not

value. If the aims of the law are good, then co

law will aid the efficacious achievement of


aims, and therefore 'instrumental' moral v

such conformity. But this moral value is conti

put to good substantive purposes, which me


the rule of law does not necessarily secure a

Any suggestion that there is some 'non-ins


inherent in law and its instrumental princ

rather than clear thinking. This line of argum

appropriate counter to Fuller's assertions of

might trouble legal positivism's general rej


connections between law and morality.
This interpretation, attributing to Hart an

mulation of the argument against the moral v

does not sit at the margins of our present d

law. In fact it is the orthodox interpretation o


as can be seen in a number of textbooks and ar

thought that Hart was 'intent on maintai


principles of legality represent nothing

27 There is also a difference between cutting people to harm the


28 See also Brian Bix, Natural Law: The Modern Tradition, in The

aND Philosophy of Law 81 (Jules Coleman & Scott Shapiro eds., 20

Natural Rights 274 (1980); Evan Fox-Decent, Is the Rule of Law Really

27 Law C pHiL 533, 537, 559-560 & 567; J W Harris, Legal Ph

Kavanagh aND John Oberdiek Arguing About Law 178 (2008); Andr
Limits 23 Law C Phil. 1, 38-39 (2004) & Marmor, supra note 3, at 5; C
Moral Value of the Rule of Law 24 Law 8C Phil. 239, 246-249 (2005); J
Connection Between Law and Justice (2008) 27 Law C Phil. 1, 21-23;
fn 26 C N E Simmonds, Central Issues n Jurisprudence (3d ed. 20
Fuller 37 (1984); Brian Tamanaha, The Perils of Pervasive Instrume
Tilburg University 46-47, (Vol. 1, 2005), available at http://ssm.c
note 21 C Waldron, supra note 23, at 76.

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

HART AND RAZ ON THE RULE OF LAW 611

efficiency for the attainment of governmental aims'.29 B

Fuller's theory was beset by 'an argument frequently m


that his "principles of legality" were amoral solutions
efficiency'.30 Similarly, George has argued that Raz pursu
line of argument to deflate Fuller's claim that the el

rule of law constitute an internal morality... Raz sugg


rule of law is a purely instrumental, rather than any s

good'; he goes to say that Hart and Raz 'refuse to

requirements of the rule of law any... more-than-me

mental value'.31 This is not a view limited to juri

prominent constitutional law textbook states that 'Ra


linkage between the rule of law and morality'.32
Additionally, this argument has been the basis of a
detailed recent analyses of the moral value of the r
prominent journals of legal philosophy. For example,
article, Marmor states:33

These conditions [of the rule of law] which the law must meet in or

as law, regardless of its specific contents, Fuller argued, are valuabl

in that they instantiate certain moral virtues, and therefore rend

form alone, morally valuable. H.L.A. Hart and Joseph Raz respo

virtues of the rule of law are merely functional values, not moral o

sharpness of a knife, which makes the knife a good one, so the ru

make the law good, but only in terms of its functioning as a m


control. Functional good, Hart and Raz argued, must not be conf
value.

Similarly, Murphy, in a recent discussion of the rule


value, observes that 'It is often argued that the rule
instrumentally morally valuable, valuable when and t

29 Lon L Fuller, The Morality of Law 214 (Rev.ed, 1969); see generally 200-219.

30 Brian Bix, Jurisprudence: Theory aND Context 82 (4th ed. Carolina Academi

1 Robert George, Reason, Freedom, and the Rule of Law 46 Am. J. Juris. 249,
therefore must think that Raz's position is in opposition to the following statem

requirements of the rule of law is not a morally neutral matter. . . rulers or officials h

inasmuch as these reasons are generally conclusive, a moral obligation to respect the r

rule of law'. 252.

32 HlLAIRE BARNETT, CONSTITUTIONAL aND ADMINISTRATIVE LAW 79 (5* ed. 2004).

33 Andrei Marmor, The Rule of Law and its Limits 23 Law C Phil. 1, 38-39 (2004). See also Andrei
Marmor The Ideal of the Rule of Law (University of Southern California Legal Studies Research Paper No.

09-6, 5 (2008), available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1106243: 'Some prominent legal philosophers... maintain that the values we associate with the rule of law are not moral
values; they do not make the law good in any moral-political sense, but only functionally good'.

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

612 MARK J. BENNETT

that a legal system is used to purse morally


labels the view that 'respecting the rule of
non-instrumental moral significance' the 'R
on this view, provides the paradigmatic anti
that conformity to the principles of the rul
moral value. Clearly, the orthodox reading o

they oppose Fuller by denying that conformity

any inherent moral value.


It is important to understand exactly what

to claim about the rule of law's moral value. The reference above to

'instrumental' and 'non-instrumental' moral value is necessary to


distinguish between two ways in which conformity to the rule of law

could be seen as morally valuable.36 It is often said that Hart and Raz

think that the only moral value that conformity to these principles
can possibly secure is the efficacious achievement of morally valu-

able substantive aims of the law. This would be moral value secured

'instrumentally', and it would not apply where the substantive goals


of the law were not morally valuable: as Murphy puts it, 'When the

system's aims are morally good, then the rule of law is morally
valuable in virtue of its role in promoting these aims. When the
system's aims are immoral, however, the rule of law has no moral
value'.37 Hart and Raz are said to acknowledge the instrumental
moral value of the rule of law, but not any other kind of moral value.
In contrast, Fuller clearly thinks that conformity to the rule of law

necessarily creates 'non-instrumental' moral value - value unrelated


to the substantive aims of the law - because such conformity means
that the legislator is creating law that respects people's autonomy.
The moral value that the rule of law secures is not generated by the
more efficacious achievement of the good substantive aims of the
law (instrumental moral value), but by the very fact of conformity to

Fuller's principles (non-instrumental moral value). Hart and Raz


clearly think that the rule of law is of instrumental moral value; what

most commentators mistakenly argue is that they deny that it is of


non-instrumental moral value. As stated earlier,38 1 will use the terms
34 Colleen Murphy, supra note 16, at 239.
35 Id. at 240.

This terminology is used by Colleen Murphy, supra note 16.


37 Colleen Murphy, supra note 16, at 246.

See supra, note 4.

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

HART AND RAZ ON THE RULE OF LAW 613

'moral value' and 'non-instrumental moral value' intercha


refer to moral value necessarily generated by conformit

principle of the rule of law, and 'instrumental moral value' t

moral value contingently generated when the rule of law


to the achievement of morally valuable substantive goals

In the terms introduced above, this article challenges t


held view that Hart and Raz deny the rule of law's non-in

moral value. It shows that Hart and Raz both agree wi

view that conformity to the principles of the rule of law


instrumental moral value. For Hart and Raz, conformity
value for essentially the same reasons as for Fuller: conf
the principles of the rule of law allows lawmakers to resp
dignity by respecting people's autonomy, which is possi
the lawmaker creates law that allows people to plan their
not have those plans unreasonably frustrated. Neither the

the rule of law's value to its functional or instrumental valu

orthodox interpretation suggests. Hart clearly identifies

sons for conformity with the rule of law and Raz is adamant

rule of law is a political ideal and a moral virtue. In both


are referring to non-instrumental moral value. Unfortun
are almost always presented as denying this. If we are to
analysis of the rule of law, this misattribution will have
Hart and Raz do make arguments that seem to deny t
formity with the rule of law is of non-instrumental m
otherwise, it would be mysterious why prominent legal p
would think they held this position. Hart and Raz are leg
iste, and are thus supposedly anxious to deny any necess
nection between law and morality.40 More importantly,
argue that the rule of law is of instrumental value. Hart
designating the principles of the rule of law as a 'morality
distinction between purposive action and morality,41 and
conformity with the rule of law is compatible with iniqu

argues that the rule of law is an 'instrumental' virtue of law

out principles that make law better fulfil its function o

39 I take each of these terms to refer to the same thing: what is required for somethin
knife, etc. - to best achieve its purpose or function.
40 But see, supra note 8.

41 HLA Hart, Essays n Jurisprudence aND Philosophy 350 (1983).

42 HLA Hart, The Concept of Law 207 (2d ed, 1994).

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

614 MARK J. BENNETT

human behaviour.43 Because Hart and Raz s

the rule of law, many have thought that they

to the principles of the rule of law has any


value. On this reading, Hart and Raz glimps
rule of law, but shy away from explicitly a
such an acknowledgement supposedly contr
tivist commitments. In other words, Hart a

disingenuous or wilfully blind to the implicati

non-instrumental moral value, for they clea


value, but fail to acknowledge the problem
article shows that this is not an accurate in
arguments: Hart and Raz agree with Fuller
rule of law is generally morally valuable be

value, and they do not think this is inconsisten

legal positivism.
IV. HART'S 'PURPOSIVE' CRITIQUE

Hart's critical review of The Morality of Law


statement of the instrumental objection. H
the principles as an 'internal morality' of law

preferred to use the conventional design

legality'.45 He saw Fuller's 'internal morality

craftsmanship' that state 'what is necessary fo

of the purpose of guiding human conduct by


are as suitable for achieving good aims as w
'neutral as between good and evil substantiv
Fuller's failure to make the distinction bet
and morality. He argues that we should not
principles that best allow an instrument or
purposes a 'morality', for then we would h
was an morality of, for example, poisoning.4
43 Raz, supra note 24, at 224-226.

44 This view has been suggested to me by David Dyzenhaus. S

Waldron, supra note 21, and specifically at 1159, stating that Hart go

agree with Fuller rather than to refute him, and that Hart 'take
positions.
Hart, supra note 13, at 347.
46 Id. at 347.
47 Id. at 351.
48 Id. at 350.

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

HART AND RAZ ON THE RULE OF LAW 615

the existence of internal principles guiding the efficac


ment of a purpose with a morality.
Hart's argument is understood in the literature as m

instrumental objection: because the principles are d


reflection on the instrumental virtues of law, they

valuable only where they assist the law to achieve good


aims more efficaciously. Fuller himself attributed this
saying that Hart's arguments seek to show that 'the al
morality of law is merely a matter of efficacy'.49 In
because Hart argues that the rule of law is instrumen

and not a morality, he denies that conformity with its pr


non-instrumental moral value. While this characterization of Hart's

arguments is commonly repeated, unfortunately it is only possible


on the basis of reading certain passages from Hart's review incorrectly and out of context. It is clearly incorrect when the review is
read carefully as a whole. It reads too much into Hart's arguments
about the difference between purposive activity and morality, and
neglects other passages that clearly show that Hart denied that the
principles of the rule of law were morally neutral or that conformity

with them is generally of no non-instrumental moral value. This


view also neglects the other two key statements of Hart's position,
which show that he accepted the view that the principles do secure
non-instrumental moral value despite the fact that they are at the
same time conditions for the efficacy of law. On the basis of these
latter two statements, Waldron says that Hart was equivocal about
the rule of law's moral value, and Simmonds states that it is 'unclear
whether Hart is an enemy or a friend' of Fuller because Hart 'saw
the dangers ahead' of acknowledging the existence of moral value in
the law 'and hesitated'.50 These are accusations of intellectual dishonesty against a theorist who championed clarity and accuracy.
They are not warranted, because while Hart's arguments about the
rule of law were a very small part of his scholarly concern and
output, they were neither unclear nor inconsistent.51 Hart was
clearly a 'friend' of Fuller in terms of our present inquiry, in that he
49 Fuller, The Morality of Law, supra note 5, at 200-201.
50 Waldron, supra note 21; Waldron, supra note 23; N E Simmonds, supra note 1, at 78.

51 Cf Waldron's view that Hart was 'all over the place' Waldron, supra note 21, at 1160 and
Simmonds' view was that it is unclear what Hart thinks about this question Simmonds, supra note 1, at
69-78.

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

616 MARK J. BENNETT

denied that conformity to the formal prin

only a matter of purposive effectiveness, a

non-instrumental moral reasons for suc


are as follows.

To begin, in his review of Fuller's The Morality of Law, Hart


nowhere makes the instrumental objection that conformity to the
rule of law principles is only of instrumental value and therefore of
no moral value. As we have seen, he does say that the principles can
be seen as instrumental - in Hart's terms 'purposive' - principles of
efficacy and therefore as morally neutral between just and unjust
ends. As such, they are not in themselves a 'morality' setting out a
value of ultimate importance in human life. But rather than denying
that conformity with the principles of rule of law is morally valuable,

here Hart is taking issue with what he sees as an inapt characterization of the principles of the rule of law as principles that constitute

'a morality'.52 A morality is a general theory that tells us what


actions we ought to value and what duties we owe to one another,
by reference to some ultimate value of human life. Fuller's principles

are not a morality, even though they do secure things that are of
moral value from the perspective of certain moralities, for example
those moralities that value human dignity and autonomy.
Furthermore, Hart fears that the characterization and labelling of
these principles as a morality obscures their equally important aspect, that they are instrumental principles of the law. They make the

law better achieve its purposes. This means they are serviceable for
immoral ends, and that there are prudential reasons for rulers to
comply with them. This seems like the instrumental objection, and
this is how most theorists interpret it.53 For example, after close
analysis of Hart's review of Fuller's book, Simmonds finds that Hart
insisted 'that Fuller has no warrant for treating his eight desiderata as

in any sense "moral"'.54 But this is not what Hart said. His argument
was that the principles of the rule of law are primarily derived from a

reflection on what makes law effective in guiding behaviour.


However, this does not mean that fulfilment of these principles is of
52 This is essentially the same argument put forward by Robert S Summers, Professor Fuller on
Morality and Law 18 J. Legal Educ. 1, 24-27 (1965).
53 See the materials set out above in note 32.

54 Simmonds, supra note 1, at 72. See also 74, noting Hart's 'apparent suggestion that the compatibility of Fuller's eight desiderata with wickedness shows that those desiderata are not constitutive of
any moral virtue in law'.

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

HART AND RAZ ON THE RULE OF LAW 617

no non-instrumental moral value. All it means is that t

morality. Hart says that classifying rule of law principles

morality breeds confusion'.55 This is not because conf


the principles is of no moral value. Hart's argument i
Fuller labels an 'inner morality' is derived 'not from
justice or other "external" moral principles relating

substantive aims or content, but [is] reached solely throug

consideration of what is necessary for the efficient ex

purpose of guiding human conduct by rules'.56 Seen fr


spective, the principles make law as an instrument bet
purpose or function; they are not a morality, and are n

in terms of their moral value. The knife analogy

understanding this. Although sharpness is the purposi

mental virtue of knives, this does not mean that s

morality or is morally valuable. Sharpness just allows a

or most efficiently fulfil its function of cutting. Star


function of knives being to cut, we can derive the in

virtue of sharpness; starting from the function of

behaviour, we can derive the instrumental principles o


law. To be able to say that principles derived from an
perspective are also of non-instrumental moral value, w
to move outside this narrow perspective; we would hav
independent ideals of morality - such as human dignit
utility or happiness - and we would have to show how c
the instrumental principles serves these values.

Therefore Hart's main objection to designating the p


internal morality of law' is that 'it perpetrates a conf
two notions that it is vital to hold apart: the notions
activity and morality'.57 Simmonds states that it us un

this argument is meant to show that 'we cannot infer the

an activity from its purposive nature, or whether he

that Fuller's eight desiderata of legality are in fact simple

efficacy that are devoid of any moral status'.58 Howev


that Hart's point is not the latter one that the principles

law are in no way morally valuable, or do not 'have a


55 Hart, supra note 13, at 347.
56 Id. at 347.
57 Id. at 350.

58 Simmonds, supra note 1, at 76-77.

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

618 MARK J. BENNETT

with morality', as Fuller puts it.59 There is no

the review that denies that conformity with


erally of non-instrumental moral value. Inst
the derivation of the rule of law principles f
he terms the purposive (in other words, inst

principles of law-making means that they sh


as a morality. Purposive analysis identifies

instrument or practice to best or most efficien

tion. A knife's instrumental principles inclu


does not make sharpness a morality. Purpos
morality. We can only analyse their moral

the purposive perspective and into the pe

morality.60 This is made clear in this passage


What makes a morality of aspiration into a morality is

guided by nonperemptory indicative principles toward

end is some ideal development of human capacitie

ultimate value in the conduct of life. Only if the pu

conduct to the governance of rules, no matter what the

an ultimate value, would there be any case for classif


making as a morality[.]

In saying this, Hart does not deny that the p


law might be of non-instrumental moral val
that purposive principles do not in themselv

usually call a morality,62 such as a deontolog


virtue morality, that would tell us what we o

other words, the purported 'morality of


general theory of moral values or princip

decisions or judgments. In fact, one must re

order to show that the rule of law principles ar

argues that Fuller is led by his mistaken vie

constitute a morality to try to determine whet

of duty or a morality of aspiration, whereas

ther.

" Fuller, The Morality of Law, supra note 5, at 200.


Hart, supra note 13, at 350.
61 Id. at 351.
62 See abo Ronald Dworkin The Elusive Morality of Law 10 Vill. L. Rev. 623, 637 (1965): 'I differ with

Fuller only in denying that the very abstract canons he has produced ... in and of themselves are
principles of. . .morality'.

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

HART AND RAZ ON THE RULE OF LAW 619

Hart's understanding of what constitutes a mora

contested, but in any case Hart does not deny that subj
conduct to the guidance of rules can be morally valuab

in conformity with the rule of law. Although Hart d


Fuller's principles should be seen as 'morally neutral',63

efficient instrument'64 when viewed from the perspectiv

law as effective an instrument as possible, this does n

conformity with these principles is generally morally neu

a matter of instrumental efficiency. Conformity to th

are of non-instrumental moral value, even though


moral principles. As Summers put it:65

A way to violate a moral principle is not a moral principle. In th

conditions and circumstances, we could violate a moral princ

looking out a window. But we should not be led by this to say that t

principle against looking out of windows.

This is Hars point too: rule of law principles are not


morality, but conformity with them will generally
valuable according to some other morality, and therefo
a law-maker is to conform to their moral obligations.

terms, these principles have 'contingent moral significanc

adamant that conformity with rule of law principles d


have non-instrumental moral value, as is evident in his

Fuller s suggestion that if one did not consider the princip

internal morality of law, one would have no moral


violations of those principles.67 He asks:68

Why, to take the simplest instances, could not writers like Benth

who defined law as commands, have objected to a system of

wholly retroactive on the ground that it could make no contrib

happiness and so far as it resulted in punishments would inflict u


Why should not Kelsen or I, myself, who think law may be profit
system of rules, not also explain that the normal generality of law
63 MacCormick, supra note 20, at 122.
64 Finnis, supra note 32, at 274.

65 Summers, supra note 70, at 27.

66 Waldron, supra note 21, at 1165: 'If [the positive moral difference the observance
of legality makes] were held to be true simply because the properties of a system of r

observance of the principles of legality happened to be properties that other mor

morally significant, then a legal positivist might be willing to live with that. We can c
moral significance'.

Hart, supra note 13, at 356.


68 Id. at 356-357.

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

620 MARK J. BENNETT

only for reasons of economy but because it will enab

future and that this is a powerful contribution to hu

Hart rejects what he characterizes as Fulle

other approaches to jurisprudence',69 which


a suggestion that the only way that the pri

value is if we consider them to be an intern


Hart rejects:70

The difference between the author and those he criticize

activity of controlling men by rules and the princip

efficiency are not valued by the latter for their own s

them with the title of "a morality." They are valued so

to human happiness or other substantive moral aims

Hart thus argues that, while the principles


morality', conformity with them is general
moral value due to its contribution to huma
We therefore must view the formal princi
tives. From one perspective - that of a lawm
her goals - they are principles of purposive
that of those subject to the law - they gene
mental moral value through increasing huma

Indeed, Fuller himself recognises thes


acknowledging that a ruler has prudential
the formal principles.71

This idea of a dual perspective is found


evidence that Hart thought that conform

principles was generally of non-instrument


being required for the efficacious performa
1967, two years after his review of The Mor
lished an encyclopaedia essay on the philosop
amongst other things a discussion of the 'cr
might label 'normative', 'justificatory', or 'e
Within this discussion there is a short anal
'procedural justice', or 'the rule of law'. Here
Id. at 356.
70 Id. at 357.

71 Fuller, The Morality of Law, supra note 5, at 96. Dworkin argues that Fuller 'moves from the
language of strategy to the language of morals without the slightest caesura of transition'. Supra note 13,
at 670.

72 Hart, supra note 13, at 88.

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

HART AND RAZ ON THE RULE OF LAW 621

to observe these requirements may 'cause both injusti


ery'.73 The requirements he describes are essentially Fu

ples, which 'define the concept of the rule of law'.7


describes the dual perspectives from which the princi

viewed, making clear that the satisfaction of non-instrum

value sits alongside its instrumental or efficacy value:75

These requirements and the specific value which conformity with t

laws may be regarded from two different points of view. On the


maximize the probability that the conduct required by the law w
coming, and on the other hand, they provide individuals whose fre

by the law with certain information and assurances which assist th


their lives within the coercive framework of law.

The principles are both requirements of efficacious governance by


rules, and at the same time of moral value to those subject to those
rules. 'This combination of values' is described by Hart through the
example of the requirement of generality and promulgation:76
[G]eneral rules clearly framed and publicly promulgated are the most efficient
form of social control. But from the point of view of the individual citizen, they
are more than that: they are required if he is to have the advantage of knowing in
advance the ways in which his liberty will be restricted in the various situations in

which he may find himself, and he needs this knowledge if he is to plan his life.

Here Hart again recognizes the non-instrumental moral value of


subjecting human conduct to the governance of rules that conform
to the rule of law principles: such conformity allows people to plan
their future, and to rely on the rules they use to do so, which is very

similar to Fuller's reciprocity and autonomy arguments for their

moral value.

Hart's position is made even more clear by the way that he deals
with wicked law, which he had previously used as the basis of his

dismissive comment in The Concept of Law that the rule of law


principles are 'unfortunately compatible with very great iniquity'.77

Now that he has described in more detail the moral value that is

secured by conformity to the principles, he is forced to make his


" Id. at 114.
74 Id. at 114.

75 Id. at 114-115.
76 Id. at 115.

77 Hart, supra note 47, at 207.

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

622 MARK J. BENNETT

cautionary point in greater detail as well.


position that puts him in the company of
the moral value of the formal rule of law

Care must be taken not to ascribe to these argum

prove. Together they amount to the demonstration

pursue need the various protections and benefits w

the above requirements of... procedure can effec


man, laws conferring these protections and bene

price to be paid for them in the form of limitation

freedom will usually be worth paying. But these a

not intended to show, that it will always be reason

man to obey the law when the legal system provid

in other ways the system may be iniquitous: it m


protections of law to a minority or slave class or
injustice.

Hart thus argues that conformity to the rule of law principles is


morally valuable because of its contribution to liberty and autonomy, but that this is not the only moral standard that we evaluate
law against, and thus does not settle the question of moral obligation
to a particular law or legal system. Waldron has suggested that this is

the correct understanding of the rule of law's moral value and its

relationship to questions of obedience, and that although Hart


recognised this position he failed to acknowledge it.79 But Hart does
make this argument in the paragraph cited above, based on his clear
view that conformity to the rule of law principles is morally valuable. No effort to correct Hars inconsistency is needed, for there is
none.

The reason why Hart has been misunderstood fo

probably that his view is found in its most famous a

form in the aforementioned passage from The Concept of

the heading 'principles of legality and justice', Hart ad


78 Hart, supra note 13, at 115-116.

Waldron, supra note 21, at 1161-1162: 'I have said a number of times that a pe
that legality has moral significance need not also believe that legality conclusively
of the moral quality of a given law. Certainly, he need not believe that legality co
the political obligation implied by such a law. Thus, while Hart does seem to believ
the principles of legality is compatible with great iniquity, this claim could survive a
to (2)-that legality does have moral significance-if, for example, that significance
number of factors that might enter into a law's overall moral value. Indeed, thi
consistent with quite a strong version of (2a): We might say that conformity to the
always makes things better, even though it is not necessarily capable of rescuing
iniquity of its content'.

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

HART AND RAZ ON THE RULE OF LAW 623

'may be said that... a minimum of justice is necessari

whenever human behaviour is controlled by general rule


announced and judicially applied'.80 Thus, to the degree
are applied in like cases without partiality, 'we have, i
notion of applying a general rule of law, the germ at le
tice'.81 He further observes that when a method of social

used that involves people generally following rules thro


cation of the law to themselves - with official interventi
case of breach or dispute - the rules used must82

satisfy certain conditions: they must be intelligible and within the capa

to obey, and in general they must not be retrospective[.] This means


most part, those who are eventually punished for breach of the rules

the ability and opportunity to obey.

The very idea of effective guidance by rules requires tha


sible for people to be guided by the rules. Without rules
out in advance in intelligible fashion, social control can on

there are enough officials to go around prodding each


comply with the law. Hart follows these observation
famously subdued acceptance of Fullers position:83

Plainly these features of control by rule are closely related to the req

justice which lawyers term principles of legality. Indeed one critic of po

seen in these aspects of control by rules, something amounting to

connection between law and morality, and suggested that they be cal

morality of law'. Again, if this is what the necessary connectio

morality means, we may accept it. It is unfortunately compatible wit


iniquity

Hart is observing that any effective system of governance that relies

on people applying rules to their own conduct will have to conform


to the principles of legality to some degree, and will therefore in
some way conform to these 'requirements of justice'. Conformity to
the requirements of efficacious social control by rules will lead to
some degree of moral value. Hart does not go into any detail about
what moral value is furthered by conformity to the principles of

legality; if he were pushed, he would likely have produced


80 Hart, supra note 47, at 206.
81 Id. at 206.

82 Id. at 206-207.
83 Hart, supra note 47, at 207.

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

624 MARK J. BENNETT

something like the arguments that he made


and his encyclopaedia essay, in which the '
look very similar to the argument made by
reason, Hart thought it unnecessary to exp

The Concept of Law, except through the


compliance with the rule of law principles
patible with very great iniquity'. It is unfo
extensive analysis is found in his most famo
his clearer discussions came later, provoked

of his own position in The Morality of Law. Bu

has been misinterpreted are not the concern


should be clear by now is that Hart ought n
the non-instrumental moral value of the r

inconsistent about it because of his anxi


positivism.

In itself, Hart's point - that rule of law

morality and must be evaluated against mo


and relatively obvious one that causes very
project. A charitable reading of Fuller is th

the moral value of conformity to the ru

morality that values autonomy.84 Hart cou


relatively minor nature of his objection to F
prevented Fuller and others from thinking
stronger objection that conformity to its p

valuable. To the degree that it has been

misreading, the debate on the moral value o


generated far more heat and far less light t
thermore, even if one accepts this argumen

that conformity to the rule of law is generall

not hard to agree with the view that Hart


and approach may have led him away from
In dealing with Fuller's views so cursorily in
in driving home his point about the rule of
in his review of Fuller's key book, Hart so
into the misinterpretation of his position,
examination of some of the most important
84 Fuller, The Morality of Law, supra note 5, at 162-163.

85 Waldron, supra note 21, at 1164; Fuller, The Morality of Law

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

HART AND RAZ ON THE RULE OF LAW 625

In discussions of the rule of law that proceed on the


orthodox interpretation, Hart's acknowledgment of th
in the review and his brief but perceptive analysis of t

of instrumental and moral value in his encyclopae

dormant under the weight of his arguments about the


'inner morality of poisoning'. However, Hart's view wa
buried, however, because his position is a precursor t
Raz articulates in much greater detail.
V. RAZ ON THE RULE OF LAW'S MORAL VALUE

Like Hart, Raz's views on the moral value of conformity to the

of law have also been fundamentally misinterpreted in the literatu


A recent statement of the orthodox interpretation of Raz is ma
Murphy:86
For Raz the rule of law is not morally valuable in itself. . . . Raz rejects the claim
that the rule of law has non-instrumental moral value. To the extent that a

particular society uses the tool of the law to achieve morally valuable social ends,
then the implementation of a legal system acquires derivative moral value. It then
becomes morally important to have the legal system perform its function well,
thus establishing the moral value of respecting the rule of law. However, absent
some such connection with a morally important purpose, the function facilitated
by the rule of law, namely, guiding behavior, remains itself morally indifferent. . . .

In the Razian view, then, respecting the rule of law achieves nothing of noninstrumental moral significance. The Razian view implies that saying that officials

and citizens respect the rule of law cannot in itself tell us anything morally
significant about their relationship. . . . The reciprocity and duties undermined by
the violations of the rule of law are, for Raz, morally insignificant.

This perception of Raz as representing the antithesis to Fuller's view

of the moral value of the rule of law principles has led to a lack of
engagement with Raz's actual arguments. Raz's famous knife analogy and his view that instrumental virtue is not the same as moral
virtue are often briefly set out and used as the canonical foil against
which Fuller's views can be reaffirmed. This lack of engagement
with Raz's arguments about the rule of law principles' moral value is
disappointing because he points this analysis in useful directions.

Raz's essay provides a precise and comprehensive analysis of his


view of the connections between law, the rule of law, and morality.
86 Murphy, supra note 16, at 246-249.

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

626 MARK J. BENNETT

But because Raz has been taken to be the

long, we have not benefited fully from t

Hart, if we read carefully what Raz h


instrumental moral value of the rule of

are the opposite of those that the orthod


This is because, contrary to the orthod

accepts that conformity to the formal prin

non-instrumental moral value. He states ear

is a political ideal,87 and his key arguments

value are very similar to Fuller's. He firs

ability to choose our way of life, whi

energies towards the goals that we rega


plan our actions so as to achieve our goa
frameworks of rules that enable and co

many societies the law is the most impo

However, law will only assist us in p

achieve our goals if it is 'a stable and saf

ning', which it will be only if it conforms


of law.88 There is a sense in which conform

by securing a predictable framework of


allowing us to see what our options are.
More important than the above points,
are:

90

necessary if the law is to respect human dignity. Respecting human di

treating humans as persons capable of planning and plotting their fu

respecting people's dignity includes respecting their autonomy, the

control their future.

The two ways in which violations of the principles of legal


people's autonomy are by causing uncertainty (where peop
have any expectations of the law and are thus unable to f
future) or the disappointment of expectations (where expe
stability or certainty are 'shattered by retro-active law-maki
preventing proper law-enforcement, etc.')91 While uncerta
87 Raz, The Authority of Law, supra note 24, at 210 & 211.
88 Id. at 220.
89 Id. at 220.
90 Id. at 221.
Id. at 222.

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

HART AND RAZ ON THE RULE OF LAW 627

vents planning for the future and allows for arbitrary power,

of disappointment of expectations are greater:92

Quite apart from the concrete harm [that frustrated expectations] caus

offend dignity in expressing disrespect for people's autonomy. The


cases encourages autonomous action only in order to frustrate its purp
such frustration is the result of human action or the result of the activi

institutions then it expresses disrespect. ... A legal system which does


observe the rule of law treats people as persons at least in the sense that

to guide their behaviour through affecting the circumstances of their ac

presupposes that they are rational autonomous creatures and attemp


their actions and habits by affecting their deliberations.

Raz thus argues that respect for the rule of law expresses resp

people's autonomy, thereby securing non-instrumental mo

By setting out secure guidance for human action, the l


people as 'rational autonomous creatures' who can com

rules and plan their lives in light of those rules. Note the mar

unacknowledged, similarity with Fuller's view that '[e]ver

ture from the law's inner morality is an affront to man's dig

responsible agent', as a 'responsible, self-determining cen


tion'.93 It seems that Fuller's argument about the princip
value is one of those that Raz views as 'suggestive and
because Raz substantially agrees with Fuller that the princ

non-instrumental moral value because of their contribution to hu-

man autonomy. Conformity with the rule of law does not prevent
the law from disrespecting human dignity in other ways, because law

may treat some people as subordinate or sub-human, while still


respecting human autonomy through conforming to the rule of law
principles. Or we could see the opposite situation, in which law that

is generally respectful of human equal worth disrespects human


dignity by violating rule of law principles.95 There are a number of
ways of respecting and violating human dignity, and a conscientious
lawmaker must respect each of them, including conformity to the
principles of the rule of law.
Given that Raz spends a whole section of his essay discussing and
affirming the rule of law's non-instrumental moral value in securing
92 Id. at 222.

93 Fuller, The Morality of Law, supra note 5, at 162-163.


94 Raz, The Authority of Law, supra note 24, at 223 fn 10.
95 Id. at 221.

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

628 MARK J. BENNETT

human dignity and autonomy, it may se


commentators have attributed to him th
denying any such moral value. Most likel

argument, which portrays conformity to p


virtue, which sets many commentators on
that later discussion does not retract nor contradict the claim that the

rule of law principles have positive moral value, because it is not


intended as a discussion of the moral value of the principles, but
instead as a discussion of their relation to the concept of law. Raz
argues that that conformity with the moral ideal of the rule of law is

not necessary for there to be law. Nevertheless, he claims that there


may be said to be some connection between law and the rule of law,
in that the rule of law is the 'instrumental virtue' of law - it allows

law to better serve its purpose or function. He then goes on to note


that instrumental virtues are not moral virtues, and this argument is
the one that is mistakenly read as an argument that the rule of law is

of no moral value. To make it clear why these arguments are not a


denial of the rule of law's moral value, they may be elaborated as
follows.
Raz's first claim is that fulfilment of the moral ideal of the rule of

law is not 'essential for the existence of law'.97 For Raz, whether a
system is a legal system is one inquiry, and when there is an affir-

mative answer to that question one can then examine the legal
system to see whether it conforms to the ideal of the rule of law. The

rule of law is a moral ideal that law ought to conform to, but Raz
argues that a system could violate it 'radically and systematically'
without ceasing to be law.98 Although the rule of law makes law
conform to its function of guiding human behaviour, this merely
indicates that the rule of law describes the specific excellence of law,
rather than being necessary for the existence of law, or being the
only ideal that law aspires to. In short, one can have law without
having the rule of law.
96 This is clear in Murphy's statement that 'Raz rejects the claim that the rule of law has noninstrumental moral value. To the extent that a particular society uses the tool of the law to achieve
morally valuable social ends, then the implementation of a legal system acquires derivative moral value.
It then becomes morally important to have the legal system perform its function well, thus establishing

the moral value of respecting the rule of law. However, absent some such connection with a morally
important purpose, the function facilitated by the rule of law, namely, guiding behavior, remains itself
morally indifferent'. Murphy, supra note 16, at 248.

97 Raz, The Authority of Law, supra note 24, at 223.


98 Id. at 223.

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

HART AND RAZ ON THE RULE OF LAW 629

It may seem that Raz is flatly denying Fuller's claim th


system must of necessity conform to the rule of law to
degree'.99 This depends on whether one thinks that any c
with the principles, however minimal, is also conformity
of law. Raz accepts that most of the principles that Fulle
ated could not be 'violated altogether by any legal syste
seems to be a concession to Fuller's position, a kind of we
law in which to have law there must be some minimal c
with a moral ideal, but Raz insists it is not. He observes t

the point of view of a positivist legal theory - a num

principles of the rule of law will be at least minimally fu

legal system exists. It is not that substantial conformity to p

of the rule of law is determinative of whether a legal sy


(Fuller's argument), but that the determination of whet
system exists requires enough conformity with the princ
rule of law for there to be rules. Raz's point is that this
conformity with the principles is insufficient to secure

value that is created by substantial conformity required by t

law ideal, but it is nonetheless sufficient for there to be


Therefore there is a distinction that should be drawn between the

principles as constitutive of our moral ideal of the rule of law, and


their being 'conceptual or constitutive conditions for the existence of
a legal regime'.101 This distinction is perhaps opaque, so consider this

explanation. To make a rule that can be applied, you must comply


minimally with the same principles which substantial conformity to
makes up the rule of law ideal, because someone has to be able to
apply the rule (otherwise it is not a rule). So it is clear that two
important features of legal positivist concepts of law - that officials

apply the secondary rules (rules determining how law is to be


recognised, changed, and applied), and citizens obey the primary
rules (governing human conduct in general)102 - require this kind of
extremely minimal satisfaction of the principles that any existing rule

must have. Raz notes that the positivist legal system requires judicial
" Id. at 223.
100 Id. at 223.

101 Matthew Kramer, In Defense of Legal Positivism 51 (1999). In Kramer, supra note 2, at 101-103
Kramer makes a distinction between the rule of law as the morally-neutral existence conditions for any
legal system, and the rule of law as the moral ideal that becomes possible in benign legal systems. See
also Fuller, The Morality of Law, supra note 5, at 41 for a similar formulation.
102 Hart, supra note 47, at 113.

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

630 MARK J. BENNETT

institutions, and such institutions must be

Legal systems, to be legal systems, must


and prospective rules of recognition and a
relatively clear. Because these are rules, th
mally satisfy the same principles that th
requires substantial conformity to. Even

some kind of support for Fuller's argument,

because 'the extent to which generality, c

are essential to the law is minimal and

violations of the rule of law'.104 If no-one

not really a rule, for it cannot guide any


only very few people can understand it,
applied even though it does not conform
law.

Thus, it is misleading to think of this minimal compliance with

the principles that is required to even have a system of rules as


'conformity to the rule of law'. Indeed, Raz does not speak of
minimal compliance with these principles as minimal 'conformity' to

the rule of law. A system that violates the rule of law 'radically and

systematically', while still managing to be an affair of rules by


complying at least minimally with the rule of law principles, is not a

system that is minimally 'conforming to the rule of law'. (That


would be like saying that because a blunt knife can still cut some
things it is sharp.) Raz argues that while the principles must be
adhered to minimally by any legal system, this does not give the
legal system any moral value, because these principles must be by
and large fulfilled if it is to avoid vices of arbitrary power and violations of freedom and dignity, and therefore constitute the moral
ideal of the rule of law. In other words, there is a continuum from

the most minimal fulfilment of the principles that is required to


create any rule or system of rules, through to the substantial compliance with these principles that constitutes the rule of law, which
respects human dignity by allowing planning and reliance on rules.
Only a well-ordered set of rules that substantially conforms to the
principles has the moral value that Raz previously identified as the
rule of law ideal.

103 Raz, The Authority of Law, supra note 24, at 223.


104 Id. at 223-224.

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

HART AND RAZ ON THE RULE OF LAW 631

Raz makes his argument in a way that that obscures th


point that minimal conformity to the principles is not

conformity to our ideal of the rule of law, but merely confor

the existence conditions of rules that is necessary for law to e

acknowledges Fuller's claim that '[a] legal system must of n

conform to the rule of law to a certain degree', and the furth

that this is a necessary connection between law and moralit


then makes the above move, by refraining from calling m
conformity to these principles 'conformity to the rule of l
admits that minimal conformity to these principles is nece
there to be rules, which are necessary for there to be law,

that such conformity is 'consistent with gross violations of th

law'.107 It is no virtue of law that it cannot be completely

obscure or retrospective, and that it must - to be law - h


minimal stability, intelligibility, and prospectivity. But thi

conformity to principles is not conformity to the rule of law

is a 'moral virtue... which should but may fail to becom


ity'.108 Law would not exist if minimal conformity with

failed to be a reality, but law can exist without minimal or su

conformity with the moral ideal of the rule of law.109


What Raz does in this part of his essay is to challenge to

positivist claim that he takes Fuller to be making: that th


'essential link between law and morality' because (A) the ru
must be substantially satisfied before we can say that we
and ( ) substantial satisfaction of the rule of law is a moral

However, Raz does not refute Fuller, because he posits a d

concept of law - his positivist one - which rejects A, a


requires the rule of law to be minimally fulfilled. He t

changes the question, from the morality of substantial fulfill


105 Id. at 223.
106 Id. at 223 'It is, of course, true that most of the principles enumerated. . . above cannot be violated
altogether by any legal system'.
107 Id. at 224.
108 Id. at 224.
109 CfN Barber, Must Legalistic Conceptions of the Rule of Law Have a Social Dimension 17 Ratio Juris

474, 477-478 (2004) 'Raz's dictates of the rule of law are attempts to flesh out this claim: All legal
systems must therefore comply with the principles of the rule of law to some extent, and a legal system

qua a legal system is better the more it conforms. Raz's rule of law is not just a nice constitutional
diversion, but a central feature of his understanding of a legal system'. The argument in the body of this

text is that law is does not necessarily conform to the rule of law to some extent though it does
necessarily conform to formal-procedural principles.
110 this, see Waldron, supra note 21.

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

632 MARK J. BENNETT

the rule of law (Fuller's concept), to the m


fillment (Raz's concept). From the perspecti
of law, 'Fuller's attempt to establish a necess

law and morality fails. In so far as conformity

moral virtue it is an ideal which should bu


reality'.111 This is correct from the perspe
law, but it is incorrect from the perspecti
law. Because Fuller thinks that conformity
moral virtue (B), and that the rule of law is

substantially conform to (A), it follows th


between law and morality. Raz, after succi
ment, takes a detour around it by relying on
law.

In other words, Raz's argument - that Fu


Hart or Raz's concepts of law do not require

of the rule of law - is no argument against Fu

positivist concepts that Fuller rejects. Readin

that Raz accepts this criticism - or rathe

Tucked in a footnote, he admits that he is r


cept of law, and thus is not directly assessing

However, Raz is relying on his concept rath

argument (at least in that essay), and therefor

for him to claim in the main text that Full


essary connection between law and morality
has by his own admission not properly consi
all. It may be that Fuller's concept of law s
ertheless, it is the view of many that Full

plausible alternative to theories of law th

connection between law and the moral ideal of the rule of law.

Near the end of the essay, we find another argument that seems

to mislead many readers. To not be misled, it is crucial to note


exactly what Raz is seeking to do with that argument. He is not
trying to say that the rule of law is of no moral value - 'part 2' of his

essay emphatically rejected that view. The general aim in 'part 4' of

the essay is to deny that the moral value the rule of law has is
present in all legal systems, as an existence condition of any legal
111 Raz, The Authority of Law, supra note 24, at 224.
112 Id. at 223, note 11.
113 Id. at 224.

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

HART AND RAZ ON THE RULE OF LAW 633

system. That was the burden of the previously discusse

and it is also the aim of the following argument, which ob

the rule of law is the instrumental virtue of law, but

instrumental virtues are non-moral virtues. Despite ac


that the rule of law is law's 'most important inherent v
'specific excellence of law',114 Raz goes out of his way t
the principles of the rule of law are necessarily used f
attractive ends, and are in that sense intrinsically moral
Regarding the rule of law as the inherent or specific virtue of law
instrumental conception of law. The law is not just a fact of life.

social organization which should be used properly and for the prop

tool in the hands of men differing from others in being used for a l

proper purposes. As with some other tools, machines, and instrum

not of the kind unless it has at least some ability to perform its func

not a knife unless it has some ability to cut. The law to be law mu

guiding behaviour, however inefficiently. Like other instruments,

specific virtue which is morally neutral in being neutral as to the end

instrument is put. It is the virtue of efficiency; the virtue of the ins


instrument. For the law this virtue is the rule of law. Thus the rule of law is an

inherent virtue of the law, but not a moral virtue as such.

In other words, because the law is an instrument for guiding


behaviour, the rule of law can be seen as the 'virtue' that allows that
instrument to fulfill its function efficiently - that makes law 'good'
law in the instrumental sense of 'good at achieving its aims'. 'Virtue'
here means the good-making property of an instrument, the property that allows the instrument to effectively fulfill its function; such
virtue is not 'moral' virtue.116

On the orthodox reading, this is the key statement of the


instrumental objection to the rule of law's supposed moral value. If
the rule of law is a non-moral instrumental virtue, how can it also be

a moral virtue? Perhaps Raz's answer would be to turn the question


around and ask, 'Why can't an instrumental virtue also be a moral
virtue'? Raz's essay has been seen as an antithesis to Fuller's morality

argument because people have thought Raz to be saying that the


rule of law is an instrumental virtue and therefore not a moral

virtue. He is somewhat complicit with this interpretation, as seen in


114 Id. at 225.
115 Id. at 226.
116 Id. at 226.

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

634 MARK J. BENNETT

these words quoted above: 'the rule of l


the law, but not a moral virtue as such'.1
Raz thinks that principles that are instru
moral value. That seems to be the reason
that Raz denies Fuller's argument that co
is morally valuable. But this interpretat
shown above, Raz clearly states that the r
earlier in his essay. In the paragraph th

mental virtue' argument, Raz expressly rei

is a moral virtue of law, but that it is 'not

This is because it is also an instrumenta


passage that follows the instrumental vi
that:119
The special status of the rule of law [as a non-moral instrumental virtue of law]
does not mean that conformity with it is of no moral importance. Quite apart from

the fact that conformity to the rule of law is also a moral virtue, it is a moral
requirement when necessary to enable the law to perform useful social function[.]

It is hard to see how Raz could have made it clearer that the rule of

law is morally valuable as well as instrumentally valuable. Nothing


in his instrumental argument suggests otherwise. Raz clearly believes
that the rule of law is a moral virtue - thus affirming Fuller's
morality thesis - while at the same time believing that it can be seen
as an instrumental virtue of law.
VI. CONCLUSION

The simple and confined point that this article has attempt
show is that Hart and Raz, so often cast as Fuller's critics,
took much from Fuller's conception of the rule of law. Thei

on the rule of law's content and its moral value are in essence the

same. Rather than being in opposition with one another, they are
'peas in a pod' when compared with other positions in the rule of

law literature. The rule of law's content is identified with a number

of formal principles such as prospectivity, clarity, stability over time,

etc. These principles are of moral value because they allow people to
1,7 Id. at 226.
118 Id. at 225.

1,9 Id. at 226.

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

HART AND RAZ ON THE RULE OF LAW 635

plan their lives in the knowledge of the standards that will be a


to their actions - this is value of people being treated as auton

The major difference between Fuller's position and that of H


Raz is whether the rule of law ideal is a part of the very id

concept of law. Fuller provides the anti-positivist perspecti

says that the ideal is central to the concept of law, whereas H

Raz say that the ideal is just that: and ideal to which we
whatever we identify law against. Law is law notwithstandi
violation of the ideal of the rule of law. If we are discussing
ences between Fuller and these two influential legal thinke

this 'positivism vs. anti-positivism' battle-ground on wh


debate should proceed, because they are at peace on what th
of the rule of law requires and what moral consequences follo
it. Too much time has already been wasted trying to defen
from Hart and Raz's attacks, and consequently not enough h
spent trying to integrate their insights.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

I am grateful to David Dyzenhaus and for many discussions of thi


and comments on earlier drafts of this article, to William Lucy a

anonymous referee for detailed written comments, and to Sarah

Joel Colon-Rios, Grant Morris, and Kristen Rundle for helpful com
on earlier drafts.

Faculty of Law,
Victoria University of Wellington,

Wellington 6012, New Zealand


E-mail: mark.bennett@vuw.ac.nz

This content downloaded from 196.255.240.116 on Mon, 15 Aug 2016 15:17:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Você também pode gostar