Você está na página 1de 17

This article was downloaded by:[Cabezas, Joan Manuel]

On: 9 January 2008


Access Details: Sample Issue Voucher: Contemporary Buddhism [subscription number 789377086]
Publisher: Routledge
Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954
Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK

Contemporary Buddhism
An Interdisciplinary Journal
Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:
http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/title~content=t713694869

Form and Emptiness: Aquinas and Nagarjuna


Paul O'Grady a
a
Department of Philosophy, Trinity College Dublin, Dublin 2, Ireland

Online Publication Date: 01 November 2005


To cite this Article: O'Grady, Paul (2005) 'Form and Emptiness: Aquinas and
Nagarjuna', Contemporary Buddhism, 6:2, 173 - 188
To link to this article: DOI: 10.1080/14639940500478687
URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/14639940500478687

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE


Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.informaworld.com/terms-and-conditions-of-access.pdf
This article maybe used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction,
re-distribution, re-selling, loan or sub-licensing, systematic supply or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly
forbidden.
The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents will be
complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae and drug doses should be
independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims, proceedings,
demand or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with or
arising out of the use of this material.

Downloaded By: [Cabezas, Joan Manuel] At: 09:13 9 January 2008

FORM AND EMPTINESS: AQUINAS


AND NAGARJUNA
Paul OGrady

This paper compares arguments from Aquinas and Nagarjuna on contingency and
necessity, examining the ways in which they arrive at opposed positions. However, neither
set of arguments is unproblematical and both require appeal to further positions to
support them. A curious parallelism begins to emerge between the positions when seen
with their background assumptions, despite their obvious differences.

Introduction
In this article I wish to compare Aquinass argument for a metaphysical source
of necessity in the third way of the famous five ways of the Summa Theologiae with
Nagarjunas rejection of such a position in the Mulamadhyamikakarika and assess
the relative merits of each position. However, before beginning the comparison,
I wish to discuss some possible objections to the very idea of such a project.
The notion of incommensurability has come to be used more and more in
recent times in philosophical discussions. Gaining its currency from Kuhns work in
philosophy of science where he suggests that there may be different paradigms for
scientific research which are incommensurable with each other, the term has come
to have wider use. It is used to signal a multiplicity or heterogeneity of approaches
to a thinker or topic, none of which can claim pre-eminence. So, for example, in
a recent survey of studies of Thomas Aquinas, Fergus Kerr (2002) repeatedly
notes the incommensurability of approaches taken, generally viewing this in
a positive light, as a sign of the fruitfulness and pluralism of studies in this area.
However, talk of incommensurability often comes up short when faced with
issues about truth. While difference may well be celebrated and methodological
or hermeneutical agility embraced, few enough want to commit themselves to
relativism about truth. That is, most recognise that accepting relativistic accounts
of truth leads to problems of self-refutation and self-stultification. So, to avoid that
cul-de-sac, diversity of interpretation is emphasised, which by precisely affirming
difference, avoids problems about contradiction. Things which simply differ do
not contradict each other. To form a contradiction there has to be a connection,
one has to affirm p and not-p, whereas with difference there is p and q, different
things happily co-existing.
Contemporary Buddhism, Vol. 6, No. 2, November 2005
ISSN 1463-9947 print/1476-7953 online/05/020173-188
q 2005 Taylor & Francis DOI: 10.1080/14639940500478687

Downloaded By: [Cabezas, Joan Manuel] At: 09:13 9 January 2008

174

P. OGRADY

One way of ensuring such peaceful co-existence is to emphasise the notions


of the hermeneutical and the contextual. Reading texts in context allows the
proliferation of difference, since the differences of context disallows first-order
debate between positions. So, for example, Hume comes out of an entirely
different context to that of Aquinas, and hence his concerns cant address the
same issues as Aquinas. A theologian reading Aquinas comes with different
questions and presuppositions to a philosopher, and so they have incommensurable approaches. A fortiori, Aquinas and Nagarjuna have different contexts,
different cultures, different questions, different inheritances, different presuppositions and so different positions. Therefore, on this outlook, it would be just too
crude to think of them as actually dealing with the same issue.
Overemphasising incommensurability is a generally unfruitful way of
reading thinkers. It evades the fundamental issue which motivates the inquirer,
the quest for truth. While contextualisation is vital and hermeneutical situating is
essential, these are nevertheless but preparatory for dealing with substantive
issues. General arguments for this view have been offered and I shall not rehearse
them here (see OGrady 2005). However, I believe that a specific demonstration of
the engagement of such philosophers with each other will dispel some of the
doubts deriving from considerations of incommensurability. What emerges in the
case of Aquinas and Nagarjuna is that they genuinely address the same
metaphysical issue: that both approaches fall prey to various problems, that a
curious structural parallelism emerges in their positions as they strive to avoid
these problems and that elements of Aquinass position may well prove vital to a
coherent defence of that of Nagarjuna.
In the next section I shall introduce the two protagonists, contextualising
them and providing background information for the specific debate. The third
section looks at the key point of conflict between them. Initially there is a broader
conflict of general positions which crystallises into a specific disagreement on a
basic question in metaphysics, namely whether there has to be a source of
metaphysical necessity in existence (Aquinas), or whether absolutely everything
can be contingent (Nagarjuna). After presenting the sharp clash in views, I then
want to examine various problems besetting both positions. Aquinass argument
is notoriously difficult to interpret, and I shall examine attempts to make sense of
it. Nagarjuna, likewise, lends himself to different schools of interpretation and
questions of the stability of his position arise. In the sixth section, I want to suggest
that modifications of both positions required by their internal tensions push them
both to an oddly similar sequence of metaphysical distinctionswherein the
differences between them soften, if they still dont disappear.

The Protagonists
(a) Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas (12251274) was a thirteenth-century Italian Dominican
friar who is best known for the voluminous writings he produced over a relatively

Downloaded By: [Cabezas, Joan Manuel] At: 09:13 9 January 2008

FORM AND EMPTINESS: AQUINAS AND NAGARJUNA

short career of 20 years as a university teacher in Paris and at various places in


Italy.1 He studied and taught at the University of Paris at one of its most turbulent
stages, just over half a century after its foundation. Two main opposed tendencies
in the university were a conservative religious appeal to Platonically inspired
thinking, fostered by the religious authorities and a radical appeal to an
interpretation of Aristotle, heavily influence by the Islamic philosopher Averroes,
which flourished in the arts faculty. Aquinas attempted to steer between these
two tendencies and engaged in controversies with both sides. Therefore Aquinas,
in some respects, exemplifies the Buddhist doctrine of the middle way. However,
his approach is not a kind of syncretism, seeking easy assimilation of disparate
views by blending them all together. Rather, there is a genuine openness to other
participants in the search for truth and an attempt to seek out what is true in other
positionsignoring whether they appear to be friends or foe. Aquinas notes,
just as in a courtroom you cant make a judgement until you have heard both
sides of a case; so also, if you are going to be a philosopher, you have to listen to
all the thinkers with their opposing positions in order to have more resources for
making a good judgement.2

This even-handedness goes with a tough-minded approach to the questions he


addresses. Reading Aquinas, one gets a sense of a relentless intellect making
distinctions, clarifying, arguing, seeking supporting argumentation, analysing
claims, offering reasons. The argumentation is compact, explicit, tight and has
little rhetorical excess. Using William Jamess typology of philosophical intellects,
however, this tough-minded approach is linked to tender themesthe existence
of God, free will, virtue ethics, immortality. The mode of argumentation is closer to
Russell or Ayer than to Augustine or Pascal. He combines a religious sensibility
with an analytical approach to philosophy.3
His philosophical work constitutes a genuine innovation in the history of
western thought. Sometimes derided as merely Christianised Aristotelianism,
Aquinas uses Aristotle in distinctly unAristotelian ways. His account of existence,
the eternity of the world, the virtues, the soul, while all based in a generally
Aristotelian framework, nevertheless constitute developments of Aristotles work
(see Owens 1992). A recent scholarly issue has been a re-evaluation of the role of
Platonism in his work. This comes out most clearly in his discussion of the
metaphysics of participation (dismissed by Aristotle as a mere metaphor) and in
his account of the divine ideas. Aquinas harnesses together both Greek traditions
and articulates a rational position which attempts to make sense of the JudaeoChristian worldview (see Booth 1983; Boland 1996).
Hence Aquinass work constitutes one of the classic articulations of
a philosophical theism. The account is subtle, non-anthropomorphic and
metaphysically nuanced, drawing on Jewish and Islamic sources. He presents an
account where there is space for faith to co-operate with reason, but in the
reasoned parts his claims make no special pleading. It is intended as rationally
compelling for any disinterested party. Now clearly this position doesnt have the

175

Downloaded By: [Cabezas, Joan Manuel] At: 09:13 9 January 2008

176

P. OGRADY

same force in the modern world where Aristotelianism is by no means universally


acceptedwhich has led to some curious contortions among theologians
wanting to read Aquinas as really a fideist and not attempting to offer
straightforwardly philosophical defences of his beliefs (Kerr 2002; Rogers 2004).
Finally one might note that Aquinas, as a pre-modern, appears unusually
attuned to contemporary movements in philosophy which seek to throw off some
of the more characteristic features of modern philosophy. Since he has no
investment in Cartesian subjectivity, or in solipsistic notions of the self, his views
can seem interesting to those in recovery from modernity. The agenda of his
epistemology is not set by scepticism. His view of ethics doesnt suffer from the
characteristic modern split of on the one hand having realistic psychology with
a dubious account of normativity, versus on the other a worked-out story
of normativity in a thoroughly implausible psychology. Hence a steady growth in
secular interest in Aquinass work in recent years.

(b) Nagarjuna
It is probable that Nagarjuna was a second-century Indian Buddhist monk.
Little is known with any certainty about his life.4 We do know that he wrote
a number of important textsbut issues about the exact number of authentic texts
and the status of the extant texts are fraught. Schools of Buddhist thought
distinguish themselves by their interpretations of his texts. His most important work
is called the Mulamadhyamikakarikaor fundamental verses on the middle way.5
The middle way is traditionally ascribed to the teaching of Buddha who, like
Socrates, put nothing in print. Despite many pious protestations about the inability
of putting such sublime teaching into mere human language, an enormous amount
of writing was generated by it, including philosophical treatises.6 Classical Indian
philosophy was basically characterised by systems which presented views on reality
(Brahman) and the individual soul (Atman), grouped together under the label
orthodox by virtue of their recognition of the Vedas as an authoritative vision of
the world. Buddhism was unorthodox in that it rejected any special role for
authoritative revelations, privileging individual experience, rejecting the view that
there is such a thing as the stable reality called Brahman and rejecting the notion
of a substantive self (Anatman) (see Williams 1998).
Early schools of philosophical Buddhism resembled Logical Atomism in
western philosophy (see Gudmunsen 1977). Reality was analysed into
conventional and ultimate reality. Conventional reality was a construction made
on the basis of the more fundamental atomistic realities which existed, called
Dharmas. Such Buddhist schools were called the Abhidharma and much of their
work consisted in giving extensive lists of categories of Dharmas. For such schools,
the notion of the ultmate furniture of the world made senseeven if it consisted
of a kind of Heraclitean fleeting play of atoms.
Nagarjuna inaugurated a new kind of approachdenying the very validity of
the idea of the ultimate furniture of reality. This approach was called Madhyamika

Downloaded By: [Cabezas, Joan Manuel] At: 09:13 9 January 2008

FORM AND EMPTINESS: AQUINAS AND NAGARJUNA

and it consitutes the philosophical basis of one of the two main strands of
Buddhismthe Mahayana tradition. Tibetan Buddhism and Zen Buddhism both,
in different ways, represent developments of the Mahayana ideal and see
Nagarjuna as a key figure in their development. The key idea articulated by
Nagarjuna is emptiness (Sunyata). The most salient feature of reality is this
emptinessnot substantial things, or even fleeting atoms. However, making sense
of this idea of emptiness is central to the philosophical divisions within Buddhism.
Buddhism after Nagarjuna had a flourishing philosophical diversity. Some
held that Nagarjuna advocated that the fundamental nature of reality is ineffable,
that rational thought cannot reach to it, yet non-rational, intuitive thinking, whose
best exemplars are in various kinds of meditative practice, can pierce the veil of
illusion and get to reality as it is (see Battacharya 1990). Others rejected this
approach, holding that the core doctrine is that there is no ineffable reality, that
emptiness really is empty itself and that one has to constantly beware of falling
into reifying modes of thought.7 Others still, saw Buddhism as articulating genuine
scepticism (see Matilal 1986).
One remarkable feature about Nagarjunas position is that the philosophical
positions and manoeuvres taken by him are the ones which usually characterise
militantly antireligious thinkersfor example Sextus Empiricus, Hume or Nietzsche.
He appears as a naturalistwith rejection of design, of essence, of causation, of
necessity. Nevertheless these views are articulated within a thoroughgoing
religious culture, with meditative practices, rituals and monasticism. In different
Buddhist traditions he is treated as a saint or a revered teacher of the dharma.
So there is this paradox of what is in the West extremely antireligous
thought being housed in what would be seen in the West as archetypally religious
practicereeking of what Hume disdainfully called the monkish virtues.8

The Conflict
It certainly looks, from a general survey of their work, that Aquinas and
Nagarjuna defend opposed philosophical positions. Aquinas can be characterised
as a metaphysical realist. He holds to the reality of essences, of genuine causal
powers and the ability of mind to grasp reality as it is. Nagarjunas system is much
more sceptical. His basic method of argument is the reductio ad absurdem, which
he uses against Indian realists to attempt to show the instabilities and problems
of their systems. Many of the positions he attacks are ones held by Aquinas
(i.e. attacking essences, attacking genuine causal powers).
At this general level one might be tempted to adopt the strategy outlined in
the Introduction and suggest that they offer incommensurable views of the world
and that it is an issue of tradition, training, culture or temperament as to whether
one finds Aquinas or Nagarjuna congenial. One might characterise it in the
manner that debates between theists and atheists have come to be seen in some
quarters, as expressing outlooks on the world, strategies of interpretation of
reality.9 However, such an easy resolution of the debate goes against philosophys

177

Downloaded By: [Cabezas, Joan Manuel] At: 09:13 9 January 2008

178

P. OGRADY

interest in trying to achieve a reasoned analysis of the conflict. It is a too ready


concession to a general scepticism about the possibility of achieving insight and
truth by means of reasoning. It is possible that this latter may well be the truth of
the situation (i.e. scepticism may be true)but it cannot be taken as the initial
default position. Much more work needs to be done to show that it is true and that
a resolution is not available. In the meantime it is important to try to understand
how exactly they differ from each other.
The general clash of approach concretises in a specific point on which they
hold opposed views which arises as part of Aquinass sequence of arguments for
theism.10 There is a great deal of interpretative debate as to how Aquinas actually
viewed the famous five ways for demonstrating the existence of God.11 Does he
think of them as a rational foundation for the rest of his edifice? Or are they rather
internal to a religious worldview and should be interpreted accordinglynot as
free-standing rational supports for that worldview? Are they to be construed
as original arguments or are they perfunctory presentations of what Aquinas and
his contemporaries viewed as non-gainsayable truths accepted by all rational
people? For the purposes of a dialogue with Nagarjuna I shall read them as freestanding metaphysical arguments designed to convince a philosophical opponent
of the truth of the conclusion.12
The third of the five ways is the one which is most relevant to this discussion.
Aquinas begins by noting that things in the world come into being and pass away
out of being. He then argues that everything cannot be like this. If everything were
like this, then at some time there would have been nothing. If there ever had been
nothing, there would be nothing now. Since that is patently not the case, then it
must be the case that not everything is coming to be and passing away, but there
are some things which must benecessary beings. Given such necessary things,
Aquinas asks whether this necessity comes from themselves or from another?
If from another there would be an infinite regress unless one postulates a
necessary being whose necessity is not explicable in terms of any other being.
Aquinas, as is his fashion, says this is called God. There are two main parts to
this argument. An initial stage argues to the existence of necessary beings.
Such necessity is not logical necessityit is not a covert ontological argument.
The mere existence of such necessary beings does not yield God. Aquinas accepts
a multiplicity of such necessary beingones which do not corrupt. Examples in his
worldview include the heavenly movers and rational souls. Because of their
metaphysical lack of composition of matter and form, they do not, so to speak,
have the wherewithal for corruption. He then argues that among such necessary
beings there must be one which is uniquely singled out as the source of necessity
in the others. It is that which is called God. To specify the point of conflict with
Nagarjuna, Aquinas argues that there is a unique source of metaphysical necessity
in existencenot everything is dependent.
Nagarjuna holds that the metaphysical core of reality is captured in the notion
of dependent co-origination.13 This is a way of understanding the Buddhist idea that
everything that exists is fleeting, depending on other things for its existence.

Downloaded By: [Cabezas, Joan Manuel] At: 09:13 9 January 2008

FORM AND EMPTINESS: AQUINAS AND NAGARJUNA

The central ethical teaching of Buddhism, the Four Noble Truths, holds that
suffering characterises the human condition (see Conze 1959, 186). The origin
of suffering is attachment to fleeting reality, which is doomed to disappoint us.
The remedy for suffering is the realisation of the transitoriness of all things, and the
corresponding cultivation of detachment in the face of this. Nagarjuna supplies a
metaphysical gloss on the meaning of the transitoriness of reality. His view is
that entities lack any self-existence (svabhava).14 All things are dependent.
His arguments for this position, in general, are along the lines that if you attribute
self-existence to any entity, you end up with unacceptable consequences, a classic
reductio ad absurdem strategy. What is most important about his position is that this
is absolutely general. There is no single being which escapes this transitoriness.
All beings are characterised by emptiness. And emptiness is itself emptyhe is not
articulating a kind of negative theology, where the word covers a hidden reality, in
the manner of Denys the Areopagite, for example. So Nagarjuna articulates a
position which diametrically opposes that of Aquinas. Aquinas says not everything
can be transitory and erects a doctrine of theism on this view. Nagarjuna holds that
everything is transitory, and enlightenment comes about by the personal realisation
of this truth. Lets look in some more detail at each side of this impasse.

Aquinass Realist Argument


Aquinass argument is by no means perspicuous or straightforward. It is the
focus of a great deal of interpretative controversy and there is no single clear
canonical interpretation of the argument which is regarded as obvious by most
commentators. For the sake of clarity, lets look at the argument in logical
reconstruction.
1. There are contingent things. [uncontroversial observation of the world]
2. Contingent things are such that they dont exist at some time [explanation of
contingency]

3. If everything is contingent then at some time there is nothing [crucial move]


4. If at one time there was nothing there would be nothing now. [accept ex nihilo
nihil fit ]

5. That conclusion is falseso there never was nothing. [observation and modus
tollens ]

6. If there never was nothing, then not everything can be contingent [from 3]
7. If not everything is contingent, then there is something necessary [from the
meaning of contingent]

8. Whatever is necessary derives its necessity from itself or another [truism]


9. No infinite regress of necessary beings [general argument against infinite
regress]

10. 10 A first necessary being must exist. [conclusion]


The first phase of opposition lies in challenging line 3. As it stands it contains
a gross logical errorpounced on by critical commentators such as J. L. Mackie

179

Downloaded By: [Cabezas, Joan Manuel] At: 09:13 9 January 2008

180

P. OGRADY

(1982, 89) and Anthony Kenny (1969, 56). It contains a quantifier error. The move
from everything is capable of going out of existence to at some time everything
goes out of existence is fallacious. It is analogous to making the inference from
All roads have an ending to there is one ending to which all roads lead.
Now Aquinas wouldnt have been familiar with the label quantifier error, but
would nevertheless have been familiar with the kind of fallacy involved, known in
Aristotelian parlance as the fallacy of composition and divisionwrongly applying
properties of an aggregate or group to a member of that group.15 So the question
arises whether Aquinas just simply failed to see the error, or whether there was
a deeper reason why he didnt think this move was fallaciousthat there were
hidden premises operating. Given his knowledge of the kind of error involved and
his general logical acuity, the principle of charity counsels us to look for such
hidden ways of making the argument come out as valid.
One suggested solution is that Aquinas is assuming the eternity of the world
(see, e.g. Lovejoy 1964). Given an infinity of time and a genuine possibility, that
possibility must be realised. Hence if it is a genuine possibility that everything
could cease to exist simultaneously, this would actually come about. If it didnt
come about then it wasnt a genuine possibility and its negation would be
necessary, namely it would be necessary that not everything is capable of ceasing
to exist. Such a suppressed premise would make valid the argument and get rid
of the fallacy. Unfortunately Aquinas cannot make use of such a premise, since he
actually believes it to be false. While he doesnt think there are good philosophical
reasons showing that the world is not eternal, he nevertheless holds on the basis
of revelation that the world did actually begin. Because he holds the eternity of
the world as actually false, he couldnt have it in mind as a suppressed premise
in the argument (Davies 2001).
Another proposed solution is to gloss everything is such that it does not
exist at some time as meaning everything is dependent (Davies 2001). This moves
straightforwardly to the argument that not everything can be like this, since
dependent things only exist by virtue of something else. Holding that absolutely
everything is like this is incoherent. Hence there are some things which are not
dependent, that is, which do not come to be by generation and which are
perishable. Of these things one can ask whether they have this property
intrinsically or by virtue of another. An infinite regress of such things is not
possible, and so one has to posit a first cause of necessity. The first problem with
such an interpretation is that it moves from the text quite a long wayit doesnt
explain away the quantifier error, it ignores it (Wippel 2000, 464). Secondly, it
collapses the third way into an argument rather like the first waya first cause
argumentremoving any particular use for the notion of necessity. Thirdly, it
doesnt have the resources to answer critics such as Kenny (1969, 69) who note
that even if the argument is valid, it is compatible with positing eternal matter as
the source of necessity. Fourthly, and most importantly in this context, it simply
begs the question against a position like Nagarjuna. It doesnt argue that
everything cannot be dependent, it merely asserts it.

Downloaded By: [Cabezas, Joan Manuel] At: 09:13 9 January 2008

FORM AND EMPTINESS: AQUINAS AND NAGARJUNA

A different, more fruitful and quite traditional way of looking at this argument
is to think that it implicitly involves the distinction between essence and existence
which is the keystone of Aquinass metaphysical position. Things are given a
metaphysical analysis, in that they consist of essence (their structure) and
existencethe instantiation of that structure in reality. These are two distinct
principles which make up a thingprinciples which are not things themselves.
Aquinas holds that nothing in the world contains the basis for its own existence
within itselfexistence always comes from without. Contingent things rely on other
contingent things for their existence. Even things which do not go out of existence
require an external source of their existence. Such a source of existence would
be a reality whose essence is to existwhatever that might be like. This would be
an absolutely independent reality. It wouldnt be quite right to call it a beingsince it
is the source of all being, and the sole reality in which the principles of being
are identical, essence existence. On this way of looking at the third way, the
argument is indeed about dependence, but it is explicitly about dependence in
respect of existence. If absolutely everything which exists were dependent in this
way, then there would be nothing. An independent reality is required.
Objections to this reading query the intelligibility of the distinction between
essence and existence. The bare idea of existence, removed from all other possible
specifications of a thing, is seen as an empty idea, a non-genuine predicate. While
there may be an intuitive basis for this distinction, namely that there is something
to be said about the instantiation as distinct from the non-instantiation of
properties, the full-blown metaphysical distinction of essence and existence is not
sustainable. Existence is a kind of metaphor, a residual Platonically-inspired
reservoir idea of being, wherein all things are connected. English-speaking
commentators on this idea generally tend to be sceptical about such metaphysics.
However, for the moment, I want to mark it as a plausible candidate for
interpreting the third way as a valid argument.16

Nagarjunas Anti-Realist Argument


Nagarjuna begins his assault on realism by challenging realist notions of
causation.17 This holds that entities have real causal powers, that causes feature
in the genuine list of things which exist in reality. Nagarjuna changes the focus
of explanation. When confronted with the vast web of interconnections which is
nature, we select and note aspects which reflect our explanatory needs. We select
regularities and nodes of interaction which have salience for usbut we should
beware of projecting such patterns into nature itself. Such patterns are conditions
but conditions, unlike causes, are not occult metaphysical entities with mysterious
powers. Rather they play a role in explanationuniting explanandum and
explanansbut with no commitment to the metaphysical reality of causes.
Observed regularities explain nature. We trace patterns and make predictions.
However, this is possible in a metaphysically light-weight fashion. One way
of characterising this light-weight approach is to deny the notion of essence.18

181

Downloaded By: [Cabezas, Joan Manuel] At: 09:13 9 January 2008

182

P. OGRADY

There are no objective patterns existing in nature which hold independently of the
web of interconnections. Even the separation of entities into self-standing discrete
realities involves choice, arbitrary separation from what is contiguous, from what
went before and goes after, from causes and results. Nature does not carve itself up
into explanatory unitswe do that. Our discriminations, which are natural habits,
mask the metaphysical emptiness of reality. There are no self-standing independent
existents, independent of categorisation of them. Note that this blocks all forms of
metaphysical realismspecifically it doesnt sustain idealism, which holds that the
real nature of entities is that they are constituted by mind. This denies any validity to
the very idea of the way things are in reality.
Nagarjunas distinctive thesis on this is to deny that entities have svabhava,
or independent existence, sometimes glossed as essence.19 Another way of
expressing this is to say that emptiness (sunyata) characterises entities. The
fundamental metaphysical nature of things is that they are empty. Now such
a view is at face value difficult to sustain and seems to be a straight form of
nihilism. To hold that entities are empty seems to be to hold that entities do not, in
fact, exist. Opponents of Nagarjuna picked on this very point and indicated the
troublesome consequences of such a view.20 All the apparatus of Buddhism
would crumble on such a viewno Four Noble Truths, no Buddha, Dharma (the
teaching) or Sangha (community). Rather than sustaining and explicating
the Buddhist world-picture, such a view would wipe it out.
To respond to this criticism, Nagarjuna has recourse to a doctrine of two
perspectives on reality, a view which would be familiar to his Buddhist audience.21
There is a conventional way of looking at reality, in which one posits beings, causes,
events, properties and all the familiar paraphernalia of the world. This is the normal,
pre-critical way of seeing the world. However, there is also a more reflective
philosophical way of looking at realitythe absolute perspective. On such a view
one can see the conventions which hold together the conventional view of the
worldand realise that all things are in fact empty, that there is no self-existence.
Such a view does then bolster the Buddhist worldview. It explicates the fleeting
nature of reality and the natural human tendency to cling to what is really transient.
How the absolute perspective relates to the conventional perspective is at
the core of Nagarjunas position. It does not eradicate it, or supersede it. What
it amounts to is a principled denial that there is an ultimate way things are and as
such is in agreement with contemporary forms of anti-realism. Thus Nagarjunas
notion of emptiness is not a reified metaphysical reality. It is the denial of the kind
of reality which metaphysics usually holds to. So the absolute perspective doesnt
eradicate the conventional. In fact it allows a deeper realisation of the
conventionality of all that we call reality. What exists is the flux of change,
which we conventionally sort and pattern for brief periods of time, with entities
appearing and disappearing. Thus the doctrine of emptiness coincides with the
doctrine of dependent origination.
Nagarjuna therefore answers the challenge that he is really a nihilist by
indicating that the doctrine of emptiness doesnt wipe out conventional reality.

Downloaded By: [Cabezas, Joan Manuel] At: 09:13 9 January 2008

FORM AND EMPTINESS: AQUINAS AND NAGARJUNA

It doesnt hold that absolutely nothing exists. Rather it gives a characterisation of


conventional reality, showing that such reality is precisely conventional (see
Garfield 1995, 307ff). Included in the scope of this conventionality is the very
notion of the self. There is no trancendental ego which constitutes reality, the ego
is a conventional realityand Nagarjuna would agree with standard Buddhist
analyses of the self into aggregates (see Gethin 1998, 135ff). However, what is
distinctive of his position is that the aggregates themselves are not substantial
they lack independent existence.
The most obvious line of objection to this is to accuse his position of
undermining itself. The distinction between absolute and conventional is itself
conventional and so not real. Therefore it is an unusable distinction, and cannot be
used to sustain his position. Nagarjunas response, of course, would be to say that
one must understand the distinction itself as conventionalthat from the
absolute level it also lacks reality, but this doesnt make it unusable (see Garfield
1995, 316ff; Huntington Jr 1989). Like Wittgensteins ladder in the Tractatus, it
helps one see things rightly. Yet it still seems of doubtful coherence to use a
distinction which is under suspicion to defend the use of that very distinction. One
requires a different line of argument to avoid charges of begging the question.

Structural Parallels
It should now be clear that Aquinas and Nagarjuna are dealing with the
same metaphysical issue and coming up with contradictory accounts of it. Aquinas
defends the existence of a single independent source of necessity for all beings.
Nagarjuna denies the existence of any such source and affirms the dependence of
absolutely everything.
As we have also seen, neither Aquinas nor Nagarjuna have positions which
avoid internal problems. To make sense of Aquinass argument for a source of
necessity, one had to invoke the metaphysical distinction of essence and existence
and even using that, it is still questionable whether it really avoids logical error.
One might think that perhaps a parallel argument could be made using Aquinass
ingredients, but the one Aquinas actually offers is flawed. On Nagarjunas side,
despite his protestations to the contrary, it is not at all clear that he escapes the
charge of nihilism.
However, what I want to draw attention to here is a curious alignment of
both their positions, despite the fact that they appear diametrically opposed.
Nagarjunas worked out position entails a distinction between conventional and
absolute reality. Within conventional reality it makes sense to speak of essences or
forms, while in absolute reality it makes no sense to so speak. Given Nagarjunas
view that emptiness characterises all of reality, we can find a distinction of form
and emptiness in conventional reality. Forms have conventional reality, but
emptiness is their absolute reality, and this emptiness pervades even conventional
reality. The essence of the Prajnaparamitra literature, which Nagarjuna is
interpreting, is summed up in the refrain form is emptiness, and the very

183

Downloaded By: [Cabezas, Joan Manuel] At: 09:13 9 January 2008

184

P. OGRADY

emptiness is form.22 From an absolute perspective there is an identity of what,


from a conventional perspective, seem distinct. Nagarjuna is therefore committed
to two related sets of distinctions:
Conventional / Absolute
and
Form / Emptiness
The second distinction (form/emptiness) occurs in the first half of the former
distinction (conventional reality), while it collapses in the second half (absolute
reality).
Conventional
Form / Emptiness

Absolute
Emptiness

With this set up, one can see a striking structural parallel to Aquinass
position. He likewise has two sets of distinctions, where the second distinction
holds in the first side of the former distinction and collapses in the second. His
initial distinction is between Dependent (created) reality and Absolute (uncreated)
reality. The second distinction is between form and existence.
Dependent / Absolute
And
Form / Existence
Form and existence are distinct in dependent reality. All things that exist in
the world are constituted by the metaphysical distinction between form and
existence. However, in the second half of the distinction, absolute reality, this
distinction goes. What remains is self-subsistent existent, a unique reality whose
essence is to exist. Thus the parallel to Nagarjunas position:
[Nagarjuna]
[Aquinas]

Conventional
Form / Emptiness
Dependent Reality
Form / Existence

/
/

Absolute
Emptiness
Absolute Reality
Existence

Now despite the structural parallel, the fundamental difference between the
intended positions remains. For Nagarjuna, the whole structure (Conventional/Absolute) is dependent, whereas for Aquinas there is an independent reality.
Is there a way of adjudicating this stand-off?
In relation to the objections levelled against their respective positions,
it seems that Nagarjuanas position is less stable that Aquinass. Despite Nagarjunas
awareness of the danger of nihilism and his insistence that his position isnt nihilist,
it still seems he falls into it. It is unclear that he can sustain the view that
holding all entities are empty isnt nihilistic. His way out of nihilism is to invoke
the conventional/absolute distinction. Emptiness is as things are seen
from the absolute stance and this doesnt wipe out the conventional. Yet the
employment of this very distinction doesnt seem defensible, it doesnt seem

Downloaded By: [Cabezas, Joan Manuel] At: 09:13 9 January 2008

FORM AND EMPTINESS: AQUINAS AND NAGARJUNA

possible to sustain it without invoking some independent argument for it.


The situation is akin to C. I. Lewiss observation about coherentism. Lewis holds that
it is absurd to think that beliefs can support each other when they themselves do not
stand on anythingit being like two drunken sailors attempting to stand up by
leaning against each other. It just dont get off the ground!23 Likewise with the
conventional/absolute distinction. Without appeal to independent existence, it is
unclear how such a distinction is possible.
Furthermore, given that Nagarjuna denies that emptiness is equivalent to
nihilism and complete nothingness, it seems as if emptiness has to have some
positive content. With even a residual amount of positive content, the distinction
between conventional and absolute could be sustained. What might such content
be like? Well, it is merely to hold that emptiness has some reality independent of
that of conventional reality. A plausible candidate for such contentful emptiness
would, ironically in this context, be Aquinass notion of existence. Aquinas doesnt
reify existenceit is not a thing and neither is it a form or essence. It is not the
possible object of conceptual knowledge, since concepts track essences, not
existence. Hence substituting existence for emptiness yields the distinction

Conventional / Absolute

Form / Existence Existence

The required feature of the conventional realm is preserved, in that things


come to be and pass away, they do not have independent existence. Yet the very
possibility of this contrast is assured by having an independently contentful
notion of existence on the absolute side of the distinction. Thus Nagarjunas
distinction is altered by accepting Aquinass notion of an independent reality, but
underwritten by the postulation of that very reality.
A contextual response to the objection that Aquinass notion of existence is
unintelligible would be to contrast it with Nagarjunas emptiness. The kinds of
critic hostile to existence would be even more hostile to emptiness. So while not
an absolute rejoinder to such critics, it strengthens Aquinass position vis-a`-vis
Nagarjuna.

Conclusion
I began by noting a currently fashionable doubt about the possibility of
bringing protagonists from different cultural and historical periods into dialogue
with each other, and then proceeded to engage Aquinas with Nagarjuna. At a
surface level their positions are diametrically opposed, Aquinas affirming a source
of metaphysical necessity, Nagarjuna denying this. On closer inspection both sets
of arguments had troublesome dimensions. Aquinas might overcome the
objections to his position by invoking the essence/existence distinction,

185

Downloaded By: [Cabezas, Joan Manuel] At: 09:13 9 January 2008

186

P. OGRADY

Nagarjuna responding to charges of nihilism by deploying the conventional/absolute distinction.


I then noted a structural parallel between their sequence of distinctions and
indicated that Nagarjunas position still seemed vulnerable to charges of nihilism.
It seems as if something resembling Nagarjunas position could be salvaged by
using Aquinass notion of existence.
Does that then turn Nagarjuna into a theist? No. The positing of existence as
a metaphysical principle which serves as the basis on which to make the
conventional/absolute distinction doesnt say anything about what such existence
has to be like. It merely accepts the point, which Aristotle makes about Heraclitus,
that change presupposes some form of fixity. Whether such a metaphysical fixed
point has any further characteristics which point in the direction of theism is
another matter altogether. The current argument merely holds that in the dialectic
of the debate between the postulation of a metaphysical source of necessity and
the rejection of such, Aquinass position appears to be more secure than that of
Nagarjuna.
NOTES
1. The best recent biographical study of Aquinas is Torrell (1996).
2. Commentary on the Metaphysics Bk.3 lect.1.
3. For an interpretation of Aquinas in this way see OGrady (2005). For competing
interpretations see papers by Rogers and Jordan in the same volume. See also
n.12 below.
4. For some discussion see Murti (1955, 87ff). For criticism of Murtis interpretative
presuppositions see Burton (1999, 5ff)although Burton doesnt attempt any
claims about the historical figure.
5. Translated as The Fundamental Wisdom of the Middle Way, Jay N. Garfield, Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1995.
6. For a survey of Buddhist writings see Gethin (1998, ch. 2, The Word of the
Buddha: Buddhist Scriptures and Schools).
7. Garfields commentary furnishes this interpretation.
8. And as every quality which is useful or agreeable to ourselves or others is, in
common life, allowed to be a part of personal merit; so no other will ever
be received, where men judge of things by their natural, unprejudiced reason,
without the delusive glosses of superstition and false religion. Celibacy, fasting
penance, mortification, self-denial, humility, silence, solitude, and the whole
train of monkish virtues; for what reason are they everywhere rejected by men of
sense, but because they serve no manner of purpose. . . Enquiries Concerning the
Principles of Morals, Section IX, part 1, #219.
9. Consider the following: The main themes of postmodernism thus become
clear. They amount to a comprehensive rejection of virtually everything that
the Enlightenment in general and Descartes in particular believed in. There is a
sharp criticism of the received ideas of representation, objective Truth,

Downloaded By: [Cabezas, Joan Manuel] At: 09:13 9 January 2008

FORM AND EMPTINESS: AQUINAS AND NAGARJUNA

10.
11.
12.

13.
14.
15.

16.
17.

18.
19.
20.
21.
22.
23.

Reason and historical progress, leading eventually to the death of man,


a thoroughly wholesome loss of interest in the individual subject, his selfmastery through self-consciousness, his moral autonomy and the justification of
his knowledge of the world. Instead we turn more to language, the sign,
communication, art and culture-criticism. (Cupitt 1989, 39). Hence the
theist/atheist debate becomes pretty small beer indeed. A problem for positions
such as that of Kerr is how to articulate clearly how he can distinguish his view
from this one, without re-inflating the traditional Thomism he is seeking to
overcome, and without simply acceding to fideism.
In Summa Theologiae Ia q.2 a.3.
See Kerr (2002, ch. 4 Ways of Reading the Five Ways) for a good survey.
See Aquinas, Philosophical Theology and Analytical Philosophy for a defence of
this view. This current paper, generating a dialogue between Aquinas and
Nagarjuna, furthers the claim of that paper, by means of a particular study. Those
who want to read Aquinas as essentially a Christian theologian, without an
essentially philosophical dimension, have to hold that his initial confessional
presuppositions would preclude such an encounter between the views of
Nagarjuna and Aquinas. They just dont connect; they could perhaps proselytise
each other, but not engage in disinterested philosophical argument. This is the
very reason why such a reading impoverishes Aquinas.
Pratityasamutpada. Whoever sees dependent arising also sees suffering and its
arising and its cessation as well as the path. MMK ch24.40.
See Burton (1999 ch. 2) for a defence of the view that Nagarjuna is not a sceptic
and that the denial of svabhava is a positive doctrine.
Aristotle, Sophistical Refutations, ch. 4. For the proliferation of thirteenthcentury textbooks based on this, see Ebbesen (1982). Theres scholarly dispute
over whether Aquinas himself wrote such a textbook, the De Fallaciissee
Torrell (1996, 523). The point is, however, that he would have been well aware of
the flaw involved.
For examples of the kind of objections which can be levelled at this kind of
reading, see Kenny (2002).
As I noted above I use the English translation of the Mulamadhyamikakarika
(hereafter, MMK) given by Jay Garfield in his The Fundamental Wisdom of the
Middle Way, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995. I also accept his generally
anti-realist reading of Nagarjuna, in contrast to, say, T. R. V. Murtis absolutist
reading in Murti (1955). For the attack on a realist account of causation see MMK
ch. 1.
MMK15.
See Garfield p. 89 n.4 on translating this term.
A plausible interpretation of MMK 24. 7 14 sees Nagarjuna responding to such
opponents.
MMK 24.18.
The Heart Sutra in Conze (1973, 142).
Argument cited in Haack (1993, 27).

187

Downloaded By: [Cabezas, Joan Manuel] At: 09:13 9 January 2008

188

P. OGRADY

REFERENCES
AUTHOR. 2002. Relativism. Chesham: Acumen.
2004. Aquinas, philosophical theology and analytical philosophy. In The theology
of Thomas Aquinas, edited by R. Van Niewenhove and J. Warwykov. Notre Dame:
Notre Dame University Press.
BATTACHARYA, K. 1990. The dialectical method of Nagarjuna. 3d ed. Delhi: Matilal
Banarsidass.
BOLAND, V. 1996. Ideas in God according to Saint Thomas Aquinas: Sources and synthesis.
Amsterdam: Kluwer.
BOOTH, E. 1983. Aristotelian aporetic ontology in Islamic and Christian thinkers.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
BURTON, D. 1999. Emptiness appraised. London: Curzon.
CONZE, E. 1959. Buddhist scriptures. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
CUPITT, C. 1989. Radicals and the future of the church. London: SCM Press.
DAVIES, B. 2001. Aquinass third way. New Blackfriars. 82 (968) 450 466.
EBBESEN, S. 1982. Ancient scholastic logic as the source of medieval scholastic logic.
In N. Kretzmann, A. Kenny, J. Pinborg (eds) The Cambridge History of Later
Medieval Philosophy. Cambridge University Press.
GETHIN, R. 1998. The foundations of Buddhism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
GUDMUNSEN, C. 1977. Wittgenstein and Buddhism. London: Macmillan.
HAACK, S. 1993. Evidence and inquiry. Oxford: Blackwell.
HUNTINGTON, C. W. JR. 1989. The emptiness of emptiness. Honolulu: University of Hawaii
Press.
KENNY, A. J. P. 1969. The five ways. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
KERR, F. 2002. After Aquinas: Versions of Thomism. Oxford: Blackwell.
LOVEJOY, A. O. 1964. The great chain of being. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
MACKIE, J. L. 1982. The miracle of Theism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
MATILAL, B. K. 1986. Perception: An essay on classical Indian theories of knowledge. Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
MURTI, T. R. V. 1955. The central philosophy of Buddhism. London: Allen and Unwin.
OWENS, J. 1992. Aristotle and Aquinas. In The Cambridge Companion to Aquinas, edited
by N. Kretzmann, and E. Stump. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
TORRELL, J. P. 1996. St. Thomas Aquinas, Vol. 1, The person and his work. Washington D.C.
Catholic University of America Press.
WILLIAMS, P. 1998. Indian philosophy. In Philosophy 2, edited by A. C. Grayling. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
WIPPEL, J. 2000. The metaphysical thought of Thomas Aquinas. Washington, DC: Catholic
University of America Press.
WITTGENSTEIN, L. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

Paul OGrady, Department of Philosophy, Trinity College Dublin, Dublin 2,


Ireland. E-mail: pogrady@tcd.ie

Você também pode gostar