Você está na página 1de 4

Science Technology And Society

Assignment 3 Solutions
Govind Shukla (201301088)
September 2, 2016

1.

Question 1 Solution

Nancy Cartwrights Philosophy of Science is an excellent collection of thought-provoking


essays on Cartwrights many and varied contributions to philosophy of science. Cartwright
is without doubt one of the most influential philosophers of science writing today and a
volume like the present one has long been overdue. Her contributions have been seminal
in many different areas: her work on models and idealizations, for example, played an
important role in the development of an entire sub-discipline in philosophy of science
focusing on the role of models in application driven science, and her widely-cited work on
causal laws and effective strategies has helped frame the contemporary debate on the role
of causation in science. The volume devotes considerable attention to these issues and
many more with one unfortunate omission. In recent years Cartwright has urged us to
investigate in more depth the connection between science, values, and politics and I was
disappointed to see that there is no examination of this topic in the volume. Yet overall the
book, which includes brief responses by Cartwright to each paper, presents an extremely
valuable resource for both students and researchers and should be required reading for
those interested in Cartwrights philosophy of science.
Anyone looking for a brief overview of Cartwrights views should consult Carl Hoefers
excellent introduction to the volume. The first set of papers focuses on how theories
and models represent the world, while the second set focuses on causes and capacities.
Ronald Gieres paper, straddling both issues, provides an especially clear and sympathetic
summary of Cartwrights account of how models represent reality, while the exchange
between Cartwright and Giere can serve as a useful introduction to Cartwrights claim
that we need to invoke capacities over and beyond a notion of causal structure. newline A
central component of Cartwrights view is that high-level theories do not directly represent
physical systems and that instead the relation between theoretical laws, like Newtons
laws or the Maxwell-Lorentz equations, and the world is mediated by two kinds of models:
interpretive and representative models. Interpretive models are laid out within the theory
itself and allow us to understand the theorys laws by providing concrete representations
of the abstract formalism. The toy models discussed in physics textbooks are examples
of interpretive models. Representative or phenomenological models, by contrast, represent actual phenomena, but in general go beyond any particular theory in the way they
are constructed. Since representative models generally do not satisfy the theorys laws,
Cartwright has argued that the high-level laws either lie, if construed representationally,
or ought to be construed non-representationally as tools for model-building. The term
model not only plays different roles in Cartwrights account but has been used in many
different contexts and with many different meanings in philosophy of science, which has
resulted in a fair amount of confusion in the literature. Daniela Bailer-Joness essay is
helpful here, offering a careful examination of the place of models in Cartwrights account
that clarifies the different roles of interpretative and representative models.
Ulrich Ghde focuses in more detail on Cartwrights account of how theories are applied
to concrete systems. According to Cartwright, theory application is a three-step process,
only the last of which is the derivation of a representative model, governed by phenomeno-

logical laws, from a theorys fundamental laws. The first two steps are providing, first, an
unprepared description of the system in question and, second, a prepared description in
the language of the theory. Ghde illustrates this process using the discovery of Haleys
comet as a case study and argues, perhaps surprisingly, that Cartwrights account bears a
certain affinity to the formal account of theories developed by the Munich structuralist
school in the tradition of Wolfgang Stegmller.
While I agree with Ghde that Cartwrights and the structuralists accounts are similar in
that they describe the relation between a theory and a physical system in terms of multiple
layers, I am not sure whether the two accounts are really as closely parallel as he suggests.
Ghde likens Cartwrights unprepared description to the data structures of the structuralists account. But the structuralists data structures are already formalized and the move
from unprepared to prepared description merely consists in restricting the data structure
to a proper substructure. By contrast, Cartwrights unprepared description is informal and
need not yet involve parameters recognized by the theory. Thus, Cartwrights unprepared
description takes place prior to and outside of the structuralists formal framework.

2.

Question 2 Solution

Evelyn Fox Keller has devoted most of the years of her life to the study of the manner
in which gender and science are related. Using psychoanalysis, she delves into the construction of such terms as man, woman, science, nature, gender and sex. Her work has
helped to open the floodgates to a critique of the scientific process and has questioned our
fundamental understanding of science within Western culture and civilization.
Keller seeks to show that the notion of masculine science is thoroughly entrenched in
our society in the following ways:
The identification between scientific thought and masculinity is so deeply embedded in the culture at large that children have little difficulty internalizing that
identification
The complement of the scientific mind is Nature when viewed so ubiquitously as
female (Psychoanalysis and Contemporary Thought). Science is considered to be
antithetical to Eros, hence any woman interested in the study of science is by
definition "unfeminine." Thus, the heavily- stockinged, glasses-wearing, frumpy
image of a woman scientist emerges, as evidenced in James Watsons description
of Rosalind Franklin. Nature is objectified because the knower is divided from the
known, so the very act of obtaining information becomes genderized.
The task of explaining the associations between masculine and scientific thus becomes, short of reverting to an untenable biological reductionism, the task of understanding the emotional substructure that links our experience of gender with our
cognitive experience.

The recognition of the independent reality of both self and other is a necessary
precondition both for science and for love
Through this construction concerning the role of masculine and feminine, the truth itself
takes on a genderized value. Unlike girls, boys must actually separate themselves from
the mother figure twice - once to establish a separate identity and a second time in order to
recognize their gender difference. Keller believes that one possible outcome of this process
of separation is excessive delineation in boys because they are required to go through the
process twice and an inadequate attention to delineation in girls. This process in turn
leads to men who have difficulty participating in emotional relationships and women who
feel threatened by the concrete abstraction of science. To support this assumption, Keller
uses data from a number of studies including those of Anne Roe to show such trends in
gender identification. The article basically focuses on the question of the intermingling of
masculine bias with what purports to be objective, scientific statement.
Keller points out that there are a number of critiques of science that run the gambit of
the political spectrum. Leftist criticism singles out unfair employment practices insisting
that the sex of scientists should not matter and that the quality of science would not be
affected by the presence or absence of women scientists. This movement is supported by
the experience of feminists in other areas and recent developments in the history and
philosophy of science itself, including Thomas Kuhns explanation of the influence of society
on science - scientific knowledge being shaped by political and social surroundings

Você também pode gostar