Você está na página 1de 26
Athens, Jerusalem, Mecca: Leo Strauss’s “Muslim” Understanding of Greek Philosophy Rémi Brague Phitosophy, Paris 7 Abstract The contrast “Athens vs. Jerusalem” played a major part in the late work of Leo Strauss (1899-1973). His scholarly career, from the outset, can be described asa motion from Jerusalem (Spinoza, Msimonides) to Athens (Plato, Xenophon), Nevertheless, a third city, Mecca, and what it stands for, unspokenly synthesizes the first two. For instance, Strauss’s interpretation of Plato is grounded on Farabi's view of philosophical style, His rediscovery of exotericise— that is, of the possibility of a silent oral teaching—depends on an Islamic conception of Revelation, which opposes the Christian one: Athens and Jerusalem meet in Mecca, but they are at loggerbeads im Rome. The Athens and Jerusalem Theme ‘The second-century church father Tertullian may have been the first to de~ clare, What has Athens to do with Jerusalem?, but it was not until the Rus- sian philosopher Leo Shestov used the two city names as the title of'a book (1951, posthumous) that they became a kind of catchword for the opposi- ‘Some words on the Isbyrinthine history of the present text: A first version was prepared in ‘English and sent to symposium that, for reasons of health, I could not attend. Its pro~ ceedings were due to be published but finally were not. My article was later translated into French (Brague ig8ga). The present version takes advantage of remarks by the lave David R. ‘Lachterman (Lachterman 1991: 298-45). Poetics Teday 19:2 (Summer 1998) Copyright @ 1998 by the Porter Institute for Poetics and ‘Semiotics. 236 ~— Poetics Today 19:2 tion between Hellenism and Hebraism. Among the people who took up Shestov’s yoked pair, Leo Strauss must probably be given pride of place. Leo Strauss (1899-1973) began his career in Germany as a student of Jewish and Muslim philosophy. In the 1930s, he fled to France, Britain, and finally settled in the United States, where he taught first in New York, then in Chicago. He in famous for his attempt at reviving the idea of Natural Right, to which he devoted one of his most well-known books, as well as for his rediscovery of the classical philosophy of Plato and Aristotle, which he contended to be still relevant for our time and age, if we read them as they wanted to be read. Strauss put the theme of “Athens and Jerusalem” at the very core of his later thought, from the late 19408, hence, before he could have read Shestov’s book. This theme is voiced at a relarively late date in Strauss’s progress. But the thing is present from the outset in his writings, if we take the phrase in its broadest meaning —that is, the relationship between both cities that stand for two “cultures,” two “worldviews,” and so on, whose conflict is supposed to be the backbone of European history.’ As for the formula, the earliest occurrence 1 know of is a letter to Karl Lawith, dated from August 15, 1946 (Strauss 1g8ga: 108, 111). It only announces a lecture by the same title, to be held in November 1946. In 1951, Strauss wrote: “Classi- cal authors bore witness to the fact that truly human life, life of acience, is the life that is devoted to knowledge and looking for it. From the vantage- point of the Bible, the hen enagksion [the only necessary thing] is totally different. One reaches no plausible aim by covering up this contrast, by denegating the tertiun non datur. Every synthesis is in fact a choice either for Jerusalem or for Athens” (Voegelin et al. 1993: 30)- ‘The theme was firat made public in 1952: “The iasue of traditional Juda- iam versus philosophy is identical with the issue Jerusalem versus Athens” (Strauss 1952: 20). On the content of this contrast, Strauss gives ua brief hints only. The same complex of ideas received a full treatment in a series of lectures given in Chicago in 1952 and partially published two years later, in a Hebrew translation (Strauss 1979). But there the names of Athens and Jerusalem are missing. They make their first, very stealthy appearance in 1954, on the occasion of a paper given in Jerusalem (!); There the faithful city stands for prophecy, and Athens for political philosophy. Finally, some years before 1964, Strauss began a lecture on Thucydides with a staterient of the theme: 1. See the quotation by Goethe in Strauss 1959: 5, probably alluded to in Stranm 1995: 28. g. Strauss 1959: 9-10. with a quotation without references to Isaiah 1: 261. Brague + Leo Strauss's “Muslim” Understanding of Greek Philosophy 237 [Western] tradition has two roots. It consists of two heterogeneous elements, of two elements which are ultimately incompatible with each other—the Hebrew element and the Greek element. We speak, and we speak rightly, of the an- tagoniam between Jerusalem and Athens, between faith and philosophy. Both philosophy and the Bible assert that there is ultimately one thing, and one thing only, needful for man. But the one thing needful proclaimed by the Bible is the very opposite of the one thing needfill proclaimed by Greek philosophy. According to the Bible, the one thing needful is obedient love; according to phi- losophy, the ane thing needful is free inquiry. The whole history of the West can be viewed aa an ever repeated attempt to achieve a compromise or a synthesis between the two antagonistic principles. But all these attempts have failed, and necessarily so. . . . The Western tradition does not allow of a rynthesis of ita two elements, but only of their tension: this is the secret of the vitality of the West. (Scrauss 1989: 72-73) Unfortunately, though, some lines afterwards, we read an important craliicetion, not to iy a recantation: Speaking ofthe Wester traction ax Strauss did is “impossible . . . in the last analysis,” and acceptable, nay eurary, only “as eng. as we speak polisally ic, crudely” By tie oben, wwe cannot ascertain to what exent Straus macau his own statement seri ously. The theme finally becomes central in 1967, on the occasion of the publication of the proceedings of'a conference given in the same year under this very title (Strauss 1989b).* Again, we are at a loss how to understand a text that does not claim to be more than “preliminary reflections" and whose content is highly cryptic. It has already puzzled several scholars,’ so a frank avowal of perplexity might be the least dishonorable evasion. Between Athens and Jerusalem: To and Fro ‘The main discovery that Strauss made, or claimed to have made, is a for- gotren way of reading‘ Unfortunately for our present purpose, he rediscov- ered an art of writing, too: Since “people write as they read” (Strauss 1959: 144), he wrote in the same way as the authors he studied are supposed to have done, and he concealed what he believed to have found. Hence such sentences as: “Let us then keep them (sc. Machiavelli‘s blasphemics) under 3+ Strum 1999: 72-75, On the date, see ibid: xxxt-anunii. 4 This text may be the same as the one referred to in Strauss 1983a. On the “classical. ‘Struggle in the Middle Ages,” ace ibid: 165. 5 See Momigfiano 2987: 197 n. 29, 198. A useful introduction appears in Sales 1 Coderch and Montserrat i Molas 1991. 6. On Straum’s hermeneutics, see Brague 1991, which the present cmay presupposes and completes, and Rosen 1987: 107~98. On Strauss's thought in general, the best overview I knew of is Marshall 1985 (which has exceptionally rich foomotes). ze Poatiks Today 19:2 the veil under which he has hidden them” (Strauss 199: 41). Therefore, in- terpreting Strauss is an almost desperate task. One can never tell whether one is probing the depths of his thought or merely blundering about and sliding on its glittering surface. Our task is made all the more difficult by the facts that Strauss, on the one hand, underwent an evolution as to his style, and that the trend of this evolution, on the other hand, led him to an avowedly esoteric style in which his real thought, if any, was deliberately buried under either painstaking and fastidious analyses of texts, or moral and/or political preaching, Strauss excelled in the art of window-dressing and paying lip service to conservative and “square” opinions. His pleading for Natural Right might belong to that kind of rhetoric, as well as other theses the refutation of which always runs the risk of becoming an exercise in shadow-boxing. ‘The “Athens and Jerusalem” theme furnishes us with a good example of both dimensions of Strauss’s thought, as well as of the predicament we face when we try to interpret him. For we cannot tell to which layer of thought this theme actually belonged: Is it Strauss’s last position on some fandamental questions, or merely the ultimate, and most elaborate, way of concealing an original and/or subversive standpoint under the mask of a traditional formula? I will bere choose a safer way of inquiry, which consists in looking at Strauas’s career, as seen from the outside. It can be described as a journcy from Jerusalem to Athens: Whereas the first publications dealt with Jew- ish thinkers like Maimonides—not to mention Mendelssohn, Hermann Cohen, and so on—or Jewish in origin like Spinoza, the last ones, for the most part, are commentaries on Greek philosophers and writers like Plato, Aristotle, Xenophon, Thucydides, or Aristophanes. These interpretations are the most famous and the most controversial.’ Yet Strauss's interest in the ancients is relatively late, since his first published text on a Greek author is the 1939 essay on Kenophon (Strauss 1939b). When, in 1946, he wrote a scathing critique of a book on Plato’s political philosophy, he was already in his late forties (Strauss 1946). Initially, classical Greek thinkers were studied as sources, but Strause’s main purpose was to explore medieval thought. See, for instance, the re- search program Strauss drafted at the end of his 1996 French essay on Maimonides’ and Farabi’s political science. Plato is to be studied ex Mai- monides’ source or inspirer: “One cannot avoid to ask the questions, cru- cial to the understanding of Maimonides, as to the relation of the theology of the Moreh to the Platonic doctrine of the One, and the relation of the 7. See, for example, Burnyeat 1995 and the ensuing discussion. Brague - Leo Strauss’s “Muslim” Understanding of Greek Philosophy = 239 cosmology of the Morsk (that is, the discussion about the creation of the world) to the doctrine of the Timacus” (Strauss 1936c: 95). Or we can point to the parallel thrust of his book on Hobbes: unveil- ing the second book of Aristotle’s Rhetorics (his “treatise on the passions”), as well as Thucydides’ Peloponnesian War, a3 sources for the British philoso- pher’s thought (Strauss 19968). ‘A Stop-Off In Mecca: Farabl Nevertheless, this backward movement from medieval or modern thinkers to their ancient forerunners or inspirers is not the only one. We can spot another trend: reading the ancients with medieval eyes. Straus, in my opinion, did exactly that, and never ceased to do that, although he seldom acknowledged it explicitly, Thus, the thesis I should like to defend in this essay is that the pattern of reading Strauss applied to the Greeks ia neither ancient nor modern, but medieval—to be precise, Islamic—in origin. In other words, Strauss read the Greeks from a point of view that is neither Greek (Athenian) nor Jewish (Jerusalemite), but Muslim—"Meccan,” if I may coin the phrase, This outlook seems to stem from a thinker who deeply influenced the young Strauss, Nietzache* An aphorism that Strauss, to the best of my knowledge, never uses" can be read as a program for Strauss, or at least for his early work on the medievals.” The influence of Avicenna and Razi notwithstanding, the most impor tant source of Strauss’s hermeneutics is probably Farabi. Especially im- portant is the view of Plato that is to be found in the writings of this tenth- century thinker (872-950). It is therefore apposite that we should pause in. order to examine briefly Strauss's relationship to him. Strauss wrote three articles on Farabi, the first two of which were not republished in book form. In the first one, Strauss, who follows a suggestion by Moritz Stein- schneider (Steinschneider 1869: 176-78, quoted in Strauss 1996a: 100 n. 5), 8. See Brague agg: 104-5, Let me add sone words om Nietesche’s influence on Stranss, Let me firet state that my intention never was to blame Strauss for that, nor to debunk him as a Nietzsche. critique of Nictmche, This argument suppowes that this critique is to be taken einer ene ee Moncove, his lens open the pony cure, Seraum, eave agreed: general diagnosis proposed by 9. Nevertheless, Stranas himself points to the parallel draws by Nietzsche between Plato and Muhsnmad in The Will te Proer (Straus 1935; 62 1. 1), 10. The Den of Dey, V, § 496, in Nictasche 1974 [1911]: 345-47. See Brague 1996. 240 ~—— Poetics Today 19:2 aacribes long fragments of Falgcra’s Reshit Hokmah to a lost work by Farabi: The third part of the Jewish author's compendium on philosophical sci- ences excerpts Farabi’s writing on Plato and Aristotle (ibid.: 100-104)." Strauss invites the reader to reconsider the history of medieval philosophy aa a whole by giving Farabi the place that becomes him: the place of pri- macy (ibid.: 105~6). The second essay (Strauss 1945) deals with the very work that the first one tried to elicit fom its Hebrew adaptation. The origi- nal text had just been published in a critical edition by F, Rosenthal and R. Walzer in 1949. Some pages of this article became part of the introduc- tory essay to Strauss’s main “hermeneutical” text (Strauss 1945: 371-73; 1952: 13-14). The third and last article is devoted to the analysis of a newly published summary of the Lazes (Strauss 1959 [1957]). Strauas’s Plato is basically the same as Farabi’s. Let us quote some salient points: According to Strauss's and Farabi's common outlook, Plato is first and foremost a political thinker. Aspects that transcend the politi- cal realm are systematically given short shrift: the doctrine of “ideas,” the soul and its immortality, the gods and religious aspects in general. The ‘views of Farabi's Socrates are distinguished from Plato's own views, not to say criticized by the latter (Strauss 1945: 362 [politics], 964 [ideas], 371-72 [soul], 3913 Strauss 1959: 194, 248, 153). The question must arise as to whether Farabi was faithful to Plato. Strauss supposes he was not: “He (Farabi) conccives of the Laws not, as Piato himself had done, as a correction of the Republic, but as a supple- ment to the Republic, . . . Farabi’s views are closely akin to that of Cicero” (Strauss 1945: 380 n. 55). A difficulty must then arise: If Farabi corrected Plato, he must have understood him better than Plato himself had done. Now, this is a modern hermencutical rule, defended by Kant and Schleier- macher~--and a rule that Strauss never tired of exposing as inadequate (Strauss 1991: 25; 1946; 329; 1959: 66-68; 19g6b: xv). ‘The important point is not our assessing Strauss's importance or short- comings in his interpretation of Farabi. What I want to emphasize is that Strauss made use of Farabi as an interpretive key to unlock Plato’s dia- lpgues. For instance, we have good reasons for surmising that his under- standing of the Rafublic, set forth in The City and Man, stems from 2 para- graph in Farahi's Philosophy of Plato. We read in this work: When he had done this, he afterwards investigated the manner and the method by means of which the citizens of cities and nations ought to be instructed in this Other fragments of Falgera's work, which Straus tentatively ascribed to nother wosk by Farah (pce Seramme 1956396, 19967 * gO M. 3), could be identified as translations from the Sree Bel ofan Soe Pas satobs rien 92, 9751969! 1b 2 Brague + Leo Strauss's “Musiim" Understanding of Greek Philosophy 241 science and their character formed by those ways of life, whether the method was more able than Socrates to form the character of the youth and instruct the multitude; Socrates possessed only the ability to conduct a acientific inves- tigation of justice and the virtues, and a power of love, but did not possess the ability to form the character of the youth and the multitude; and the philoso- pher, the prince, and the legisiator ought to be able to use both methods: the Socratic method with the elect, and Thrasymachus’ method with the youth and the multitude. (Farabi 1949: X, § go, 21-29, or 1969, X, § 96, 66-67). ‘The whole background of the passage seems to be an exegesis of the Ghtophon, 2 dialogue whose Platonic anthenticity is dubious (Slings 1981). In this text, Clitophon, who ia named here, as elsewhere (Plato, Republic I, 40a), as a friend of Thrasymachus, launches a violent attack on Socra- tes, taunting him with one-sidedness in a way that reminds one of Hege!’s critique of subjective morality on behalf of objective Sitlichkeit, The Chto- phon may have been interpreted on the basis of the Hellenistic ideal, as expressed in Cicero, of the unity of the philosopher and the orator (Walzer in Farabi 1985; xiii). Be that as it may, the general thrust of Straum’s reading of the Republic reminds one of Farabi's utterances, This fact has already been highlighted (Benardete 1978: 9; Berrichon-Sedeyn 1987: xxix; Strauss 1964: 116, 125- 24, 194). The very way Strauss puts Thrasymachus at the center of his interpretation, bringing into relief the impartance of the friendship that finally arises between him and Socrates, is borrowed from Farahi (Strauss 1945: 383; 1959: 159). On the other hand, the combination of “Socratic” bold izing and “Thrasymachean” cautious speech characterizes Strauss's own art of writing. Farabi is all the more interesting for us because we are dealing with Athens and Jerusalem—in this context, with the relationship between Greek philosophy and revealed, monotheistic religion. From the point of view of the historian, Farabi’s works happen to embody the passage fram the former to the latter. By this token, he may be the most perfect link be- tween the two worlds. We possess a fragment by him which was handed down to us by a Muslim biographer and daxographer and in which Farabi explains how he received his training in Aristotelian philosophy (and above all in higher logic and epistemology, through Aristotle's Pusterior Analytics) 12. Another reference to Thragymachus is in Farabi 1968: 10. me Poetics Today 19:2 from an uninterrupted chain of direct master-disciple transmission that reaches back to the last scions of Greek philosophical schools. To be sure, Farahi's text is not devoid of any self-praise: He wants to appear as the last heir of antique wisdom. Nevertheless, his account, barring soroe details, has an authentic ring.” Now, this claim, which prerumes the presence of a historical continuity between later Greek (pagan) thought and Islam, raises still other ques- tions: Can we speak of Farabi’s interpretation of the Greeks as his own achievement, or should we rather look at it as arising from Farabi's half- critically taking over some Hellenistic and/or middle Platonic to put it bluntly, Farabi “just cribbed the whole thing” from some second- Tate treatise of late Hellenistic origin, a view criticized by Strauss (Strauss 1945: 359, 377). In any case, Strauss’s winding way from the Greeks and back to them is not easy to assess from the vantage paint of the historian of ideas: Strauss read Plato from Farabi’s point of view, but Farabi himeclf’ may have taken up ideas from the Hellenistic (Stoic or middle Platonic) interpretation of Plato. Esoteric Style In any event, putting on medieval spectacles in order better to look at ancient texts is made possible by the (alleged?) rediscovery of a commen feature supposed to run through the whole history ef philosophy up to the Enlightenment: esoteric style. It is a matter of common knewiedge that the most impertant thing in Strauss’s hermencutics is his rediscovery of esoteric writing. His book Persecution and the Art of Writing bears sufficient witness to this, It gives a large harvest of facts in a field that still requires detailed historical study—and has received little (ee Hokzhey and Zim- merli 1977). Eaotericiam as a means of communicating dangerous truths without endangering one's own security or civil peace is as old as pliloso- phy. For the danger to be coped with is itself as old as philosophy. The possibility of an esoteric meaning, and hence of an esoteric inter- pretation of texts, ia not essentially linked’ to the ides of religious ortho- doxy. We can spot traces of this basic attitude in the ancient world prier to the emergence of monotheistic world religions. The danger is older than they are—as the case of Socrates illustrates, viewed against the background 1g. Thm Abt Upaybi'a n.d. 604-5, The classical seudy on the historical background is Meyer- bof 1ggo. Discussion in S, Stroumsn 1991. Brague - Leo Strauss’s “Muslim” Understanding of Greek Philosophy 243 of the various lawsuits for impiety leveled at Anaxagoras and others. Burn- ing books was a very old way of eliminating heterodoxy, even in classical antiquity, before the very idea of orthodoxy had even emerged.* More disquieting is the fact that philosophers themselves were reported not to have had misgivings against such a practice. This is at least the case if we are to trust Aristoxenos’s report on Plato's proposal that Democri- tus's books be burned. The reason alleged there—Plato wanted to hide that he had stolen ideas from Democritus!|—may be apocryphal and may stern from the increasing trend of late antiquity toward personalizing the history of philosophy. Nevertheless, some later philosophers toyed with this idea: Prochus, according to his biographer, thought that every philo- sophical book should be hidden from the youth, with the exception of the Chaldean Oracles and Plato’s Timasus (Marinos 1814: chap. 98). Esoteric writing is traditionally admitted or simply discussed in con- nection with phenomena belonging either to the medieval world (the so- called Averroists, crypto- Jewish literature among Marranos, etc.) or to the modern period (¢.g., “enlightened” writers concealing their “Spinozism”). Since Strauss avowedly took his departure from their study and his ken to other thinkers, an easy objection is that he saw esotericism not only where it is actually to be found but where it never was, too." One point deserves to be heavily streased: Strause’s hermencutical origi- nality does not lie in the claim that there is a difference between (a) levels of readers, more or Jess gifted and acute, and (b) levels of meaning, more or less superficial. Neither is this originality to be looked for in his assert- ing that some texts are esoteric. For these can be explained, completed, corrected, and the like orally by the master who wrote them, in living communication. Written works can very well be meant to lure the reader through their very aporetic character so as to drive him or her toward a living encounter with their author, Some dialogues by Plato, for example, may have had this fimction (Gaiser 1959), Normally, written texts are exo- teric, whereas esotericiam belongs to oral teaching, which takes place in the inner circle of disciples. All those facts are relatively well-known. On the other hand, Straus’s central assumption is the existence of eso- teric writing, that is, written texts that are meant, in themselves and out of Hesse geet nt ert on Frotagaras (IX, 59) For examples in Rome, vee Momi- Gxher plenaae i Bec 96 me * 16. Seo, for insamce, the open-minded review in Beleval 1955 and Straum's rejoinder in Seraus i939: 208-ga. For an analogous bat la fair attack on Stranm’s method appBed to medieval falésfe, ee, for instance, Leaman 1980, 244° Poetks Today 19:2 themselves, to convey their full meaning to the acute reader while keeping it out of the reach of run-of-the-mill people. The paradax lies in the blend- something like, if I may coin a bold formula, silent oral teaching. The singularity of the kind of esotericism Strauss supposes is ita capability of establishing communication between philosophers in spite of their being kept apart by centuries, It enables a philosopher A to “speak,” to convey his oral teaching, to a hearer B still to be born, through a text written ac- cording to definite rules. Since such a text is planned to be accessible to men of future gen- erations, when death will have definitely precluded the possibility of any “living” communication, it is necessary that it should be completely self- sufficient. Plato, for instance, must have written not only esoteric texts in general also but self-sufficient esoteric texts. This may be the reason why Strauss could not abide the idea of an oral teaching of Plato, at least if this implies a definite doctrine, for example, Plato's alleged metaphysics of numbers, such as it is reconstructed by the Tabingen school (Kramer 1982), not the discussions at the Academy, understood as a living inquiry and communication (spnusia) in philosophical leisure, without any definite doctrine, let alone orthodoxy. Strauss agrees with Harold Cherniss’s at- tack on the former (Strauss 1946: 349-50). Plato must be the author of books comparable to sacred books. They must at least have been written with a view to a way of reading analogous to the way sacred books are read. Strauss tacitly discards or downplays the admission that external circumstances such as the adventure in Sicily, immer Academic debates, or even death, thar prevented Plato from giving the Zavws the last touch-up might have played their patt in Plato’s literary activity (Strauss 1991: 25). Foremost among these external circumstances is the very fact that the texts were transmitted to us or lost (e.g., Aristotle’s Jost dialogues), the choice being made by later transmitters with regard to criteria that are not necessarily to be supposed identical with the author’s books should be read as sacred, as a critique commonly leveled against Strauss has it,” that is, as absolutely true and free of contradictions. The accent does not lie so much on “sacred” as on “books”: Their being sacred and their being books are two aspects of a single fact. They must be sacred as books, in 90 far as their flawless composition unswervingly mirrors di- vine perfection.” 17. See the cartoon in Burnyeat 1985: g2—small people paying obsisnnce to dusty old folios. 18. Cf. the description of the “Jerusalemite” understanding of contradictions in a sacred Brague - Leo Strauss's “Muslim” Understanding of Greek Philosophy 245, The link between external circumstances and inner meaning is pro- vided by the author's statement about his work and the way he wanted it to be read, A general problem arises as to whether the author of an cso- teric piece of writing has to confess that he is writing in an esoteric way: “The case of the authors who explicitly say that they intentionally contra- dict themselves in order to indicate a secret teaching to an elite among the teaders, is entirely different from that of authors who neither say nor indi- cate anything of that kind” (Strauss 1959: 224). It must be said somewhere: “This very work you are actually reading is an esoteric work.” Otherwise, readers may mistake their own fancies for the elicitation of the secret meaning the author intended to veil/unveil in his or her work. Hints are not enough. Therefore, the authors about whom. the use of eaoteric style cannot be denied just let the cat out of the bag without further ado about their making use of such a style. There are some examples of such writers. Maimonides is among them, at least in the intro- duction to the Guide for the Perplexed, as well as the anonymous authors of the Encyclopedia of the Pure Brethren, who wrote: “Know, brother, that in this epiatle (risdla) we have made clear what final end is sought. Do not think ill of us and do not regard this epistle as an amusement of adolescents and as an idle tale of the Brethren; for (according to) a habit we follow, we cover up truths by words, expressions and indications in order that we should not be (farced to abandon our present way of life)” (Iwan as-Safa’ 1983, 2:97)” In view of such examples, we feel compelled to qualify the statement according to which “it is essential to the success of this style that the fact that an author is employing it should be communicated indirecly* (Mahdi 1957: 118). Now, to what extent are we allowed to interpret works in which no such open statements occur as fraught with a secret meaning? Esotertcism and the Three Medieval Religions Even if we may admit the existence of esoteric texts outside of religious traditions, the use af esoteric style is more convenient when a religious orthodoxy has scized power. Maimonides alludes to this fact: He quotes Alexander of Aphrodisias’s On the Principles of the Whole on the three main causes of error (Badawi 1978 [1967]: 276). He then adds that there now book in Straums 1979: 16 with, on the other hand, Strauss 1981: 19-20, where the Bible and Plato's dialogues are played off againat one another. 19- Translation in Pines 1980: 185-86. It should be noted, however, that the text of this crucial passage is not entirely sound. In Dieterici’s edition, we read words that are to be translated otherwise, See Brague 1999: 99. 6 Poetics Today 19:2 exisis a fourth cause of difficulty in the attainment of truth that did not exist in ancient times—habit and education. He means thereby, he ex- Plains, the existence of religions founded on texts whose authority should not be challenged.” This crucial difference between medieval and Greek thought should preclude any too harsh reasoning upward from the former to the latter. At any rate, the question of the relationship between “Athens” and “Jerusalem” could not be asked in a meaningful way before the latter became powerful enough to match the former. We thus have to ask what kind of relationship obtains between the Straussian enterprise and the three main versions of monotheism. The first one to come to the dock must be Judaism. A current image of ‘Strauss is that of a rabbi turned mad, of a perverse reading of philosophi- cal texts as if they were the Talmud. This image, in my opinion, is radically mistaken. The question at stake is not whether the man Strauss was Jewish or not: He himself stated that he was (Strauss 1968: 260), and the ques- tion of the worth of this statement, of the meaning of “Jewish,” and so on roust be left aside. The only question we have to face is the Jewish nature of Strauss’s enterprise. We thus have to ask, Is the Straussian idea of eso- tericiam a Jewish one? Now, the interpretation devices that are brought to bear, insofar as they are technical, have nothing specifically Jewish or “Greek” about them, nor any specificity whatsoever. Strauss mzy allude somewhere to the Jewish way of dealing with words, to the utmost par- ticular way of eliciting meaning from obscure texts (Strauss 1924: 295). But what really matters is, in my opinion, his general view of the context of esotericism. Strauss's discovery arose from the study of a Muslim (Farabi) * and of an outcast (Spinoza). Strauss repeatedly points toward a more gen- eral medieval background, the basic assumptions of which were shared by Jews and Muslims—although not by Christians. The idea of a secret doc- trine may have been extant in some stages of Christian intellectual hisory, but it was expelled at a relatively early date (G. Stroumsa 1986). Strauss, we may surmise, was aware of the non-Jewish origin of esotericism as he understood it. He often endeavored to enhance the non-Jewish character of the phenomena he stumbled on. For instance, he is eager to underline that a certain doctrine in Maimonides cannot be traced back to the Tal- aud but comes from a Muslim source. He always looks for non-Jewish, Islamic sources of Maimonides (Strauss 1935: 115 n. 4; 19998: 455). As a matter of fact, some dimensions of esotericism can be assessed 20. Maimonides 1929; I, 91, 44, 29-45, 16; Maimonides 1969: 66-67. Quoted or alluded to ‘in Serums 1959: 164-65, and 1969: xx. See Brague forthcoming. Brague + Leo Strauss's “Muslim” Understanding of Greek Philosaphy 247 more easily in the Islamic world, for historical reasons." A permission, and in some extreme cases, a duty of dissimulation (tagiyya) is present in Shi'ism, and especially in the Ismaeli circles with which the faldsi shared some ideas Esotericim could iink up philosophy with a more or less political mysticism. As for the fact of esotericiam in Islamic philosophers, it is commonly admitted, we are at no pains for how to find examples. ‘The central witnesses in medieval times are, as is well-known, Ibn Tufayl's preface to his Hayy ibn Yaqzin (1936: 1-16) and the suspicion leveled by Averroes against al-Ghazlt (1987 [1990]: 1, § 52, 90). Moreover, in recent times, many medieval works on which Strauss never published, including treatises by Avicenna (1969; see Gardet 1951), are commonly recognized as meant for an elite only, ‘The fact of esotericism in Muslim thought is manifest. Hence, Straus- sian hermencutics takes its bearings from, and finds its stronghold in, the historical exploration of this field, although some results of previous and, for Strauss, paradigmatic research on Islamic esotericiam have undergone and al-Biruni, had supposed that the Brahmins quoted by Islamic heretics were sheer puppets on which they could foist their own critique of Reve- lation (Kraus 1994: 167). Strauss had taken this procedure as a model of esoteric communication (Strauss 1952: 125 n. 95). But in fact, the Islamic writer probably relied upon sound historical evidence on Indian-Muslim encounter? But even supposed that assumption of esotericism can be true by and large, we should not content ourselves with mere fact. This means that esotericism should not be considered as stemming from merely exterior causes that the historian could assess without further ado. It corresponds to inner features of the Islamic conception of Revelation, that is, to the way it conceives of the basic relationship of man to the Absolute. First, Revelation in Islam is a mere fact, a fachon brutum. This is the way Strauss conceives religious Revelation: “There is only ane objection to Plato- Aristotle: and that is the factum brufum of revelation, or of the ‘personal’ God. I say: fachon brutum—for there is xo argument whatsoever, theoretical, practical, existential... , not even the argument of paradox (a paradox as such, after all, can be called for by reason, as Kierkegaard shows all too well) a1, Sct Reve 16. Phe ame method if applied to the etudly of modern thinker of the Arabic renascence in Keddie 1972. See Jadaane 1973: 96: 92. a2, On the Shi'ite conception of taxiyye, wif county Peek we Mapes soho Processual coming: to light of wath, ig crmmed by God, see Meyer 180 6 Tg. The fatal blow agelant Krauss thee, S, Pines, was given i 48 Poetics Today 19:2 from the agnoia thew, which characterizes the genuine philosopher, to be- Bef (Strauss 198ga: 108). Second, its content is a text, a written text, a book. The phenomenon of the Sacred Book is far more peculiar to Islam than to Christianity. In Islam, what is revealed by God is the Sacred Book itself. The latter is, liter- ally speaking, the word of God, dictated to the Prophet (through the angel Gabriel). Christianity possesses sacred books, too, one of which it shares with Judaism. But what is revealed, properly speaking, is not 90 much a book as a person. The Word of God is first and foremost Jesus Christ, and only derivatively the written records of his teachings and life in the New ‘Testament. Judaism stands midway: Unlike Christianity and like Islam, it does not admit an incarnation, and what is revealed is a law; unlike Islam, however, its sacred writings are not immediately present but mediated through the very process of their reception, discussion, and interpretation. Basic Concepts of Esotericism ‘We can lend some probability to our hypothesis abeut the Muslim origin of Strauss’s conception of esotericiam by examining the basic concepts it involves, Historicity In a very interesting article, Aviewer Raviteky (1981: 108-9, 110-11 0. 95, 111) has shown that Strauss's reading of Maimonides was anticipated by some medieval commentators to the Gwide. To begin with, this is espe~ cially the case with Samuel ben Judah ibn Tibbon, the very translator of the Guide: Somie quotations can't help but remind us with an outstanding clarity of Straust’s hermeneutics, a paint Raviteky himeelf underlines —for example, on Solomon (considered as the author of Qeheld), on repetition of contradictory teachings, or on our baving to pick up the rarest statement as expressing the author's view. On the other hand, Ravithy underlines elsewhere that there are momentous differences between Strauss and the medieval commentators. In particular, their views about the content of the hidden doctrine is that the bidden teaching of the Bible is identical to Aristotelian physics and metaphysics; Strauss's view, an the other hand, is that what Maimonides endeavors 'to conceal from the common reader is that the two cannot be reconciled (Ravitzky 1990: 178-8). As for the idea of history, Raviteky mentions, “Ibn Tibbon’s intrigu- ‘24. See the implications of the text by Machiavelli (Disors, IT, 5) quoted in Sermuas g8gb: 206, Brague - Leo Strauis’s “Musiim" Understanding of Greek Philosophy 249 ing notion of the dynamic nature of the spiritual history of Israel and the gradual purification of the religious concept of the community through- out the ages” (1981: 111). He quotes fascinating statements by Ibn Tibbon. according to which esotericiam is a necessity under certain circumstances only and, consequently, may vary according to them. A greater or lesser degree of esotericiam can be apposite in certain times. The general trend is toward progress: Enlightenment increases steadily” The issue at stake is the provisional character of esotericism or its definitive necessity. Mai- monides’ early commentators viewed esoteric communication as a device whose usefulness varies according to the more or less widespread enlight- enment of their contemporaries. Strans's outlook, on the other hand, apparently denies progres in quite a radical way. His view of history is a static one. On this point, too, he is a follower of Maimonides. Therefore, caotericism cannot be provisory; no Enlightenment whatsoever will ever be able to bridge the gap between the elite and the vulgar: “They believed that the gulf separating ‘the wise’ and ‘the vulgar’ was a basic fact of human nature which could not be influenced by any progress of popular education: philosophy, or science, was essentially a privilege of ‘the few’” (Strauss 1952: 94). This is more in keeping with Muslim than with Jewish views. According to the former, Revelation (in philosophical terms: man's relationship to the Absolute) does not take place through history—although it does take place ix history, because of man’s historical nature; therefore no idea of a salvation history is available (Falaturi 1977), and consequently, no secularization of this idea is “progress”: “I in characteristic that the believers in progress are found. largely among the sectarians and those not in good standing with ortho- doxy* {von Grunebaum 1961: 71)—for example, Razi (1939: 301). The idea of Elite Strauss’s csotericist hermencutics supposes that philosophical writings are genuinely addressed to elite readers to whom their real purpose is dis- closed, whereas common people are paid lip service and consolidated in elite may consist of ons individual. Since Socrates always addressed a single man, esoteric writing is “Socratic” (Strauss 1g99b: 595; 198gb: 272). ‘This idea has clear antecedents in later Greek philosophy, for instance in Galen* The same holds true for the idea of a “philosophy of the elite.” Sx in peti: he ne pg of Mowe bom 75 act Mae of Ne 6. Seed pat Tg (VII gb ack), quod a Weer 7, See Porphyry 1856: ete The tic "Polonopy ofthe REGS covae a the walled 20 —s~Poettics Today 19:2 The constitution of an elite is quite a common feature of all religious or scientific systems. Yet, a further step is taken when the existence of an elite is thematized. As a rule, this happens in the elite itself and through its reflection on its own status. This leads to the coining of a special word, something like the “rest” of the Prophets. Such a word is not extant before medieval Judaism. Jewish esotericism is rooted in the Tabnud. The considered themselves as representatives of Israel, which stands for man- Kind: “Rabbinical Judaiam understood iteelf as a vicarious elite, which means that a group separates iteelf inside of an over-arching bond, The iso- lation of rabbinical Judaisen was not primarily socially motivated, but its roots were in the theological idea of Israel's isolation vis-a-vis the nations of the world, in the inner isolation of Israe! that was rendered necessary by that, and which the rabbis used to represent” (Wevers 1975: 199, atid sce 203, my translation), The idea of representation is the central one: There is no knowledge reserved to a select elite, since the elite iteelf is meant to function as a substitute for the vulgar. The elite ia not an end in iteelf. Its role is a vicarious one. Therefore, it is not self-centered but responsible for the rest of the community to which it belongs. On the other hand, if an elite is conceived of as radically severed from the rest of mankind, for which it does not stand and toward which it bears no responsibility, the gap that separates it cannot be bridged. Its separa- tion must then be definitive, whereas a representative, hence responsible, elite is but provisionally separated from mankind. Islamic conceptions of the elite may vary (Beg 1978). But “the philosophers restricted the elite most, and had no hope of bringing the masses up to elite status, as the other groups [shi’a, sufia] might” (Keddic 1963: 59). An extreme cxample of the philosophic attitude is to be found in Farabi’s identification of the elite, absolutely speaking, with the philosopher who ia a philosopher in the absolute meaning of the term (1g69b: IH, 19, § ug, p. 18g). In another work, the same author appears to have a more balanced stance toward the rest of the city: ‘We [philosophers] are political in nature. It is incumbent to us therefore to (a) live in harmony with the public, love them and prefer doing what is useful to them and redounds to the improvement of their condition (just as it is incam- bent on them to do the sume in our regard). (b) Associate them in the good whose care is entrusted to us (just as it is incumbent on them to amociate us in the good things whose care is entrusted to them) by showing them the truth concerning the opinions they hold in their religions; for when they share with Se Theology of Aristotle, TV, § 61, in Badawt 1977 [1 |: 61; English in “Theology of Aristotle” 1959: 2: 361. See Bragwe 1997. toss! Brague « Leo Strauss's “Muslim” Understanding of Greek Philosophy 251 us the truth, it will be possible for them, to the extent of their ability, to amso- ciate with philosophers in the happincas of philosophy. (c) Move them sway from things—arguments, opinions, lews—in which we find they are not right. (Kitab ab;Jodal, English translation cited in Mahd, 1986: 2-15)" ‘The best thing that the philosopher can do toward the vulgar is to cor- rect their opinions. Basically, however, the philosopher has no responsi- losophers. The nonphilosophical mob must be kept at bay. It is cared for only insofar as its existence and well-being secures the existence of a society in which philosophy is possible. The vulgar are always a means, never an end. Esotericism could be justified, and actually was, as a means of pro- tecting the faith of the weak (see, for instance, 1 Corinthians 8: 9-19). For the philosopher, it does not protect anything but the philosopher's know!- edge. For even “respect,” if any, for the faith af the weaker ones is a way of avoiding rioting among the rabble, of preserving social order, and hence of allowing the philosopher to go on pursuing his own goal, contemplation. In later Jewish thought, the idea of an elite does occur. The question is to which of the two models of the “elie” we have just briefly outlined this idea belongs, when it is handled by Jewish authors. Now, everything lying model in Saadia is probably the “vicarious” one: The benefits result- ing from the choice of an individual (khass, same root as thacm) are ori- ented toward the well-being of the commumity.” In Bahya, the idea of an elite is undoubtedly present but has as balance-weights, on the one hand, the general consideration according to which every privilege involves an enforced responsibility, and, on the other hand, the traditional warning against standing apart from tradition and community.” In Jehuda Halevi's Fuzari, the idea of an elite, or “substance,” or “heart” (saffea / Tbn Tibbon: segula) of mankind, transmitted from Adam to the Patriarchs, and so on, is well-known. But its ultimate origin should be most probably looked for in the Muslim world, more precisely in Shi’iam (Pines 1980: 167-79). Tt looks as though Maimonides’ idea of an elite is the second, “philo- sophical” one, which originates in pagan or Islamic cultural surroundings (Heinemann 1996: 70 n. 2). But his elitism did not remain unchallenged; for example, Gersonides polemicizes against Maimonides’ taste for es0- teric communication and the devices he makes use of—lack of order, 98, The mu, translated is now published, for instance in Farabi 1987: 12982, 1-6 (I omit to signal two textual emendations by Mahdi). 9. Sandia 1970: IIT, 116; 1948: 197, and see TH, § 2; Saaciia 1970: 121; 1948: 143. go. Bahya b. Paquda sgie: IIT, 6, 156-58; IIL, , n° 7, 199-40; VIL, 2; V, 5, 241, 1-2. 22 Poetics Today 19:2 obscure phrases, and so forth. The duty of communicating one’s results, which behooves the scholar, is deduced from an ontology that Gersonides, in his introduction to the Wars of the Lord, grounds on 2 theory of ema- nation: the well-known Neoplatonic or Bonaventurian boawm difesioom st (Gersonides 1569: gab and ad; 1866: 8, 6-go, and 5, 93-96, 2; 1984; 1:100- 101; see Strauss 1995: 79-86). Christianity as a Third City Tt looks like that for Strauss the real alternative to “Athens” and “jeru- salem" (as Strauss understands the latter's fundamental stance) is Chris- tianity, Strauss expresses this idea in a text that, in my opinion, is particu- larly instrumental to our understanding of what is at stake with the “Athens and Jerusalem” theme, his 1936 French essay on Farabi’s and Maimonides’ political science. We read at the beginning: What lead to the break with ancient thought was neither the Bible nor the Koran, but perhaps the New Testament, and doubtless Reforraztion and mod- ern philosophy. The leading idea upon which Greeks and Jews agpee is precisely the idea of divine Law as of a unique and all-encompassing law that is at the same time a religious law, a civil law and s moral law. And actually, a Greek of divine Law lies at the ground of Jewiah and Miualim philosophy of Torah or of shari’ah: according to Avicenna, Plato's Laws are the standard work on prophecy and shari'ah. (Strauss 1936c: 2; on Reformation, Strauss 1946: 598) ‘We can find other statements to the same effect. For example, “Islamic and Jewish philosophers of the Middle Ages are more ‘primitive’ than modern philosophers, because they are not led, as these are, by the deriva- tive idea of natural right, but by the original, ancient idea of Law as of a unified, total order of human life. In other words: because they are dis- ciples of Plato and not disciples of Christians” (Strauss 1995: 62). Or again: “Judaism and Islam on the one hind and Christianity on the other." As against Christianity, the lslamic-Jewish world is-said to resemble classical Greece (Strauss 1952: 9, 18-19, 21). ‘We can elicit from these statements a basic idea: A deep harmony ob- tains between “Athens” and “Jerusalem” when the latter is understood from what we could call a “Meccan” vantage; this harmony ia dispelled when both are seen from the point of view of Christianity (perhaps “Rome” could do). Nietzsche's critique of culture, if we are to trust Strauss, “strove downwards to the depths of pre-Christian’ Jewish .as well as Greco- European mind” (Strauss 199g: 2438). If Christianity is scen as a shallow Brague + Leo Strauss's “Muslim” Understanding of Greek Phiosophy 253 that underlies and conceals the deeper truth of both Athens and Jerusalem, it is little wonder that Strauss should not simply forget (Beneton 1987: 79-80), but should systematically neglect, every Christian clement in Western history, Silence is for Strauss the best way to indicate that a subject does not deserve interest (Strauss 1958: go). What is more, we read under his pen phrases like “the whole kingdom of darkness with Thomas Aquinas at its head” (Strauss 1968: 219). We could complement Strauss’s explicit contrast of Athens and Jeru- salem by our giving names to their possible coming together, on the one hand, and to their greatest divergence, on the other hand. I should like to take advantage of the meaningful character of the names of some other cities and propose the following schema: Se At the bottom of this more or less explicit structure lies the (very ex- plicitly emphasized) idea of Law. “Revelation, as understood by Jews and Muslims, had the form of Law” (Strauss 1937: 97). This statement is an obvious truth. Strauss generalizes it and supposes that the content of any Revelation must be a law (Strauss 1g8gb: 234, 244). Christianity does not present itself as a Law, not even as a “New Law," so the characterization of Christianity—even by its own supporters—as a “New Law” should not be taken for granted, as it commonly is. The phrase “new law” (katnos nomos), which occurs in some Christian writers, is utterly absent from the New Testament. What does exist there is the idea of a “New Covenant” or, in John’s Gospel, “new commandment.” It does not seem that Strauss has Teflected on the parallel between the passage from the Old Covenant to the New, that is, from the law to Jesus Christ as the man on the one hand, and the Socratic revolution, seen as the passage from the cosmos to the human soul, on the other hand. Still more remarkable is the fact that, ac- cording to Strauss, the same idea of Law holds true for the “world.” Both “Athens” (the cosmos) and “Jerusalem” (revealed Law) are basically laws. Strauss draws a parallel between coamos and Law: “The Torah is, like the world, as ‘world,’ before philosophy” (Strauss 1935: 86). By so doing, See, for example, Bernard af Clairvaux E legislator); Aqui: eter co hc Lown ene tig eae goo we A Poetics Today 19:2 Strauss reminds us of—strange berficllows— Schelling, who wrote: “Juda- ism and Paganism, though they differ in other respects, have in common that both are under the Law” (Schelling 1857: 57). On the other hand, one could perhaps look at the antithesis between Athens and Jerusalem from a non-“Meccan,” nay “Roman,” point of view. One would have then to see to what extent the very antithesis between Athens and. Jerusalem owes its survival and its permanent fruitfuloess in Western culture to the “Roman” character of the latter. But that is another story" Conclusion Be that as it may, we may conclude, as for Strauss himself, that his herme- neutics arose from a study of medieval thought, more especially of its Jew- ish version, and later on extended to the atudy of classical Greek thought. But the Jewish philosophical writers from whom he took his bearings were precisely those upon which the influence of Islamic thought patterns pre- vailed. At any rate, his understanding of the Greeks betrays unmistakable “Muslim” features. This holds true, on the one hand, because of the obvi- ous influence of the /alasife, whom we may safely cal] Muslims since they lived in a Muslim surrounding, although, according to Strauss, they were hardly devout believers (or even if, like Razi, they were outspoken free- thinkers). On the other hand, we should acknowledge the more discreet presence of some basic “Islamic” assumptions as to the nature of Revela- tion and “religion.” Strauss’s interpretation of the ancients, an the face of things a Jewish one, bears witness of the deep influence Islam exercised on the way in which medieval Judaism had to formulate its basic tenets. If we want to understand him more deeply, we should complement the “que- telle des anciens et des modernes” by an older, medieval quarrel among the three religions that claim a share in Abraham's heritage. References Averroes 1987 [1990] Zahgfet at-Tahafet. LYncohivence de Mincohtrence, Texte arabe itebli par M. Banyger (Beirut: Dar el-Machreq), 1969 Epistela sulle vite fature, edived by F. Lucchetra (Padua: Antenore). Badawi, Abdurrahman 197 [1988] Pletinas apd Arshes (Kurwait: Wakalat al-matbe‘at). 1978 [p47] Avistetaes pad Avaber (Kuwait: Wakslne al-rastbo'se). 32. 1 tried to sketch such « story in Brague 19999. For an English sinumary, sec Brague 2.4, Braque « Leo Strauss’s “Musil” Understanding of Greek Philosophy 255 1989 [1973] Platon ox pays islam (Beirut: Dar al-Andaloas). Bebyab Pqoda sg Hoa ie Df ee, cy A. 8 Yabuda (Leyde: Brill). 1 tine eto! ” Encyclopedia of Islan, t. 4, col. 10988-11008. veg “Foor ane wciologe dela ploeopie," Critique g: 850-66. Benardete, Seth 1978 *Leo Straus: The City and Man," Political Science Reviewer 8:.-20. Beneton, Philippe : 1987 Introduction @ la politiqus moderne. Démecratis libivale ot tctalitariswe (Paris: Hachette), Bernard of Clairvaux 263 [457] De conetrascne in Traciatar a oprsesie, edited by J. Leclercq and H. M. ] Eocknis, Opere, sol . 999-488 (Rome: Eeitiones (Cistercienaes) Teak ki Pench traction of Za si Pomme, raz (Paris Ago Bollack, Jean 1967 “Un silence de Platom [ . .. }," Reows de Philolagie 41: 042-46. Rémi ig8ge “Athénes, Jérumlem, La Mecque. La lecture ‘musulmane’ de la philosophic Fees per tee Sen French translation by B. Vergely, Rene os Mdaplpriqne ot de Mande, 99- (00D Roney eel and Rached 108, Raa de Mitapgign ode Mena, 4-7. 3991 “Leo Straus and Maimonides,” English translation by C. J. Sheldon in Leo Sivmas’ 7 aenglt: Toward « Criteal Exgagenens, ited by A. 5 93-114 (Boulder, CO: Lynn Rienner). 1g9gb Review of A. Giese (transl), Ikhwan as-Safa', Mensch und Tier vor dem Kenig der Dachimen, elit Crip de Amol Lemaire, 10: 9-90 1996 “Korum prasclara ingenia: Conscience de le nouveauté et prétention & la continuité cher Farabi et Matmomide,” in Kéudas de Philesaphis Arab, Actes hs Colloqua, Bordemnx, 17- op Not edited by D. Mallet, Bulletin d'Etudes Orientales 1996: 87-102. ws “La philosophic dans la ‘Théologie d’Aristote.’ Four un inventaire,” Decementi ¢ studi tradizions flsegica madioeale 8: 365-87. Sattnomning Memes Mpussee inn Fmages de Platon ot lectures da ses orwores: La trans- formation de Platom & irene les sities, dined by A. Neschke (Louvain: Peete). nud. “Is Western Culture a “Tale of Two Citics’?” Unpublished lecture. Burnyeat, Miles F, 1985 “Sphynx without a Secret,” New York Reolas of Bosks, May go: 50-36. Fulanuri, Abdoljawad 1977 “Daa Feblen einer Heilageachichte io Inlam,” Miscellanea Madiassalia, 1: Die Macht des Guten und Bésen, 72-80. Farabi 1943 Alfarabius, De Platonir ptilssophis, edited by F, Rosenthal and R. Walzer (Plato ‘arabus, vol. 2) (London: Warburg Institute). 1968 Unierancer Eanployed ix Logic (Arabic text), edited with introduction and notes by ‘MM. Mahdi (Beirat: Dar )- 196ga Aferobi’s Phileenphy of Plats and Arisetl, ranalated with an introduction by Mubsin ‘Mahdi (Ithaca, NY: Cornell Universit 196gb Book of Letters, edited by M. Mahdi (Beira: Dar 1985 Ferabi’s Meal Stete, edited by R. Walzer (Oxford: Oxford University Press). 1987 Ab-Mantigiyyst i-al-Ferabi, edited by M, T. Dancsh-Pajuh (Qum: Makiabat Ayay Allah al-Uzma al-Marashi al-Najafi). 256 ~=—s- Poetics Today 19:2 Gaiscr, Konrad 1959 Pretraptih und Partnese bei Platen (Seongart: KobJharomet). Gardet, Louis 1951 “Un cas typique de l'ésorérinme avicennien: sx doctrine de la résurrection des corps,” Rane du Caste, 2° 14 (141): 68-94. - Loxet}, 2 Wit of he Lr emedy &. b, we.»(Phcein jh Pabon Hdmeae ne “peas Sacer fmt Hlolahey, Helomt, and Walter Obritoph Zimmesti, cs, ‘Thm Abt Us Fasc . wt OT ena derne ‘Dar maktabat al-Hayah). 096 Fle len Yap. Rec phesophique Tba Thos sted by L. Gti, ed ed (Beyrouth: Imprimerie Catholique) Thwin ar$ 1985 Rerk'l, edited by B, Bustint : Dar. Ii"uibe'a wa ‘crnale) by ((Beyrouth: Dar Bayrug iiibe'a wa ) 1973 “Les conditions socio-culturelles de la philosophic islamique,” Stntia Adamica 98: 5~ fo. Jotiver, Joan, and Roshdi Rashed, ec, 1984 Eades sar Aviconne (Paria: Lca Belles Lettres}. Keddio, Nikkie R. 1963 “Symbol and Sincerity in Talamn,” Stadia Ilemioa 1p: 27-65, 107 Si Jnl ab ott: A Pon Beery (ete University of Califor- ‘aia Preas). Kohlberg, Ean 1975 "Some Imdmt-Sht Views on tagiyys,” Journal of the American Oriental Society 99: 905- Kearsr, Hans-Joachim 198 Plaions 6 i fondamenti della mstgfsice. Segui sulle teoria doi grincipi «.sulle dettrine nem scritte Kenn Peat +Family Rese (Man: Vie ¢ Pender) ). 1904 Alchentis, Katcsrei, Apokyphen in ain Lien. Ge Gemma Anise, berguaqageben, und elngeleees vom R. Brague (Hikiebcir: Omg ‘Lachterman, Devid. Fed nan Feces" Riswiew of Politics, 224-45. 19g) “Strauss. ‘Leaman, Oliver 1980 “Does the Interpretation of Islamic Philosophy Rest on a Miyake?” Jatsractiona! ‘Journal of Middle Fast Studies 12: 595-98. Lerner, Ralph, and Muhsin Mabdi, eda. ee Mabe Plea Poaply 1 dausea(Chicaga: Univer of Chicago Pre). ‘Mahdi, Muhsin 8. 1957 Hin Kheldr's Philosophy of History: A Study in the Philesephic Foundation of the Scinucs of Calters (London: G. Allan & Uswia). 1986 “Man and His Universe in Medieval Arabic Philosophy” in L'Hlomme ot sot weiss au reopen age: Actes du septs congris international ds; wmddldoale [ .. Pe C. Wenin, 1: 12-19 (Louvain la Neuve: Editions de! ‘Supérieur de Brague + Leo Strauss's “Muslim” Understanding of Greek Philosophy 257 Maimonides 2oep Det o8, etd by LJ (Joralem: Joni 198 The Guid of the Pepe, tracalaed with an introdoction and notes by 8, Pines (Chi ac Cen of Cee Prem 1814 Vise Preci, edited by I. F. Boissonsde (Leipaig: Weigel). Marshall, Terence 1985 “Leo Seraam, la philosophic et la science politique,” Revus Fraspais de Scions Politique 35: 605-98, 81-39. ‘Marx, Alexander 1995 “Texts by or about Maimonides,” Jewich Qperterly Revinw 05(4): 371-408. 1980 “Anla8 und Anwendung der tagiyps,” Der Islam 57(2): 246-Bo. ‘Meyerhof, Mex 1ggo “Von Alexandrien nach Bagdad, Ein Beitrag sur Geschichte des philosophischen ‘und medizinischen Unterrichts bei den Arabern,” Siteungsberichte der Preyfischen Ake- ene der Wiemscefe, Phillies bioriche Kiam: 285-409 Seerac Miariena of the Claical World and thee Aen" in Sesto contribute alla storia degli studi classici « del monde antice, 361-76 (Romie: Edizioni di Storia ¢ Letteratura). 1987 “Ermeneutica e pensiero politico in Leo Scraus,” in Papine braid, « care di Silvia Barti, 1Bg~98 (Torin: Einaudi). Moses Ibn Tibboa 3857 Ma'amar Yigqevu hewe-Megim, ccited by M. L. Bisscliches (Presburg). ‘Moees of Narbonne 1852 Der Comonenicr des Rabbi Moses Nerbonensis [ .... ] tx dam Werke More Nebuckion des Mai- ‘menider, edited by J. Goldenthal (Vienna). , Friedrich so] Te Deo of Dy eee by M. Kennedy, in The Complete Works of Friadrich Nistexchs (New York: Gordon Pres) Pines, Shlomo agBo “Shi'ite Terms and Conceptions in Judah Halevi's Kuzazi," Jeresalom Studies in Ara bie and Islam 2: 165-251. Porphyry $838 De ponphia ex aa hain ora rua, edited by G, Wolf (Berlin). ere Tom he Che fe ete ed? ARS 6: 1990 “The Secrets of the Guide to the Perplexed: Between the Thirteenth and Twentieth Centuries,” in Studies ot Maimonides, edited by I ‘Tweraky, 159-207 (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press). Rasi, Abu Bakr 1999 Abi Bakr Mohammadi fiki Zachsriae Raghensis (Rexi), Opera Philscaphice fragmen- taqus ques supersent, edited by P, Kraus (Cairo). cht Hamasorta ex Poi (Orsord: Outs Univers Prem) 1948 The Book of Beligs and Opinions, tranalated by S. Rosenblatt (New Haven, CT: Yale 1 ft bem eh, Ma ep, ny Qefih (Jeruza- Sater Cesc, Jon und Joep Montesa i Mele agg2 “Introduceié a la lectura de Leo Strauss,” in L. Strauss, Jenoalem i Atenes, edited by Sales i Coderch and Montaerrat i Molas, 7-62 (Barcelona: Barceloncea d'edicions). 258 = Poetics Today 19:2 Schelling, F. W. 1857 Philesephie der Ofenbarung (Stuttgart: Cotta). Shesov, Leo 238 fy {rin (Pac: YMCA Prem. Td Cnt Ps Cpls Amer: Po Steinschneider, Morita 8g A Aphis Pepin ann Sif -f (Saint Petere- Serauss, Leo 3909 “Das Heilige,” Der jude (Bertin) 7: 240-48, 1904 “Coleus Analyse der ibelwimenechelt Sploogas,” Der Jade (Berlin), 8: 293-914. 199% Philesphis wad Gente. Beitrage com Vostandhis Misimanis wad seiner Voriaujor (Bertin: “og “Bin vera Sent Feb” Matec ft Cac el Wiracl do 1oaae Th PAGist Pap of Hobbs: Bai and ht Gees Onl Crenon Prem). gg6c “Quelques remarques sur la science politique de Matmonide et de Parabi,” Rams 1997 "On Abravanel’s Philosophical Teodency and Political Teaching.” in lsase Adasen, ccited by J B. reed and H. Loewe, 9-109 (Camtedig: ‘Cambridge University Prem). vee Mishach Torah, Book 1, edited by M. Hyamson, Re- snag re hc ts or the Tut of Keoopleon .” Sorial Resserch 6: 502-96. 1945 "Farabi's Plato,” Louis Ginzberg Jubilee Volume, 957-93 (New York: American Academy for Jewish Research). 1946 “On a New Interpretation of Plato's Political Philosophy," Social Research 13::526-67. 1959 Whet Js Political Philesaphy? and Other Studies (Glencoe, EL: Free Press). 1964 “How to Begin to Study the ‘Guide of the Perplexed,’” in Moses Maimonides, ‘The Guide of the Proplered, translated by S. Pines, xi-lvi (Chicago: University of Chi- cago Prem). 198 The Gy and Man (Chicago: Rand MeNally) 1966 Socrates end Aristaphanes (New York: Basic Booka). 1968 Liberalism Ancient and Modern (New York: Basic Books). 1g70 “A Giving of Accounts,” The Colles (Arnapolis end Santa Fe) 2 (F 15. 1975 Ths Argument and Action of Plate’: Laws (Qhicago: University of Chicago Press). 1979 “The Manoa nfuence of Thoslogy aod Palomo” Endapendest Jornal of Philaophy sa "On the Interpretation of Genesis," L’Hamne oe Sp Capen a at cn Independent Journal of Phi- desophy 4: 1oQgh Sui is Pleonic Fool Pieiply (Chicago: Univenity of Chicago Prem). 1989 The Rebirth of Clasrical Political Ratinmalism. An Introduction to the Thonght of Lvo Stomess, Eas ond Lace by Le Sven, ele wot intocuoed by Thomas L. Faas (RE se ey clad expand elton, ied by V, Goureviash and M. 8. Beth (New York: Free Press). Scroumsa, Guy G. 2986 “Paradosis: Traditions ésotériques dans le Christianieme des premiers sitcles,” Brague - Leo Strauss's “Musiim” Understanding of Greek Philosophy 259 Ecole pratique des Hautes Etudes, 5th section, Collogus du Centensire, 5, Les lititratures serie, Feri, Seprember 2-25, 1966, Communications, 9-208. 3985 “The Barahima in Early Kalim,” Jerusalem Studies on Arsbic and Inlem 6: 299-41. 3991 “Al-Farabi and Maimonides on the Christian Philosophical Tradition: A Reevalna- tion,” Der Inlem 68: 263-87. “Theology of Aristotle” Lew _ wy and vol ee ven ner) . ‘Thomas Aquinas, Saint 1907 Summa theolegica (Rome: Forzani). ‘Voegelin, Eric, Alfred Schitz, Leo Straum, and Aron Gurwitech 1995 Brigfcecksel aher “Dis neus Wissenschaft dor Foliit,” edited by Peter J. Opitz (Frei- ‘burg: Alber). vou Grunebaum, Gustav E. 1961 Aslam: Essays im the Nature and Growth of « Cultwrel Traditien, od ed. (London: Routledge god Kegan Pani) i a oe Chrisie On Uy Pre a7 Gini und Ceeing in rebinichn Jodo (ex: De Grey Copyright © 2003 EBSCO Publishing

Você também pode gostar