Você está na página 1de 4

Introduction

WHAT IS THE PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION?

What is the philosophy of religion? It was at one time generally understood


to mean religious philosophizing in the sense of the philosophical defense of
religious convictions. It was seen as continuing the work of "natural," distin-
guished from "revealed," theology.1 Its program was to demonstrate ration-
ally the existence of God, thus preparing the way for the claims of revelation.
But it seems better to call this endeavor "natural theology" and to term the
wider philosophical defense of religious beliefs "apologetics." Then we may
reserve the name "philosophy of religion" for what (by analogy with philos-
ophy of science, philosophy of art, etc.) is its proper meaning, namely, philo-
sophical thinking about religion.
Philosophy of religion, then, is not an organ of religious teaching. Indeed,
it need not be undertaken from a religious standpoint at all. The atheist, the
agnostic, and the person of faith all can and do philosophize about religion.
Philosophy of religion is, accordingly, not a branch of theology (meaning by
"theology" the systematic formulation of religious beliefs), but a branch of
philosophy. It studies the concepts and belief systems of the religions as well
as the prior phenomena of religious experience and the activities of worship
and meditation on which these belief systems rest and out of which they have
arisen.
Philosophy of religion is thus a second-order activity, standing apart from

These terms are defined on pp. 57-58.

1
2 Introduction

its subject matter. It is not itself a part of the religious realm but is related to it
as, for example, the philosophy of law is related to the realm of legal phenom-
ena and to juridical concepts and modes of reasoning, or the philosophy of art
to artistic phenomena and to the categories and methods of aesthetic discus-
sion. The philosophy of religion is thus related to the particular religions and
theologies of the world as the philosophy of science relates to the special
sciences. It seeks to analyze concepts such as God, dharma, Brahman, salva-
tion, worship, creation, sacrifice, nirvana, eternal life, etc., and to determine
the nature of religious utterances in comparison with those of everyday life,
scientific discovery, morality, and the imaginative expressions of the arts.
What, however, is religion? Many different definitions have been proposed.
Some of these are phenomenological, trying to state that which is common to
all the acknowledged forms of religion; for example, religion is "human
recognition of a superhuman controlling power and especially of a personal
God or gods entitled to obedience and worship" (Concise Oxford Dictionary).
Others are interpretative. Thus there are psychological definitionsfor exam-
ple, "the feelings, acts, and experiences of individual men in their solitude, so
far as they apprehend themselves to stand in relation to whatever they may
consider the divine" (William James). Others are sociologicalfor example,
"a set of beliefs, practices, and institutions which men have evolved in various
societies" (Talcott Parsons). Others, again, are naturalisticfor example, "a
body of scruples which impede the free exercise of our faculties" (Salomon
Reinach) or, more sympathetically, "ethics heightened, enkindled, lit up by
feeling" (Matthew Arnold). Yet others are religious definitions of religionfor
example, "Religion is the recognition that all things are manifestations of a
Power which transcends our knowledge" (Herbert Spencer), or again,
"humanity's response to the divine."
But such definitions are all stipulative: they decide how the term is to be
used and impose this in the form of a definition. Perhaps a more realistic view
is that the word "religion" does not have a single correct meaning but that the
many different phenomena subsumed under it are related in the way that the
philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein has characterized as family resemblance.
His own example was the word "game." You cannot define a game as being
played for pleasure (for some are played for profit), or as being competitive
(for some are solo performances), or as requiring skill (for some depend on
chance), or indeed it would seem by any single feature. Yet all these different
kinds of game overlap in character with some other kinds, which in turn
overlap in different ways with yet other kinds, so that the whole ramifying
collection hangs together in a complex network of similarities and differences
which Wittgenstein likened to the resemblances and differences appearing
within a family.2 We may apply Wittgenstein's idea to the word "religion."

^Philosophical Investigations, 2nd. ed., trans. G.E.M. Anscombe (Oxford: Basic Blackwell & Mott,
Ltd., 1958), pp. 66-67.
Introduction 3

Perhaps there is no one characteristic of everything that can be called a religion


but rather a set of "family resemblances." In much religion there is the worship
of a God or gods; but in Theravada Buddhism, for example, there is not. Again,
religion often makes for social cohesion; yet in some strands it is aptly
characterized as "what man does with his solitariness" (A. N. Whitehead).
Again, religion often makes for the inner harmony of the individual; yet some
of the greatest religious innovators seemed to their contemporaries to be
unbalanced and even insane. The family resemblances model allows for such
differences. It also allows us to acknowledge the similarities as well as the
differences between more standard examples of religion and such secular
faiths as Marxism. Marxism has its eschatological ideal of the ultimate class-
less society, its doctrine of predestination through historical necessity, its
scriptures, prophets, saints, and martyrs. Thus we can see it as sharing some
of the features of the family of religions while lacking other and probably more
central ones. But whether a movement is religious is not an all-or-nothing
matter but a question of degree within a widely spreading network of resem-
blances and differences.
Within this ramifying set of family resemblances there is, however, one
feature which is extremely widespread even though not universal. This is a
concern with what is variously called salvation or liberation. This is probably
not a feature of "primitive" or "archaic" religion, which is more concerned
with keeping things on an even keel, avoiding catastrophe. However, all the
great developed world faiths have a soteriological (from the Greek soteria,
salvation) structure. They offer a transition from a radically unsatisfactory
state to a limitlessly better one. They each speak in their different ways of the
wrong or distorted or deluded character of our present human existence in its
ordinary, unchanged condition. It is a "fallen" life, lived in alienation from
God; or it is caught in the world-illusion of maya; or it is pervaded throughout
by dukkha, radical unsatisfactoriness. They also proclaim, as the basis for their
gospel, that the Ultimate, the Real, the Divine, with which our present exis-
tence is out of joint, is good, or gracious, or otherwise to be sought and
responded to; the ultimately real is also the ultimately valuable. Completing
the soteriological structure, they each offer their own way to the Ultimate
through faith in response to divine grace; or through total self-giving to God;
or through the spiritual discipline and maturing which leads to enlightenment
and liberation. In each case, salvation or liberation consists of a new and
limitlessly better quality of existence which comes about in the transition from
self-centeredness to Reality-centeredness.
In this discussion I have been following the conventional view of religions
as clearly demarcated entitiesChristianity, Hinduism, Buddhism, and so on.
In fact, however, the picture is more complex than this, and in Chapter 9
I shall describe the important critique of the idea of "a religion" offered
in our time by Wilfred Cantwell Smith.
In the meantime the discussion will focus upon the Judaic-Christian concept
4 Introduction

of God, which lies behind our western Atlantic civilization and still constitutes
the main religious option within our culture. It will also be important to see
how contemporary philosophical methods can be applied to the ideas of quite
different religious traditions, and this will be done, as a sample, in relation to
the Indian belief in reincarnation (Chapter 11). It is also necessary, in the "one
world" of today, to face the problem of the apparently conflicting truth claims
of the various religions. This issue, which constitutes one of the main growing
points of the philosophy of religion today, will be explored in Chapter 9.

Você também pode gostar