Você está na página 1de 10

C HA P T E R 1 9

The Physics of Gases

19.1 The Nature o f Gases are bodies and there is void in which these bodies
are placed and through which they move
Early Concepts
about. . . . " Ordinary matter is composed of these
two realities: solid, everlasting particles and, on
From the time of the earliest recorded philo
the other hand, the void, or what we might
sophical speculations to the present day, the
loosely call the vacuum.
human mind has been haunted by some para
Note that by their very definition these
doxical propositions: On the one side we can with
atoms are not directly perceptible, and until
our hands cut or subdivide gross matter-a rock
about 150 years ago there were very few fruit
or a quantity of water-into smaller and smaller
parts, until the crudeness of our tools or te
ful and unambiguous consequences that could be
drawn from the atomic hypothesis to serve as
deficiency of our sight, but never the matenal
experimental tests of this challenging sp:culative
itself, calls a halt to our experiments. Consequent
idea. Even at the beginning of the twentieth cen
ly, we might conclude that matter is inherently
tury when such confirmation was at hand, there
wer important scientists who still rejected the
infinitely subdivisible. But on the other hand, our
imagination encounters difficulty when ,!,e
concept of atoms as too convenient a fable,
demand that it present to us matter as a collectlon
unworthy of serious consideration by " hard
of truly infinitely small parts, and this view
boiled" investigators.
makes for logical problems as well. So where our
It is therefore not surprising that the struc
senses tend to one view of mattel; our reason per
ture of matter was for a long time the subject of
suades us of another.
inconclusive discussions, whether the atomistic
The great compromise was formulated about
view was rejected (as by Plato, Aristotle, and their
2400 years ago by the Greek philosophers Leu
diverse followers) or in some form accepted (by
cippus and Democritus, and later extended by
Galileo, Gassendi, Bacon, Descartes, Newton,


Epicurus. It is of course the atomistic idea (Sec
Leibniz and many of their contemporaries) . We
tion 3.2). Our senses and our reason would both
might s eculate that the idea of small particles
rest satisfied if we assumed that matter is indeed
became more convincing as a consequence of
divisible far beyond immediate experience, but
Newton's work, in which, as we have seen, the
that there does exist an ultimate substructure of
postulates leading to the law of universal grav
infinitely hard, uncuttable, indivisible particles,
itation provided that the particles of matter are
which we might provisionally name corpuscles
the agencies of mutual attraction. Of course,
or atoms.
these are not necessarily identical with ultimately
The Roman poet Lucretius, whose book
De Rerum Natura (The Nature of the Universe) indivisible particles or atoms. Yet the surpassing
success of the treatment of gravitation in terms
was cited before in connection with the origins
of the mechanics of particles could turn the
of the law of conservation of mass, exemplified
thoughts again to the idea that the mechanics of
the teaching of those now-largely-lost Greek
small discrete bodies is the key to all phenomena.
original works. He gave a summary of this atom
Newton himself wrote in the introduction to
istic science, which (according to George Sarton)
the Principia:
marked the climax of Roman scientific thought.
We have noted, of course, that Lucretius' work Then the motions of the planets, the comets,
is not to be regarded as primarily a science text. the moon, and the sea are deduced from these
His leading theme is "All nature then, as it [gravitational] forces, by propositions that are
exists by itself, is founded on two things: There also mathematical. If o nly we could derive
266 I The Physics of Gases

the other phenomena of nature from mechan that we must not pass over if we wish to under
ical principles by the same kind of reasoning! stand fully the development of the atomistic
For many things lead me to have a suspicion that view. Ever since its early inception, atomism has
all phenomena may depend on certain forces by generally been regarded as atheistic; as the excerpt
which the particles of bodies . . . either are from Lucretius (Section 1 5 . 1 ) indicated, the
impelled toward one another and cohere in atomist openly professed to give an explanation
regular figures, or are repelled from one another of matter and events not in terms of impenetra
and recede. Since these forces are unknown, ble designs of an ever-present Creator and Ruler,
philosophers have hitherto made trial of nature but by means of the interplay and structure of
in vain. But I hope that the principles set down material bodies. In the seventeenth century,
here will shed some light on either this mode of philosophers such as Pierre Gassendi had
philosophizing or some truer one. attempted to remove the taint of atheism by
proposing that atoms are not self-animated, but
Later, in the Opticks (published 1704), we find
are inert pieces of matter that required a divine
this visionary, yet still unformalized opinion on
agency to set them into motion at the creation
atomism:
of the world.
All these things being considered, it seems In the "mechanical philosophy, " as it was
probable to me that God in the Beginning advanced especially in England by Robert Boyle,
formed Matter in solid, massy, hard, impene God was assigned the role of designer and cre
trable, movable Particles, of such Sizes and ator of the world machine, which, once set in
Figures, and with such other Properties, and in motion, could run from then on by His pleasure
such Proportion to space, as most conduced to without continual active intervention; all observ
the end for which he formed them; and as able events should then be ultimately explainable
these primitive Particles being Solids, are incom by the configurations, sizes, and shapes of the
parably harder than any porous Bodies com eternal particles or by the mathematical laws of
pounded of them; even so very hard as never force and motion ruling among them.
to wear or break in pieces; no ordinary Power As we have seen in the previous chapter,
being able to divide what God himself made Newton himself did not accept the extreme ver
one in the first Creation . . . . And therefore that sion of the world-machine theory that would
Nature may be lasting, the Changes of cor forbid God to take constantly an active part in
poreal Things are to be placed only in the the physical world. Yet the above quotation
various Separations and new Associations, from the Opticks shows that in formulating the
and Motions of these permanent Particles; principles of his own system of the world, New
compound Bodies being apt to break, not in the ton was primarily concerned with specifying the
midst of solid Particles, but where those Par results of God's initial creative acts, so that in
ticles are laid together . . . practice the Newtonian system could easily be
God is able to create Particles of Matter of interpreted as a world machine.
several Sizes and Figures and in general Pro Some of Newton's other remarks on the
portion to the space they occupy, and perhaps properties of atoms did give support to those who
of different Densities and Forces . . . . Now, by were dissatisfied with the mechanistic philosophy
the help of these Principles, all material Things advocated by Descartes (Section 6.1). The Carte
seem to have been composed of the hard and sians rejected the hypothesis of " action at a dis
solid Particles above mentioned-variously tance," preferring to believe that all apparent
associated in the first Creation by the Coun long-range forces, such as gravity, could be
sel of an intelligent Agent. For it became him explained by contact actions propagated through
who created them to set them in order. And if an intervening material medium (the ether) .
he did so, it's unphilosophical to seek for any Newton, while rejecting in principle the possibility
other Origin of the World, or to pretend that of true action at a distance (see his letter to
it might arise out of a Chaos by the mere Laws Bentley, quoted in Section 1 1.10), did explain
of Nature; though being once form'd, it may many phenomena in terms of attractive and
continue by those Laws for many Ages. repulsive forces acting between atoms.
These remarks encouraged scientists like
Part of Newton's preoccupation here is the Boscovich and Priestley in the eighteenth century
ological, and for a most excellent historic reason to develop an atomic theory of matter that relied
1 9 .2 Air Pressure / 2 6 7

more on the atoms' attractive and repulsive


Evacuated spaces
forces than on their hardness and impenetrabil
ity. The concept of an atom as a point center of
attractive and repulsive forces survived into the
twentieth century, a long with the alternative
concept of the atom as something like a billiard
ball that could interact with other billiard balls I
only by contact.

1 9 .2 Air Pressure
1
In the meantime the atomistic view of matter was Fig. 19. 1. Torricel l i barometer (two forms). The mer
extended from an entirely different direction cury col u m n in each vertical g lass tube is balanced
the research on gases. by the pressu re of the atmosphere on the free mer
Gal ileo, in his Two New Sciences ( 1 63 8 ) , cury surface in the trough. Usually h is about 0.76 m
noted that a suction pump cannot lift water at sea level.
more than about 1 0 . 5 meters. This fact was
presumably well known by the time Galileo
wrote his book; pumps were a lready being is j ust sufficient to raise water by 1 0.5 m by
used to obtain drinking water from wells and means of a pump, no more, no less!
to remove water from flooded mines, so their Evangelista Torricelli ( 1 608-1 647), once
limitations must have become evident to many briefly the pupil o f Galileo, realized that the
workmen. atmosphere exerts a pressure at the surface of the
One important consequence of the limited earth, and suspected that this air pressure might
ability of pumps to lift water was that some be sufficient to account for the phenomena pre
other method was needed to pump water out of viously attributed to Nature's abhorrence of a
deep mines, and this need provided the initial vacuum. He made the fortunate guess that mer
stimulus for the development of steam engines, cury, a liquid nearly fourteen times as dense as
wruch allowed water to be conveyed out in buck water, might be a more convenient medium for
ets. Another consequence was that physicists in laboratory experiments; indeed, it turned out
the seventeenth century became curious to dis that the same vacuum pump that could raise a
cover the reason why the suction pump worked column of water 1 0 . 5 m could lift a column of
at all, as well as why there should be a limit on mercury only 1114 as rugh, 0 . 76 m.
its ability to raise water. The pump itself is not even necessary to
If you remove air from a container and cre hold up a column of liquid in the simple instru
ate a vacuum, there is a tendency for things to ment that came to be known as the Torricelli
be sucked in. The Aristotelian phil osophers barometer. One takes a straight glass tube some
explained this fact by saying that "Nature abhors what more than 0.76 m long, open at one end
a vacuum." It is unnatural, they said, for space and sealed at the other; a bowl; and enough
not to be filled with matter, and therefore mat mercury to fiji the ulbe and the bowl. Fill the tube
ter will move so as to fill up any empty space. Trus to the brim, close the open end with your finger,
is an example of a teleological explanation, one rum it upside down in the bowl, and remove your
based on an "ultimate cause" (another one would finger, and you will find that the mercury runs
be: " Rain falls because crops need water" ). One down into the bowl, but only until the difference
of the basic goals of the new mechanical phi between the level in the tube and the level in the
losophy of the seventeenth century was to elim bowl is about 0.76 m. The result is shown in Fig.
inate such teleological expla nations, and to 1 9 . 1 (the left tube). There is now found to be an
explain phenomena instead in terms of immediate evacuated space at the top of the tube above the
physical causes. mercury. Torricelli then repeated the same pro
The Aristotelian theory seemed especially cedure with a tube that had a large bulb at the
weak in this particular case: Even if one accepts closed end, thereby making available an evacu
the assertion that Nature abhors a vacuum, one ated space of larger size in which small objects
finds it difficult to explain why this abhorrence could be fastened.
268 / The Physics of Gases

The announcement of Torricelli's experi While the height of the mercury in the tube
ments in 1 643 prompted other scientists (Otto depends on (and thus allows one to measure) the
von Guericke and Robert Boyle were among local atmospheric pressure, it does not depend on
the first) to develop better vacuum pumps for the diameter of the tube or the size of the bowl.
experimenting on vacuum phenomena and the This might at first seem rather strange, since the
properties of gases at low pressures. 1 With a pump force exerted by the mercury depends on how
and a glass j ar, one could prepare an experi much of it there is-that is, on its total volume,
mental space in which to discern the effect of not just its height. Similarly, the force of the air
light, sound, and magnetic or electric forces outside will be greater on a large bowl than on
within an atmosphere rarefied in varying degrees. a small one. Nevertheless, the mercury always
One could attempt to discover, by the difference rises to the same height whether the tube is thick
in weight of a hollow vessel before and after "ex or thin and whether the bowl is large or small.
suction" (sucking out), the weight of the gas This fact is explained if we recognize that it is the
within. Conversely, one could also pump gases balance of pressure, not force, that determines the
into a vessel at higher pressures. height of the mercury column (and the equilib
According to Torricelli and other followers of rium of fluids in general).
the mechanical philosophy, the force that holds the It is important to distinguish dearly between
column of mercury up in the tube is simply the pressure and force. Pressure is defined as the
pressure of the atmosphere, transmitted through amount of force acting perpendicular to a sur
the mercury in the bowl. The air pushes down on face, divided by the area of the surface:
the surface of the mercury, and since there is
practically no gas in the space at the top of the p= FlA. (19.1)
tube, the mercury rises until its weight is sufficient
to balance the force exerted by the air outside on A large force may produce only a small pressure
the top surface of the pool of mercury. if it is spread over a large enough area; for
In France, the scientist-philosopher Blaise example, if you wear large snowshoes, you can
Pascal ( 1 623-1 662) reasoned that if the pressure walk on snow without sinking in. On the other
of the atmosphere is indeed the force that sup hand, a small force may produce a very large pres
ports the column of mercury in the Torricelli sure if it is concentrated in a small area; when
barometer, then the height of that column should spike heels were used on ladies' shoes some years
be less if the pressure of the atmosphere is ago, many wooden floors and carpets were dam
reduced. He assumed that the atmospheric pres aged because the pressure at the place where
sure at the earth's surface results from the weight the heel touches the floor-a very small area
of the rest of the atmosphere above it, just as the can be greater than that exerted by an elephant's
pressure one experiences under water increases foot!
at greater depths. Conversely, then, by taking the It is instructive to calculate the numerical
barometer to the top of a mountain one should value of the pressure exerted by the atmosphere,
find a lower atmospheric pressure, and conse to see how large it is and why it does not depend
quently the height of the mercury supported by on the diameter of the tube in the barometer. The
that pressure should be reduced. The experi column of mercury stands 0.76 m high (the aver
ment proposed by Pascal was successfully per age height of the barometer column at sea level at
formed in 1 648 by his brother Florin Perrier. It OC). If this column has a cross-sectional area of
is often called the Puy de Dome experiment, 1 m2, the volume of the column is 0.76 m3 A cubic
after the mountain on which it was conducted. meter of mercury has a mass of 13,600 kg. The
mass of the mercury in the column is therefore

lThese pumps were relatively crude and could not pro m= 0.76 m3 x 13,600 (kglm3 ) = 10336 kg.
duce what we would now call a vacuum. For that matter,
the complete removal of every trace of gas from a closed ves The force exerted by this amount of mercury is
sel is impossible even today. But considerable advances in F = mg = 10336 kg x 9.8 mlsec2
the construction of vacuum pumps in the second half of the
nineteenth century made possible evacuation good enough = 1.013 x lOS N.
to allow, on the one hand, the discovery of subatomic par
ticles (Section 25.5) and, on the other, the development of (Remember that N is the abbreviation for the
the incandescent electric light bulb. newton, the unit of force in the SI system. )
1 9.2 Air Pressure / 269

Since the pressure is defined as PIA, and A


= 1 m2, we find that
Atmospheric pressure = 1 .0 1 3 x 1 05 N/m2.

Note that we had to multiply by the cross-sec


tional area to calculate the force and then divide
by this same area to calculate the pressure, so that
the final result is i ndependent of the value
assumed for the area.
The actual height of the mercury column in
a barometer is not precisely 0.76 m; it varies from
one day to the next and from one place to
another, being itself an index of changing climatic
conditions. It is now customary to define the
"standard atmosphere" as 1 .0 1 3 x 1 05 N/m2. The
unit of pressure in the 51 system is the pascal,
abbreviated Pa, which is defined as 1 N/m2; so
atmospheric pressure is approximately 105 Pa. In
common units this is about 15 Ib/in.2. Weather
reports in the United States still use an older
unit for atmospheric pressure, the bar, defined as
1 05 Pa. Weather maps usually give local atmos Fig. 19.2. Robert Boyle ( 1 627- 1 69 1 ), B ritish physicist
pheric pressures in terms of millibars ( 1 bar =
and chem ist who advocated the mechanistic "clock
1 000 millibars).
work u niverse" p h i l osophy a n d estab l ished by his

The expression "gauge pressure" is some


experiments that suction is due to a i r pressure rather
than the Aristotelian " natu re's abhorrence of a vacu
times used to indicate the excess of the actual u m . " Note in the background one of his p u m ps, set
pressure over atmospheric pressure. For example, up to evacuate a g lass g lobe.
if you inflate your tires and then check the pres
sure with a gauge and it shows 30 Ib/in.2, the
actual pressure inside the tires is about 45 Ib/in.2 In another experiment, Boyle placed a Tor
It was hard for many people to believe that ricelli barometer inside a closed container and
the atmosphere really exerts a pressure as great then removed the air from the container. The level
as 15 Ib/in.2. A famous experiment, conducted of the mercury in the tube fell as the air was
by Otto von Guericke in Magdeburg, Germany, removed from the container, until finally i t
in 1 654, helped to dramatize the magnitude of reached the same level as the mercury in the
atmospheric pressure. Two large hollow bronze bowl. Boyle realized that this result proved it was
hemispheres were fitted carefully edge to edge, the pressure of the atmosphere outside that had
and the air was removed from the inside of this been holding up the mercury in the tube, rather
space by a vacuum pump. A team of eight horses than the vacuum itself exerting some pull on
was harnessed to each hemisphere and the two the top of the tube. He had essentially done
teams were driven in opposite directions; they Pascal 's experiment without leaving his own
were j ust barely able to pull the hemispheres laboratory.
apart against the force with which the external Soon after Boyle p ublished his experiments
atmospheric pressure pressed them together. in 1 660, his conclusions were challenged by
The properties of air and of atmospheric Franciscus Linus, a Jesuit scientist and professor
pressure were thoroughly investigated by the of mathematics and Hebrew at the University of
British scientist Robert Boyle ( 1 627-1 69 1 ), who Liege, in Belgium. Linus asserted that the appar
heard a bout Guericke's experiments in 1 657. ently empry space above the mercury really con
Using an improved vacuum pump built for him tains an invisi ble cord or membrane, which he
by Robert Hooke, Boyle was able to obtain a called the funiculus (a Latin word meaning
large evacuated space in which several new "small rope " ) . According to Linus, when a ir is
experiments could be done. In one rather macabre stretched or rarefied, the funiculus exerts a vio
test, he found that small animals became uncon lent attractive force on all surrounding objects,
scious and eventually died when deprived of air. and it is this attraction that pulls the mercury up
270 / The Physics of Gases

the tube. He would argue that if you put your perature on the pressure or the volume of a gas.
finger over the end of the tube from a vacuum In the eighteenth century, Guillaume Amontons
pump (or a modern vacuum cleaner), you can and Jacques Charles suggested that if a constant
actually feel the funiculus pulling in the flesh of pressure is maintained in a sample of gas, its vol
your finger. (Try it! ) ume would increase proportionately to the rise
The funiculus theory sounds like a fantastic in temperature (A V oc AT at constant Pl. This law
idea, which no scientist would take seriously was definitely established by extensive experi
nowadays. But this kind of pseudomechanical ments on a number of gases conducted by the
explanation of physical phenomena was quite French chemist Joseph Louis Gay-Lussac, around
popular in the early days of modern science. 1 800, and confirmed shortly afterward in Eng
Boyle did not simply ignore Linus, perhaps real land by John Dalton. For brevity we shall call it
izing that the new idea of air pressure needed fur Gay-Lussac's law, as Gay-Lussac seems to have
ther justification before it would be generally had the greatest share in establishing its validity,
acceptable. Along with his refutation of the but recognizing that, just as in the case of Boyle's
funiculus hypothesis, Boyle published in 1662 law, several scientists made important contri
some quantitative measurements of the relation butions by proposing and testing it.
between pressure and volume of air, in support To visualize the meaning of Gay-Lussac's law
of what is now called Boyle's law, to be dis in an actual experiment, think of a quantity of
cussed in the next section. gas contained in a very thin, easily stretched
While it is for his pressure-volume law that balloon. The pressures inside and outside tend to
Boyle is chiefly famous, we should not forget that be the same-if the pressure were higher inside,
in his own time his work in establishing the the balloon would expand, thereby reducing the
qualitative importance of air pressure was more inside pressure until it was the same as the out
significant. side pressure; if the pressure were lower inside,
the balloon would be squeezed down to a smaller
size, and its inside pressure would increase. So
19.3 The General Gas Law we can assume that the pressure inside is equal
to atmospheric pressure (about 105 Pa l .
The compressibility of air, a fact realized gener A s we now proceed to heat the surroundings
ally for some time, was put on a quantitative basis (AT), the balloon expands (A V). What is so very
through Boyle's celebrated experiments, from startling is the fact that the fractional increase in
which it appeared that for a given mass of air volume per degree rise in temperature is exactly
trapped in a vessel at a constant temperature, any the same for all gases, even though their chem
decrease of volume raises the gas pressure pro ical constitutions are different.
portionally; conversely, any increase in pressure To appreciate the unexpectedness of this
decreases the volume. In modern terminology, we finding, recall that on heating a solid or a liquid
write this result one ordinarily also obtains a length or volume
expansion that is proportional to the tempera
P x V = constant
ture change; but there is a great difference in the
(at constant temperature) ( 19.2) relative amount of volume expansion per degree
where P refers to the actual pressure of the gas of temperature among different solids or liq-
considered (for example, in N/m2 ) and V to the
volume of the gas (for example, in m3 ). 2 William Croone, in London. The title of the paper was
Following Boyle's work, continued effort "Additional experiments made at Towneley Hall, in the years
was made to discover the effect of changes in tem- 1660 and 1661, by the advice and assistance of that Hero
ick and Worthy Gentleman Richard Towneley. " But Power
neglected to put his own name on the paper. Croone sent
2The complicated history of the discovery of Boyle's law has the paper to Boyle, forgetting to mention that Power was
only recently been disentangled by historians. It appears that the author. Boyle was very careful to give proper credit for
the law was first proposed by two other British scientists, the information he had received, and in his monograph of
Henry Power and Richard Towneley, on the basis of their 1662 replying to Linus, he stated that he had not realized
experiments, begun in 1653. They did not publish their that the simple relation PV constant applied to his own
=

results immediately, but after Boyle's first experiments on data until Richard Towneley pointed it out. Later scientists,
air pressure had been published in 1 660, Power sent a who read Boyle's works carelessly or not at all, assumed that
paper describing the results of their joint work to his ftiend Boyle had made the discovery all by himself.
1 9.3 The General Gas Law 1 27 1

uids (about 0.01 % for ice, 0.0025 % for quartz,


0.02 % for mercury and for wateJ; and 0.15% for
acetone) .
But under normal conditions, almost all
gases expand roughly 1/273 (that is, 0.37% ) of I

their volume when heated from 0 to 1 C. The 1rernperature


same volume change is also observed at much t t
lower temperatures, provided that the pressure -273C or O K OC or 273 K
of the gas is sufficiently low. (If a gas is contin
ually cooled at a constant pressure, it will even
tually condense to a liquid, and then, of course, Fig. 19.3. Relation between volume and temperatu re
for a gas at constant pressu re. The dotted l i ne rep
cease to obey Gay-Lussac's law. ) We can thus
resents a n ideal gas.
define an ideal gas as a gas that obeys both
Boyle's law and Gay-Lussac's law with complete
precision; the behavior of real gases approaches
this as a limit at low pressures. in 1 865, uses this temperature scale (see Sec
Assume that an ideal gas could be cooled to tion 18.4).]
273 below the ice point (that is, to Tc = -273);
Problem 1 9 . 1 . Figure 1 9.3 is a hypothetical plot
then since by Gay-Lussac's law-if it holds over
such a large range-it should contract 1/273 of of experimental data for a sample of gas at con
its volume at Tc = 0 for each degree of cooling, sta nt pressu re; here the vol ume V is plotted
it would eventually have no volume at all. While against the temperature T. The graph illustrates
this condition cannot be realized experimen !!. VI!!. T = constant (Gay-Lussac's law) . Show by
tally, it suggests that we should recognize the spe geometrical reasoning that if Gay-Lussac's law
cial temperature Tc = -273 ( more precisely, holds, then also VOC T (at constant P) provided T
-273.15) as the absolute zero of temperature, in is measured on the absolute scale. Show that
the sense that no lower temperature can ever be the proportionality Voc Tis not true if Tis measured
reached. 3 Consequently, we can simplify the law on the Celsius scale.
8 V oc 8T (at constant P) by writing V OC T at con
stant P if T is measured on a new temperature What interests us most, however, is the obvi
scale, that is, the absolute or Kelvin scale, where ous next step: combining the two laws into one.
T = Tc + 273.15. The unit of temperature is the If for each gas, by Boyle's law, V oc 1/p, and by
kelvin, abbreviated K. Thus a temperature 5 Gay-Lussac's law, V OC T, then V oc TIP. This
degrees above absolute zero would be written T implies that the quotient PVIT is a constant
= 5 kelvins or T = 5 K. (usually called r), whose value depends only on
Comparing the two scales, we see that for the sample. Thus we can write:
example, OC is equivalent to 273 K; room tem
perature (about 20C) is 293 K; water boils at PV = rT. ( 1 9.3)
373 K. Note that the size of the degree-the
kelvin-is the same on both the Celsius and the We may call the last equation, which is of great
Kelvin scale. However, in the SI system of units usefulness, the ideal gas law; it relates in a simple
the degree symbol " 0 " is no longer used for K, way the three variables of interest in any given
but it is still used for Celsius degrees (0C). sample of gas, and is approximately valid for all
The letter K was chosen in honor of William real gases under ordinary conditions.
Thomson, Lord Kelvin, who first proposed this
scale in 1 848, and showed that it is consistent Problem 1 9.2. Find r in Eq. (1 9.3) for a sample of
with the second law of thermodynamics. [Recall hydrogen gas weighing 2 g and filling 22.4 L at OC
that the definition of entropy, given by Clausius and 1 0 5 Pa pressure (approximately atmospheric
pressure) . Then determine the volume of this
3According to the third law of thermodynamics, proposed sample at room temperature (20C) and a gauge
by Walther Nernst in 1906, all thermal properties approach pressure of 1 07 Pa ( = 1 0 M Pa ) . ( Remember:
zero values as the absolute zero of temperature is Gauge pressure is defined as the pressure above
approached, and as a consequence it is never possible to atmospheric.)
reach this temperature.
272 I The Physics of Gases

At this point we may call attention to an and indeed, it seemed to explain qualitatively the
important temperature: the triple point of water, behavior of gases well enough. (Boyle attempted
the unique temperature at which all three phases to find experimentally this subtle fluid, sepa
(gas, liquid, and solid) can coexist. The triple rated from the particles on which it supposedly
point was found by experiment to be at 273 . 1 6 acted. This was the start of a 2S0-year-Iong
0. 0 1 K . A t the Tenth General Conference on futile search for direct evidence of ethereal fluids.)
Weights and Measures in 1 9S4, it was decided Having named the first of these the static
to establish a new absolute temperature scale model of a gas and the second the kinetic model,
based on two fixed points: absolute zero and the we must make a brief comment on each. As to
triple point of water, which was defined to have the first, a springlike compressibility of static
the exact value T = 273 . 1 6 K. The new scale particles cannot easily account for one very con
agrees with the old one for nearly all practical spicuous property of gases-their ability to
purposes, but has the advantage that the fixed expand infinitely in all directions, unless of
points are no longer quite so arbitrary. (Since the course we allow the improbable, namely, that
melting and boiling points of a substance vary each atom itself can grow infinitely on expand
with pressure, one had to specify a particular pres ing. For a pile of ordinary springs opposes com
sure, namely the average pressure of the atmos pression, but does not disperse continuously
phere at the earth's surface. The triple point, when put into the open. Therefore some fol
however, occurs at a definite pressure, 6 1 1 .73 Pa.) lowers of the static view found it necessary to con
sider that gas corpuscles do not change in size but
can repel one another at a distance. Evidently
1 9.4 Two Gas Models some special new agency of repulsion, some new
force among gas atoms, would have to be
One is immediately tempted to interpret these invented, because the well-known mutual grav
observations and the experimental gas law that itational force between large bodies, also the
summarizes them in terms of some model or logical candidate for intercorpuscular forces,
structure. Even qualitatively, the great compressi was, unfortunately, always found to be a force
bility of all gases and their "springiness" (ten of attraction, as is evidently also the nature of
dency to expand again when the external pressure those forces that hold the particles together in
is reduced) seem to call for some explanation. solids and liquids.
In 1 660 Boyle himself, while favoring one The distinguished authority of Newton
model "without peremptorily asserting it, " pre seems to lend some aid to the static picture, for
sented two opposing explanations by models, in the Principia he had shown, by way of a
both atomistic, for he and his time had begun to mathematical demonstration, that if a sample of
accept atomism as part of the rising materialis gas were made of mutually repulsive particles,
tic worldview. That view, expressed in his words, and if a force of repulsion between any two par
is: "whatsoever is performed in the material ticles were inversely proportional to the distance
world, is really done by particular bodies, acting between their centers, then the gas pressure in this
according to the laws of motion. " sample would increase with a small decrease in
The two models that Boyle presents repre volume, just as found by Boyle's law.
sent respectively the static and the kinetic views. Newton did not mean to prove that gases
If air consists of contiguous particles at rest, the really do correspond to this model; on the con
corpuscles must themselves be compressible, trary, he writes, " But whether elastic fluids do
rather like little springs or, as Torricelli had pre really consist of particles so repelling each other,
ferred, like pieces of wool. If, on the other hand, is a physical question," in other words, one that
the corpuscles of the gas do not touch at all has to be settled by appeal to experience. And
times, they need be neither variable in size them indeed, this postulated type of force would cause
selves nor maintained by a static assembly, but gases to exhibit different behavior for different
then they must be in violent agitation, being shapes of the container, which does not corre
whirled through all available space within a tur spond to anything observed. Nevertheless, New
bulent though "subtle" fluid. We recall that the ton's was the first quantitative deduction obtained
subtle-fluid theory, then recently proposed by for the behavior of gases on the basis of any
Descartes to account for the motion of planets, atomistic hypothesis, and it appears to have
had captured the imagination throughout Europe; been quite impressive.
1 9 .4 Two Gas Models 1 273

walls is larger, that is, the pressure should become


greater, as is actually observed. Bernoulli even cal
culated the magnitude of this expected increase
and found that it corresponds to Boyle'S exper
imental law. Then he continued:

The elasticity of air [the pressure in the con


tainer] is not only increased by the condensa
tion [decrease of volume] but by heat supplied
to it, and since it is admitted that heat may be
considered as an increasing internal motion of
the particles, it follows that if the elasticity of
the air of which the volume does not change
is increased [by heating the sample of gas], this
indicates a most intense motion in the particles
Fig. 19.4. The pressu re on the piston exerted by the
of air; which fits well with our hypothesis . . . .
weight P is balanced by the impact of high-speed gas
particles. From Da niel Bern o u l l i's Hydrodynamica, (Hydrodynamica)
1738.
This model, this line of reasoning, and this
result, are all quite similar to the work that more
The second or kinetic view of a gas might than a century later finally clarified simultane
well have been formulated without recourse to an ously the main problems of the nature of gases,
imponderable fluid (if it had not been for the heat, and chemistry. But at the time, Bernoulli's
inescapable, almost hypnotic hold of that idea), work was generally neglected. That lack of gen
for it had been the opinion of Greek atomists, as eral attention and the long interval, are both
reported by Aristotle and Lucretius, that particles, remarkable, and cannot be entirely explained
particularly those not joined in specific form, by pointing out that gases were not yet clearly
are "ever passing about in the great void," just understood by chemists, that density measure
as minute specks of dust can be seen dancing irreg ments were lacking that would have been needed
ularly in a sunbeam that pierces a dark room. to obtain the numerical values for the average
In fact, the Swiss physicist Daniel Bernoulli speed of the particles, and so forth.
in 173 8 did publish a prophetic, quantitative The other model, the Boyle-Newton theory
development of a Lucretian type of kinetic model based on repulsive forces between gas particles,
for gases. Bernoulli thought of the "corpuscles" proved to be more congenial to the eighteenth
of the gas as so minute as to be "practically century scientists who adopted the caloric theory
infinite in number" under ordinary conditions, of heat (Section 17.7). The repulsive force was
even in a small container. In their rapid motion now attributed to atmospheres of caloric fluid
hither and thither these corpuscles collide with surrounding each atom. Heating a gas meant
one another and with the rigid walls of the pouring in more caloric, expanding the "atmos
closed vessel. But the collisions can be assumed phere" around each atom, and thereby intensi
to be perfectly elastic; therefore, as we would put fying the repulsive force. Although the caloric
it, the kinetic energy of the particles is conserved theory did not completely exclude the notion that
and the motion can continue undiminished. The heat might be associated with the motion of
pressure that the gas is expected to exert against particles, it did seem to be incompatible with
all sides of the container is thus caused by the Bernoulli's hypothesis that heat is nothing but the
incessant impact of millions of high-speed par motion of particles.
ticles-hence the name "impact theory of gas The discovery of latent heat by Joseph Black
pressure. " seemed to indicate that a simple proportionality
Let u s say that the gas-filled container used between heat and temperature could not be gen
here is cylindrical, and that the top end can be erally valid, since a finite amount of heat must
made to slide in like a piston (see Fig. 19.4). If be added to a liquid in order to change it to a
the volume is slowly decreased, the corpuscles are gas, without any change of temperature-as in
more crowded in the progressively smaller space the case of liquid water, boiling away into vapor
and the number of collisions per second with the at a steady 1 00C. This was one of several
274 1 The Physics of Gases

phenomena that were thought to be more easily examine some other ideas about atomic prop
explicable by the caloric theory than by the erties that were being developed in the meantime.
kinetic theory. Again, Bernoulli's theory, by pos
tulating free motion of the atoms through empty
space, ignored the ether, which was thought to RECOMMENDED FOR FURTHER READING
pervade all space; whereas caloric could easily be
S. G. Brush (editor), Kinetic Theory, Vol. I, excerpts
identified as a special kind of ether.
from Boyle, Newton and Bernoulli, pages 43-65
Perhaps we may compare Bernoulli's aston
J. B. Conant, " Robert Boyle's experiments in pneu
ishing insight to some quick, isolated, premature matics, " in Harvard Case Histories in Experi
stab from a general holding position, far through mental Science (edited by J. B. Conant), pages
enemy lines, bringing no strategically valuable 1-63
consequences until in time the whole main force C. C. Gillispie, Dictionary of Scientific Biography,
has moved ahead to link up with this almost for articles by Marie Boas Hall on Boyle, Vol. 2,
gotten outpost. For Bernoulli, in effect, had pages 377-3 82, and by H. Straub on Daniel
made two enormous j umps in his thinking for Bernoulli, Vol. 2, pages 3 6-46
which the great majority of scientists was not yet Marie Boas Hall, "Robert Boyle," Scientific Ameri
ready: first, the direct equivalence of heat and can, August 1 9 67, pages 97-1 02
S. Sambursky Physical Thought, excerpts from
internal molecular motion, ignoring any inter
Torricelli, Pascal, and Boyle, pages 256-263,
actions with the ether; and second, the idea that
282-284
a well-defined numerical relationship, such as Martin Tamny, "Atomism and the mechanical phi
Boyle's simple law, could be deduced from the losophy," in Companion (edited by Olby), pages
chaotic picture of randomly moving particles. We 597-609
must postpone our account of the final victory Stephen Toulmin and June Goodfield, Architec
of these ideas to a later chapter, turning now to ture of Matter, Chapter 8

Você também pode gostar