Você está na página 1de 9

ARTHUR C.

DANTO

Embodied Meanings, Isotypes, and Aesthetical Ideas

The translator into Hungarian of several of my becomes the basis for a common cultural life and
writings on art theory recently sent me a catalog of a common cultural relationship.”2 Just consider
the work of a young artist from her country, Ágnes their international use in giving traffic directions to
Eperjesi.1 The translator—Eszter Babarczy—is a drivers who may or may not be able to read the lan-
gifted critic in her own right, and I cannot do better guage of the country in which they are traveling,
than quote from her letter, which explains why she or in guiding us through foreign airports. Isotypes
felt I would be especially interested in Eperjesi’s are among the rare practical and positive contri-
art. butions made by modern philosophy to the com-
mon life of humankind. When these pictograms
She thought your ideas about transfiguration and the are recycled—or transfigured—into works of art,
commonplace applied to her work, and she took inspi- their implied universality is elevated to a portrait
ration from your essays. Hers is a remarkable and long of the society in which the products are to be used.
journey from experimental photography to an absolutely I would not altogether follow Babarszy in call-
unique venture of collecting wrappings of household ing Eperjesi’s works beautiful and, in truth, I am
products, and taking the humble sign language of or- somewhat at a loss to describe them aesthetically.
dinary household chores, and recreating them as objects But I can appreciate that in transfiguring the iso-
of beauty and irony. type into an artwork, an interesting reversal of
Walter Benjamin’s famous distinction has taken
The products, like dishwashers and vacuum place: the art of mechanical reproduction has ac-
cleaners—or underwear—were in all likelihood quired, through transfiguration, an aura, and in
intended for export to countries anywhere in the virtue of that the images may acquire an aesthetic
world, which implies that they will fit into forms interest they heretofore lacked. At least, as art, we
of life that must be much the same the world over. look at them as critics, and notice their aesthetic
So the images must themselves belong to the sign qualities, such as they are. Just knowing that an
language of globalism, necessarily universal in that object is intended as a piece of fine art may trig-
they have to be legible to consumers who can- ger the sense that it must be beautiful. Or better,
not be counted on to have a common language. we use this standard term of aesthetic commenda-
The signs show what the consumers need to know tion in connection with them that we would hardly
about the products they have purchased—which use in characterizing the pictograms on which they
side of a pair of underpants is front and which side are based. The term ‘beautiful’ may simply be a
is back, for example. In many, though not, all cases, compliment paid to art as art, without really being
they are pictograms or even isotypes—an acronym descriptive of the art at all.
for “International System of Typographic Picture The goal of trans-cultural communication may
Education”—signs of a kind initially invented in mean that features that imply ethnic differences
1936 by the Logical Positivist, Otto Neurath, who will be erased—the persons are depicted neither
may have been influenced by Wittgenstein’s so- as white nor black nor red nor yellow—leaving
called picture theory of language. Neurath antic- figures that are abstractly human, which in a way
ipated globalism in saying: “The visual method look quite “modern.” But is “looks modern” an
122 Global Theories of the Arts and Aesthetics

Figure 1. Ágenes Eperjesi.

aesthetic characterization or a stylistic one? Mod- product it stands for, though I would guess that it
ernist design strove for a kind of simplification belongs to what we might think of as the secret life
through its distaste for ornament, and this led of women. The image could show a woman living
to stylization in modernist pictography. This does a full active life, thanks to the product in question.
not explain why the isotypical pictograms are styl- Whatever its rhetorical aim, Eperjesi captions it
ized as they are, which comes, rather, from glob- this way: “My new boyfriend gets along fine with
alist imperatives—so “looks modern” is façon de my daughter. I hope it’s not just a show for now”
parler. But in any case, the pictogram has under- (Figure 1). This is interesting because the woman
gone some sort of aesthetic transformation in the is evidently a single mother, looking for a new re-
course of its artistic transfiguration, however we lationship. The irony derives from the implication
finally describe it. Eperjesi’s aesthetic enhance- that while women in contemporary society have
ment of workaday images is as distinctive as Andy been greatly liberated, they remain in a disadvan-
Warhol’s transformations of Polaroids into por- tageous position in relationship to men, as much
traits. so in Hungary as in America or western Europe.
As to Eszter Bararcszy’s description of the work They are the ones left to do the housework, and
as “ironic,” that is true—but it is due more to Eper- to hope that men are not just out to exploit them
jesi’s titles—or perhaps they are captions—than sexually.
to the images themselves: the covers of The New The irony goes well beyond the power of iso-
Yorker Magazine have titles, the cartoons have types. The three figures could, after all, just rep-
captions. Either way, the titles/captions express resent a family. Interestingly, most of the women
thoughts that the images alone do not. Eperjesi are in Western clothing, which has become fairly
has often selected her images with the intention isotypical: I imagine that the isotype on the door
of using them to convey how women in contem- of women’s’ toilets, shown with a short flaring
porary Hungary regard themselves, and how they skirt, would be recognized in airports everywhere
think about the housework for which the prod- in the world, even by women who wear burkhas.
uct designated by the image is intended to be In any case, the titles/captions have to be trans-
used—usually by women as a matter of course. lated, as the artist has done, from Hungarian into
One of her images shows a man, a woman, and a the language of the country in which they are to be
child on bicycles. It is difficult to determine what shown—English, for example, in the catalog I saw.
Danto Embodied Meanings, Isotypes, and Aesthetical Ideas 123

English itself is not, for all it ubiquity, isotypical. subject to formalist analysis. That is to say, he ap-
Even if it were universally used, as Latin once was, preciated painting in terms of what we might call
there would be a distinction between pictures and the aesthetics of medium, since painterly excel-
words, which means that while isotypes may vali- lence is determined by what pertains to properties
date the picture theory of language, they do so in essential to that medium, namely, in Greenberg’s
ways having nothing to do with natural languages view, relationships between flat forms, irrespective
as spoken or written. The semantics of sentences of what the forms may signify. Aesthetic value is
in a natural language differ from the semantic of what these forms convey to visual perception, in
a sentence used pictorially, as in a quotation. But which all concepts are put out of play. Kant him-
even quotations have to be translated. self spoke of the pleasure taken in an object in-
Tempting as it is to dwell on the artistic se- dependently of any concept. For Greenberg, the
mantics of Eperjesi’s pictures, my immediate pur- critic’s eye alone mattered, with whatever histor-
pose in using her work has to do with its extreme ical knowledge he or she may possess put for the
contemporaneity, and to the way it illustrates the time in brackets. The task of the artist was to elim-
pluralistic structure that has increasingly come to inate from painting whatever did not address the
define the production of contemporary art, espe- critic’s eye. The aim was the production of pure
cially since the 1960s when artists first began to ex- beauty for contemplative delectation.
plore the possibility of using vernacular imagery. The impact of Greenberg’s modernist aesthet-
I have already touched on the question of their ics on so-called art professionals in the United
indeterminate aesthetic qualities, but I want ulti- States was inestimable. What is astonishing is
mately to discuss this with reference to the prob- how pluralism should have emerged at all when
lems that artistic pluralism has raised for aesthetic the Greenberg-inspired professionals had all the
theory, and especially for Kantian aesthetic theory, power and authority in the artworld, at least so
which more or less dominated discussion until the far as contemporary visual art was concerned. But
decade when pluralism became a driving force in for reasons that demand an historical explanation
art. I understand “Kantian” to mean the view that I am unable to furnish, the Kant-Greenberg aes-
artistic excellence is one with aesthetic excellence, thetic began to give way in the late 1950s, and be-
which is understood to be a matter of pleasure and came untenable just when Greenberg published
value distinct from the pleasure of sensual gratifi- his most considered statement in his 1960 essay,
cation, and internally connected with an ideal of “Modernist Painting.” The underground imper-
disinterested contemplation. It concerns what the ative, implied by Robert Rauschenberg in 1961,
classical aestheticians designated “taste,” and the in the catalog for the exhibition “Sixteen Ameri-
main features of the theory are laid out in the sec- cans” at the Museum of Modern Art, was to erase
tion of the Critique of Aesthetic Judgment titled the boundary between art and life. (Kant would
“The Analytic of Taste,” which served as the great have spoken instead of erasing the boundary be-
empowering text for aesthetic theory in modern tween art and reality so far as both were beau-
times, especially, at least in America, in the critical tiful.) In Rauschenberg’s artistic practice, that
thought and practice of Clement Greenberg. meant disregarding the imperatives of medium al-
Immanuel Kant’s initial interest was in natu- together, giving himself license to make art out of
ral beauty, which it was easy enough to relate to anything—socks, bedclothes, Coke bottles, auto-
the visual arts, understood—the decorative arts mobile tires, stuffed animals—“whatever.” Purity
apart, which were appraised in terms of “free of medium had become obsolete almost the mo-
beauty”—either as accurate representations of ment it was declared.
natural beauty, or else as beautified representa- Aesthetics was not rendered irrelevant when
tions of natural objects that in reality fell short of Modernism ended in the 1960s, but the kind of aes-
beauty. For what would be the point of making pic- thetic quality presupposed by the Kant-Greenberg
tures of aesthetically repellent or deficient motifs? conception almost certainly disappeared, making
Greenberg had no such interest, as far as I can tell, room for what one may think of as a pluralism
and his chief focus was on abstract painting, which of aesthetic modalities. There is, for instance, a
could be treated in terms of “free” beauty. This Rauschenbergian aesthetic that is almost the op-
had the advantage for him that he could treat even posite of the kind of aesthetic excellence Kant and
representationalist art as if abstract, and hence Greenberg took for granted. It is the aesthetics
124 Global Theories of the Arts and Aesthetics

of grunge and mess, as exemplified in Rauschen- “quality in art can be neither ascertained nor
berg’s Bed, where he slathered paint over the proved by logic or discourse. Experience alone
bedclothes and quilt in which the work materi- rules in this area—and the experience, so to speak,
ally consists. He applied paint, as it was used by of experience.”3 Greenberg’s view here is essen-
Abstract Expressionist painters, to an object of tially Hume’s: that quality is what qualified critics
domestic use in connection with which cleanli- agree is good.
ness and neatness are ordinarily mandated—as in Greenberg cherished Kant for explaining how
hospitals, army barracks, or bedrooms as main- it was possible to be right or wrong in questions of
tained by what Matisse once described as “coun- aesthetic merit. He did not think one had to know
try aunts.” Grunge is the aesthetic of disorder, anything of the kind that art history concerns it-
flaunted by rebellious adolescents, and there is lit- self with in order to be right or wrong about art.
tle question that a taste for it can be developed, Indeed, he believed that modernism had opened
and even exploited, by marketing torn blue-jeans, up the possibility of appreciating “all sorts of ex-
tacky tee-shirts, and athletic jerseys to young peo- otic art that we didn’t 100 years ago, whether an-
ple concerned with identifying themselves through cient Egyptian, Persian, Far Eastern, barbaric or
a style of affected slovenliness. primitive.”4 What makes art good has nothing to
Kant’s main ambition was to combat what one do with historical circumstance. He once boasted
might call a pluralism of taste, by which I mean the that though he knew little about African art, he
common and somewhat cynical view that beauty would almost unfailingly be able to pick out the
is in the mind of the beholder and that differences two or three best pieces in a group. They need not
in taste are relative to differences in beholders’ be best by the criteria by which Africans them-
minds. Kant rightly undertook to show that beauty selves judged such matters, but probably that was
is and ought to be univocal, the same for all. This because they were driven by beliefs that had little
was a kind of aesthetic colonialism—the view that to do with aesthetic qualities as he himself under-
so-called primitive societies were simply aestheti- stood them. There was little to say, in front of a
cally retrograde in their taste—which was the the- piece of good art, beyond an admiring “Wow!” But
oretical underpinning for the supremacist views that in no sense meant that one was merely venting
of Western taste in what came to be Victorian feelings, as Greenberg’s positivist contemporaries
anthropology. Greenberg was convinced that his in philosophy would have said, having come to the
critical practice was validated by Kant’s Critique view that aesthetic discourse is noncognitive. That
of Aesthetic Judgment, which he often proclaimed it was, on the other hand, nonconceptual is under-
the greatest book ever written on art. In truth, written by Greenberg’s way of closing his eyes and
the direction of validation might equally have opening them only when the work to be judged
gone in the opposite direction: the remarkable was in front of him. What immediately flooded
success of Greenberg’s critical judgments could the eyes, as if a blinding flash, before the mind
be taken to have conferred a measure of validity had time to bring anything to bear by way of ex-
on Kant’s otherwise exceedingly abstract formu- ternal associations, was what aesthetic experience
lations, which derived a surprising confirmation rested upon.
from a body of painting hardly thinkable in his Greenberg’s “home-made aesthetics” was val-
own century. idated through his actual success in identifying
Two of Kant’s claims give particular support to artistic merit, particularly in championing Jackson
Greenberg’s practice, which came to typify aes- Pollock, at a time when there was still resistance
thetic attitudes that prevailed in the New York on the part of many critics to abstract art as such.
School. First, there was Kant’s argument that judg- This would have included conservative art critics
ments of beauty are nonconceptual, and second, on the major New York newspapers—John Cana-
that they are universally valid, that is, they are in day at the New York Times and Emily Genauer
no sense merely personal. Greenberg rarely spoke at the New York Herald-Tribune. “They lack the
of beauty. His interest was in what he termed right to pronounce on abstract art, because they
“quality” in art, which meant that his views could have not taken the trouble to amass sufficient ex-
not easily be extended to the aesthetics of na- perience of it. Without experience enough to be
ture, which would of course have been of central able to tell the good from the bad in abstract
interest to Kant. In 1961, Greenberg wrote that art, no one has the right to be heard on this
Danto Embodied Meanings, Isotypes, and Aesthetical Ideas 125

subject.”5 However, European critics were also globalized art world, in the United States and
resistant, including David Sylvester, who came England, but also in Germany, Italy, France,
round to agreeing with Greenberg on Pollock’s Spain, Japan, and finally everywhere that art was
preeminence (“What could I have been using for made, down to the present moment. The artists
eyes?”). Greenberg was the “high-brow New York that mattered philosophically were preeminently
intellectual” referred to in the 1949 Life magazine Duchamp and Warhol, Eva Hesse, the minimalists,
article that made Pollock famous. The massive en- and the conceptualists, in whose work aesthetics
dorsement of his assessment of Pollock had about was of negligible significance. And since the defi-
it the quality of a scientific proof. It gave him im- nition of art had to deal with the ready-mades and
mense authority as well as great power in the art- the Brillo Boxes, in which aesthetic qualities were
world. marginal at best, there was a question of whether
Where Greenberg and, more excusably, Kant aesthetics had anything really to do with art at
went wrong was in their failure to recognize that all. This was a revolutionary shift, given that from
there is a nearly boundless set of aesthetic quali- the outset it had seemed self-evident that aesthetic
ties, something that came to be recognized when pleasure was what art was all about.
philosophers of language touched on the vocab- I was fairly bearish about the importance of aes-
ulary of aesthetics at about the same time that thetics for art. In my main work in the philosophy
Greenberg dominated critical discourse in Amer- of art, The Transfiguration of the Commonplace,
ica. I have in mind particularly an obiter dictum of I emerged with what I thought of as two neces-
J. L. Austin’s: “How much it is to be wished [that] sary conditions for a philosophical definition of
we could forget for a while about the beautiful and art—that art is about something and hence pos-
get down instead to the dainty and the dumpy.”6 sesses meaning; and that an artwork embodies its
Austin stated this in describing his philosophi- meaning, which is what art criticism addresses. I
cal practice, in his important 1956 paper, “A Plea condensed this by calling works of art embodied
for Excuses,” as linguistic phenomenology. Essen- meanings. In my latest book, The Abuse of Beauty,
tially this meant working out the rules that gov- I more or less acknowledged Austin’s discovery
ern linguistic practice—“what we say when,” to that aesthetics is wider than had been traditionally
use the slogan of ordinary language philosophy— recognized, and asked if there were not a third nec-
and some interesting discoveries were made by essary condition, namely, that to be a work of art,
analysts such as Frank Sibley, who attempted to something has to have some aesthetic quality—if
prove that aesthetic predicates were not “rule- not beauty, then, say, grunge. If not grunge, then
governed.” It would have been interesting to find something else. I ended the book skeptical that
out if this was the criterion for aesthetic predicates art need have any aesthetic quality at all. I did,
as a class—for “beautiful,” “dainty,” “dumpy,” however, make a distinction worth emphasizing
“grungy” for starters—and if not, what criteria, between internal and external beauty, and, by gen-
if any, there are. eralization, between internal and external α, when
Linguistic phenomenology did not survive α stands for any aesthetic predicate that may ap-
Austin’s death in 1960—the year Greenberg’s ply.
“Modernist Painting” was published. But aesthet- Here is what I meant by internal beauty. The
ics took a backseat in the ensuing decade to the beauty of an artwork is internal when it con-
philosophy of art, beginning, I am obliged to say, tributes to the work’s meaning. I offered several
with my 1964 paper, “The Art World,” which was examples of this from contemporary art, including
inspired by Pop and to a lesser degree by mini- Robert Motherwell’s Elegy for the Spanish Repub-
malism. With the work of Richard Wollheim, and lic and Maya Lin’s Vietnam Veterans Memorial in
especially of George Dickie, the central issue be- Washington, DC. In a subsequent essay I thought
came the definition of art, and that has more a very successful example was the use that Jacques
or less been the project for the analytical phi- Louis David made of beauty in painting the body
losophy of art ever since. What was interesting of Marat as beautiful in Marat Assassiné, which
was how minor a role aesthetics played in that looks like a descent from the cross. The beauty of
collective investigation—almost as minor as the Marat was like the beauty of Jesus, and the mean-
role aesthetic qualities played in advanced artis- ing of the painting was that Jesus/Marat died for
tic production and criticism in the increasingly the viewer, who must acknowledge the meaning
126 Global Theories of the Arts and Aesthetics

of this sacrifice by following their imperatives. If shyness, and like vexations of the loveless. It is
the beauty is not internal in a work of art it is, the aesthetics of “cheap black-and-white ads,” ex-
strictly speaking, meaningless, which means that it plained by the need to make salient the blemishes
is, in Kant’s terms, “free beauty” and mere deco- that would cause viewers to buy the product ad-
ration. In brief, my effort was to break away from vertised. But that aesthetic gets to be internal to
the Kant-Greenberg aesthetic of form, and instead the works Warhol made of them, as the aesthet-
develop an aesthetics of meaning. It is at this point ics of package images gets to be internal to the
that one might recognize that the internal/external work Ágnes Eperjesi based on them. Both bod-
distinction applies throughout the vast domain of ies of work show their origins and draw meaning
aesthetic qualities to which Austin and the ordi- from them—though this is not the whole meaning
nary language aestheticians drew attention in the of either artist’s work.
early 1950s. Let us consider grunge once more. In The upshot of this excursion is that the answer
certain artists—Dieter Roth is a good example— to the question of whether aesthetics survives into
grunge had just the meaning that the work was de- the era of pluralism is yes and no. It is “no” if we
liberately anti-aesthetic, meaning anti-beautiful. are thinking of the Kant-Greenberg aesthetic of
When Roth first saw the 1962 exhibition of Jean taste and disinterested contemplation. It is “yes”
Tinguely in Basel, it was a conversion experience if we are thinking of the way in which different
for him. “Everything was so rusty and broken and aesthetic qualities, many of them antithetical to
made so much noise,” he said afterward. “I was taste as construed by Kant and Greenberg, are in-
impressed half to death. It was simply a com- ternal to the meaning of works of art construed as
pletely different world from my Constructivism, embodied meanings. In brief, the age of pluralism
it was something like a paradise that I’d lost.”7 In has opened our eyes to the plurality of aesthetic
a sense, Roth’s quest from that moment on was qualities far far wider than traditional aesthetics
the recreation of a lost infantile paradise, made up was able to countenance. I would say, moreover,
of detritus, noises, and noxious smells. He moved that each of these aesthetic qualities is as objective
from a Kantian to an anti-Kantian aesthetic, as as Kant supposed beauty was. Aesthetics is in the
did Duchamp when he applied as his criterion for mind of the beholder, but only in the way in which
the ready-mades that they have the zero degree sense qualities are in the mind of the beholder, just
of aesthetic interest—meaning that they caused as Hume argued they are. “Beauty in things exists
neither pleasure nor pain to the eye. They were in the mind,” he wrote, but this in no sense distin-
nonaesthetic from the narrow perspective of “the guishes it from anything else, inasmuch as “tastes
analytic of taste”—but they were entirely aesthetic and colours, and all other sensible qualities, lie not
from the widened perspective that was to open up in bodies but in the senses.
in the 1960s, when aesthetic blandness became an
aesthetic quality, internal to the meaning of the The case is the same with beauty and deformity, virtue
ready-mades, and itself a matter of taste, the way and vice. This doctrine, however takes off no more from
grunge had been for Dieter Roth. the reality of the latter qualities than from that of the
There is, one might say, an aesthetic of ready- former . . . Though colours were allowed to lie only in
made images, of the kind out of which Ágnes Eper- the eye, would dyers or painters ever be less regarded or
jesi makes her art. It is not easy to describe this esteemed? There is a sufficient uniformity in the senses
aesthetic, but it is easy enough to recognize, and and feelings of mankind to make all these qualities the
it is probably due to the contingencies of design, objects of art and reasoning, and to have the greatest
itself due to the requirement of making the images influence on life and manners.8
easy to read and to understand everywhere in the
world. There is, to take a kindred form, an easily Having taken the matter to this point, however,
recognized aesthetic in the coarsely drawn images I must make some amends to Kant, whose view
of the simple advertisements that Andy Warhol on works of art takes a very different direction
used in his first exhibition in April 1961, in the in a later section of the Third Critique—the bril-
store windows of Bonwit Teller’s women’s store liant Section 49, “Of the Faculties of the Mind that
on 57th Street. They were the kind of advertise- Constitute Genius,” where he introduces his con-
ments that were printed on pulp paper in cheap cept of aesthetical ideas. The Kant of Section 49 is
publications, advertising cures for acne, baldness, not the Kant of Kantian aesthetics, which is based
Danto Embodied Meanings, Isotypes, and Aesthetical Ideas 127

almost entirely on the “Analytic of Taste.” I owe lightning must have extraordinary power. The im-
it to Kant—and to myself—to show how close my age tells us more than “Jupiter is all powerful”
views are to his in this section of his book, the alone tells. Presenting the idea of power aesthet-
mere existence of which shows how Kant was reg- ically, that is, via an image, “gives occasion to the
istering the deep changes in Enlightenment cul- imagination to spread itself over a number of kin-
ture that the age of Romanticism was developing dred representations that arouse more thought
from within. He certainly realized that taste alone than can be expressed in a concept determined
was not the entire story when it comes to art: “We by words.”
say of certain products of which we expect that It is in regard to the expression of “aestheti-
they should at least in part appear as beautiful cal ideas” that Kant speaks of “spirit” and of “the
art, they are without spirit, although we find noth- imagination as free from the guidance of rules and
ing to blame in them on the score of taste.”9 By yet as purposive in reference to the presentment
spirit, he means “the animating principle of the of the given concept.” This was much in the air in
mind”; and this principle, he goes on to say, “is the 1790s, when he published his Third Critique.
no other than the faculty of presenting aesthetical In 1792, for example, Francisco Goya composed a
ideas.”10 It is characteristic of Kant that he will set of proposals for reforming the Royal Academy
seek a kind of faculty in order to account for a of San Fernando, of which he was at the time as-
difference, when the difference, one might say, is sistant director. His fundamental principle must
really ontological. An “aesthetical idea” is really, have seemed entirely contrary to the concept of an
as it turns out, an idea that has been given sen- academy, namely, that there are no rules in paint-
sory embodiment—he uses “aesthetic” in the way ing: No hay reglas en la pintura. It follows in par-
it was used by Alexander Baumgarten, where it ticular from this that we cannot base the practice
generally refers to what is given to sense. What is of painting on the canon of Greek sculpture, or on
stunning is that he has stumbled onto something any set of paradigms. His text ended with a plea
that is both given to sense and intellectual—where to allow the “genius” of the students to “develop
we grasp a meaning through the senses, rather than in full freedom, without suppressing it, and to use
merely a color or a taste or a sound. means for turning them away from the tendency
Kant gives as an example one of Frederick the that shows them the way to this or that style of
Great’s French poems, which we are likely to pass painting.”12 Historically, Goya’s text marks a shift
over, thinking that Kant is writing here as a sort of from the neoclassicism that defined his early work
courtier, flattering the monarch, when in fact the to the romanticism of his mature work, but it also
poem, whatever its actual merits, does something expresses a deep truth about art. Strictly speaking,
that poetry often does—mean one thing by saying art involves a deep originality and is not something
another. The king speaks in the poem of “finishing that can be taught.
ones life and dying without regret” through the Aesthetical ideas have nothing much to do with
image of a beautiful summer day ending peace- the aesthetics of taste, and they are what is miss-
fully.11 This is a quite commonplace use of poetry, ing entirely from Greenberg’s agenda, who seldom
and has nothing to do with genius, as Kant seems spoke of meaning in his discussions of quality in
to feel it has. “The aesthetical idea” is merely one art. In a sense, aesthetics, which has application
meaning given through another, as in irony or in to natural and physical beauty, has little to do
metaphor. We realize that the poet, in this case with art, which in Goya’s time was imitated in the
Kant’s sovereign, is talking about the course of a academies in copying plaster casts of what were
day as a way of talking about the course of a life. It felt to be paradigms of classical beauty. There is
is a beautiful thought, which need have nothing to very little of that in his masterpiece, Los Capri-
do with the beauty of the words. The poetic exam- chos. However one characterizes them, these are
ple comes just after two examples from the visual hardly celebrations of ideal beauty. “Caprice” em-
arts: Jupiter is represented as an eagle grasping bodies the idea of spirit, but I draw attention to
lightning in its claws, and Juno as a peacock (actu- Goya’s advertisement for this work, published in
ally, as a male peacock, with glorious tail feathers). the Diario de Madrid, where he claimed for “la
The power of Jupiter is made vivid through the fact pintura” a right to criticize human error and vice,
that lightning is not something than can ordinar- “although [such] criticism is usually taken to be ex-
ily be grasped—that a being capable of holding clusively the province of literature.”13 If “no hay
128 Global Theories of the Arts and Aesthetics

reglas en la pintura,” there is no rule against using But its presence in those works is internal to their
painting for purposes of “holding a mirror up” to beauty as art. One can accept that without for
“the innumerable foibles and follies to be found in a moment believing that nature itself is God’s
any civilized society.” Greenberg would have re- message in the medium of mountains and mighty
jected this as having nothing essential to do with waterfalls.
plastic art at all. “Literary” was a term of critical The 1961 works of Andy Warhol I spoke of con-
dismissal in Greenberg’s vocabulary, and in for- vey aesthetical ideas—though they have only as
malist vocabulary generally. aesthetic qualities what belongs to cheap adver-
My own view is that the relationship of aes- tisements through their cheapness. They convey
thetics to art was always external and contin- the small vexations of the flesh, and the promise
gent. The advent of pluralism has changed nothing that for a mere few dollars our complexion will be
in this respect. But the theory of art as embod- clear, our hair grow luxuriant, and that love and
ied meanings—or the “aesthetical presentation of happiness will finally come our way. What Ágnes
ideas”—makes it clear how aesthetic qualities can Eperjesi discovered in the throw-away packag-
contribute to the meaning of the work that pos- ing in which consumer products are wrapped are
sesses them. This I am certain is what Hegel in- portraits of the society in which those products
tuited when he declared, at the beginning of his are used. They are ready-made portraits or bet-
lectures on aesthetics, why artistic beauty is “supe- ter, assisted ready-mades, as her melancholy wit
rior” to natural beauty. It is because natural beauty makes clear. Beneath a picture of what looks
is meaningless—not, incidentally, something Kant like a bride in her veil—which may in fact be
could have accepted since for him natural beauty the negative of a photograph of a woman with a
is a symbol of morality, and gives us the sense handkerchief—she writes: “Once in a while some-
that the world is not indifferent to our hopes. thing gets into my eyes. Then I can let go of
Beauty, for him, has a kind of theodical meaning, my feelings” (Figure 2). An innocent, even bland
as the philosopher Fred Rush has recently claimed image of a woman with a hanky is turned into
in his writings. Painting natural beauty, as in the a psychological representation of stifled feelings
immense canvases of the Hudson River School, and a comment on repression for the sake of
was an effort to capture this kind of meaning. appearance.

Figure 2. Ágenes Eperjesi.


Danto Embodied Meanings, Isotypes, and Aesthetical Ideas 129

ARTHUR C. DANTO same may be true of Thierry de Duve’s Kant After Duchamp,
Columbia University which makes a heroic effort to transform Kant’s aesthetic
into the kind of philosophy of art one can live with today.
New York, NY 10027, USA
For obvious reasons, his is not a path I can follow.
2. Otto Neurath, “Visual Education: a New Language.”
internet: acd1@columbia.edu Survey Graphic 26. (1937): 25; this essay can be found at:
http://newdeal.feri.org/survey/37025.htm.
1. This essay was written at the invitation of Bernard 3. Clement Greenberg, The Collected Essays and Crit-
Lafargue, of the Universite de Pau; and it appeared un- icism, Volume 4: Modernism with a Vengeance (1957-1969),
der the title, “Les Significations incarnées comme Idées ed. John O’Brian (University of Chicago Press, 1993),
esthétiques,” in Figures del’art 10 (2006). I am grateful to p. 118.
Diarmuid Costello for having drawn my attention to Kant’s 4. Greenberg, The Collected essays and Criticis, p. 309.
concept of aesthetical ideas as conveying a philosophy of 5. Greenberg, The Collected essays and Criticis, p. 119.
art quite different from the rather shallow one implied by 6. J. L. Austin, Philosophical Papers, ed. J. O. Urmson
the “aesthetics of taste.” He felt that Kant’s concept has and G. J. Warnock (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1961), p. 131.
something of the same logic as my own view of artworks as 7. Dirk Dobke and BernadetteWalther, Roth Time: A
embodied meanings. Kant was annoyed when critics claimed Retrospective of Dieter Roth (New York: Museum of Modern
that some of his ideas had been anticipated by earlier writers Art, 2003), p. 64.
when, as he said, no one had the wit to see them before they 8. David Hume, “The Skeptic,” Essays Moral and Po-
appeared in his writings. I certainly did not have the wit to litical, n. 2.
see Kant as having anticipated ideas of my mine, but no one 9. Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgment, trans. J. H.
can begrudge having Kant as a predecessor. My own feel- Bernard (New York: Hafner Publishing Co., 1951), p. 156.
ing is that aesthetical ideas dropped out of aesthetic theory 10. Kant, Critique of Judgment, p. 157.
until they emerged in the guise of embodied meanings in a 11. This and the following two quotations are from Kant,
very different artworld than Kant could have imagined. If I Critique of Judgment, § 49.
am right, aesthetics really wandered in the wilderness until 12. Francisco Goya, “Address to the Royal Academy of
the anti-aesthetic bias of contemporary art set it on course San Fernando Regarding the Method of Teaching the Visual
once again. Robert J. Yanal’s “Duchamp and Kant: Together Arts,” in Janis A. Tomlinson, Goya in the Twilight of the
Again,” Angelaki 7 (2002): 161–166, was very much on the Enlightenment (Yale University Press, 1992).
right track, had I been able to follow his thought, and the 13. Francisco Goya, Diario de Madrid.

Você também pode gostar