Você está na página 1de 11

Jenaer Schriften zur Wirtschaftswissenschaft

A Decision Rule Based on


the Conditional Value at Risk
Werner Jammernegg und Peter Kischka

09/2005

Arbeits- und Diskussionspapiere


der Wirtschaftswissenschaftlichen Fakultät
der Friedrich-Schiller-Universität Jena

ISSN 1611-1311

Herausgeber: Schriftleitung:
Wirtschaftswissenschaftliche Fakultät Prof. Dr. Hans-Walter Lorenz
Friedrich-Schiller-Universität Jena h.w.lorenz@wiwi.uni-jena.de
Carl-Zeiß-Str. 3, 07743 Jena
Prof. Dr. Armin Scholl
www.wiwi.uni-jena.de a.scholl@wiwi.uni-jena.de
A Decision Rule Based on the Conditional Value at Risk

Werner Jammernegg

Vienna University of Economics and Business Administration, Department of Information


Systems and Operations, A-1090 Wien, Austria
Tel.: (0043) 1-3 13 36 56 33, Fax: (0043) 1-3 13 36 56 10
(werner.jammernegg@wu-wien.ac.at)

Peter Kischka

Friedrich Schiller University Jena, Department of Business Statistics, D-07743 Jena, Germany
Tel.: +49 3641 94 33 00, Fax: +49 3641 94 33 02
(p.kischka@wiwi.uni-jena.de)

Abstract:

We introduce a decision rule where the risk dimension is measured by the conditional value of
risk. We characterize the risk attitudes implied by the decision rule in a way similar to the
well known mean variance framework. We show that the rule is consistent with Yaari’s dual
theory for all risk attitudes. Finally a reformulation of the decision rule is presented which is
based on two conditional expected values.
2

1 Definition of the Decision Rule

Let I be a random variable, e. g. an income stream. Let F be the distribution function of I:


F(x) = P(I ≤ x). Within the well known mean variance framework the utility of I is given by

(1.1) E(I) − δ Var(I)

with some constant δ, expected value E(I) and variance Var(I). For two income streams I and
I ' we have: I is preferred to I ' if and only if

E(I) − δ Var(I) > E(I ') − δ Var(I ') .

In (1.1) the expected value represents the value dimension of I and the variance represents the
risk dimension of I.

It is well known that the variance is not a coherent measure of risk as defined in (Artzner et
al., 1999), indeed it does not fulfil any of the four axioms. In the following, we will replace
the variance in (1.1) by a coherent risk measure, the negative conditional value at risk
(CVaR). For 0 < α ≤ 1 the CVaR α with level α is defined for a random variable I as the
conditional expected value of I given I is below the α-quantile. For invertible distribution
function F we have

(1.2) CVaR α (I) = E(I | I ≤ F−1 (α))

In general, with F−1 (α) = inf { x | F(x) ≥ α} we have

α
1
(1.2 ' ) CVaR α (I) =
α ∫
0
F−1 (t)dt

For invertible F (1.2) and (1.2 ' ) coincide (Acerbi/Tasche, 2002).


It is reasonable to consider an approach where the utility of I is measured by the value
dimension E (I) and the risk dimension -CVaR; instead of (1.1) we will consider the decision
rule.

(1.3) E(I) − δ (-CVaR α (I) )

or

(1.3 ' ) E(I) + δ CVaR α (I) .

Such an approach with positive δ is presented in (Hanisch, 2004); moreover, it is the result
from the maximization of the expected net present value (Pflug/Ruczczynski, 2004):
Let z denote consumption which is derived from I. If z exceeds I there is a shortfall (z –I), if I
exceeds z the surplus I –z has to be discounted.

The rational decision maker will choose a consumption z which maximizes


3

f (z) := z + a ⋅ max (0, I − z) − q max (0, z − I)

where 0 < a < 1 is a discount factor and q > 1 determines the insurance premium q E(z − I)+ .
There is an equivalent definition of the CVaR α as a solution from a maximization problem
(Rockafeller/Uryasev, 2000) which implies

max f (z) = aE(I) + (1 − a) CVaR α (I)


z

1− a
with α = (see Pflug/Ruczczynski, 2004): Dividing by a > 0 we get the decision rule
q−a
1− a
(1.3 ' ) with δ = . Note that δ > 0 since a < 1 in this approach. In the following we will
a
consider the case δ ≤ 0 ( a ≥ 1 ), too.

2 Risk Aversion

A decision maker is risk averse (in the sense of Arrow/Pratt) if the expected value of I is
preferred to the stochastic income stream I. In the mean variance context of (1.1) a decision
maker therefore is risk averse for δ > 0 , otherwise a decision maker is risk neutral ( δ = 0 )or
risk seeking ( δ < 0 ). Whereas risk aversion or risk neutrality are standard assumptions in
finance and some other economic fields, these assumption are e. g. no longer obvious in
operations management. E. g. for the newsvendor problem it is shown that decision makers
show a risk seeking behaviour dealing with low profit products (see Schweitzer/Cachon,
2000). The following proposition shows that with (1.3) all attitudes to risk can be covered.

Proposition 1
A decision maker with decision rule (1.3) is risk averse (risk neutral, risk seeking) if and only
if δ > 0 ( δ = 0 , δ < 0 ).

Proof:
Since CVaR α (I) ≤ E(I) and CVaR α (k) = k for any constant k we have for δ > 0

E(I) + δ CVaR α (I) ≤ E(I) + δE(I)


= E(E(I)) + δ CVaR α (E(I))

The latter term is the ‘utility’ of E(I) according to (1.3). The cases δ = 0 , δ < 0 can be proved
analogously.

Remark:
If I, I ' are two income streams with E(I) = E(I ' ) a risk seeking decision maker will choose
that income stream with the smaller conditional value at risk, i. e. the decision maker over-
estimates the impact of the random variable given it is higher than the α-quantile. A detailed
analysis of this effect will be given in section 4.
4

Further insights concerning the risk attitude of a decision maker can be obtained by analyzing
the decision rule

(2.1) a E(I) + (1 − a) CVaR α (I)

for some constant a ≥ 0 . For a = 0 (2.1) is the decision rule based only on the CVaR, a case
not covered by the approach (1.3). This case can be interpreted as extreme risk aversion. For
a > 0 (2.1) and (1.3) are equivalent decision rules: Dividing (2.1) by a > 0 (2.1) and (1.3) will
1− a
yield the same result with δ = ; note that δ > −1 . Conversely, starting with (1.3) with
a
1
δ > −1 the decision rules are equivalent for a = .
1+ δ

For any a ≤ 1 (2.1) is a convex combination of the value dimension and the risk dimension.
For a = 1 we get the expected value criterion. We will give special emphasis to the case a > 1.
The following example shows an interesting consequence of this assumption.

Example:
Let I ~ N(µ, σ 2 ) . Let ϕ, Φ denote the density and the distribution function of the standard
normal distribution. We have

1
CVaR α (I) = µ − σ ⋅ ⋅ ϕ(Φ −1 (α ))
α

(see Johnson et al., 1994, p. 156 f).

Therefore (2.1) is given by

1
a µ + (1 − a) (µ − σ ⋅ ⋅ ϕ(Φ −1 (α)) =
α
1
= µ − (1 − a) ⋅ ⋅ σ ⋅ ϕ(Φ −1 (α))
α

For a > 1 the ‘utility’ of I increases with increasing σ.

3 Relations to Dual Utility Theory

In this section, we show that the criterion (2.1) is consistent with Yaaris’s dual theory. We
generalize a result of J. Hanisch (Hanisch, 2004) who has shown this consistency for
0 ≤ a ≤ 1.

Yaaris’s theory (Yaari, 1987) is a special case of the rank dependent utility theory. It is based
on the idea, that the probability of a bad result is judged differently from the same probability
of a good result. There is some evidence for the dual theory (see e. g. Diedicue/Wakker, 2001)
from an empirical point of view. Further evidence is given by a reformulation of (2.1) in
section 4 (see proposition 5 and following remarks).
5

Lemma
1
For 0 < α < 1 and for 0 ≤ a ≤ the function
1− α
(3.1) ϑ : [0,1] → [0,1]
⎛x ⎞
x → ax + (1 − a) min ⎜ ,1⎟
⎝α ⎠

is a continuous, monotonically increasing function with ϑ(0) = 0, ϑ(1) = 1.

Proof:

x ≥ α : ϑ(x) = a x + (1 − a) with ϑ '(x) = a


1 1
x ≤ α : ϑ(x) = a x + (1 − a)x with ϑ '(x) = a + (1 − a)
α α

1
So, for 0 ≤ a ≤ ϑ has the required properties.
1− α

In Yaari’s dual theory I is preferred to I ' if for some function ϑ with the properties stated in
the above lemma and for the (generalized) inverse distribution functions F, F ' we have

1 1

∫ F (x) dϑ(x) ≥ ∫ F' (x) dϑ(x)


−1 −1
(3.2)
0 0

(see e. g. Guriev, 2001).

Note that the above integrals exist for continuous functions ϑ since any distribution function
is of bounded variation (see e. g. Apostol, 1974, p 128, 139).

Proposition 2
1
For ϑ defined in (3.1) and for 0 ≤ a ≤ we have
1− α
1
aE(I) + (1 − a) CVaR α (I) = ∫ F−1 (x) dϑ(x)
0

Proof:
From the linearity properties of the Riemann-Stieltjes integral (see e. g. Apostol, 1974), p
142) we have
6

1 1
x
∫F ∫F
−1 −1
(x) dϑ(x) = (x) d(ax + (1 − a) min( ,1))
0 0
α
1
= a ∫ F−1 (x) dx +
0
α
x
+ (1 − a) ∫ F−1 (x) d(min( ,1))
0
α
1
x
+ (1 − a) ∫ F−1 (x) d(min( ,1))
α
α
1 α
1 −1
= a ∫ F−1 (x) dx + (1 − a)
α ∫0
F (x)dx
0

= a E(I) + (1 − a) CVaR α (I)

So from proposition 2 and (3.2) we can conclude that a decision maker with a decision rule
given by (1.3) or (2.1) satisfies the axioms of the dual utility theory.

4 A characterization of risk behaviour

From proposition 1 we know that a decision maker using (1.3) as a decision rule is risk averse
if and only if δ > 0 . From (2.1) we conclude that a decision maker is risk averse if and only if
a < 1, since (2.1) can be transformed to (1.3) by dividing by a. For convenience we assume
that F is invertible in the following.

Further characterizations of the risk behaviour can be derived from the following decision rule

(4.1) λ E(I | I ≤ F−1 (α )) + (1 − λ)E(I | I > F−1 (α))

with some constant λ ∈ [0,1] .

Proposition 3
We have

λ E(I | I ≤ F−1 (α )) + (1 − λ )E(I | I > F−1 (α )) = a E(I) + (1 − a) CVaR α (I)

1− λ
with a= .
1− α
7

Proof:

λ E(I | I ≤ F−1 (α)) + (1 − λ )E(I | I > F−1 (α))



1
1 − α F−1∫( α )
= λ ⋅ CVaR α (I) + (1 − λ) x dF(x)

1
= λ ⋅ CVaR α (I) + (1 − λ) (E(I) − αCVaR α (I))
1− α
1− λ λ−α
= E(I) + CVaR α (I).
1− α 1− α

So (2.1) and (4.1) define the same decision rule. In (4.1) E(I | I > F−1 (α)) may be interpreted
as a value dimension. The smaller λ the smaller is the impact of the risk dimension
E(I | I ≤ F−1 (α)) .The reformulation (4.1) of (2.1) is an additional hint that the criterion (1.3) or
(2.1) respectively can be interpreted as a special case of the dual theory, since the decision is
based on a ranking of the possible realizations.

The relations between α and λ in (4.1) determine the risk attitude.

Proposition 4
A decision maker using (4.1) is risk averse (risk neutral, risk seeking) if and only if
λ > α (λ = α , λ < α ) .

Proof:
The proposition follows from proposition 3 and CVaR α (I) ≤ E(I) .
8

References

Acerbi, C., Tasche, D., 2002. On the Coherence of Expected Shortfall. Journal of Banking
and Finance 26, 1487 – 1503.

Apostol, T., 1974. Mathematical Analysis. Reading (Mass.), Addison-Wesley.

Artzner, P., Delbaen, F., Eber, J.-M., Heath, D., 1999. Coherent Measures of Risk.
Mathematical Finance 9, 203 – 228.

Diedicue, E., Wakker, P., 2001. On the Intuition of Rank Dependent Utility. Journal of Risk
and Uncertainty 23, 281- 298.

Guriev, S., 2001. On Microfoundations of the Dual Theory of Choice. Geneva Papers on Risk
and Insurance Theory 26, 117 – 137.

Hanisch, J., 2004. Risikomessung mit dem Conditional Value-at-Risk:


Entscheidungstheoretische Grundlagen und Implikationen für das Risikomanagement.
Dissertation, Friedrich-Schiller-Universität Jena, Jena.

Johnson, N., Kotz, S., Balakishnan, A. 1994). Distribution in Statistics, Continuous


Univariate Distributions. Vol. 2. John Wiley, New York.

Pflug, G., Ruczczynski, A., 2004. A Risk Measure for Income Processes. In: Szegö, G.(ed).
Risk Measures for the 21st Century, West Sussex, John Wiley, 249 – 269.

Rockafellar, T., Uryasev, S., 2000. Optimization of Conditional Value-at-Risk. Journal of


Risk 2, 21 – 41.

Schweitzer, M., Cachon, G., 2000. Decision Bias in the Newsvendor Problem with a Known
Demand Distribution: Experimental Evidence. Management Science 46, 404 – 420.

Yaari, M., 1987. The Dual Theory of Choice Under Risk. Econometrica 55, 95 – 115.
Jenaer Schriften zur Wirtschaftswissenschaft

2005

1 Reinhard Haupt: Patent analysis of a company’s 8 Roland Helm und Oliver Mauroner: New Firms
technology strength. from Research-based Spin-offs.

2 Axel Braßler, Christoph Grau, Herfried Schnei- 9 Werner Jammernegg und Peter Kischka: A Deci-
der: Wissenslabor Betriebswirtschaft - Eine Lehr-, sion Rule Based on the Conditional Value at Risk.
Lern- und Kommunikationsumgebung für die uni-
versitäre und betriebliche Aus- und Weiterbildung.
10 Roland Helm und Wolfgang Stölzle: Out-of-
Stocks im Handel: Einflussfaktoren und Kundenre-
3 Wolfgang Kürsten: Risikomanagement und aktio- aktionsmuster.
närsorientierte Unternehmenssteuerung - Mehr
Fragen als Antworten.
11 Uwe Cantner, Kristina Dreßler, Jens J. Krüger:
Knowledge Compensation in the German Auto-
4 Roland Helm, Reinhard Meckl, Nicole Sodeik: mobile Industry.
Wissensmanagement – Ein Überblick zum Stand
der empirischen Forschung.
12 Volkmar Botta, Martin Köhler: Zur Wertaufhel-
lungskonzeption nach IAS 10.
5 Uwe Cantner, Kristina Dreßler, Jens J. Krüger:
Knowledge and Creative Destruction over the In-
dustry Life Cycle - The Case of the German Auto- 13 Roland Helm und Michael Gehrer: Zum Aufbau
mobile Industry. von Vertrauen in interaktiven Entscheidungspro-
zessen.

6 Reinhard Meckl, Robert Schramm: Empirical evi-


dence for a theory of international new ventures. 14 Andreas Feytag and Donato Masciandaro: Finan-
cial Supervision Fragmentation and Central Bank
Independence: The Two Sides of the Same Coin?
7 Andreas Freytag, Dirk Schiereck, Thomas W.
Thomas: Consolidation and Market Power of En-
ergy Utilities - The case of US-American and Ger-
man Utility Takeovers.

2004

1 Uwe Cantner, Werner Güth, Andreas Nicklisch, metrics”. Erscheint in: Hanusch, H., Pyka, A.
Torsten Weiland: Competition in Innovation and (Hrsg.), The Elgar Companion to Neo-
Imitation – A Theoretical and Experimental Study. Schumpeterian Economics, 2005.

2 Uwe Cantner, Andreas Freytag: Eliten, Wettbe- 6 Roland Helm: Export Market Entry Strategy and
werb und langer Atem – Ein praktikabler Vorschlag Success – Conceptual Framework and Empirical
zur Schaffung von Eliteuniversitäten. Erschienen Examination. Erschienen als: Market Commitment,
als: Elite-Universitäten können nur im Wettbewerb Export Market Entry Strategy and Success - Concep-
entstehen, Orientierungen zur Wirtschafts- und Ge- tual Framework and Empirical Examination, in:
sellschaftspolitik 99 (2004), S. 51-52. International Journal of Globalisation and Small
Business, Vol. 1, No. 1 2004, S. 58-78.
3 Johannes Ruhland, Kathrin Kirchner (Hrsg.):
Räumliche Datenbanken – Überblick und prakti- 7 Roland Helm, Michaela Ludl: Kundenkarten als
scher Einsatz in der Betriebswirtschaft. Kundenbindungsinstrument des Handels. Erscheint
als: Kundenbindung im Handel durch Kundenkar-
4 Uwe Cantner, Holger Graf: The Network of In- ten [...], in: Bauer, H. H., Huber, F. (Hrsg.), Stra-
novators in Jena – An Application of Social Net- tegien und Trends im Handelsmanagement, 2004,
work Analysis. Vahlen, München, S. 61-82.
5 Uwe Cantner, Jens J. Krüger: Empirical Tools for 8 Uwe Cantner, Kristina Dreßler, Jens J. Krüger:
the Analysis of Technological Heterogeneity and Firm Survival in the German Automobile Industry.
Change – Some Basic Building Blocks of “Evolu-
II

9 Marcus Lange, Martin Zimmermann: Patent- 21 Wolfgang Kürsten: Unternehmensfinanzierung –


Chart – Das Monitoring von Patentportfolios auf Grundlagen, Entwicklungslinien und aktuelle Per-
der Basis von Zitatbeziehungen. spektiven. Erscheint in: Vahlens Kompendium der
Betriebswirtschaftslehre.
10 Jens J. Krüger: Capacity Utilization and Technol-
ogy Shocks in the U.S. Manufacturing Sector. 22 Markus Pasche: Voluntary Commitment to Envi-
ronmental Protection: A Bounded Rationality Ap-
11 Andreas Freytag: EMU Enlargement: Which Con-
proach.
cept of Convergence to Apply?
23 Andreas Freytag, Simon Renaud: Langfristorien-
12 Andreas Freytag, Simon Renaud: From Short-
tierung in der Arbeitsmarktpolitik.
Term to Long-Term Orientation – Political Econ-
omy of the Policy Reform Process. 24 Reinhard Haupt, Karsten Jahn, Marcus Lange,
Wolfgang Ziegler: Der Patentlebenszyklus: Me-
13 Martin Kloyer, Roland Helm, Wolfgang Burr:
thodische Lösungsansätze der externen Technolo-
Compensation Preferences of R&D-Suppliers –
gieanalyse.
Some Empirical Results.
25 Axel Braßler, Christoph Grau: Modulare Organi-
14 Roland Helm, Michael Gehrer: Interaktion und
sationseinheiten. Erschienen als: Modulare Organi-
Information in der Anbieter-Nachfrager-Bezie-
sationseinheiten – eine intraorganisationale Betrach-
hung: Voraussetzungen, Konsequenzen und Impli-
tung, in: WSt 34 (2005), Teil I: S. 182-189, Teil II:
kationen der zentralen und peripheren Informati-
S. 242-250.
onsverarbeitung.
26 Werner Jammernegg, Peter Kischka: Performance
15 Wolfgang Kürsten: Synergies, Shareholder Value
Measurement for Inventory Models with Risk
and Exchange Ratios in “Value Creating” Mergers
Preferences.
– Why Shareholders Should Doubt Management’s
Pre-Merger Promises. Erscheint in: Managerial Fi- 27 Reinhard Haupt, Armin Scholl: Fundamental-
nance. entscheidungen bei unvollkommener Information –
UMTS-Lizenzen ersteigern oder verweigern, über-
16 Jens J. Krüger: Using the Manufacturing Pro-
nehmen oder übernommen werden, Rentenwende
ductivity Distribution to Evaluate Growth Theo-
oder -ende, Glaube oder Unglaube?
ries.
28 Roland Helm, Oliver Mauroner: Innovative Spin-
17 Andreas Freytag, Klaus Winkler: The Economics
offs aus der Forschung als neue Unternehmen –
of Self-regulation in Telecommunications under
Zum Stand der empirischen Forschung.
Sunset Legislation.
29 Simone Martin: Sabotagekosten als Ursache für
18 Markus Pasche, Sebastian von Engelhardt: Volks-
geschlechtsspezifische Unterschiede in Einkom-
wirtschaftliche Aspekte der Open-Source-Software-
menshöhe und Fluktuationswahrscheinlichkeit?
entwicklung.
30 Jens J. Krüger: Productivity Dynamics and Struc-
19 Robert Klein, Armin Scholl: Software zur Ent-
tural Change in the U.S. Manufacturing Sector.
scheidungsanalyse – Eine Marktübersicht.
20 Roland Helm, Michael Steiner, Armin Scholl,
Laura Manthey: A Comparative Empirical Study
on Common Methods for Measuring Preferences.

Você também pode gostar