Você está na página 1de 632

^l|{Io(osicaf Seminary Xibrarg

' '.h THE (3IFT OF

'...
, X 31tetttg ''lai, Sage

^*i^^# OF ITHACA.

CorneK "ainitieirisitg
5LIN lIBR- ^-i^^"^^^
DATE DUE
^.- .
THE

STOICS, EPICUEEANS
AND

SCEPTICS
LONDON : PRINTED BT
SP0TTI8W00DH AND 00., NEW-STBEBT SQTJABB
AND PAELIAMBNT STEBET
7<i^' CORNELL <
v^ UNIVERSITY^.

THE

STOICS, EPICUEEANS
<
^
AND

SCEPTICS

TRANSLATED FSOU THE GEBMAN OF

m E. ZELLEK
Professor of the University of Heidelberg

BY

OSWALD J, EEICHEL, B.C.L. & M.A.


Ticar of Sparsbolt, Berks

A NEW AND BEVISEB EDITION

LONDON
LONGMANS, OREEN, AND CO.
1880
50
X6\

t
PEEFACE,

The present translation aims at supplying an intro-

ductory volume to a later period of the history of

mind in Greece, which may be collectively described

as the post-Aristotelian. To the moralist and theo-

logian no less than to the student of philosophy this

period is one of peculiar interest ; for it supplied

the scientific mould into which Christianity in the

early years of its growth was cast, and bearing the

shape of which it has come down to us.

Spaesholt Vicarage :

October, 1879.
CONTENTS.

PAET I.

STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.

CHAPTER I,

THE INTELLECTUAL AND POLITICAL STATE OP GREECE


AT THE CLOSE OP THE POUETH CENTURY, B.C.
PAGE
A. Merits and defects of the systems of Plato and Aris-
totle . . . . . .1
B. Connection between the theories of Aristotle and the
Greek character . . . . .6
C. Greece after the battle of Chseronea . . 12

CHAPTER II.

CHARACTER AND CHIEF FEATURES OF THE


POST-ARISTOTELIAN PHILOSOPHY.

A. Causes forming the post-Aristotelian philosophy . 15


1. Political causes . . . . 1.5

2. Intellectual causes . . . .17


B. Common characteristics of the post - Aristotelian phi-
losophy . . . . .19 .

1. Theory subordinated to practice . 19.

2. Peculiar mode of treating the practical problem 21 .

3. These peculiarities illustrated by subsequent phi-


losophy . . . . . .22
viii CONTENTS.

C. Development of the post-Aristoteliau philosophy 5

1. Dogmatic Schools Stoics and Epicureans, Dogma-

tic Scepticism . . . 25
2. ScepticalSchoolsinfluences producing Sceptic-
ism and Eclecticism .
26
3. Eeligious School of Neoplatonists . . .31

PAET II.

THE STOICS.

CHAPTER in.

HISTORY OP THE STOICS UNTIL THE END OF THE


SECOND CBNTTJEY, B.C.

A. 36
40
40
41
43
45
45
48

AUTHORITIES FOE THE STOIC PHILOSOPHY; ITS PROBLEM

A. Authorities
1.
...... AND

Review of authorities'
DIVISIONS.

. . .
53
53
2. Use to be made of authorities . . .55
.
CONTENTS.
PAGE
Dynamical theory of Nature .139

.....
. . .

1. Matter and force . . . . .139


2. Nature of force 141
3. Deity
Pantheism
1. God
......
God as force God as matter
identical with the wofld .
.

.
.


148
156
156
2. Relative difference between God and the world . 158
3. Views of Boethus . . . . .159

CHAPTER VII.

THE STUDY OF ITATUEE 2. COUESB, CHAEACTEB,


:

AND GOVERNMENT OP THE UNIVBESB.


The General Course of the Universe . . . 161
1. Origin of the world . . . 161
2. End of the world . . . . .163
3. Cycles in the world's course

Government of the World .... . . . 165


170
1.

2.
......
Nature of Destiny as Providence as Generative
Reason
Arguments in favour of Providence

170
173 . .

3.

Nature of the World .....


The idea of Providence determined 175 . .

182
1.

2.
Itsunity and perfection
Moral theory of the world ....
. . . 183
187

CHAPTER VIII.

THE STUDY OP NATUEB : 3. IRRATIONAL NATURE.


THE ELEMENTS. THE UNIVEESE.

A. The most general ideas on Nature 194


B. The Elements 197
(}. The Universe 202
1. The stars 204
2. Meteorology 206
3. Plants and animals .
208

CONTENTS. li

OHAPTER IX.

A. The Soul .....


THE STUDY OF NATtjEB : 4. MAN.

.210
PAGE

1.

2.
MateriaKstio nature of the soul
Divisions of the soul .... . . . 210
213
B.
C.
The Individual Soul and the Soul
Freedom and Immortality ....of the Universe . 216
219

CHAPTER X.

ETHICS: 1. THE GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF THE STOIC ETHICS.


ABSTEACT THEORY OP MORALITY.
A. The Highest Good . . . . .225
1. Nature of the Highest Good . . 225
2. The Good and Evil . . .230
3. Pleasure and the Good . . 235
4. Negative character of Happiness 239

.....
. .

5. The Highest Good as Law . . 240


B. Emotions and Virtue 243
1. The Emotions
their nature varieties of . . 243
2. Idea of Virtue
position and negative aspects of

.......

the virtues severally their mutual relations
unity of virtue 254
C. The Wise Man . . 268
1. Wisdom and Folly 268

.....
. . .

2. Universal Depravity . . . 272


3. Conversion 275

OHAPTER XI.

ETHICS: 2. THE STOIC THEORY OP MORALS AS


MODIFIED IN PRACTICE.

1.

2.
Secondary goods .....
A, Things to be preferred and eschewed

Classes of things indifferent


.

,
.

.
.

.
278
280
281
3. Collision of. modified and abstract theory . . 284
xu CONTENTS.

B.

C.
.

CONTENTS.

CHAPTER XIV.
THE STOIC PHILOSOPHT AS A WHOLE AND ITS

A. Inner connection of the system


1. Ethical side of Stoicism
....
HISTOEICAL ANTECEDENTS.

....
PAGE
381
382
2. Scientific side of the Stoic system . . . 383
3. Connection of the moral and scientific elements . 385
B. Relation of Stoicism to previous systems . 387
1. Its and the Cynics
relation to Socrates . . 387
2. Relation to Megarians and Heraclitus . . 392
3. Relation to Aristotle . . . .396

C.
4. Relation to Plato
The Stoic philosophy as a whole
.

....
.

.....
. . .399
400
1. Its

2. Its
place in history
onesidedness ..... 400
402

PART in.
THE EPICUREANS.

CHAPTER XV.

A. Epicurus .....
EPICtTREANS

....
B. Scholars of Epicurus
AHD THE EPICUEEAJT SCHOOL.
404
408
C. Epicureans of the Roman period 411

CHAPTER XVI.

OHAEACTEE AND DIVISIONS OF THE EPICUREAN


TEACHING. THE TEST-SCIENCE OF TKUTH.

A. Character of Epicurean system . 418


1. Its power of self-preservation 418
XIT CONTENTS.
PAGE
2.
3.
Aim
Divisions of philosophy ....
of philosophy according to the Epicvireans . 420
424

1.

2.
Sensation and perception
Notions . . .
....
Canonic or the Test- Science of Truth .

.
.425

.428
425

3. Opinion . . . ,. . .429
4. Standard of truth suhjective . . . 431

CHAPTER XVn.

A.
CONTENTS.

OHAPTEK XIX.

THE MOKAL SCIENCE OF THE EPICUREANS :

A. Pleasure .....
1. GENERAL VIEWS.
. .

xvi CONTENTS.

PAET IV.

THE SCEPTICS: PYJRSSO AND THE OLDER


ACADEMY.

CHAPTER XXII.
PYEKHO.
PAGE
Historical position of Scepticism . . 614
1. Relation to cotemporary dogmatic systems 514
2. Causes producing it 515
3. Pyrrho and his followers 517
Teaching of Pyrrho 521
1. Impossibility of knowledge 521
2. 'Withholding of judgment 523
3. Mental imperturbability 525

CHAPTER XXIII.

THE NEW ACADEMY.


A. Arcesilaus . . . 528

B.
1

2.

Cameades
1.

2.
...
Denial of knowledge
Probability .

Negative views of
Positive views of
.

.
.
.

.
528
534
535
588
553
C. School of Carneades .
563

GENEEAL INDEX . . .567


;

PART I..

STATE OF CVLTURE IN GREECE.

CHAPTER I.

THE INTELLECTTJAL AND POLITICAL STATE OF GREECE


AT THE CLOSE OF THE FOURTH CENTURY.

In Plato and Aristotle Greek PMlosophy reached Chap.


^'
its greatest perfection. In their hands the Soeratic
philosophy of conceptions had been developed into
elaborate systems, embracing the whole range of A.. Merits
contemporary knowledge, and grouping from de- 'Ti "^S'^x
it

finite points of view so as to afford a connected view systems of


of the universe. The study of nature had been sup-
:^^f^^^
plemented by careful enquiries into morals, and had
been itself transformed, enlarged, and enriched by
Aristotle. In metaphysics, the foundations of a phi-
losophical building had been by him laid deeply,
everything that is having been thoroughly referred
to first principles, so as no previous philosopher had
attempted. A multitude of phenomena which earlier

thinkers had carelessly passed by, in particular the


phenomena of mental life, had been pressed into the
service of research ; new questions had been raised
B
STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.
Chap, new answers given. Into every branch of knowledge
"

new ideas had reached and penetrated. Idealism,


that beautiful and telling expression of the Greek
mind, had been set forth by Plato in pure brilliancy,
and had been united by Aristotle with the most
careful observation. Practice and theory had brought
the dialectic method to the position of an art, and a
valuable instrument of thought had been gained in
the scientific use of terms of which Aristotle was the
T-eal originator. Within a few generations the intel-
lectual treasures of Greece had been increased mani-
fold both in extent and value. The heritage received
by Socrates from his predecessors could hardly be re-
cognised as the same left by Aristotle to his successors.
Oreat as was the progress made by Greek phi-
losophy in the fourth century before Christ, equally
great, however, were the difficulties with which it
had perpetually to contend not less difficult the
;

problems for the solution of which it had to labour.


Already Aristotle had pointed out the weak points
in the system of Plato, rendering it impossible for
him to rest therewith content. From the platform
of present knowledge still further objections would
be naturally urged. And again as r^ards AristotleJ
even in his system inconsistencies on some of the
most important points may be found concealed under*
a certain indefiniteness of expression, fatal if once
brought to light to the soundness of the wholeJ
"With all his ingenuity, Aristotle had not succeeded
in blending into one harmonious whole all the ele^
ments out of which his system was composed. Hence
MERITS AND DEFECTS OF EARLIER SYSTEMS.
the divergencies of his immediate followers from the Chap.
original Aristotelian teaching may be explained.
'

Nor were these defects of a kind that could be


easily got over. On the contrary, the more the
matter is gone into, the clearer it becomes that these
defects were embedded in the foundations of the
systems both of Plato and Aristotle, underlying in
short the whole previous career of philosophic thought.
Leaving details and minor points out of considera-
tion, they all ultimately may be traced to two main
sources, either to an imperfect knowledge and expe-
rience of the world, or to the hasty conclusions of an
idealistic philosophy of conceptions. To the former
cause may be attributed the mistakes in natural
science into which Plato and Aristotle fell, and the
limited character of their view of history; to the
latter, the Platonic theory of ideas with all that it
involves the antithesis of ideas and appearances, of
reason and the senses, of knowledge and ignorance,
of the present world and the world to come and
likewise the corresponding points in the system
of Aristotle ; such, for instance (to mention some of
the principal ones only), as the relation of what is

particular and what is general, of form and matter,


of God and the world, of the theory of final causes
and of natural explanations, of the rational and the
irrational parts of the soul, of speculative theory and
practice.
Both causes are, however, closely connected. The
Greek philosophers were content with an uncertain
and defective knowledge of facts, because they trusted
b2
STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.
Chap, conceptions too implicitly, being ignorant of their
'

origin and worth ; and they had this unconditional


trust in the truth of conceptions because the study
of nature was yet in its infancy. Their knowledge
of history was as yet too limited for them to note
the difference between the results of a careful obser-
vation and those of ordinary unmethodical experience,
the uncertainty of most of the traditional principles
and the necessity for amore stringent method of
induction. The fault common
to both Plato and
Aristotle lay in attaching undue prominence to the
dialectical method inherited from Socrates to the
neglect of observation, and in supposing that con-
ceptions expressing the very essence of things can be
deduced in a purely logical way from cxirrent beliefs
and the uses of language. In Plato this dialectical
exclusiveness appears more strongly, finding expres-
sion in a telling manner in the theory of recollection.
For certainly, if all our conceptions are inherent
from the moment of birth, needing only the agency
of sensible things to make us conscious of their exists
ence, it may be legitimately inferred that, to know
the essence of things, we must look within and not
without, obtaining our ideas by development from
the mind rather than by abstraction from experience.
It may be inferred with equal reason, that the ideas
drawn from the mind are the true standard by which
experience must be judged. Whenever ideas and
experience disagree, instead of regarding ideas as at
fault, we ought to look upon the data of experienci

as imperfect, and as inadequately expressing thi


MERITS AND DEFECTS OF EARLIER SYSTEMS. i

ideas which constitute the thing as it really exists. Chap.


'

The whole theory of ideas, in short, and all that it

implies, is a natural corollary from the Soeratic


theory of conceptions. Even those parts of this
theory which seem most incongruous are best ex-
plained by being referred to the principles of the
Soeratic process.
PVom the onesidedness of these suppositions
Aristotle is only partly free. Undoubtedly he at-
tempted to supply the defects in the Soeratic and
Platonic theory of conceptions by observation, with
which Plato's experimental knowledge cannot be
compared, either in point of accuracy or extent.
Neither can it be ignored that therewith is con-
nected that complete transformation of 'the Pla-
tonic metaphysics, whereby the same right is

secured for particulars over against the universal, as


the philosopher had already secured for observation
over against conceptional knowledge. But Aristotle
did not go far enough. In his theory of knowledge
he cannot wholly discard the supposition that the-
soul has its knowledge by a process of development
from within, being not only endowed with the capa-
city of thinking, but possessing from its birth the^
substance of ideas. In his scientific method the
critical investigation of common notions and of idiom,
that in fact which he himself calls proof by proba-
bilities, is constantly taking the place of strict

induction. His endeavours to harmonise the two


antagonistic currents in Plato's teaching may have
been undertaken in all sincerity, but the antagonism
6 STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.
Chap, was too deep-seated to yield to his efforts. It not
"

only reappears in the fundamental ideas, but colours


the most general results of his system. Beginning
with the antithesis between forvn and matter, it
ends in the contrast between the world and a sovl
outside the world, in the conception of reason re-
garded even in man as something coming from
without, and never combining with the lower parts
of his nature to form one complete living unity.
B. Con- Granting that the above features may be proxi-
tween the niately deduced from the Socratic theory of concep-
theories of tions, still that philosophy, it must be owned, expresses
and Greeh the character of the nation to which it belonged. In
clmraeter.
^^ earlier work it has been shown ' that the com-
monest peculiarity of life in Greece consists in the
undisturbed unity of the outer and the inner world,
in an artless belief that mind and matter were origi-
nally connected, and are still in perfect harmony j

with one another. "When the whole mental life of a


people bears this impress, it is not likely to be want-
ing in its philosophy also. Besides the advantages,!
therefore, which accrue from the close connection of
those two elements, philosophy will also share the de- \

fects unavoidably connected with any view of their


intimacy which ignores a real distinction between
them. Only gradually and imperfectly will the mind
become aware of the distinctive peculiarity of mental
life, of the notion of personality, of the independence
of moral rights and duties of all external circum^

' Zeller's Philosophie der Grieolien. Part I. 96.


PHILOSOPHT AND NATIONAL CJSAMACTEM.
stances, of the share of our own will in creating our Chap,
ideas. On the other hand, it will have less hesita- L_
tion in transferring the phases of consciousness imme-
diately to things themselves, in regarding the world
from ideal points of view borrowed from the domain
of our own minds, in accepting our own notions of
things as something real, without testing their actual
truth, nay, even treating them as higher compared
with the reality of the senses, and in confounding
the critical analysis of a notion with the experimental
investigation of a thing. If in the time of its highest
perfection the philosophy of Greece was not free from
these mistakes ; if, further, these were the cause of
aU the important faults in the systems of Plato and
Aristotle, not the framers of these systems only and
their immediate successors ought to bear the blame,
but rather the whole mental peculiarity of that people,
of which within the province of science these men
were the greatest representatives.
In proportion as the close connection of the faults
of the Platonic and Aristotelian systems with the
whole character of Greek thought becomes apparent,
the more difficult, it will be felt, was it for G-reek
thought to. emancipate itself from these faults. To
compass this a sweeping change of the customary lines

of thought would be requisite. The origin of our


ideas, the primary meaning of our conceptions, must
needs be examined much more closely; a sharper
distinction made between what is supplied from with-
out and what is supplied from within ; the truth of
several axioms received in metaphysics, more carefully
1
STATE OF CULTURE IN OBEECE.
Chap, investigated, than had been done as yet. Science
^'
must accustom itself to an accuracy of observation,
and to a strictness of inductive process, never as yet
reached in Greece. Sciences resting on observation
must have attained a pitch of completeness which it
was vain to hope to reach by the methods and means
then in vogue. The anthropomorphic way of looking
at nature, allowing questions as to facts to be an-
swered by speculations on final causes and the desire
of nature to realise beauty, must be dropped. En-
quiries into man's moral nature and functions would
have to be severed from a regard for purely natu-
ral relations, the disturbing influences of which may

be seen in the national exclusiveness of the Greeks,


in the onesided political character of their morality,
in the institution of slavery.
How much would have to be changed in the con-
ditions and views of Greece before this pass would be
reached !Could it be expected that a stricter and
more scientific method would obtain rule so long as
the tendency to look upon the life of nature as ana-
logous to the life of man was
kept alive by a religion
such as that of Hellas Or that moral science would
?

shake off the trammels of the Greek propriety of


conduct, whilst in all practical matters those trammels
were in full force? Or that a sharper distinction
between what comes from without and what from \

within in our ideas a distinction which we vainly


look for in Aristotle would
prevail, until a depth
and an intensity had been given to the inner life, and \

the rights and value of the individual as such had i



PHILOSOPHY AND NATIONAL CHARACTER.
obtained a recognition which it required the combined Chap
influence of Christianity and the peculiar Grermanic
character to bring about? The more vividly we
realise the national stamp and the surrounding na-
tional conditions of the Greek philosophy, with all
the characteristics of the national life, the more ready

to hand is the conviction, that to heal its defects


defects which are apparent even in its greatest and
most brilliant
achievements nothing short of an
actual revolution in the mental tone of Greece would
avail such as history has at length seen accom-
plished after many shifts and many centuries.
On the platform of the ancient life of Greece
such a change could not possibly have come about.
Thereby certainly the possibility is not excluded,
that under more favom-able circumstances a further
development of Greek philosophy might have taken
place in the same course of purely intellectual en-
quiry which it had followed hitherto in the hands of
its earlier representatives, and more particularly of
Aristotle, with the most important results. The
results which might in this way have been possibly
attained, we cannot exactly determine. Speculation
is, however, useless. In point of fact, the historical
circumstances under which philosophy had to grow
cannot be ignored. It had only become what it had
under the influences of these circumstances. The
Socratic theory of conceptions, and the Ideal theory
of Plato, presuppose on the one hand the high cul-
ture of the age of Pericles, and the brilliant career
of Athens and Greece following on the Persian war.
10 STATU OF CULTURE IN GREECE.
Chap. Not do they presuppose the political degradation
less
'

and the moral exhaustion of Grreece during and after


the Peloponnesian war. In his purely intellectual
attitude, despairing of every direct practical activity,
in his broad view of things, his knowledge of every
kind, in his system matured and elaborate, and em-
bracing all the results of previous enquiry Aristotle
appears as the child of an age which was bearing to
its grave a great historical development, in which
intellectual labour had begun to take the place of
hearty political action.
The bloom of Greek philosophy was short-lived,
but not more so than the bloom of national Ufe, A
closer examination shows that the one depended- on
the other, and that both of these phenomena were
due to the operation of the same causes. With
a high appreciation of freedom, with a ready aptitude
for politics, with a genius for artistic creations, the

Greeks produced, within the sphere of politics, one


result of its kind unrivalled and unique. They
neglected, however, to lay the foundations wide and
deep. Their political duration could not keep pace
with their versatility and excitability. Communi-
ties limited in extent and simple in arrangement
sufficed for them, which, however, could not include
all branches of the Greek family, nor satisfy at once
all legitimate interests. Within the range of science
we likewise see them forming rash conclusions, advanc-
ing from individual experiences at once and without
any mediating links to the most general conceptions,
and constructing theories upon a foundation of
PHILOSOPHY AND NATIONAL CHAMACTEJR. 11

limited and imperfect which it was


experience, Chap.
'

wholly inadequate to bear. Whether, and in how


far, the intellect of Greece, if left to itself, might
have remedied these defects in a longer protracted,
undisturbed deyelopment, is a question which it is

impossible to answer. That intellect was far too

intimately bound up with the political, the moral,



and the religious .life in short, with the whole
mental tone and culture of the people not to be
seriously affected by any of their changes. It lay,

too, in the character and historical progress of this


people to have only a brief period of splendour, and
one soon over. At the time that the philosophy
of Greece reached its highest point in Plato and
Aristotle, in all other respects Greece was then in a
hopeless state of decline. Notwithstanding indi-
vidual attempts to resuscitate it, the old morality
and propriety of conduct had disappeared since the
beginning of the Peloponnesian war. Together withi
them, too, the old belief in the gods was gone. To
the bulk of the people the rising philosophy with its

ethics afforded no substitute. Art, however carefully ,

cultivated, could no longer come up to the excellence


of the strictly classic period. Political relations

became daily more unsatisfactory. If in the fifth

century before Christ the rivalry of Athens and Sparta


had ranged the states of Greece into two groups, in
the succeeding century disunion spread further. Even
the attempt of Thebes under Epaminondas to found
a new leadership only multiplied parties. Destitute
of a political centre of gi'avity, the Greeks, of their
12 STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.
Chap, own choice, drifted into a disgraceful dependence on
'

the conquered and now declining Persian empire.


Persian gold wielded an influence which Persian
arms had never been able to exercise. The petty
jealousies of Kttle states and tribes wasted in endless
local feuds resources which needed only unity and
leadership to do wonders. With the decline of civil
order the well-being and martial prowess of the
nation declined also; and the increasing technical
cultivation of the art of war contributed to take the
decision of battle more and more out of the hands of
free citizens, and to place it in those of the numerous
mercenaries which are one of the most injurious
phenomena of this age, a sure sign of the decline of
freedom, and of the approach of a military despotism.
As this danger with the threatening rise of the Mace-
donian power came nearer, patriots in Greece might
still deceive themselves with the hope that their
self-devotion would avert the danger. An unbiassed
glance at history can, however, only see in the failure
of this attempt the natural and inevitable conse-
quence of causes so deeply rooted in the Grreek charac-

terand the course of Greek history, that not even the


most heroic exertions of individuals, nor the resist-
ance of the divided states, which came too late,
could for one moment render the final issue doubtful.
C. Greece By the battle of Charonea the doom of Greece
^^^ sealed. Never since then has Greece attained to
laUle^of
Glmronea. real political freedom. All attempts to shake off the
Macedonian supremacy ended in exhausting disasters.
In the subsequent struggles Hellas, and Athens in
DECLINE OF GREECE. 13

particular, was the play-ball of changing rulers, the Chap.


'

continual arena of their warfare. Not until the


second half of the third century was a purely Grecian
power formed the Achaean League round which
the hopes of the nation rallied. How inadequate,
however, was this attempt compared with what the
real wants of the country required! How soon it

became apparent that no remedies were here to be


found to heal the ills from which it was suffering I

That old hereditary failing of the Grreeks, internal


discord, still rendered it impossible for them to be
independent in foreign relations, and to be united
and settled at home. In perpetual struggles between
Achseans, -Sltolians, and Spartans, theii- best re-
sources were squandered. The very individual who
had led the Achseans against the Macedonians, in
the cause of independence, now summoned the
Macedonians back to the Peloponnesus, to gain their
support against Sparta. When the supremacy of
Macedonia was broken by the arms of Eome, a more
avowed dependence on Italian allies succeeded. And
"when, in the year 146 B.C., the province of Achaia
was incorporated in the Roman empire, even the
shadow of freedom which up to this time had been
assured, departed for ever.
Sad as the affairs of Grreece at this period became,
and marked as was the decline of its internal re-
sources, not less important was the extension of its

mental horizon, and the more general diffusion of its


culture. The Macedonian ascendancy, dealing as it
did a death-blow at the independence of Grreece, also
14 STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.
Chap, broke down the boundaries which had hitherto sepa-
-
'
rated Greeks from foreigners. A new worM was
opened out before the gaze of Greece, and a vast
territory offered for her energies to explore. She
was brought into manifold contact with the Eastern
nations belonging to the Macedonian monarchy,
securing for her culture the place of honour among
the nations of the East, but producing at the same
time a tardy, but, in the long run, important back-
current of Oriental thought, traces of which appeared
in the philosophy of Greece a few centuries later.
By the side of the old famed centres of learning in
the mother country of Hellas, new centres arose,
suited by position, inhabitants, and peculiar circum-
stances, to unite the culture of Eastand West, and
to fuse into one homogeneous mass the intellectual
forces of different races. Whilst Hellas, by the
number of emigrants who left her shores to settle in
Asia and Egypt, was losing her population ; whilst
the Greeks in their ancestral homes were succumbing
to foreigners; the most extensive intellectual con-
quests were being gained by her over nations by
whom and with whom she had been oppressed.
TOST-ABJSTOTELIAN PHILOSOPJIT. 16

CHAPTEE II.

CHAEACIEK AND CHIEF FEATURES OF THE POST-


AEISTOTELIAN PHILOSOPHY.

The circumstances which have been hastily sketched Chap.


in the preceding chapter, are of the greatest import-
ance as affecting the character of the post- Aristotelian ^- Ca^'Ses

philosophy. Greek philosophy, like Grreek art, is the tlmpost-


offspring of Greek political freedom. In the play of f^'^i'i^
political life, throwing every one on himself and his

own resources, in the rivalry of unlimited competition O-) Politi-

for all the good things of Ufe, the Greeks had learned
to make free use of all their mental powers. From
his consciousness of dignity connected by a Greek
far more closely than by us with the privilege of
citizenship from his superiority to the needs of daily
life, a freedom of thought had sprung up in his mind
which could boldly attack the problem of knowledge,
without any ulterior aim,' With the decline of poli-
tical independence, however, the mental powers of the
nation received a fatal blow. No longer borne up by
a powerful esprit de corps, weaned from the habit of
working for the common weal, the majority gave
' Conf. Arist. Metaph. I. 2, 282 b, 19.
16 STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.

Chap. themselves up to the petty interests of private life


^^-
and their personal affairs. Even the better disposed
-were too occupied in contending with the low
much
tone and corruption of the times, to be able to devote
themselves in their moments of relaxation to a free
and speculative consideration of things. What could

be expected in such an age as that which preceded


the rise of the Stoic and Epicurean systems, but that
philosophy would take a decidedly practical turn, if
indeed it were studied at all ?

An age like this did not require theoretical know-


ledge. It required to be morally braced and streng-
thened. If these desiderata were no longer to be
met with in the popular religion in its then state ; if

amongst all the cultivated circles philosophy had


taken the place of religion, it was only natural that
philosophy should meet the existing need. Is it

more particularly asked what course, under the cir-


cumstances, was it possible and more especially neces-
sary for moral energy to take ? the answer is not far
to seek. There was less scope for creative ingenuity
than for resolute self-devotion; less for outward
actions than for inward feeling ; less opportunity for
public achievements, more for private reforms. So
utterly hopeless had the public state of Greece be-
come, that even the few who made it their business
to provide a remedy could only gain for themselves
the honour of martyrdom. As matters then stood,
no other course seemed open for the best-intentioned,
save to withdraw entirely within themselves, to en-
trench themselves within the safe barriers of their
CAUSES OF POST-ARISTOTELIAN PHILOSOPHY. 17

own inner life against outward misfortunes, and to Chap.


^^'
make happiness dependent entirely on their own in-
ward state.

Stoic apathy, Epicurean self-contentment, and


Sceptic imperturbability, were the doctrines which
suited the political helplessness of the age. They
were therefore the doctrines which met with the most
"general acceptance. Suited, too, was that sinking of
national distinctions in the feeling of a common
humanity, that severance of morals from politics /
which characterise the philosophy of the Alexandrian
and Eoman period. Together with national indepen-
dence, the barriers between nations had been swept
away. East and West, Greeks and barbarians, were
united in large empires, placed in communication,
and compared in most important respects. In de-
men are of one blood and equally
claring that all
privileged citizens of one empire, that morality rests
on the relation of man to man independently of his
nationality and his position in the state, philosophy
was only explicitly stating a truth which had been
already partly realised in actual fact, and which was
certainly implied therein.
By the course, too, which it had taken during (2) .intcl-

the last century and a half, philosophy itself had pre- ^"^^'^'^^

pared the way for the turn which now set in. Socrates
and the Sophists, in different ways no doubt, had
each devoted themselves to the practical side of
philosophy and more definitely still the Cynic School
;

had paved the way for Stoicism, the Cyrenaic for


Epicureanism. These two Schools, it is true, play
c
;

18 STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.


Chap, a subordinate part in tlie general conditions of the
"

pMlosophy-of the fourth century, and sophistry by the


close of the same century was already a thing of the
past. Nor can Socrates, although turning his back
on physical enquiries, be at compared with the
all

post-Aristotelian philosophers, the desire for know-


ledge being still keen in him. He wished, however,
to busy himself only with subjects which were of
practical use in life ; and yet his theory of knowledge
involved a reform quite as much of speculative as of
practical philosophy, and that reform was accom-
plished on a grand scale by Plato and Aristotle. I

Little as the course of development taken by Greek


philosophy during the fourth century agrees with the
course of its subsequent development, still the specu-
lations of Plato and Aristotle helped to prepare the
way for the coming change. The chasm between the
ideal and phenomenal worlds which Plato set up, and
Aristotle vainly attempted to bridge over, leads ulti-
mately to a contrast between what is within and what
is without, between thought and the object of thought.
The generic conceptions or forms, which Plato and
Aristotle regard as most truly real, are, after all,
fabrications of the human mind. The conception of
reason, even in its expanded form as the divine Eea-
son, or reason of the world, is an idea formed by
abstraction from our inner life. And what is really
meant by identifying form in itself with what is, and
matter only with what is possible, or even (as Plato;
does) with what is not, or by placing G-od over against
and in contrast to the world, except that man finds in
POST-AJRISTOTELIAN PHILOSOPHY. 19

his own mind a higher and more real existence than Chap.
any which he and
finds outside of it in the world,
that what is truly divine and unlimited
must be in
the mind in its ideal nature, apart from and inde-
pendent of all impressions from without ? Plato and
Aristotle in fact declared that reason constitutes the
real essence of man reason coming from above and
iiniting itself with the body, but being in itself

superior to the world of sense and life in time and


that man's highest activity is thought, turned away
from all external things, and meditating only on the
inner world of ideas. It was only one step further
in the same direction for the post-Aristotelian philo-
sophy to refer man back to himself, in complete
severance from the outer world, that he may find that
peace within which he can find nowhere in the world
besides.
This step was taken by the Schools of the Stoics, B. Com-

Epicureans, and Sceptics. Appearing in the first


^l^f^ig'
half of the third century before Christ, superseding ties of the

the influence of the older Schools, and asserting this- totelia/a

supremacy without great variation in their teaching i'**-


until the beginning of the first century, these three
Schools, however else they may differ, at least agree
in
two fundamental points in subordinating theory
to practice, and in the peculiar character of their
practical philosophy.
The former point appears most clearly, as will be (i) Theory

seen, in the School of Epicurus. It is nearly as clear


^^^fll
in the case of the Sceptics, who, denying all possi- practice.
2
20 STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.
Chap, bility of knowledge, left as the only ground of action
"

conviction based on probabilities; and both these


Schools agree in considering philosophy as only a
means for securing happiness. By the Stoics, on the
other hand, the need of philosophic speculation was
felt more pressingly but even in their case
; it may be
readily seen that this need was not felt simply and
for its own sake, but was subordinated to practical
considerations and determined by these. For, first

of all, the Stoics, like the Epicureans, restricted them-


selves in the speculative part of their system to more
ancient views a fact of itself proving that speculation

was not the cause of their philosophical peculiarities,


but that other investigations were of greater value in
their eyes, in which, too, they considered themselves
more proficient. Moreover, they expressly stated that
the study of nature was only necessary as a help to the
study of virtue. It is also beyond question, that their
chief peculiarities, and those which give them an
importance in history, are ethical the other parts of
their system, and those in which their distinctive
tenets appear, being only regulated by practical con-
siderations. Hereafter, these statements will be sub-
stantiated in detail. It may therefore suffice to
observe here, that the most important question in
the logic of the Stoicsthe question of a standard of
truth was decided by a postulate that the
practical ;

fundamental principles of the Stoic metaphysics are


only intelligible from the ground of their ethics ; that
for natural science the Stoics did very -little ; that in
their theory of final causes on which they lay so much
;

FOST-ARISTOTELIAN PHILOSOPHY. 21

stress nature is explained by moral considerations ; Chap.


'

even their natural as well as their positive theology


bearing ample testimony to the practical tone of their
system. Standing in advance of the Epicureans by
their higher intellectual bearing and their learned
energy, and decidedly opposing the Sceptics by their
dogmatism, the Stoics nevertheless agree with both
these Schools in the essentially practical character of
their teaching. _
This relationship is more strikingly seen in the (2) Pem-
way in which they dealt with practical problems. / dealing
The Epicurean imperturbability is akin to that of the "^^^ **,
^ ^ practical
Sceptics ; both resemble the Stoic apathy. All three problem.
Schools are agreed that the only way to happiness
consists in peace of mind, and in avoiding all those^ , ,.;-|'. ii_i^

disturbances which sometimes arise from external j


' ' ,

influences, at other times from internal emotions ;

they are only divided as to the means by which peace i

ofmind may be secured. They are also agreed in


making moral activity independent of external cir-
cumstances, and in separating morals from politics,
although only the Stoics set up the doctrine of the
original unity of the whole human family, and in-
sisted on being citizens of the world. Through all

the Schools runs the common trait of referring every-


thing to the 'subject, of withdrawing everything
within the sphere of mind and of the inner life, one
consequence of which is to press into notice practice

rather than speculation, another being that the satis-


faction of this want can only be had in internal self-
conseiousness, and in a mental equilibrium attained
;

22 STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.


Chap, by the exercise of the will and the cultivation of the
"

intellect.

(3) Their The same character attaches to philosophy in the


centuries succeeding the rise of these three Schools
Ue^flZt
trated by nor were the circumstances out of which it grew
^^^myent
^^aterially altered. In addition to the followers of
iojphy- the old Schools, Eclectics were now to be met with,

gathering from every system what was true and


probable. In this process of selection, however, the
determining element was a regard for the practical
wants of man, and the ultimate standard of truth
was placed in our own immediate consciousness,
everything being referred to the subject as its centre.

In ethics, too, and natural theology the Eclectics


were also mainly indebted to the Stoics. A new
School of Sceptics also arose, not differing, however,
in its tendencies from the older one. Neopytha-
goreans and Platonists appeared, not satisfied with
human knowledge, but aspiring to higher revelations.
Professing to appeal to the metaphysics of Plato and
Aristotle, these philosophers nevertheless betray their
connection with the later post-Aristotelian Schools,
not only because they borrowed extensively from the
Stoics the material for their theology and ethics, but
far more by their general tone, knowledge being
for them even far less than for the Stoics an end in
itself, and they are further from natural science.

Their philosophy is subservient to the interests of


religion, its aim being to bring men into proper re-
lation with Grod and the religious needs of mankind
;

are the highest authority for science.


POST-ARISTOTELIAN PHILOSOPRT. 23

The same observations apply also to Plotinus and Chap.


his successors. These philosophers are not lacking '_

in a developed' science of metaphysics. The care,


too, with which they elaborated this science leaves no
doubt as to their lively interest in scientific com-
pleteness and systematic correctness. Still these
scientific efforts bear with them the same relation to
the practical aim of philosophy as with the Stoics,
who in point of learning and logical elaboration of
a system are quite their match. Undoubtedly a
real interest in knowledge was one of the elements-
which brought Neoplatonism into being ; but it was
not strong enough to counterbalanee another ele-
ment, th& practical and religious one. The mind
was not suflBciently independent to be able to get on
without appealing to intellectual and theological-
authorities ; the scientific procedure was too complex
to lead to a simple study of things as they are. As-
in the case of the Neopythagoreans, the ultimate
ground of the system is a religious want. The divine
world is only a portion of human thought projected
out of the mind, and incapable of being fully grasped
by the understanding. The highest business of phi-
losophy is to reunite man with the divine world
external to himself. To attain this end, all the
means which science supplies are employed. Phi-
losophy endeavours to explain the steps by which the
finite gradually came to be separated from the origi-
nal infinite being ; it seeks to bring about a return
by a regular and systematic course; and in this

attempt the philosophic spirit of Greece, by no


;

24 STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.


Chap, means extinct, proved its capabilities by a result of

_ J^l itskind unrivalled. If, in the first instance, the

problem was so raised as to impress philosophy into


the service of religion ; still, in the long run, it
could not fail to be seen that, with the premises

assumed, a scientific solution of the religious ques-


tion was impossible. "With its idea of an original
being, the system had started from a conception
which in this form was a reflex of the religious sen-
timent, and not the result of scientific research. In
its doctrine of a mystical union with a transcendental
being, it had concluded with a religious postulate,
the gratuitous assumption of which betrays an origin
in the mind of the thinker. Neoplatonism, there-
fore, in its whole bearing, stands on the sam ground
as the other post- Aristotelian systems ; and it is

hardly necessary in further proof of this relationship


to point to its agreement in other respects with
Stoicism, and especially in ethics. Far as these two
systems lie asunder, the one standing at the begin-
ning the other at the end of the post-Aristotelian
philosophy, nevertheless both display one and the
same attitude of thought ; and we pass from one to
the other by a continuous series of intermediate
links.
The character of the post- Aristotelian philosophy
assumed, as might be expected, various modifications
in course of time in passing from School to School
nevertheless, it reproduced certain common ele-
ments. Such was the neglect of intellectual origi-
nality, which drove some thinkers to a sceptical
.
;

POST-ARISTOTELIAN PHILOSOPHY: 25

denial of all knowledge, and induced others to take Chap.


"

their knowledge at second hand from older authori-


ties. Such was the prominence given to practical
over speculative questions. Such was the disregard
for natural science, and, in comparison with former
times, the greater importance attached to theology,
appearing not only in the controversy between the
Epicureans and Stoics, but also in the apologetical
writings of the Stoics and Platonists. Such, too,
was the negative morality which aimed at indepen-
dence of the outer world, at mental composure, and
philosophic contentment; the separating of morals
from politics ; the moral universalism and citizenship
of the world ; the going within self into the depths
of the soul, the will, and the thinking powers
the deepening of the consciousness accompanied at
the same time by a narrowing and isolation of it,
and the loss of a lively interest in the world without,
and in the simple scientific study thereof.
This mental habit, first of all, found a dogmatic C. Dcve-

expression in philosophy. Not only moral science,


^^2.ria-
but logic and natural science were treated in a way totelian

corresponding therewith, though partially built on to sophy.


the older teaching. In the treatment of moral (i) Sog-
science in particular, two Schools come to view, ^j*^j,
.

markedly different and decided in their peculiarities, (-^j) s'^aics

The Stoics regard


almost exclusively the universal "-'^^ ^^
cureans.
element in the mah who seeks contentment withm,

the Epicureans catch at the individual side of his


being. The Stoics regarded. man exclusively as a
thinking being, the Epicureans as a creature of feel-
; ~

26 STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.


Chap. ing. The-Stoics made happiness consist_inhis subor-
II.
dination tailifi-iaiW_of the whole, in the ju^ression
of all personal feelings and inclinations, in virtue

the Epicureans in the independence of the indi^ddjial


I from eve7rytMng external, in the unrufl0[ed_serenity
'of the inner_life, in painlessness. The theoretical
assumptions on which their teaching was based cor--

responded with these fundamental ethical positions.


(J) Boff- Violent as was the rivalry between these .two

7c'epticism. Schools, both, nevertheless, stand on the same plat-

form. Absolu te composu re ^f min^jjrefidomjaf Jhe


inner life from every external disturbance, is the
"goal at which both Schools aim,^althongh following
different courses. Therewith arises the demand to
'
elevate this common element, making it the essential
aim and subject matter of philosophy. If the philo-
sophic axioms of these systems contradict one another,
what may be thence concluded save that the aim
may be attained independently of any definite dog-
matic view in short, that we may despair of
;

knowledge in order to pass from the knowledge of


our ignorance to a general indifference to every-
thing and to an unconditional repose of mind. Thus
Scepticism joins on to Stoicism and Epicureanism,
as the third chief form of the philosophy of that age,
finding detached representatives in Pyrrho's School,
and most influentially represented in the New
Academy.
(2) Seep- The rise, the growth, and the conflict of these

*Soh0als.
three Schools, by the side of which the older Schools
have only a subordinate value, occupies the first por-
POST-AJtISTOTELIAN PHILOSOPHY. 27

tion of the period of post-Aristotelian philosophy, Chap.


extending from the end of the fourth to the begin- 1 _

ning
" of the first century before Christ. The ('*) ^"''
fluenoes
distinctive features of this epoch consist partly in produdni/
the predominance of the above tendencies, and "fi'**'

partly in their separate existence, without being (-) Pouti.


modified by intermixture. After the middle of the *""
"f^ ,
fluenec oj
second century a gradual change may be observed. Rome.
Greece was now a Eoman province, and the intellec-
tual intercourse between Greece and Eome was con-
tinually on the increase. Many learned Greeks
resided at Eome, frequently as the companions of
families of high birth ; others living in their own
country, were visited by Eoman pupils. How, ia
the face of the clearly defined and sharply expressed
Eoman character, could the power and independence
of the Greek intellect, already unquestionably on the
decline, assert its ancient superiority ? How could
Greeks become the teachers of Eomans without ac-
commodating themselves to their requirements, and
experiencing in turn a reflex influence ? Nor could
the philosophy of Greece be exempt from such an
influence, its originality long since in abeyance, its
Scepticism now openly avowing that it could place
no trust in itself. To the practical sense of a Eoman ,

no philosophical system could commend itself which


'

did not make for practical results by the shortest


possible route. To him practical needs were the
ultimate standard of truth. Little did he care for

rigid logic and conclusive accuracy in the scientific


procedure. Differences of schools, so long as they
;

2S STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.


Chap. had no practical bearing, were for him of no im-
II.
portance. No wonder that Greek philosophy, touched
by the breath of Eome, lent herself to Eclecticism !

(0) JCrdcl- Whilst on the one side of the world the Greeks
lectual in-
Jluence of were experiencing the influence of the nation that
Aliixmi-
had subdued them, on the other they were assimila-
ting the views of the Oriental nations whom they had
subdued alike by martial as by mental superiority.
For two centuries, in philosophy at least, Greece had
held her own against Oriental modes of thought.
Now, as her internal incapacity continually increased,
those modes of thought gained for themselves a
foothold in her philosophy. Alexandria was the
place where first and most completely the connection
of Greece with the East was brought about. In that
centre of commerce for all parts of the globe, East
and West entered into a connection more intimate
and more lasting than in any other centre nor was ;

this connection a mere accident of circumstances


it was also a work of political forecast. From its
founder, Ptolemy Soter, the Ptolemsean dynasty in-
herited as its principle of government the maxim of
always combining what is native with what is foreign,
and of clothing things new in the old and venerable
forms of Egyptian custom and religious ceremony.
At Alexandria, accordingly, there arose, towards the
beginning of the first century before Christ, a School
calling itself at first Platonic, afterwards Pythagorean,
which later still, in the shape of Neoplatonism,
gained the ascendency over the whole domain of
philosophy. The very fact, however, that such a
POST-ARISTOTELIAN PHILOSOPHY. i'i)

change in philosophic views did not appear before, Chap.


may suffice to show that it was called for and produced ;

by external circumstances, but that notwithstanding


these circumstances it would never have come into
being had not the intellect of Greece in the course
of its own development been ripe for the change.
The same remark holds good of the rise of that (j) Scep-
"'"^
practical Eclecticism which we have before traced *^*s"'.

to the influence of Kome. Even in the period of dsm.


its intellectual exhaustion, G-reek philosophy became
what it did not simply from the force of circumstances,
but, under the influence of those very surroundings,
it developed in a direction to which its previous
course already pointed. If we except the lingering
remains of a few small Schools, which soon expired,
there existed, after the beginning of the third cen-
tury before Christ, only four great philosophic
Schools the Peripatetic, the Stoic, the Epicurean,
and the School of Platonists, converted to Scepticism
by Arcesilaus. These four Schools were all perma-
nently established at Athens, and thus a lively
interchange of thought, and a thorough comparison
of their several teachings were rendered compara-
tively easy. That they would not long exist side by
side without making some overtures towards union
and agreement was a perfectly natural prospect, one,
too, hastened on by Scepticism, which, after denying
the possibility of knowledge, only allowed a choice
between probabilities, that choice being decided by
the standard of practical needs. Hence, towards
the close of the second century before Christ, these
30 STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.
Chap, philosophic Schools may be observed to emerge more
'

or less from their exclusiveness. An eclectic ten-


dency steals over philosophy, aiming not so much at
scientific knowledge as at attaining certain results
of a practical kind. The distinctive doctrines of
each School drop into the background ; and in the
belief that infallibility resides solely in the mind
itself, such portions were selected from each system
asseemed most in harmony with the selecting mind.
Yet just as this eclectic mode of thought lay in
germ in Scepticism, so, on the other hand. Eclecti-
cism involves doubt, which appears again, soon after
the Christian era, in a new school of doubt, continuing
until the third century. There is thus, on the one
hand, an urgent demand for knowledge, which is

first sought for in the practical interest of religion


and m'orals ; and, on the other hand, a disbelief in
the truths of existing knowledge, and, indeed, of
knowledge generally, which some openly avow as
Sceptics, others clearly enough betray in the unset-
tledness of their Eclecticism. These two currents
coalescing, we arrive at the thought that truth,
which could not be attained in the form of intellec-
tual knowledge, exists outside of it, and is partly to
be sought in the religious traditions of the early
days of Greece and the East, partly by immediate
divine revelation. This effort gives rise to such a
notion of God, and of His relations to the world, as
is suited to this belief in revelation. Man knowing
that truth lies outside himself, and doubting his own
capacities to attain thereto, has removed deity, as
POST-AHISTOTELIAN PHILOSOPHY. 31

the atsolute source of truth, into another world. Chap.


The need of a revelation of truth still existing, the
interval between God and the world is peopled with
intermediate beings, who were sometimes conceived
of as purely metaphysical entities, and at others
appeared, according to the popular belief, as demons.
This mental habit, which, among the older systems,
belongs particularly to the Platonic and Pythagorean,
forms the transition to Neoplatonism, the appear-
ance of which introduces the last stage in the
development of Greek philosophy.
Yet even this last phase of Greek philosophy was (3) JRaU-

not uninfluenced by the circumstances of history. School of


Since the end of the second century after Christ, the Neopla-
tomsts.
decline of the Eoman Empire, the terrible dangers
which threatened it on all sides, the pressure and
the necessity of the time, had made startling progress.
All means of defence hitherto employed proved una-
vailing to stem destruction. With ruin everywhere
staring in the face, the desire and longing for some
higher assistance increased. Such assistance could
no longer be obtained from the old Gods of Eome or
the religious faith of the day. Despite these circum-
stances were daily becoming more hopeless. Stronger
and stronger became the inclination which had been
gradually spreading over the Eoman world since the
last days of the EepubHc, and which the circum-

stances of the empire had greatly favoured, to have


recourse to foreign forms of worship. The highest
power in the state had, moreover, favoured this incli-
nation under the Oriental and half Oriental emperors
32 STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.
Chap, who for nearly half a century a;fter Septimius Severus
__^^'_ occupied the imperial throne. The state and the
Gods of the were continually losing their hold
state
on the respect of men. Meanwhile, on the one hand,
Oriental worships, mysteries new and old, and foreign
heathen religions of the most varying kinds, were
ever gaining fresh adherents. On the other, Chris-
tianity was rapidly gaining a power which enabled
it openly to enter the lists for supremacy among the
recognised religions of the state. The attempts of
a series of powerful monarchs about the middle of
the third century to build up the Empire afresh,
could not have for their object a restoration of a
specifically Eoman form of government. Their only
aim was to bring the various elements which com-
posed the Empire under one sovereign will by fixed
forms of administration ; a result which was actually
reached under Diocletian and Constantine. The
Eoman character asserted itself, indeed, as a ruling
and regulating power, but it was at the same time
subordinate to another of an originally foreign
character. The Empire was a congeries of nations
artificially held together, and arranged on a carefully
designed plan ; their centre of gravity lay not
within the nation, but in the simple will of a prince,
standing above all rules and laws of state, and
deciding everything without appeal and without
responsibility.
In a similar manner Neoplatonism united all the
elements of previous philosophical Schools into one
comprehensive and well-arranged system, in which
POST-ARISTOTELIAN PHILOSOPHY. 33

each class of existences had its definite place as- Chap.


II
signed to it. The initial point in this system, '___

however, the all-embracing unity, was a being lying


beyond it, soaring above every notion that experience
and conception can supply, unmixed with the pro
cess of life going on in the world, and from his un-
attainable height causing all things, but himself
subject to no conditions of causality. Neoplatonism
is the intellectual reproduction of Byzantine Im-
perialism. As Byzantine Imperialism combines Ori-
ental despotism with the Eoman idea of the state,
so Neoplatonism fills out with Oriental mysticism
the scientific forms of Greek philosophy.
In Neoplatonism the post- Aristotelian philosophy
had manifestly veered round into its opposite. Self-
dependence, and the self-suflScingness of thought,
have made way for a resignation to higher powers,
for a longing for some revelation, for an ecstatic
departure from the domain of conscious mental ac-
tivity. Man has resigned the idea of truth within
for truth to be found only in God. Eemoved into
another world, God stands over against man and the
world of appearances, in abstract spirituality. All
the attempts of thought have but one aim to ex-
plain the procession of the finite from the infinite,
and the conditions of its return into the absolute.
But neither the one nor the other of these problems
could meet with a satisfactory intellectual solution.
That even this form of thought betrays imdeniably the
personal character of the post-Aristotelian philosophy
has been already seen, and will be seen still more in
D
34 STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.
Chap, the sequel. Therewith undoubtedly the creative
_ powers of the Greek mind were exhausted. Losing
the platform of her national existence for centuries
step by step, Greece saw the last remaining fragments
torn from her gi'asp by the victory of Christianity.
iBefore surrendering them, Neoplatonism made one
more futile attempt to rescue the forms of Greek
culture from her mighty rival. With the failure of
that attempt Greek religion and Greek philosophy
set together.
;

HISTORY OF THE STOICS, 36

PART II.

THU STOICS.

CHAPTEE III.

HISTORY OF THE STOICS UNTIL THE END OF THE


SECOND CENTDKT B.C.

A STRIKING feature in the history of the post-Aristo- Chap.


telian philosophy, and one which at the same time ;_
brings forcibly home to us the thorough change
of all circumstances, is the fact that so many of its

representatives come from eastern countries in which


Grreek and Oriental modes of thought met and mingled.
For centuries still Athens continued to have the re-
putation of being the chief seat of Grreek philosophy
nor did she cease to be one of the most important
seminaries of philosophy, even when she had to share
that reputation with other cities, such 'as Alexandria,
Eome, Ehodes, and Tarsus. Yet even at Athens there

were teachers not a few whose foreign extraction indi-


cates the age of Hellenism. Next to the later Neo-
platonic School, this remark is of none more true
than the Stoic. With this fact we may always con-
nect the world-citizenship of this School, whilst we
D 2
;'

36 THE STOICS.

Chap. are careful not to attribute a general characteristic of


Ill,
the then state of the world to purely external circum^
stances. Nearly all the most important Stoics before
the Christian era belong by birth to Asia Minor, to
Syria, and to the islands of the Eastern Archipelago.
Then follow a series of Eoman Stoics, by the side of

whom the Phrygian Epictetus occupies a prominent


place ; but Greece proper is exclusively represented
by men of third or fourth rate capacity.

A. Zeno. The founder of the Stoic School, Zeno ' by name,


was the son of Mnaseas,^ and a native of Citium' ia
Cyprus. Leaving his home, he repaired to Athens,*
'
For the life of Zeno, Dio- is himself called a Phoenician
genes is the chief authority, CSiog. vii. 3 15 ; 25 30 ; ii.
; ;

who appears to be chiefly in- 114. Suid. Z-fiv. Athen. xiii.


debted for Ms information to 563, e. Cic. 1. c). A continu-
Antigonns of Carystus, who ous connection between Citium
lived about 250 B.C. In proof and Phcenicia is implied in
of this, compare the account of Diog. vii. 6 oi ^v ^iSwvt Kirtets.
;

The details are differently


Diogenes with the extracts
given by Athenseus (viii. 345, given by Diog. 2-5 31 Plwt.
; ;

d ; xiil. 565, d ; 603, e


563, e ; Inimic. Util. 2, p. 87 and Seii.
;

607, e ; and, in particular, ii. Tranq. An. 14, 3. Most accounts


65, f) from Antigonus' life of relate that he came to Athens
Zeno. Of modern authorities, for trading purposes, and ac-
consult WMjennumn, in Fa/aly's cidentally became acquainted
Eealencyclop. with Crates and philosophy
* Biog. vii. 1. SiuAd. TA\vav. after being shipwrecked. Ac-
PVut, Plac. i. 3, 29. Pamsan. ii. cording to other accounts, he
8, 4. He is called by others remained at Athens, after dis-
Demeas. posing of his merchandise, and
' Citium, which the ancients devoted himself to philosophy.
unanimously call the native Demetrius of Magnesia {The-
city of Zeno, was, according to mist. Or. xxiii. 295, D) further
Diog. vii. 1, a iriKiffiia ^'LWrtvtKbv relates that he had already
^oiviKas iTTOiKovs iiTxvi^^s, i.e. occupied himself with philo-
Phoenician immigrants had sophy at home, and repaired to
settled there by the side of the Athens to study it more fuUy
old Greek population, whence a view which seems most
its inhabitants are sometimes likely, because the least sensa-
called e Phoenicia prof ecti
' tional.
(Oic. Pin. iv. 20, 56), and Zeno
ZENO THE STOIC. 37

about the year 320 b.c.,^ wh,ere he at first joined the Chap.
Cynic Crates.^ He appears, however, to have been
m.
previously disgusted with the extravagances of the
Cynic mode of life.' Besides, his keen desire for
knowledge could no satisfaction in a teaching so
find
meagre as that of the Cynics/ To supply its defects
he had recourse to Stilpo, who united to the moral
teaching of the Cynics the logical accuracy of the

' The dates in Zeno's life are he only attained the age of
very uncertain. He is said to seventy- two {CUnton Fast.
have been thirty when he first Hell. n. 368 capriciously sug-
came to Athens (Siog. 2). Per- gests 92), and was altogether
sseus, however {Ibid. 28), his only fifty years in Athens. On
pupil and countryman, says the other hand, in his own
twenty- two. These statements letter to Antigonus (Diog. 9),
are of little use, since the date he distinctly calls himself an
of his coming to Athens is un- octogenarian, but the genuine-
known. If it is true that after ness of this letter, borrowed by
reading with Crates he was for Diogenes from ApoUonius, the
ten years a pupil of Xenocrates, Tyriau about 50 B.C., may per-
Who died 314 B.C. (Timoerates haps be doubted. The year of
in Diog. 2), he must have come Zeno's death is likewise un-
to Athens not later than 328 known. His relations to Anti-
B.C. But this fact may be gonus Gronatas prove at least
doubted. For his whole line of that he was not dead before the
thought resembles that of Crates beginning of his reign in 278
and Stilpo. How then can he B.C., and probably not till long
have been for ten years a pupil afterwards. It would appear
in the Academy, and in addi- from the calculation of his age,
tion have enjoyed Polemo's that his death did not take
teaching? Altogether he is place till 260 B.C. He may,
said to have frequented the then, have lived circa 350 to
S'chools ef different philosophers 260 B.C.; but these dates are
for twenty years before opening quite uncertain.
his own (Bioff. i). According ' Diog. vii. 2
; vi. 105.
to ApoUon. in Siog. 28, he pre- ' Diog. 3 ivrevSey fixovir eroS
:

sided over his own school for KpdTTjTOS, \Aws fieu eiirovos nphs
fifty-eight years, which is tpihoffofplav, alB^fioav 5k us nrphs
hardly reconcileable with the T7IV KvifiKriv a.vai<Txvvrlai>.
' Conf
above data, even if he attained ., besides what imme-

the age of ninety-eight [Diog. diately follows, Diog. 25 and


28 ; Zmeian. Macrob. 19). Ac- 15 : ^v Sk (riTTiTtKhs kbL irepl
cording to Perssus {Diog. 28), jrAvTuv aKpiPoAoyoifjtevos,
38 THE STOICS.

Chap. Megarians. He also studied under Polemo; it is


III.
said likewise under Xenocrates and Diodorus the
logician, with whose pupil Philo' he was on terms of
intimacy. After a long course of intellectual prepa-
ration, he at last appeared as a teacher, soon after
the beginning of the third, or perhaps during the last
years of the fourth century B.C. From the Stoa
TToiKikf),the place which he selected for delivering
his lectures, his followers derived their name of Stoics,
having first been called after their master Zenonians.^
Such was the universal respect inspired by his ear-
nestness, moral strictness,' and simplicity of life,* and
the dignity, modesty, and affability of his conduct,*

IHog.vu.2;i;-ie;20;2i; very simple. According to one


ii.114; 120. Numen. in JSJus. acooimt CDiog. 13), he brought
Pr. Bv. xiv. 5, 9 6, 6. Polemo ; to Athens the fabulous sum of
is called his teacher by Oie. 1000 talents, and put it out to in-
Fin. iv. 16, 45 Acad. i. 9, 35.; terest. Theinist. Or. xxi., p. 252,
Straio, 67, p. 614.
xiii. 1, On says that he forgave a debtor his
Xenocrates compare p. 37, 1. debt. He is said to have paid
How ready he was to learn from a logician 200 drachmas, in-
others is proved by the saying stead of the 100 which he asked
in Diog. 25; Phd. Fragm. in for (Diog. 25). Nor is there
Hesiod. ix. T. T. 511. W. any mention of a Cynical hfe
' Diog. 5, according to whom, or of poverty. But, according
he gave instruction walking to to Divg. 5, Plut. and Sen., how-
and fro, like Aristotle, but ever, he had lost his property
never to more than two or three almost entirely. According to
at a time (^Dig. 14). It is not Sen. Consol. ad Helv. 12, 5 (con-
probable that he gave any for- tradicted by Diog. 23), he owned
mal lectures. no slave. Had he been well to
Which, however, must be
' do, he would hardly have ac-
judged by the standard of that cepted the presents of Anti-
time and of Greek customs. gonus. That Zeno was un-
Gonf. Diog. 13 and the quota-
; married appears from Diog. 13.
tions in Athen. xiii. 607, e ; 563, ' GoM. Diog. 13 16; 24; 26;
;

e, from Antigonus of Carystua. Athen. in the passage quoted p.


* SeeMusonius inStob. Serm. 36, 1 Suid.
; Clem.. Stiom. 413,
;

17, 43. His outward circum- A. It is mentioned as a pecu-


stances also appear to have been liarity of Zeno, that he avoided
ZENO THE STOIC. 89

that Antigonus Gonatas vied with the city of Athens Chap.


III.
in showing his appreciation of so estimable a philo-
sopher.' Although lacking smoothness of style and
using a language far from pure,' Zeno had neverthe-

all noise and popular display his countrymen in Citium fail


{Biog. 14); that, though gen- to show
their appreciation
erally grave, he relaxed over (,IHog. 6; Plin. H.N. xxxiv. 19,
his wine, and that too much ; 32) of him, and Zeno always
that he could not tolerate many insisted on being a Citian
words, and was very fond of {Mog. 12 ; Pint. I.e.).
epigrams. See Dwg. 16 ; 20 ;
2 He himself {jDiog. vii. 18)
24 ; Athen. I.e. Stol. Serm. 34 ;
compares the \iyoi iTnjpTio-jiieVoi
10 ; 36 19
; ; 23. He is said to of the dffrfAoiKoi to the elegant
have carried his parsimonious- Alexandrian coins, which, in-

ness too far in this respect a stead of being better, were often
thorough Fhcenician (^Diog. 16). lighter than those of Athens,
The presents of Antigonus he He is charged in particular
never sought, and broke with with using words in a wrong
an acquaintance who asked for sense, and with inventing new
his interest with the King. ones, whence do. Tuso. v. 11,
Still he did not despise them, 34,oalls him ' ignobilis verborum
without abating from his dig- opifex,' and Chrysippus, in a
nity. The loss of his property treatise tr^pi rod Kvplas Kexp^ff^cw
he bore with the greatest com- Z-fivuva Tois ov6fia(riif, dispar-
posure {IHog. 3 Pkit. and Sen.).
; ages this KaiviiTO/ieip 4y ro7s
Antigonus (conf. Athen. ovdijiaai (_GaUn. DifC. Puis. Ill,
xiii. 603, e Arrian, Diss. Epict.
; 1., vol. viii. 642, K.). He is also
ii. 13, 14; Simpl. in Epict. Bn- charged with maintaining that
chir. 283, c ^l. V. H. ix. 26)
; nothing should be concealed,
was fond of his society, attended but that even the most indeli-
his lectures, and wished to have cate things should be called by

him at court an ofEer which their proper names. He is fur-
Zeno declined, sending two of ther charged with having pro-
his pupils instead. The Athen- pounded no new system, but
ians, to whom, according to with having appropriated the
Elian's untrustworthy account thoughts of his predecessors,
V. H. vii. 14 he had rendered concealing his plagiarism by
political services, honoured hira the use of new terms. In Diog.
with a public panegyric, a gol- vii. 25, Polemo says KKfTirav ri
:

den crown, a statue, and burial


in the Ceramicus. That the and Cicero frequently repeats
keys of the city were left in the charge (Fin. v. 25, 74 ; iii,.
his keeping is not probable. 2, 5; iv. 2, 3; 3, 7; 26; 72; v.
The ofEer of Athenian citizen- 8,22; 29, 88. Acad. ii. 5, 15.
ship he declined {Phit. Sto. Legg. i. 13, 38; 20; 53. Tusc.
Sep. 4, 1, p. 1034). Nor did ii. 12, 29).
40 THE STOICS.

Chap. less an extensive following. Leading a life of singu'^


III.
lar moderation, he reached an advanced age untouched
by disease, although he naturally enjoyed neither
robust health nor an attractive person.' A slight

injury having at length befallen him, which he re-


garded as a hint of destiny, he put an end to his own
life.'^His not very numerous writings* have been
with the exception of a few fragments, some no
lost,

doubt dating from the time when, as a pupil of Crates,


he adhered more strictly to Cynic ideas than was
afterwards the case ; * nor ought this point to be for-

gotten in sketching his teaching.


B. Pupils The successor to the chair of Zeno was Cleanthes,'
of Zeno.
(1) CU-
a native of Assos in the Troad,^ a man of a strong and
anthes. firm character, of unusual endurance, energy, and con-
' Biog.
28, 1. The statement thorities are given by Fah-io.
that he was &voiros must be Bibl. Gr. iii. 580.
taken with some limitation, ac- ' This appears at least prob-

cording to Diog. vii. 162; Stoi. able from Diog. 4 cms fikv oZv
:

Floril. 17, 43. rivbs iJKOVffe TOV KpoLTIJTOS ' 5t


^ Diog. 28 ; 31. Lucian, KOI T V T^oKireiav avTOv yptiypavros^
Macrob. 19. Lacta/nt. Inst. Tiyes eXeyov vai^ovres itrl rrjSTOV
iii. 18. Stdb. Floril. 7, 45. Kuvhs oitpas aur^v yeypatftevai.
* Mohnilie, Cleanthes d. Sto. :

' The list of them in Diog. Greifsw.1814. CleanthisHymn.


i, to which additions are made in Jovem, ed Sturz, ed. nov.
Diog. 34; 39; 134. The cur. Merzdorf. Lips. 1835.
:

AtarpiPal QDiog. 34 ; Sext. Pyrrh. ' Straio, xiii. 1, 57, p- 610.

iii. 205.; 346; Math. xi. 90; may Diog. vii. 168. ^/wm, Hist.
perhaps be identical with the Anim. vi. 50. How Clemens,
'ATTo/uirnKwsifi.aTa 'KpdriiTOS {Diog. Protrept. 47, A, comes to call
4), the Tex>"l ^piTiKri {Diog. 34), him niiraSeus, it is hard to say,
with Tex"^ (Diog. 4). An ex- nor is it of any moment. Mohi
position of Hesiod, which had nike, p. 67, offers conjeoturesw
been inferred to exist, from (M.o. Mohnikealso rightly maintains;
N. D. 14, 86, Ki-ische, Forsch.
i. p. 77, that Cleanthes i novnKhs
367, rightly identifies with the in Diog. ix. 15 must be the same
treatise toG Sa.ou, and this
Trepl as this Cleanthes, and Cohet
with the treatise irtpl lijs <f>i!ircws strikes out the words 6 liavTi,Kh^
{Stoh. Bel. i. 178). Other au- after KK^ivBiis,
;

ARISTO AND HERILLUS. 41

tentment, but also slow of apprehension, and some- Chap.


what heavy in intellect. Eesembling Xenocrates in
mind, Cleanthes was in every way adapted to uphold
his master's teaching, and to recommend it by the
moral weight of his own character, but he was inca-
pable of expanding it more completely, or of establish-
ing it on a wider basis.'

Besides Cleanthes, the best known among the (2) Arixto

pupils of Zeno are Aristo of Chios,^ and Herillus of ^g,.,7^,

' According to Antisthenes Sto. Eep. 4, p. 1034). He died


(the Ehodian), in Diog. 1. c, of self-imposed starvation ( Biog.
Cleanthes was a pugilist, who 176; Lucicm, Macrob. 19; Stob.
came to Athens with four djaoh- Floril.7, 54). His age is stated by
mae, and entered the school of Diog. 176,at eighty; hj Zucian
Zeno (according to Hesyoli. v. and Valer. Max. viii. 7, ext. 11,
Suid., that of Crates, which is at ninety-nine. Diog. 174, gives
impossible for chronological a list of his somewhat numerous
reasons. Conversely, Valer. writings, mostly on moral siib-
Max. viii. 7, ext. 1 1, makes him which is supplemented by
jects,
a pupil of Chrysippus, con- Fah'ic. Bibl. iii. 551, Harl. and

founding the relations of pupil Moknike, p. 90. Cleanthes was


and teacher, as we have met held in great esteem in the
with elsewhere), in which he Stoic School, even in the time
Studied for nineteen years of Chrysippus (^Diog. vii. 179 ;
(^Diog. 176), gaining a mainten- 182; ao. Acad. ii. 41, 126).
ance by working as a labourer At a, later time, the Boman
imog. 168; 174 Plwt. Vit. ^r.
; Senate erected a statue to him
Al. 7, 5, p. 830 Sen. Ep. 44, 3
; at Assos {Simpl. in Ej>ict. En-
Kj'isohe Forsch.). A public chir. c. 53, 329, b).
maintenance, which was ofEered ^ Aristo, son of Miltiades, a

him, Zeno induced him to re- Chian, discussed most fully by


fuse, who, in other ways, tried Krisclie, Forsch. 405, known as
his power of will by the severest the Siren, because of his per-
tests. It is, therefore, all the suasive powers, and also as the
more improbable that Antigonus Baldhead, was a pupil of Zeno
gave him 3000 minje (JDiog. iDiog. 37; 160; Cic. N. D. i.
169). On the simplicity of his 14, 37 ; Acad. ii. 42, 130 ; Sen.
life, his constant application, Bp. 94, 2), but is said, during
his adherence to Zeno, &c., see Zeno's illness, to have joined
moff. 168 170; 37 PVwt. De
; ;
Polemo (Diool. in Diog. 162).
Audi. 18, p. 47 Cie. Tusc. ii.
; Although it may be objected
25, 60. He also refused to be- that his teaching does not di-
come an Athenian citizen {Plut. verge in the direction of Pla?.
;

43 THE STOICS.

Chap. Carthage,' who diverged from his teaching in the


III.
most opposite directions, Aristo confining himself

tonism, but rather in the op- with his being called a cotem-
posite direction, still Polemo's porary and opponent of Arcesi-
contempt {Biog. iv, 18) for laus {Straho, 1. c. ; Diog. vii.
dialectic may at one time have 162 ; iv. 40, and According
33).
had its attractions for him. It to Dlog. vii. 164, he died of
is a better established fact that sunstroke. Not only had his
his attitude towards pleasure School disappeared in the time
was less indifferent than it of Strabo and Cicero ( Cie. Legg.
ought to have been, according i. 13, 38 Fin. ii. 11, 35 ; v. 8,
;

to his principles (Bratos and 23 Tusc. v. 80, 85 Off. i. 2, 6


; ;

Apollophanes in Atlien. vii. Strabo, 1. c), but no traces of


281, c) but the charge of flat-
; it are found beyond the first
tery towards his fellow-pupil generation. The writings enu-
Persseus appears not to be sub- merated by Diog. vii. 163, with
stantiated(jiiAera.vi.351,c). His the single exceptiou of the
letters show that he was on in- letter to Cleanthes, are said tp
timate terms with Cleanthes have been attributed by Panse-
{T/icviift. Or. xxi. p. 255, b). tius and Sosicrates to the Peri-
His loquacity is said to have patetic but Krische's remarks,
;

been displeasing to Zeno {Diog. p. 408, particularly after


vii. 18). He appeared as a Sauppe's demurrer (Philodemi
teacher in the Cynosarges, An- de Vit. Lib. X. Weimar, 1853,
tisthenes' old locality (JOiog. p. 7), raise a partial doubt as
161), thus claiming descent to the accuracy of this state-
from Cynicism. Of his numer- ment. The fragments, at least,
ous pupils {Diog. 182 Plut. C. ; of 'O/ion^/iaro preserved by Sto-
Princ. Philos. i. 4, p. 776), two bseus seem to belong to a Stoic.
are mentioned by Diogenes, 161; Perhaps from the"0;uoio come
Miltiades and Diphilus. Athen- the statements in Sen. Ep. 36,
Eeus names two more Apollo- : 3 ; 115, 8 Pint. De Aud. 8, p.
;

phanes, and the celebrated 42 De Sanit. 20, p. 183


; De ;

Alexandrian sage, Eratosthenes, Exil. 5, p. 600 Prsc. Ger. Reip. ;

both of whom wrote an 'Aristo.' 9, 4, p. 804 Aqua an Ign. Util.;

The latter is also named by 12, 2, p. 958.


Strabo, 1. 2, 2, p. 15, Smd. ' Herillus's native place was
'EparoirB. Apollophanes, whilst Carthage (Diog. 37; 165). vii.
adopting Aristo's -views of If XoXxiSiicios is read by Cobetia
virtue in JDiog. vii. 92, did not the last passage, we have again
otherwise adopt his ethics. His the same confusion between
natural science is mentioned by Ka\xiScl)i' and KapmjSSi', which
Diog. vii. 140, his psychology made Xenocrates a Kapxt^irios.
by Tertul. De An. 14. Since He came as a boy under Zeno
Erastosthenes was born 276 (_Dwg. 166; Cic. Acad. ii. 42,
B.C., Aristo must have been 129). Diog. 1. c. enumerates the
alive in 250 B.C., which agrees writings of Herillus, calling
; ;

PUPILS OF ZENO. 4.3

rigidly to Cynicism, Herillus approximating to the Chap.


III.
leading positions held by the Peripatetic School.
Other pupils of Zeno were Persssus, a countryman (3) Other

and companion of Zeno Aratus, the well-known ^ ' ;


'
'

poet of Soli ;
^ Dionysius of Heraclea in Pontus,

them, however, oKir^imix"' M'" have taken a very easy view of


5uf(ju6Q); Be fieffrd. Oio. De the Stoic principles (Diog. 13 ;

Orat. 62, speaks of a


iii. 17, 36 Athen. iv. 162, b ; xiii. 607,
;

School bearing his name, but no a). It is. therefore probable


pupil belonging to it is known. that he did not agree with
' Citium was his birthplace. Aristo's Cynicism (Diog. vii.
His father's name was Deme- 162), and his pupil Hermagoras
trius (_Diog. 6 ; 36), and his own vrrote against the Cynics (Stiid.
nickname Dorotheus {Sidd. 'Ep/iay.). Political reasons were
nepir.). According to Diog. at the bottom of Menedemus'
36 ; Sotion and Nicias in Athen. hatred for him (Diog. ii. 143).
iv. 162, d ii. 18, 8; Orig.
; Gell. Otherwise, he appears as a
C. Cels. 483, d he was first
iii. ; genuine Stoic (Diog. vii. 120
a slave of Zeno's, which agrees ao. N. D. i. 15, 38 ; Mintte. Felix
with his being a pupil and in- Octav. 21, 3 ; Philodem. De
mate of his house {Diog. 36 Mus., Vol. Here. i. col. 14).
13,; do. N. D. i. 15, 38 ; AtJien. Compare p. 39, 2. The treatises
xiii. 607, e ; Pauma. ii. 8, 4). mentioned by Diog. 36 are
It is less probable that he was chiefly ethical and political. In
presented by Antigonns to Zeno addition to these, there was a
as a, copyist (_I)iog. 36). He treatise on Ethics (Diog. 28) ;
subsequently lived at the court the ffviiiroTtKa wiro/Aj/iJ^aTO, or
of Antigonus {Athen. vi. 251, c tri'imaTiKol Buihoyot, from which
xiii. 607, a; Themist. Or. xxxii., Athea. (iv. 162, b ; xiii. 607, a)
p. 358), whose son Halcyoneus gives some extracts ; and the
\jEllian, V. H. iii. 17, says 'IffTopla(in Suid.). Whether
falsely himself) he is said to Cicero's statement is taken
have instructed (Diog. 36), and from a treatise omitted by Dio-
with whom he stood in high genes, or from that Trepl airs^ilas,
favour (Phit. Arat. 18 ; Athen. it is hard to say.
vi. 251, c). He allowed, how- ' According to the sketch of

ever, the Macedonian garrison his life in Buhle (Arat. 0pp. i.


in Corinth to be surprised by 3), Aratus was a pupil of Per-
Aratus, in 243 B.C., and, accord- sseus at Athens, in company
ing to Paitstm. ii. 8, 4 ; vii. 8, with whom he repaired to An-
1, perished on that occasion. tigonus in Macedonia, which
The contrary is asserted by can only mean that he was, to-
Plat. Arat. 23, and Athen. iv. gether with PerssEus, a pupil of
162, c. In his teaching and Zeno. Another writer in Buhle
manner of life, he appears to (ii. 445) calls him so, mention-
;; ;

u THE STOICS.

Chap. who afterwards joined the Cyrenaic or Epicurean


III.
School and Sphserus from the Bosporus, who studied
;
'

first and afterwards in that


in the School of Zeno,
of Cieanthes, and was the friend and adviser of
Cleomenes, the unfortunate Spartan reformer.^ Of
a few other pupils of Zeno the names are also known ;'
but nothing is known beyond their names. No ap-

ing one of his letters addressed B.C., but was then himself no
to Zeno. Other accounts {Ihid. longer a member of the Stoic
ii. 431 ; 442 446) describe him
; School at Athens. It is pos-
as a pupil of Dionysius of Hera- sible that Sphaerus may first
clea, or of Timon and Menede- have come to Cleomenes on a
mus. A memorial of his Stoi- commission from the Egyptian
cism is the introduction to his king. In that case, the Ptolemy
' PhiEnomena,' a poem resem- referred to must have been
bling the hymn of Cieanthes. eitherPtolemy Euergetes or
Asclepiades (Vita in Buhle ii. Ptolemy Philadelphus cer-
429), in calling him a native of tainly not Philopator, as Bwg.
Tarsus, is only preferring a 177 says. If, however, the
better-known Cilician town to view is taken that it was Pto-
one less known. lemy Philopator, it may be sup-
' Hence his name 6 Merafls- posed that Sphaerus repaired to
mevos. On his writings, consult Egypt with Cleomenes in 221
Biog. vii. 166 ; 37 ; 23 ; v. 92 ;
B.C. Sphserus' numerous writ-
Atlten. vii. 281, d ; x. 437, e ings (Biog. 178 AaKaviKii-iroXiTeia
:

Cic. Acad. ii. Tusc. ii.


22, 71 ; also in Athen. iv. 141, 6) refer
25, 60; Fin. v. 31, 94. Pre- to all parts of philosophy, and
viously to Zeno, he is said to to some of the older philoso-
have studied under Heraclides phers. According to Cic. Tusc.
i IlovTutbs, Alexinus, and Mene- iv. 24, 53, his definitions were
demus. in great esteem in the Stoic
Biog. 177 Plut. Cleomen.
' ; School.
2; 11; Athen. viii. 354, e. ^ Athenodorus, a native of

Sphserus' presence in Egypt Soli {Biog. vii. 38 ; 100) ; Cal-


seems to belong to the time be- lippus of Corinth (Biog. 38)
fore he became connected with Philonidesof Thebes, who went
Cleomenes. He was a pupil of with Persseus to Antigonus
Cieanthes (JDiog. vii. 185 (Biog. 9 38)
; Posidonius of
;

Athen. 1. c.) when he went to Alexandria (j)iog. 38) Zeno of ;

Egypt, and resided there, at Sidon, a pupil of Diodorus


the court of Ptolemy, for several Cronus, who joined Zeno {Biog.
years. He had left him by 221 38; 16; Suid.).
THE LATER STOICS: CHRYSIPPUS. ir,

preciable addition was made to the Stoic doctrine by Chap.


any one of them.
It was therefore fortunate for Stoicism that C. Chrys-

Cleanthes was followed in the presidency of the ""^f^l^^J^^


School by a man of learning and argumentative Stmcs.

power like Chrysippus.' In the opinion of the an- ^^ Chrys-


' i ./ J. J.
ij>j)us.
cients, Chrysippus was the second founder of Stoicism.'^
Born^* in the year 280 e.g.,"* at Soli in Cilicia,' after
being a pupil of Cleanthes and it is said even of
Zeno^ himself, he succeeded, on the death of
Cleanthes, to the conduct of his School,' He is also

' Bagwt, De Chrysippo. An- his birth. According to Imcian,


nal. LoTan. vol. iv. Lovan. 1822. Macrob. 20, he attained the age
^ Et jU^ yap -fiv Xp^nTtwiras ovk of 81, and, according to Valer.
tiv ^v <rrod {IHog. 183). Cio. Max. viii. 7 ext. 10, completed
Acad. ii. 24, 75 Chrysippum,: the 39th book of his logic in
qui fulcire putatur porticum his eightieth year.
Stoicorum. At/ten. viii. 335, ^ This is the view of Bioq.

b : 'Kpitriinrov rhv t^s ctoos 179; Plut. De Exil. 14, p. 605;


TiyeiiSm. See Baguet, p. 16. Strabo, xiii. 1, 57, p. 610; xiv.
' (Mog. 179)
It is recorded 4, 8, p. 671, and most writers.
that he was brought np in early Alexander Polyhistor, however,
life as a racer, which is an in Biog. and Suid. Z^c. call him
exceedingly suspicious state- a native of Tarsus and since;

ment (confer D, 168) ; and his father Apollonius migrated


that his paternal property was from Tarsus to Soli (Strabo,
confiscated (Hecato in JMog. p. 671), it is possible that
181). Subsequently, his domes- Chrysippus may have been bom
tic establishment was scanty, in Tarsus.
consisting of one old servant ' On
this point all autho-
iDiog. 185; 181; 183); but rities are agreed. When and
whether this was the result of how he came to Athens is not
Stoicism or of poverty is not recorded. He subsequently ob-
known. The Floril. Monac. (in tained the rights of a citizen
Stob. Floril. ed. Mein. iv. 289) (Pl-ut. Sto. Rep. 4, 2, p. 1034).
262 calls him Ktrhs, ^x"" ' Biog. 179. This statement
cannot be tested by chronology.
* According to ApoUodorus Authorities, however, do not
in Biog. 1 8i, he died c. 205 B.C., look promising.
in his 73rd year, which would ' Biog. Pro. 15. Strabo, xiii.
give 281 to 276 as the year of 1, 57, 610.
4(i THE STOICS.

Chap. said to have attended the lectures of Arcesilaus and


m.
Lacydes, philosophers of the Middle Academy ;
' and
so thoroughly had he appropriated their critical

methods, that later Stoics accused him of furnishing


Carneades with the necessary weapons for attacking
them,'' by the masterly manner in which he raised
(philosophical doubts, without being able to answer
them satisfactorily. This critical acuteness and
skiU, more than anything else, entitle him to be re-
garded as the second founder of Stoicism.' In
Jearning, too, he was far in advance of his predeces-
sors, and passed for the most industrious and learned
man of antiquity.* Independent in tone, as his other
conduct and the intellectual self-reliance which ani-

' JKog. vii. 183. It is pos- Comm. Not. i. 4, p. 1059).


sible, as JRitter, iii. 524, sup- ' When a learner, he is said
poses, that he was for some to have used these words to
time in doubt about Stoicism, Cleanthes Give me the prin-
:
'

under the influence of the ciples ; the proofs I can find


Academic Scepticism, and that myself.' Subsequently it is
during this time he wrote the said of him If the Gods have
: '

treatise against a-uvliBeta. This any logic, it is that of Chry-


is possible, but not probable. sippus' {Diog. 179). See cAo.
But that he should have sepa- N. D. i. 15, 30, where the
rated from Cleanthes, setting Epicurean calls him Stoicorum
up a school in the Lyceum in somniorum vaferrimus inter-
opposition to him, is not con- pres: ii. 6, 16; iii. 10, 25;
tained in the words of Biog, Divin. i. 3, 6 Chrysippus :

179; 185. acerrimo vir ingenio. Senec.


2 mog. 18i ; iv. 62. ae. Benefic. i. 3, 8 4, 1, who com-
;

Acad. ii. 27, 87. PUt. Sto. plains of his captiousness.


Kep. p. 10, 3, 1036. These pas- Dionyg. Hal. Comp. Verb. 68,
sages refer particularly to calls him the most practised
Chrysippus' six books kotJi t^s logician, but the most careless
(rw7)9eiaj. On the other hand, writer. KHsehe, Forsch. i.
his pupil Aristocreon, in Ptut. 445.
1. c. 2, 5, commends him as * Ding. 180. Athen. xiii.
566,
being ruv 'AKadTjuLaKav irrpay a. Damasc. V. Isid. 36. die.
yaMSav KoirlSa. (Conf. Plut. Tusc. i. 45, 108.
THE LATER STOICS: CRRT8IPPUS. 47

mated him* often proved,^ lie deviated from the Chap.


ni.
teaching of Zeno and Cleanthes, as might be expected,
in many respects.' Still, the fundamental principles
of the system were not altered by him ; only their
intellectual treatment was perfected and deepened.
In fact, the Stoic doctrine was expanded by him with
such completeness in details, that hardly a gleaning
was left for his successors to gather up.* In multi-
tude of writings' he exceeded Epicurus ;^ their titles,
and a comparatively small number of fragments,
being all that have come down to us.' With such
an extraordinary literary fertility, it will be easily
understood that their artistic value does not keep
pace. The ancients are unanimous in complaining
of their careless and impure language, of their dry
and often obscure style, of their prolixity, their end-
less repetitions, their frequent and lengthy citations,

Diog. 179 183.


'
; cureans disparaging to the
Diog. 185, mentions it as
2 honour of their master. Hence
deserving of especial notice, the charge that Chrysippns had
that he refused the invitation written against Epicurus in
of Ptolemy to court, and dedi- rivalry (IHog. x. 26, and the
cated none of his numerous criticism of ApoUodorus in
writings to a prince. Diog. vii. 181).
' Oic. Acad. ii. 47, 143. Diog. ' Baguet, pp. 114-357, dis-

179. Pint. Sto. Kep. 4, 1, p. cusses the subject very fully,


1034. According to the latter but omitting several fragments,
passage, Antipater had written On logical treatises, of which
a special treatise irf pi TTjs KAftiv- alone there were 311 (^Diog.
flows KoX Xpvaimrou Bio</)opSs. 198), see Nlcolai, De logicis
* Quid enim est a Chrysippo Chrysippi libris Quedlinb.
:

prjetermissum in Stoicis 1 Oic. 1859. Pramtl, Gesch. d. Log.


Fin. i. 2, 6. i- *0*- Petersen (Philosoph.
^ Accordingto Diog. 180, Chrysip. Fundamenta Ham- :

there were not fewer than 750. burg, 1827, 321) attempts a
Conf Valer. Max. viii. 7, ext.
.
systematic arrangement of all
10 Zucian, Hermotim. 48.
;
the known books.
This appeared to the Bpi-
;

48 THE. STOICS.

Chap. and their too frequent appeals to etymologies, autho-


III.
rities, and other irrelevant proofs.' But by Chrysippus
the Stoic teaching was brought to completeness and ;

when he died, in the year 206 b.c.,^ the form was in


every respect fixed in which Stoicism would be handed
down for the nest following centuries.
(2) Zate?' A extemporary of Chrysippus, but probably some-
Stoios.
what his senior, was Teles, a few extracts' from whose
writings have been preserved by Stobaeus,^ in the
shape of popular moral considerations written from a
Cynic or Stoical point of view. The same age also
produced the Cyrenaic Eratosthenes,* a man distin-
guished in every branch of knowledge, but particu-
larly celebrated for his mathematical attainments^

' See Cic. Be


Orat. i. 11, 50 ;
joyed by the Athenian Chre-
Dionys. Hal. See above 46, 3 ;
monides, who hadbeen banished
Bwg. vii. 180; x. 27. Galen, from his country. The banish-
Differ. Puis. ii. 10; vol. viii. ment of Chremonides being -in
631 K Hippoer. et Plat. Plac.
; the year 263 B.C., Teles' treatise
ii. 2; iii. 2; vol. v. 213, 295, irepl iftvjTis must have been
308, 312, 314, and ^aguet, 26. written between 260 and 250
See also Pint. Sto. Eep. 28, 2 ;
B.C. This is further proved
and Sergh, Commentat. de by the fact that there is no
Chrys. lib. TrtpX aizotpaTiKwy : reference in the fragments pre-
Cassel, 1841. served to persons or circum-
^ The circumstances of his stances later than this date.
death are related differently in The philosophers to whom re-
IHog. 184 but both stories are
; ference is made are the Cynics
untrustworthy. The story of Diogenes, Crates, Metrocles,
the ass is also told in Zuoian, Stilpo, Bio the Borysthenite,
Macrob. 25 of Philemon the ; Zeno, and Cleanthes (95, 21),
other version in Diog. iv. 44 the latter being called i
61 of Arcesilaus and Lacydes. "Aaaios.
On the statue of Chrysippus in * Ploril. 5, 67; 40, 8; 91,
the Ceramicus see Diog. vii. 33 ; 93, 31 98, 72 108, 82 and
;

182 Die. Fiu.i. 11,39 Pausan.


; ; 83.
j. 17, 2 Pint. Sto. Eep. 2, o.
; ' According to Sidd., born
' In 40, 8, mention is made c. 275 B.C., and he died in his
of the honourable position en-, 80th year.
;

THE LATER STOICS.

who was gained for Stoicism by Aristo.^ Another Chap.


III.
)i cotemporary of Chrysippus, and perhaps his fellow-
student,^ who in many respects approximated to the
teaching of the Peripatetics/ was the Stoic Boethus.
The proper scholars of Chrysippus were without doubt
numerous ; but few of their names are known to us.*
The most important among them appear to have
been Zeno of Tarsus, and Diogenes of Seleucia,^ who

' See p. 41, 2. biguous whether irpis means to


^ Conf Siog. 54
. : &li Xpi(r- or against.
ttTTTOs Sta(l>ep6fj.vos irphs ainiv. . , ' Aristocsreon, the nephew

Kpiritptd <pijffLV ?i/ai cCiffS'qfnj/ KaX of Chrysippus, is the only pupil


That he was jvmior
irp6\riftv. who can be definitely men^
to appears by his
Aratns tioned by name. See Diog. vii.
commentary on Aratus' poem. 185 Pint. Sto. Eep. 2, 5, p. 1033.
;

See Appendix to Geminws, ^ What is known of this


Blem. Astron. (Petavii Dootr. philosopher is limited to the
Temp. III. 147). The Vita statements in Kog. 35 Suid. j

Arati (Von Buhle's Aratus, Zi\v. AiooK. Mts. Pr. Bv. xv.
;

vol. ii. 443), probably con- 13, 7 Arius Didymus, Ibid. xv.
;

founding him with the Peri- 17, 2 that he was a native of


;

patetic Boethus, calls him a Tarsus (in Said, rivh say of


native of Sidon. Sidon, evidently confounding
" We shall have occasion to him with the Zeno mentioned
prove this in speaking of his p. 44, 3) that he was the son of
;

,
Tdews of a criterion, and of his Dioscorides, the pupil and fol-
denial of a conflagration and lower of Chrysippus that he ;

destruction of the world. Never- left many pupils, but few


theless, he is frequently ap- writings ; and that he doubted
pealed to as an authority among a conflagration of the world.
the Stoics. PAifc, Incorruptib. ' According to IXog. vi. 81

M. 947, C, classes him among Lucian, Macrob. 20, he was


SfSpes ev rots "ZTuiKois Siyfiaatv a native of Seleucia on the
Tigris ; but he is sometimes
* This the
follows from called a native of Babylon
great importance of Chrysip- (Diog. vii. 39; 55; C?c. N. D.
pus, and the esteem in which i. 15, 41 Divin. i. 3, 6 Plut.
; ;

he was held from the very first, De Bxil. 14, p. 605). 0,0. Divin.
and is confirmed by the num- i. 3, 6, calls him a pupil of
ber of persons to whom he Chrysippus; and Acad. ii. 30,
wrote treatises. See the list 98, the instructor of Carneades
from Siog. 189 in Fabric. Bibl. in dialectic. Plut; Alex. Virt.
iii. 549. It is, however, am- 5, p. 328, calls him a pupil of
'

50 THE STOICS.

Chap, succeeded Chrysippus in the presidency of the School.'


: The pupil and successor of Diogenes, in his turn, was
Antipater of Tarsus,^ in connection with whom his
countryman Archedemus is frequently mentioned.'

Zeno (of Tarsus). Zeno, he Acad. 1842, Hist. phil. kl. p. 103,
says, AioyeVTj rhv Ba^vKciiifLOV already remarks and Plut. ;

eTreiffe ^iXoffo<l>e1v. Diog, "vii. Tranq. An. 9, p. 469, seems to


71, mentions a SioXektik)) Te'xi"! imply that he continued to live
of his ; and, vii. 55 and 57, a at Athens after leaving Cilioia.
rex^v 'repl ipwvTJs. Oic. Divin. The same fact is implied by
i. speaks of a treatise on
3, 6, the mention of Diogenists and
divination. Atken. iv. 168, e, Pana3tiasts at Athens (^Atlien.
of a treatise irtpi ih-^eveias, xii. V. c. 2, p. 186, a) ; by the charge
626, d, of a work irepl v^ixav brought against Antipater
the same work probably which, iPlut.Garrul. c, 23, p. 514 ;

according to (Ke. Legg. iii. 5, Numen. in Eus. Pr. Ev. xiv.


14, was written a Dione Stoico.'
' 8, 6 Cic. Acad. ii. 6, 17,
; and
Cic. Off. iii. 12, 51, calls him the fragment from Acad. Post.
'magnus et gravis Stoicus ; I. in Non. p. 65), that he never

Seneca, De Ira, iii. 38, 1, men- ventured to dispute with Car-


tions a trait showing great neades and by Diog. iv. 65
; ;

presence of mind. Diogenes Stol). FlorU. 119, 19. According


was, without doubt, aged in to these two authorities, he
156 B.C. (^Oic. De Senec. 7, 28). voluntarily put an end to his
According to I/ucian, he at- own life, li Acad. ii. 47, 143,
tained the age of 88, and may Cicero calls him and Aiche-
therefore have died 150 B.C. demus duo vel principes
'

' It was often supposed, dialecticorum, opiniosissimiho-


on the strength of Cic. N. D. mines.' It appears from Off.
i. 15, 41, Divin. i. 8, 6, that iii. 12, 51, where he is also
Diogenes was the immediate called '
homo acutissimus,' that
successor of Chrysippus. The he pronounced a severer judg-
words, however, consequens ment on several moral questions
or subsequens, by no means than Diogenes. Sen. Ep. 92, 5,
necessarily imply it. On the reckons him among the magnos
authority of Arius, Eusebius, Stoicse sectae auctores. Epiotet.
and Suidas, it would seem that Diss. iii. 21, 7, speaks of the
Zeno was the successor of (popi, 'AvTiirdTpov Kal '
Apx^^'hl'.'"'-
Chrysippus, and that Diogenes See Va7i Zynden, De Panaetio,
followed Zeno. 33 and Fabric. Biblioth. iii.
;

2 Cic. Off. iii. 12, 51, only 538 for his numerous lost
calls him his pupil ; but it is treatises.
clear that he taught in Athens ' Cic. 1. c. ; Strdbo xiv. 4, 14,
from Pint. Ti. Graooh. c. 8, as p. 674, Epictet. 1. c. ; l>iog. vii.
Zwmpt, Ueber die philos. 55. It does not follow that they
Schulen in Athen. Abh. d. Berl. were cotemporaries, but only
THE LATER STOICS. 51

Under Pansetius, Antipater's scholar, Stoicism entered Chap.


III.
the Roman world, and there underwent internal
changes, to which attention will be drawn in the
sequel.'

that their writings and philo- Zenodotus (Stdd. ZrivoS.). A


sophy were the same. We third is perhaps the celebrated
have otherwise no accurate in- Aristarchus, whom Scymnus
formation as to the date of calls a fellow-disciple of Apol-
Archedemus. Passages where lodorus. A fourth. Crates of
he is mentioned may he found Mallos, called by Strabo, xiv.
in Fah-ic. Bibl. III. 540. He 5, 16, p. 676, the instructor of
also appears to be meant in Pansetius, by Suid. a Stoic
Simpl. De
Coelo Schol.in Arist. philosopher, who in Va/rro, Lat.
505, a, In X)ioff. 134, he
45. ix. 1, appeals to Chrysippus
appears to be placed between against Aristarchus.
Chrysippus and Posidonius. In Antipater's pupils are Hera-
Plut. De Exil. 14, 605, he clides of Tarsus {Diog. vii. 121) ;
follows Antipater. According Sosigenes {Alex. Apia: De Mixt.
to this authority he established 142); C. Blossius of Cume
a school in Babylon, and be- {Phd. Ti. Gracch. 8, 17 and 20 ;

cause he came there from Val. Max. iv. 7, 1 do. LebI.


;

Athens, Plutarch appears to 11, 37). Eudromus, mentioned


have considered him an Athe- by Diog. vii. 39, appears to
nian. belong to the time between
' ApoUodoms of Athens, the Chrysippus and Pansetius.
compiler of the Bi$\io6iiKri, a Between Zeno of Tarsus and
well-known grammarian, is also Diogenes, Diog. vii. 84, names
mentioned as a pupil of Dio- a certain ApoUodorus, the au-
genes (^Scymnus, Chins Perieges. thor, probably, of the fragments
v. 20). His chronicle, dedicated in Stoi. Eel. i. 408 and 520.
to Attains H., Philadelphus of Possibly, however, he may be
Pergamum (158-138 B.C.), and identical with the ApoUodorus
probably drawn up 144 B.C., mentioned by Cio. N. D. i. 34,
would seem to corroborate this 93, and consequently a co-
assertion. Pansetius, whose temporary of Zeno. In Diog.
pupil he is elsewhere called vii. 39, he is called \TToW6Saipos
'

{Swid. 'A.Trii\kiS.'), was himself a 6 'E<j)iWos, instead of which


pupil of Diogenes' successor, Cobet reads 'AiroWdSufios Koi
Antipater (<7ic. Divin. i. 3, 6), ^iwos. ApoUodorus the Athe-
and can hardly have been older nian, mentioned by Diog. vii.
than ApoUodoms. 181, is witheut doubt the Epi-
Another grammarian be- curean, known to us also from
longing to the School of Diog. X. 2 and 25. KHsche,
Diogenes is Zenodotus {Diog. Forsch. 26, thinks even that
vii. 30), supposing him to be the passages in Cicero refer to
identical with the Alexandrian him.
E 2
;

52 THE STOICS.

Chap. The age of Diogenes of ferred to by Bimpl. in Categ.


III. Ptolemais {Mog. vii. 41), of Schol. in Ajist. 40, a ; 24, b,
CEnopides mentioned by 8tob. 16; 41,b, 27; 47, b, 23; 49, b,
Eol. i. 58; Macrdb. Sat. i. 17, 43 ! 72, b, 6 74, b, 4 ; 81, b,
;

together witti Diogenes and 12 83, a, 37 84, a, 28 ; 86, b,


;
;

Cleanthes, and of Nicostratus, 20 ; 87, b, 30 88, b, 8 and 11


;

mentioned by Philodemus irepl 89, a, 1; 91, a, 25; b, 21.


flEwc Sia7B7?s Tab. I. 2 and per- For this Nicostratus used the
haps by Artemidorus Oneiro- treatise of a certain Roman
crit. I. 2 Sch. is quite unknown. Lucius, whereas Roman trea-
Nicostratus, however, must have tises on the Categories can
written before the middle of hardly have existed before the
the first century before Christ. time of Philodemus, a co-
He is probably distinct from temporary of Cicero. However,
the Nicostratus who wrote on both Lucius and Nicostratus
the Aristotelian categories in appear to have been Stoics,
an adverse spirit, and is re-
AUTHORITIES FOR STOIC PSILOSOPHY. 53

CHAPTEE IV.

AUTHORITIES FOR THE STOIC PHILOSOPHY : ITS

PROBLEM AND DIVISIONS.

To give a faithful, exposition of the Stoic philosophy Chap.


is a work of more than ordinary difficulty, owing to L
the circumstance that all the writings of the earlier ^- 4^"
Stoics, with the exception of a few fragments, have for the
been Those Stoics whose complete
lost.'
^
works are 'Si!'i'*^-
osophy.
still extant
Seneca, Epictetus, Marcus AureUus, n)jjmro
Heraclitus, Comutus
lived under the Eoman Em- / authori-
pire, and therefore belong to a time in which all
Schools alike exposed to foreign influences had sur-
rendered or lost sight of many of their original
peculiarities, substituting new elements in their
place. The same remark applies to writers like
Cicero, Plutarch, Diogenes, Sextus Empiricus, and
the commentators on Aristotle, who may be con-
sidered as authorities at second hand for the teaching

of the Stoics ; but it is more than doubtful whether


everything which they mention as Stoic teaching
really belongs to the older members of that School.

'
Already Si/m/pl. in Cat. al ^ 5iSa(rKct\[a koX t4 ir\ei(rT
Schol. in Aiist. 49, a, 16, says : tuv (rvyyfMii.niT<i>y lirt\i\oi7rev.
.54 TRE STOICS.

Chap. That teaching can, however, be ascertained with


'

sufficient certainty on most of the more important


points, partly by comparing accounts when they vary,
partly by looking to definite statements on which
authorities agree for the teaching and points of dif-

ference between individual philosophers, such as Zeno,


Cleanthes, Chrysippus ;
partly too by consulting such
fragments of their writings as are still extant. Yet,
when the chief points have been settled in this way,
many difficulties still remain. In the first place, it

will be found that only isolated points of their teach-


ing, with at most a few arguments on which to base
them, are recorded ; but the real connection of those
tenets, and the motives which gave rise to them, can
only be known by conjecture. Had the writings of
Zeno and Chrysippus conie down to us in their en-
tirety, we should have had a much surer foundation
on which to build, and far less would have been left
to conjecture. An opportunity, too, would then have
been afforded us of tracing the inward growth of the
Stoic teaching, and of deciding how much of that
teaching was due to Zeno, and how much to Chrysip-
pus. That now this work of arrangement can only be
done very imperfectly, is the second difficulty which
arises from the nature of our authorities. It may be
ascertained without difficulty what the teaching of
the Stoics was since the time of Chrysippus, but
only on a few points are the differences between
Chrysippus and his predecessors known. For the
most part, the authorities do not hesitate to attribute
to the founder of the School all that was known to
AUTHORITIES FOR STOIC PHILOSOPHY. 55

them as belonging to its later members, just as Chap.


^^'
everything Pythagorean was directly attributed to
Pythagoras, and everything Platonic to Plato. Still,

there can be no doubt that the Stoic teaching was


very considerably expanded by Chrysippus, and that
it was altered in more than one respect. But how
considerable the alterations were, and in what they
consisted, are questions upon which there is little

direct evidence.
The path is thus marked out, which must be fol- (2) Use to
"

lowed in giving an exposition of the Stoic philosophy, ^ut^iori-


Could only full information be obtained respecting <

the rise of the Stoic system and the form it assumed


under each one of its representatives, it would be
most natural to begin by reviewing the motives which
led Zeno to his peculiar teaching, and to describe the
system as it grew thereout. Next it would be right
to trace step by step the changes and expansions
which it received in the hands of each succeeding
teacher. But, in default of the necessary information
for such a treatment of the subject, it will be better
to pursue another course. The Stoic teaching will
have to be treated as a whole, in which the contribu-
tions of individuals can no longer be distinguished.
It will have to be set forth in the form which it as-

sumed after the time of Chrysippus. Nor can the


share of individuals in constructing the system, nor
their deviations from the general type, be considered,
except in cases where they are placed beyond doubt
by the statements of the ancients, or by well-founded
historical surmises. Stoicism will have to be de-
:

50 THE STOICS.

Chap, scribed in the first .place as it is traditionally known,


- -.1 _ without having its principles explained or resolved
into their component factors ; without even consider-
ing how they grew out of previous systems. Not till
this has been done will it be possible to analyse the
purport and structure of the system, so as to fathom
its leading motives, to understand the connection of
its various parts, and thus to ascertain its true posi-
tion in history.
^.ProUem Proceeding next to ask in what form the problem
^ouTsiciic ^ philosophy presented itself to the Stoics, three
pUloso- points deserve to be specially noticed. In the first
place, philosophy was determined practically by an
end in view. The character of this end was decided by
the idea of conformity with reason ; and this view
was substantiated by an intellectual proof.
{I) lu The real business of all philosophy, according to

olim-acter. the Stoics, is the moral conduct of man. Philosophy


is the exercise of an art, and more particularly of the
highest art virtue :
' it is therefore the learning of
virtue. Now virtue can only be learnt by exercise,
and therefore philosophy is at the same time virtue,^

'Plwt. Plac. Pro. 2 ol liiv


: is a striving after wisdom :

oZv SnaiKol ^t^aaai), r^v /lev wisdom isdefined to be the


(ro<j)ittv ehai Belav re Kal avBpu- knowledge of things human
jr(>/wi/ iviati\iii\v t^i/ 5f ^iKoao- and divine philosophy to be
;

iplav iffKnaiv rexvris iweniSeiott- studiwm virtutis, or gtuiHum


iiriTliSeiovS' ehaifiiai' KaiivaTaTa cm-riff enda mentis. This striving
-iperhv apcT^s Si reks yevi-
T7))/ after virtue cannot be distin-
KordTtts rpeis, (pvffiK^v, fiBiKiiy, guished from virtue itself
Xoyixiiv, K.T.A.. See also Diog, Philosophia studium virtutis
vii. 92. est, :sed per ipsam virtutem.
^ In Seneca, Bp. 89, 4, wis- Seneca further observes (Fr. 17,
dom is the highest good for the in Zactant. Inst. iii. 15) Philo-
:

human mind, and philosophy sophia nihil aliud est quam


;

PROBLEM PROPOSED TO STOICS. 57

and the several parts of philosophy are so many dis- Chap.


IV.
tinct virtues.' Morality is the central point towards
which all other inquiries converge : even natural
science, although lauded as the inmost shrine of
philosophy, is, according to Chrysippus, only neces-
sary for the philosopher to enable him to distinguish
between things good and evil, between what should
be done and what should be left undone.^ Pure
speculation, on the contrary, which Plato and Aris-
totle had commended as the height of human happi-
ness, Chrysippus so far from approving, plainly asserted
that to live for speculation is equivalent to living' y
only for pleasure.' With this view of Chrysippus
most of the statements of the Stoics as to the rela-
tion of various branches of philosophy to each other
agree, although there is a certain amount of vague-

ness about them, owing to reasons which will shortly


be mentioned; and on no other hypothesis can the in-
ternal structure and foundation of their system be

recta viveudi ratio, vel honeste deaptas iropa\7)7rT^s oStrijj jj irpbi


.Vivendi scieutia, vel ars rectse t^p irtpl ir/oBav ti Koxiei/ Sti-
vitse agendas. Non
errabimus, arairiv.
si dixerimus philosophig,m esse Cha-ys. in Phit. Sfco. Eep.
'

legem bene honesteque Vivendi, 3, 2 8<roi 8e iwoKaftfiivoviri ^lAo-


:

,et qui dixerit illam regvilam aocpots iiripiweiv //.dKiffra rhv


yitSB, siium illi [nomen] red- axo\a(rTMhvPloyi.jt'apxvs,ovToi
didit. Pint, see previous note, /lot SoKovai iiafiaprAveiv vwovoovv^
^ See JHoff. 'vii. i6 ai/T^vSk : TesSiayuyTJSTtvosUveKefSelvTovTo
r))v StoXcKTiK^i' avayxaXav eXvai woteiv ^ &K\ov tivos toiJtqj Tropa-
KOI iperiiD ir etSei ti epUxovffta' Tr\r))rlov, Koi rdy SAoc $iov oSrai

&peTis, K.T.\. Tuis SieAttiiffai touto 5' ianv,


^ C/t/rys.ia Phi. Sto. Bep. 9, tiv a-afZs fleapTjflJ, ijSias. Aiayuyii

6 ; Sei yiip Toirois [so. Tois ipvtti- had, it is true, been treated by
icots] ffvvii^ai rhv irepl iiyud^v Koi Aristotle, whose school is here
KuKuv \6yoy, oiic oSffiis JiMTji ap- referred to, as an end in itself
Xris ouTMJ' iiieliiorosoiS' ava<j>opS.s, but Aristotle had carefully dis-
ouS' &\KouTiyhseyeiteyrTJs(puaiKTis tinguished StByioy^ from riSoyf).
: ;

a THE STOICS.

(JHAP. satisfactorily explained. enough to remark


It is
^^-
here, as has been done before,' that the most impor-
tant and most distinctive points established by the
Stoic School belong to the domain of ethics. In
logic and natural science that School displays far less
independence, for the most part following older
teachers ; and it is expressly noted, as a deviation
- from the ordinary teaching of the School, that
Herillus, the pupil of Zeno, declared knowledge to be
the highest good, thus making it the chief end in
philosophy.^

(2) Neecs- This view of the problem of philosophy is more


ntyforin- precisely defined by the Stoic doctrine of virtue.
hnoreledge. Philosophy should lead to right action and to virtue.
But right action is, according to the Stoics, only
rational action, and rational action is action which
1 is in harmony with human and inanimate nature.
Virtue consists therefore in bringing man's actions
into harmony with the laws of the universe, and
with the general order of the world. This is only
possible when man knows that order and those laws

' p. 19. tionem relinquerent. v. 25,73 :

^ do. Acad. 129


ii. 42, Sspe ab Aristotele, a Theo-
Herillmn, qui in oognitione et phrasto mirabiliter est laudata
scientiasummumbonumponit: per se ipsa rerum scientia.
qui cum Zenonis auditor esset. Hoc uno captus Herillus scien-
vides quantum ab eo dissen- tiam summum bonum esse de'
serit, et quam non multum a fendit, neo rem uUam aliam
Platone. Fin. ii. 13, 43 Heril-: per se expetendam. IHog. vii.
lus autem ad scientiam omnia 165 :"HpiA\os. re'Xos elirt
. . tV
revocansunumquoddam bonum itna-Tiiiiriv. Ibid. vii. 37. With
vidit. iv. 3614, In deter-
: less accuracy, it is asserted by
mining the highest good, the Iambi, in Stob. Bel. i. 918, that
Stoics act as one-sidedly, as if we are raised to the society
ipsius animi, ut fecit Herillus, of the gods, kotA "TipiKKov, iirt-
cognitionem amplexarentur, ac- iTT^/up,
;

PROBLEM PROPOSED TO STOICS. 59

and thus the Stoics are brought back to the princi- |


Chap.
pies of Socrates, that virtue may be learnt; that
j

kno-wledge is indispensable for virtue, or rather that |

virtue is identical with right kno-wledge. They


define virtue in so many words as knowledge, vice
as ignorance. If sometimes they seem to identify
virtue with strength of will, it is only because they
consider strength of will to be inseparable from
knowledge, so that the one cannot be conceived
of without the other. Hence the practical problem
of philosophy conducts with them to the intellectual
philosophy is not only virtue, but without philosophy
no virtue is possible.' Grranting that the attain-
ment of virtue, and the happiness of a moral life are

the chief ends which the Stoics propose to them-


selves, still the possession of a comprehensive
scientific knowledge is indispensable, as the only
means thereto.
i
These remarks prove the need for the Stoics of (3) Posi-
that kind of scientific knowledge which has to do ^ardsimigic
with life, the morals and the actions of mankind, in "'^'^
short, of Ethics. Whether in addition thereto fur- science.

ther scientific knowledge is necessary, was a question


on which the earliest adherents of the Stoic teaching
expressed different opinions. Zeno's pupil, Aristo of (a) Ans-
''*<'*-
Chios, held that the sole business of man is to pursue "*

virtue,^ and that the sole use of language is to purify


'
Sen. Ep. 89, 8 Nam nee : totum dedica.
philosopMa sine virtute est neo ^ Lact. Inst. vii. 7; Ad
sine philosophia virtus. Ibid, virtutem capessendam nasci
63, 8 : We
all lie in the slumber homines, Ariston disseruit. See
of error sola autem nos philo-
: Stot. Bel. 4, 111.
Sophia exeitabit , illi te
. .
GO THE STOICS.

Chap, the This purifying process, however, is


soul.'
IV,
neither to be found in logical subtleties nor in
natural science. Logic, as doing more harm than
good, he- compared to a spider's web, which is as

useless as it is curious ;
^ or else to the mud on a
road.* Those who studied it he likened to people
eating lobsters, who take a great deal of trouble for
the sake of a little bit of meat enveloped in much
shell.* Convinced, too, that the wise man is free

from every deceptive infatuation,^ and that doubt,


J<ii the purpose of refuting which logic had been
invented, can be more easily overcome by a healthy
tone of mind ^ than by argument, he felt no par-
ticular necessity for logic. Nay, more, he considered
that excessive subtlety transforms the healthy action
of philosophy into an unhealthy one.'^ Just as little

was Aristo disposed to favour the so-called encyclical


knowledge : those who devote themselves to this
knowledge instead of to philosophy he compared to
the suitors of Penelope, who won the maids but not
the mistress.' Natural science would probably have
received a more favourable treatment at the hands of
Aristo, had he not shared the opinion of Socrates,
that it is a branch of knowledge which transcends

' Plmt. De Audiendo, c. 8, <i6<pov aS6^a<rTov eivai.


p. 42 otheykp jSaA.oce/ou, (pntrlv
: " See Diog. vii. 163.
6 'AflffTuv, aire \6yov /i?) KaBal- ' Aristo (in the
'Ofioi^iuiTa)
povTos i(p\6s isTiv. in Stoh. Floril. 82, 16 i i^Xe- :

Stob. Floril. 82, 15. Diag,


' Popos iKoaxipetrrepos faev \ii(j>8eh
vii.161. KaSalpei, eis Sh Trdvv trfUKpa rpiip-
* Stod. Floril. 82, 11. eels wlyet o8t<b koI ^ Kora
' Ibid. 7. <piKoiro(l>lav XeirroXoylo.
' I>wg. vii. 162 iidKuTTa Si
: Stob. 1. c. 4, 110.
irpoffeixe ^tu'Ck^ doy/xaTt rep rbv

PROBLEM PROPOSED TO STOICS. 61

the capacity of the human mind ; ' and having once Chap.
embraced he was inclined to pronoimce _
this notion, J

all physical enquiries useless. His attitude towards


other sciences has therefore been generally expressed
by saying that he excluded from philosophy both
logic and natural science, on the ground that both
are useless ; the former being irrelevant, and the
latter transcending our powers.^ Even ethics was
limited by Aristo to most fundamental notions to
inquiries into good and evil, virtue and vice, wisdom
and folly. The special application of these notions /

to the moral problems suggested by particular rela- (

tions in life, he declared to be useless and futile; I

proper for nursemaids and trainers of young children, I

but not becoming for philosophers ;


^ wherever there i

'See following note and Oic. ' Sext. Math. vii. 13: koI
Acad. ii. 39, 123 Aristo Chius, : 'ApiffToni Si ii.6vov, &s
6 X'los oti

qui nihil istorum (ic. phy- ipaat, xapriTeiTo Tf\vre ((juiri/tV


sicorum) sciri putat posse. kbi KoyM^v Beuplav Sick rh avaxpe-
^
JHoff. vii.lQO T6vffe(l>vffL- : \es Kal "Trphs KaKov rots (pi\o(ro'
ichv r6trov Kat rbv \<yytKhv av^pei, ipovfftv vxdpxetVj aWa Koi tov
Keyav rbv fihv etyat i/irkp Tifias, iiOiKov tSttov Tivcts ffvfi-nepieypai^s
rhv 8* ohSkv wphs ijVSy, fi6vov Se Ka6direp r6v Te irapaiveTiKhi/ Kal
rbv TjBtKhy eXvai vphs '^fias. Stob. rbv viroBeriKby riirov roirovsyap
Floril. 80, 7 'Api(TTuy ^ipi] ruv
: els rirOas ttv Kal TraiSaytayobs
(nrov/ievaiv irapct Tois </>i\0(r(ii/)<iir liirreiy (almost a literal
rk fity etyaivpbsTiiiaSjTctSi /iiiSiv translation is given of these
irpbs ijuSs,T^ S' fiirep rjfLas. irpbs words by Seneca, Bp. 89, 13)
to iidiKa, fiij irpbs ^/iSs
ittias fiey apKeitrBai Se irpbs rb /xaKapius
5e rh Sia\eKTi/cc /x^ yhp iruii^dK-
^i&vat rby olKeiovyra fiiy irpbs
\eadaL irpds iTraySpBatciy $(av
iper^v \6yov, airaWorpiovyTa Se
inrip p'/iSs Se ret ^vaiKi iSiyuTa Kaxias, KaTarpexoyTa Si ray
yhp 4yv&{T6aL Kai ouSe irap4x^ty fiera^b roiiroiy, irepl & ol iroAAoi
Xpeiay. Mimie. Fel. Octav. 13, irroifiiyres KaKoSaip.oyov(Tty. Se-
and Lactamt. Inst. iii. 30, at- neoa, Bp. 94, 1 Bam partem :

tribute this utterance to So- philosophise, quse dat propria


crates. According to (Xc. De cuiquepersonEeprEeoepta ....
Nat. De. I. 14, 37, Aristo ex- quidamsolamrecepernnt . . i .

pressed doubts about the exist- sed Ariston Stoicus e contrario


enoe of a God. banc partem levem existimat
'

iV2 THE STOICS.

Uhap. is a proper knowledge and a right disposition, such


IV.
particular applications will come of themselves with-
out teaching ; but when these are wanting, all

exhortations are useless.^


(_!/) Views These views are mentioned as peculiar to Aristo,
of Zeno
uiid Cle-
and as points in which he differed from the rest of
imtlws. his School ; and, to judge from his controversial tone,
the opposite views were those almost imiversally
entertained by Stoics. That controversial tone, in
fact, appears to have been directed not only against
assailants from without such as the Peripatetics
and Platonists but far more against those member^
of the Stoic School, who attached greater importance
than he did to special ethical investigations, and to
logicaland physical inquiries. Among their number
must have been Zeno and Cleanthes for had not ;

Zeno set the example to his School of dividing phi-


losophy into logic, ethics, and natural science ? Do '^

not the titles of his logical and physical treatises

non descendat in pectus


et quffi monitionibus tuis fama pos-
usque ;ad illam habentem sedit qui habet exaotum judi-
;

prsecepta [? ad vitam beatam] cium de fugiendis petendisque,


plurimum ait profioere ipsa de- scit, quid sibi faciendum sit,
creta philosophise constitu- etiam te tacente tota ergo
;

tionemque summi boni, quam pars ista philosophise submo-


qui bene intellexit ac didicit, veri potest. In 17, he con-
quid in quaque re faciendum tinues A madman must be
:

sit, sibi This is


ipse prseoepit. cured, and not exhorted nor ;

then further expanded follow- is there any diflEerence between


ing Axisto. general madness and the mad-
' Seneca, 12, asks for ness which is treated medi-
whom should such exhortations cally.

be necessary for him who has 2 Diog. vii. 39.
right views of good and evil, or ' Logical treatises, those
for him who has them not ?
Qui non habet, nihil a te adju- irepl \iyo\i
and if there were a
vabitur aures ejus contraria
; rhetoric (see p. 40, 3) the Tex<"I
PROBLEM PROPOSED TO STOICS. G3

prove this fact ; as also statements in reference to Chap.


IV.
theoretical knowledge and natural science which are
expressly attributed to him ? Moreover, Zeno him-
self recommended to others, and himself pursued,
logical inquiries.' Indeed, his whole mental habit,^
with keen appreciation of even the subtleties of
its

the Megarians, bears testimony to an intellectual


line of thought which is removed from that of
far
Aristo.^ It was, moreover, Zeno who chose that curt
and unadorned logical style, which is found in its

greatest perfection in Chrysippus.'' Logical and


scientific treatises are also known to have been
written by Cleanthes,' who, in his division of phi-

physical treatises, those irepl Cleanth. 102, believes this work


8\ou and irep! oialas. Diog. 4, was a treatise on life according
39. to reason. The title is against
' Plvt. Sto. Eep. 8, 2 : %Xve this view, and it is also im-
8 Kod T7]f SmA.eKTi/cjJC,
tTo<l}ifTfjiaTa probable, inasmuch as treatises
ws Toiiro iroieiv Svyafievriv, cKcAeue by Sphffirus and Chrysippus
Tohs
vapa\afj.fidveiv fia6T]Tiis. bearing the same title, are ex-
That he occasionally not only clusively logical), mentions
solved but propoimded sophisms logical treatises irepl K6yov,
is proved by the fallacy quoted irepl ivtCTiiintSt wepl iSlaiv, irepl riov
IHd. Conf. Biog. vii. 25.
1. &ir6pwv, irepl StaXe/CTiKTjy, irepl
2 See above p. 36. KUTTiyopTiiuiTav. To these may
' According to Diog. 32, he be added, from Athen. 467, d ;

declared at the beginning of 471, b, the rhetorical treatises


his polity the iyKUK\ios naiSeia and irepl fieraXit^eus.
irepl Tp6irtoy

to be useless
a testimony Of greater importance were
worth very little for it is a ; the physical and theological
moot point, in what sense Zeno treatises : irepl ttjs tov Z^vuvos
made this statement. Perhaps <j>v(rio\oylas (2, B) ; tSk 'Hpoic-
he was only anxious to exclude Aeirou i^riyi](rtis (4, B) ; irpbs

those studies from the narrower ATjfidKpLToy, irepl Se&v, irepl fiavTi-
sphere of philosophy (as Sen. K^s {Cio. Divin. i. 3, 6); irepl
Ep. 88). Perhaps his polity yiyoj'Tffli' (in Pint. De Flum.
was nearer Cynicism than any 5, 3) ; and the /nuei/cck (Atlien.
other of his writings. xiii.572, e), which is probably
* Proofs will be given later. identical with the apxaio\oyia
5 The Catalogue in Diog. of Diogenes.
174, iTfpl \6yov 3, B
:

G4 TSE STOICS.

Chap, losophy, allotted separate parts to logic, to rhetoric,


and the name of Cleanthes is

and to natural science,*


one of frequent occurrence, not only in the natural
science, but more particularly in the theology of
the Stoics. Still more exhaustive inquiries into
logic and natural science appear to have been set on
foot by Sphgerus ; ^ all proving that the energies of
the Stoic School must have been directed to these
subjects before the time of Chrysippus, although
these branches of science were no doubt subservient
to ethics, ethics holding the most important and
highest place in their philosophy. At a later time,
when Chrysippus had expanded the system of the
Stoics in every direction, and especial attention had
been devoted to logic, the necessity for these sciences
came to be generally recognised. More especially
was this the case with regard to natural science, in-
cluding ' theology.' All ethical inquiries must start,

according to Chrysippus, with considering the uni-


versal order and arrangement of the world. Only by
a study of nature, and a knowledge of what Grod is,

can anything really satisfactory be stated touching


good and evil, and all that is therewith connected.^
Diog. 41.
' OTiJfious koI tci efSaXa, irepl
Diog. -vii.nS,Toaentions(l)
' alffBrimpiaiv, vepl 'HpoKAefrou (5,
logical and rhetorical writings B),irplfiavTtKrjs. That Sphserus'
irepl T&y 'ZperpixSv <l>i\oa-6^uiv, detinitions were particularly
TTcpl 6/iola>v, irepl Spay, Tcpl efetoy, valued, has been already seen,
Trepl Twc avri\eyo/iv(ijv (3, B), 44, 2.
irepi \(i7ou, Te'xyi) Sia\eKTi/c7) (2, ' in the 3rd B, Trtpl
Clirys.
B), irepl KarnyopTifidraiv, irepl BfSiv (in Phlt. Sto. Eep. 9, 4) :

afiiptPoMciv treatises on
; (2) ou ydp iariv eipfiv t^s SiKaiocriyris
science irepl K(i(rftou (2, B), irepl
: &\\tiv apxhv oiS' &7iJ\.i\v ytviffiv ^
cnoix^iav, irepl aitipnaros, irepl tV ek toS Aibs Kol r^v 4k rrjs
""Xis. "'?! ^Aax'o'Tooi', irphs toi koiv^s tpiaeas ivTfvBfi/ yiip Sf7
PROBLEM PROPOSED TO STOICS. 65

Less obvious is the connection between logic and Chap.


IV.
the ultimate aim of all philosophical inquiries. Logic
is compared by the Stoics to the shell of an egg, or
to the wall of a city or garden ; ' and is considered to
be of importance, because it contributes towards the
discovery of truth and the avoiding of error.^ The
value of logic in their eyes is, therefore, essentially
due to its scientific .method ; its proper aim is the
art of technical reasoning; and thus, following
Aristotle, an unusually full treatment is allowed to
the doctrine of the syllogism.^ That the value,
however, attached to it must have been considerable
is proved by the extraordinary care which Chrysippus
iray rh toiovtov t^v a.pxhv ^X^'-^> K6yos irphs rh ciKhs, Strre /x^
et iiiWofXiv Ti ^petv irepl ayaSiav 4vSiS6vaL avT^'), ai^eAeyl^a ( iffx^s
KaX Kaxap. The same writer, in iv \6y(f!, ii(TTe fii] airdyetrdat uir'

^vffiKaX Beffeis (Ibid, 5) ov ydp : avTov els rh aVTlK^ifievov'), ctjtta-

iffTiif &Wojs ovS' oiKetirepov eT6\- Tai(fTT]s (,= e^ts ayiX<p4poviTa ras
Beiv iirl t))v twv ayadwy Kol icaicSiv (/layrafffas inl Thv opQhv K6yov).
X6yov oiiS 4ir\ Tcls apercls ouS' inl Its value was therefore chiefly
eitSainovlaVj oA^' ft ^T"i ttjs Koivris negative, preserving from error.
^iffeios rtol 07ri t^s toO KStrfiov See Seneca, Ep. 89, 9 Pro- :

SioiKiiaems. Further details prietates verborum exigit et


above p. 47, 2. structuramet argumentationes,
' Sext. Math. vii. 17 ; Diog. ne pro vero falsa subrepant.
40. Seari^. Math. vii. 23 oxupuTiKov :

^ The chief divisions of the Se ijvai tt)s diavoias rhv SioAe/c-


logic of the Stoics (Siog. 42, TiKhv tSttov ; Pyrrh. ii. 247 : M
46) are considered important T71V Texvvv tV ^laKeKTiK^v tfyaaiy
for special purposes. The doc- &pfi7jKei/at el SiaKeKTiKol (the
trine irepl Kav6vu>v Itai KpiTr)piiim Stoics), oiix airXitiS virep rod
is of use, helping us to truth, yvuvai ri ix rivos (Tvydyerat,
by making us examine our aWci irpoTiyoufievws imhp rod St*

notions ipmhv, because it led


; &Tro5eiKTtKuv \6yaiv ra cLKfiOTJ Kol
to the knowledge of things by- rk il'euSij Kpiutiv i-wiffTaffBat,
means of conceptions ; SiaKsx- This may he seen in Sext.
'

rmii (which includes the whole Pyrrh. ii. 134-203, 229 Math, ;

of formal logic), because it pro- viii. 300 as well as from the


;

duced airprniTaaia ( = iiruTT'liixii catalogue of the writings of


Tov irdre Se? ffvyKaTaTideffBai Chrysippus in Diogenes.
Ka\ fiii), avetKaidrris (= lirxi'pi'

F
;

66 THE STOICS.

Chap. devoted to the subject;' hence, the Stoics would


IV.
never allow, in dispute with the Peripatetics, that
logic was only an instrument, and not a part of phi-
losophy. To later writers that stiff logical mode of

description, regardless of all beauty of language,


appeared to be a peculiarity of the Stoic school,^ and
hence that school was characteristically known as
the School of the Eeasoners.^ , Frequent instances
will be found hereafter of the Stoic preference for

dry argument and formal logic ;


^ in Chrysippus this
fondness degenerated to a dry formalism devoid of
taste/
C. Divi- The foregoing remarks have already established
sions of
the three main divisions of philosophy ^ which were
pMloio-
phy. universally acknowledged by the Stoics^ Logic,
The only part whicli incurs
' AiaXeicTiKoJ is their ordinary
the blame of Chrysippus (in name. It is also found in
Plut. Sto. Rep. 10, 1) is the Plut. Qu. Plat. X. 1, 2, p. 1008.
sceptical logic, which leaves Cio. Top. 2, 6 Fin. iv. 3, 6.
;

contradictions unsolved tois : * After the example of the

ii-^vyhp inox^v ^yoviri Trepl ndvTuv Megarians, the Stoics were in


iiri^dWet, tpyjtrl, tovto jroietv, Kal the habit of couching their
ffvvepydv iffri irphs h fioiiKovTat
arguments in the form of a
Tois 5' initrT'fiiJ.riv evepya^ofieyois, question. Hence the terms
Kaff %v dfw\oyovn4vas Pia(r6fi,e8a \6yov epwTav (ZHog. vii. 186),
Tcfe evavria trrotx^iovv. interrogatio {Sen. Ep. 82, 9
' Cic. Parad. Prooem. : Cato 85, 1 87, 11), interrogatiuTunila
;

autem perfectus mea sententia {Oio.), which are employed


Stoicus . in ea est hjeresi,
. . even when their arguments
quje nullum sequitur florem were not in this form.
orationis neque dilatat argu- = See p. 48, 1.

mentum minutis interroga-


: " Called
nepri, according to
tiunculis, quasi punctis, quod JHog. 39 ailso rdTroi, tlfS?), yhi).
proposuit efficit. Cic. Fin. iv. 3, ' Diog.
39 Tpi/nepTJ </>airi>'
:

7 Pungunt quasi aculeis inter-


: eli/ai rhy KarcL tpiKoffo^iai/ \6yov'
rogatiuncuUs angustis, quibus civaL yhp auTow rh juev ti (pvaiKhVy
etiam qui assentiuntur nihil rh Sg ^BLKbv. rb 5h XoyiiiSv. oSra
commutantur animo. See also Se TrpuTos Siei\c Ziivav S KiTicfis
Diog. vii. 18, 20. ivTiji TTcpl \6yov Koi X.pianriros if
" In Sextus Bmpirious, r^ a' irepi \6yov Kal iv rfj a'
DIVISIONS OF PHILOSOPHY. 67

Natural Science, and Ethics. As regards the relative Chap.


worth and sequence of these divisions, very opposite '

views may be deduced from the principles of the (l) Three

Stoic teaching. There can be no doubt, and, indeed, sion.

all are agreed in allowing, that logic was subservient


to the other two branches of science, being only an
outpost of the system. If therefore in arranging
the parts the advance is from the less important to
the more important, logic will hold the first place.
It will occupy the last place if the opposite mode of
procedure is followed. But the relation existing
between ethics and natural science is an open ques-
tion. On the one hand, ethics appears to be the
higher science, the crowning point of the system, the
subject towards which the whole philosophical
activity of the school was directed ; was not phi-
for
losophy practical knowledge ? and was not its object
to lead to virtue and happiness ? On the other hand,
virtue and the destiny of man consist in subordina-
tion to the laws of nature, which it is the province of
science to investigate. Has not, therefore, natiu-al
science the higher object ? Does it not lay down the
universal laws which in ethics are applied to man ?
Does not, therefore, to it, in the graduated scale of
sciences, belong the higher rank ?
In attempting to harmonise these opposite consi-
derations, the Stoics did not always succeed. At one
Tav koi 'hTro\\6Sapos 6
(pvaiKoiv, Ep. 89, 9 14. The six divi-
;

'E^iWos iv rip irfiiTif -rHv eis -rk sions enumerated by Cleanthes


S/r/iia.Ta fiaayaiySiv, KuX EiSpofios (Siog. il)
Dialectic, Rhetoric,
fV Tp Tjfliicp (TTotxeiiicf', Koi ^10- Ethics, Politics, Physics, Theo-
yhris i BafivXdivios, kclI nocreiSci-
logy (^Diog. 41) are easily re-
vios. Seast. Math. vii. 16. Sen. ducible to three.
F 2
;

68 THE STOICS.

Chap. time natural science is preferred to ethics, at another


ly.
time ethics to natural science,' in the enumeration
(2) Rela- of the several branches of philosophy. In the com-
tive im-
pmiance parisons by means of which their relations to each
of each other were explained,^ ethics appears at one time,
part.
at another time natural science, to be the aim and
soul of the whole system. Different views were even
entertained in reference to the order to be followed
' 40, the
According to Biog. logical part may form the con-
first place was assigned to clusion, only refers to the order
logic, the second to Science, in which they ought to be
the third to Ethics, by Zeno, taught.
Chrysippus, Archedenms, Bu- ' In Biog. 39 Sext. Math,
;

demus, and others. The same vii. 17 Philo, Mut. Nom. p. 105S,
;

order, but inverted, is found in B. Hosch. (589 M) ; De Agricul.


Diogenes of Ptolemais, and in 189, D (302), philosophy is

Seneca, Ep. 89, 9. The latter, compared to an orchard. Logic


however, observes (Nat. Qu. answering to the fence, Science
Prol. 1) that the difference be- to the trees. Ethics to the fruit
tween that part of philosophy so that Ethics is the end and
which treats about God, and object of the whole. Philo-
that which treats about man, sophy is also compared to a
is as great as the difference fortified town, in which the
between philosophy and other walls are represented by Logic,
departments, or even as between but in which the position of the
God and man. On the other other two is not clear ; to an
hand, ApoUodorus places Ethics egg. Logic being the shell, andj
in the middle, as also Cleanthes according to Sextus, Science
does,andlikewise Pansetius and being the white and Ethics the
Posidonius, if it is certain that yolk, but the reverse according
they began with science. This to Diogenes. Dissatisfied with
appears, however, only to have this comparison, Posidonius pre-
reference to their order in dis- ferred to compare philosophy
cussion (see Sext. Math. vii. 22, to a living creature, in which
probably on the authority of Logic constituted the bones
Posidonius.) A few {Biog. 40) and muscles, Science the flesh
asserted that the parts could and blood, and Ethics the soul.
be so little separated, that they But Diogenes has another ver-
jnust be always treated at the sion of this simile, according
same time. The statement of to which Science represents the
Chrysippus (in Pint. Sto. Eep. soul and Ritter, iii. 432, con-
;

9, 1), that Logic must come siders the version of Diogenes


first, and be followed by Ethics to be the older of the two.
and Science, so that the theo-
;

I)IVISIO:S OF PHILOSOPHY. 69

iu teaching these sciences.' In describing the Stoic Chap.


system, preference will be here given to that arrange-
ment which begins with logic and goes on to natural
science, ending with ethics ; not only because that
arrangement has among its supporters the oldest and
most distinguished adherents of the Stoic School,
but far more because in this way the internal relation
of the three parts to each other can be most clearly
brought out. For, granting that, in many essential
respects, natural science is modified by ethical
considerations ; still, in the development of the
system, the chief results of science are used as
principles on which ethical doctrines are founded
and logic, although introduced later than the other
two branches of study, is the instrument by means of
which they are put into scientific shape. If the
opportunity were afforded of tracing the rise of the
Stoic teaching in the mind of its founder, it would
probably be possible to show how the physical and
logical parts of the system gradually gathered about
the original kernel of ethics. But knowing Stoicism
only as we do from the intellectual development which
it attained after the time of Chrysippus, it will be
enough, in analysing the form which it then assumed,
to proceed from without to within, and to advance
from logic through natural science to ethics. When
this has been done it will be time to attempt to re-
trace our steps backwards, and to explain how, from
the ethical tone of Stoicism, its peculiar speculative
tenets may be deduced.
> See Sext. Pyirh. ii. 13.
;:

70 THE STOICS.

CHAPTER V.

LOGIC OF THE STOICS.

Chap. Under the head of Logic, in the Stoic use of the


^- number
term after the time of Chrysippus, a of
A. Oeneral intellectual inquiries were included which would
remar s.
^^^ ^^^ -^^ considered to belong to philosophy at
of logic. all. One common element, however, characterised
them all they all referred to the formal conditions
of thought and expression. Logic was primarily
divided into two parts, sharply marked off from each
other, roughly described as the art of speaking con-
tinuously and the art of conversing the former
being known as Ehetoric, the latter as Dialectic'
To these two parts was added, as a third part, the

41 : rh Se \oyiKhv cuit vocari. Cic. Fin. ii. 6, 17


'Hepos ^irlv ivioi els Sio Siaipu<T0ai Orat. 32, 113. Qidntil. Inst. ii.
iTTKTT'fiii.as, ets pr)ropMiiv KalSitt\eK- 20,7. According to these pas-
TtK^iv . . tI\v Tf lit\ropu^v iiruTT'l)- sages, Khetorio was by Zens
firiv oiffav toS ej Ae'^Eii' TTcpl tUv compared to the palm of the
4y Sie^6Stf \6yav ko! tV SioAekti- hand, and Dialectic to the fist
Kiji'ToBopflSjSiaXe'yeirflai Treplrwy quod latins loquerentur rhe-
v sponiicrei Koi airoKpiffei \6yui>. tores, dialectic! antem com-
Sen. Bp. 89, 17 Superest ut ra-
: pressius. The Stoics agree
tionalem partem philosophise with Aristotle in calling rhe-
dividam : omnis oratio aut con- toric avriffrpotpos rp SioXeicTiicJ
tinnaestantinterrespondentem {Sopl in Hermog. v. 15, Walz.).
et interrogantem discissa hanc ; See Prantl, Gesch. der Log. i.
SibAe'ctikJ)!', illam ^TjTopi/tV pla- 413.
: : :

STOIC LOGIC. 71

doctrine of a standard of truth, or the theory of know- Chap.


V.
ledge ; and, according to some authorities,^ a fourth
part, consisting of inquiries into the formation of
conceptions. By others, these inquiries were re-
garded as the third main division, the theory of
knowledge being included under dialectic.^ By rhe-

' IHog. 41 Some divide


: Spaiv rav tov affreiov ^'. Spay Twy
logic into rhetoric and dialectic TQv {pa{>\ov j8'. Spojy Twy avap.i<roiv
Tivej Se KoX els Th bpiKhv elSos, rb ; besides the further treatises
Trepl Kav6vwv koX KptT7]pi(av' eittot nepl ray oiiK opdws To'is Spoti aVTi-
Se rh dptKhv trepiaipovo'l. (We T^eyofjL^paiy ^. HiBaya els Toifs
have no reason to read as- Men- Spovs 0. The treatise irepX elSuv
age does TreptSiaipoufft, or to con- Kal ysvav may also be included
jecture, as Meibom and Mcolai, here ;
perhaps also that vepl tSk
De Log. Chrys., Lib. 23, do, irapa- KarTiyopTjfJLtiTQiVTrpbs M7]rp6Scopoy /.
SioipoSffi.) According to this Trphs UciffvXoy irepl KaTriyoprtfidTay
passage, SpiKhy must be iden- 8',Diog. 191.
tical with the doctrine of a ^ No description of their sys-

criterimn. In a subsequent tem can dispense with this fun-


passage, however, the two are damental inquiry, which had
distinguished ; the doctrine of been already instituted by Zeno.
a criterimn is said to be useful It appears, however, to have
for the discovery of truth Kal : been treated by several writers
rh dpiKhtf 56 6pLoias irphs iiriyvwaiy as a branch of dialectic. SiogAZ
Bih yhp r<av evvoLoav
TTJs a\-r]0eias- says that the branch of dialectic
TO Trpdyfiara Kafi^dveral. We which treats of ai]ii.my6p.iva, may
may therefore suppose that in be divided 6?s re tov wepl rSov ipav-
the passage first quoted the TOffiSiv riiToy Kal Tuy iic roiraiv
words should be rh dpiKhv eiSos itpuTTaiifyav KeKTUV. (Seelficoloi
Kal rh irepl Kavoyay, k.t.X, In p. 23.) Compare with this the
this case, we may understand words of Diodes, in Diog. 49
by Spuchf not only the theory of ctp^crtet Tois ^rw'iKois irepl tpayra-

definition a theory to which ffias Kal aia6i}(reciis Trpor&TTety
Aristotle devoted a separate \6yoy, Ka96rL t6 npiriipioy ^ 7j
section at the end of his Ana- dX^Qeiu Twy irpayfidray yiydnXKe-
lytics (Anal. Post, ii.)but be- Tat, Karh yevos tpayraffla 4(rrl not
sides a theoretical disquisition Ka66Ti 6 irepl ffvyKaraQeffews Kal
on the formation of definitions, i irepl KaTa\i]^eais Kal voiiireus
a, collection of definitions of \6yos irpodyojv rcay &Way ovK Sl/ew
various objects. Such collec- r^ay-raeias ffvylffraTai. Accord-
tions are found in the treatises ing to this passage, the branch
of Chrysippus (Diocf. 199, 189) of dialectic which treated of
TreplTwv '6pav ^'. ^piav SiaKeKTiKCov included the theory of
<j>ayTa(rla

ffr'. *6puv rwv Karct yevos C' Spwi' knowledge. Diog. 43, Peter-
Tuf Kara rSts &\Kas re^vas a^ . sen's conjecture is singular
;

72 THE STOICS.

Chap. toric, however, little else was meant but a collection


V.
of artificial rules, without philosophical worth ; ' and
dialectic was in great measure occupied with in-

quiries referring only to precision of expression. ,

Dialectic was defined to be the science or art of


speaking well ;
^ and since speaking well consists in
saying what is becoming and true,' dialectic is used

(Phil. Chrys. Fund. p. 25) that 28, 1. do. Mn. iv. 3, 7, ob-
the theory of knowledge may serves, in reference to the Stoic
have been nndeirstood by Chry- rhetoric, and in particular to
sippas under the name rhetoric. that of Chrysippus, that such
' Our information on this was its nature that si quis ob-
head is very small. In the mutescere concupierit, nihil
words ^jjTopi/cj) verba curat et
: aliud legere debeat that it
sensus et ordinem, a division of dealt in nothing but words,
rhetoric is implied by Seneca, being withal scanty in expres-
little differing, except in the sions, and confined to subtleties.
position of the chief parts, from This neglect of the truly rhe-
that of Aristotle. A fourth torical element appears already
part is added to the three others in the quotations from Plut.

by Diog. 43 on Delivery Sto. Rep. 28, 2. "We have not
elpai 5' OUT7JS r^v ^laip^ffiv efs re the slightest reason to complain,
r^v evpeffiv Kol eis r^v tppdfrtj/, KaX as Prantl does, p. 413, of the
els Tti^tv Kol eU t^v im6Kpiinv. purely rhetorical value of dia-
Diogenes also claims for the lectic with the Stoics.
Stoics the Aristotelian distinc- 2 See p. 70, 1, Alex. Aphr.Top.

tion between three ways of 3 Oi p-iv &7rb t^s 'Zroas dpi^6^evoi


;

speaking a-viiPovheuriKhs, Stxa-


ftKhs, ^yKojfiiaiTTiKds and four \4yfiv ipi^ovTai, rh Si eS \4yeii'
parts in a speech irpooiijuov,
: 4v r(p iKrjBrj Koi irpotrfiKovra Aeyciy
nphs robs avriSiKovSf
Sffiyriffis, Tct elvai ri64fifvoi, rovTO Se XSiop
iirl\oyos. Definitions of Stiiyniris Tjyoifievoi Tov (l>i\o(r6(lioVj Kara
and 7ropcSei7|Ua are given from Trjs TeAcMTciTijs <j)i\o(ro^ias cl>4pou-
Zeno by the anonymous author ffiv avrh KaX dik toDto fi6yos h
in Spengel, Rhet. Gr. i. 434, 23 <t>i\6(ro(l>os kut' avroiis Sia\eKTtK6s.
447, 11. The same author {IHd. Aristotle had used the term
454, 4) says that, according to dialectic in another sense, but
Chrysippus, the iirt\oyos must with Plato it expressed the
be fiovofiipiis. The Stoic defini- mode of procedure peculiar to
tion of rhetoric has been already a philosopher.
given, p, 70, 1. Another ' See Anon.
Prolegg. ad Her-
Tex^l Tfpi K6(rixov KoL (lpr)iJ.4vov mog. Rhet. Gr. vii. 8, W. oi
\6yov jd^iv
is attributed to ZtuikoI Sk rh ei Keyetv l\e7o;' t6
;

Chrysippus by Pint. Sto. Bep. oKtjdvi \4yeiv.


STOIC LOGIC. 73

to express the knowledge of what is true or false, or Chap.


'

what is neither one nor the other,' correctness of


expression being considered inseparable from correct-
ness of thought. Words and thoughts are, according (2) Words
to this view, the very same things regarded under fji^igj^fg
different aspects. The same idea (\6yos), which is
a thought as long as it resides within the breast, is

a word as soon as it comes forth.^ Accordingly, dia-


lectic consists of two main divisions, treating respec-
tively of utterance and the thing uttered, thoughts
and words.^ Both divisions, again, have several sub-
' Diog. 4:2 SSev Koi oStus
; &ydpaiiroi oux^ Ttp irpoipopLK^ K6y(p
auT^c [t^v SiaA.6/CTi/c^w] Spl^ovrai, Sia<p4pei tS)V ^\6yay ^4'^v , . .

aWh Ttt) fvSiadeTtp. The Stoics


oiSerepasv. (The same, p. 62, alone can be meant by the veti-
quoted from Posidonius, and in Tpoi in I7ieo. Srmjrn. Mus. c.
Sext. Math. xi. 187, and Suid. 18, whoare contrasted with the
Aio\eKTiK'6.) ouSeTepio)/ being pro- Peripatetics for using the terms
bably used, because dialectic \6yos iySidOsTos and TrpocpoptKds.
deals not only with judgments, They are also referred to by
but with conceptions and inter- Plut. C. Prin. Phil. 2, 1, p.777 :

rogations. Conf. Diog. 68. Th Se \4yeiy, 8ti Si5o \6yoL elirly.


^ This is the meaning of the d fiey iySiaQsrhs, riyefidyos 'EpjuoC
Stoic distinction between \6yos Swpoy, 6 y iy vpotpopa^ SioLKTOpos
ivSidBsTos and TrpotpoptKhs^ a dis- Kal opyayiKhs e(t}\6v i(Trt. The
tinction subsequently employed double form of Hermes is ex-
by Philo and the Fathers, and plained by Ileraclitus as refer-
really identical with that of ring to the twofold \6yos
Aristotle (Anal. Post. i. 10, 76 b, 'Ep/ii)s 'X.86yios representing \6yoy

24) ov irphs rhv e^at K6yoVf aWh


: iySidSeray, and the heavenly
irphs Thy iv T^ ^v^f. On this dis- Hermes(SicKTopor) representing
tinction see HeracUt. AUeg. the Trpo^opM6y. The distinction
Hom. c. 72, p. 142 : hmKovs S passed from the Stoics to others,
\6yos T0V7UV 5' ot <f}tK6<ro(poi (the
' like Pint. Solert. An. 19, 1, p.
Stoics are meant) t))i' jnev ivSiiBe- 973 ; Galen, Protrept. i. 1.
Tov KaKovcri, Thy Se irpo^opiKdv. ' IHog. 43 r^y Sia\K7iK^v
;

6fxev oZv Twy ^ySoy Koyifffiiiov iffTty Siaipe7ff6ai eXs re Thy irepl Twy ffrj-
4^i,yye\os, d S' iwh Tois dTepyois liaiyoiiivwv koX t^s ^wvtjs Td-jroy.
KofleTjPKTai. ^affl Se Toirtf xpri- Ibid. 62 : Tvyx^vei 5" oKti;, is i
<r9oi Kol ri diloy. Sext. Math, XpiifftTrnis fpv'^t, ircpl ffTjfjLaiyoyra

viii. 275 (conf. Pyrrh. i. 76) : Kol ffiiiJ.aiy6iieya. Seneca 1. c. Sia- :

ot Si AoynaTiKoX . . (paaiv '6ti


. KiKTiKl) in duas partes dividitur.
74 THE STOICS.

Chap. divisions,' which are only imperfectly known to us.^


V.
Under the science of utterance, which was generally
placed before the science of things uttered,^ they in-
cluded, not only instruction as to sounds and speech,
but also the theories of poetry and music, these arts
being ranked under the head of the voice and of
sound on purely external considerations/ What
is known to us of the teaching of the Stoics on these
subjects, consisting, as it does, of a mass of definitions,
differences, and divisions, has so little philosophical
value, that it need not detain our attention longer.*

in verba et significationes, i.e. viii. 11, to the parts of logic is


in res, quEe dicuntur, et voca- unhappy. Nicolai (De Logic>
tula, quibus dicuntur. The Chrys. Lib. 21) has acted with
distinction between rh rrniaivov greater caution, but even much
and rii ariiiiuv6ii,tvov, to which of what he says is doubtful.
Ti Tv^x^'"*" (tlifi '^62'1 object) 3 mofj. 55.

must be added as a third, will * Diog, a elvai 8e rris 8ia-


:

.be hereafter discussed in ano- KeKTiKTJs iSiov 't6-kov Ka\ T^v irpoei-
ther place. A much narrower pjifi^poy trepl aiiTTis ttjs (fiavris, 4v
conception of dialectic, and ^ SeiKVurat tj ^yyp^fifiaros tpwy}!
more nearly approaching to Kol rtpa ra roii h6yov fi^prty KaX
that of the Peripatetics, is to be Trept tTO\omifffiov Kal fiap^aplfffiov
found in the definition given Kal iroiTHidrtav KoX afjupi^oMay /cat

by Sext. Pyrrh. ii. 213. The irepl 4p.fie\ovs fpavTJs Kal Trepl fxov-
division there given is also CLKris Kal -jrepl '6puv Kord rivas
found in the Platonist 4 WwOTa, KoL Siaipeireuv Kal \4^scej/. The-
Isag. c. 3, as Fabricius pointed theory of the
determination
out. It appears, therefore, not and division of conceptions
to belong to the Stoic School, occupies such an important
but, at most, to a few of its place in the section irepl <paiyfis,
later members. that we might feel disposed to
Seneca continues: Ingens
'
suppose some mistake in the
deinde sequitur utriusque di- authority. Still from the later
,

visio, without, however, giving authorities, pp. 60-62, it is seen


it. that by many it is usually so
' There is much which is represented.
open to doubt in Petersen's ' Further particulars may be

attempt (Phil. Chrys. Fund. obtained in Schmidt's Stoicorum


221) to settle these divisions. Grammatica (Halle, 1839) ;

At the very beginning, his re- LerscTi, Sprachphilosophie der


ferring the words of Sext. Math. Alten; Steinthal, Gesch. dei
;;

THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE. 75

Two parts only of the Stoic logic possess for us any


real interest the theory of knowledge, and that part
V.

of dialectic which treats of ideas, and which in the


main agrees with our formal logic.
The Stoic theory of knowledge turns about the B. Tlieory
of liTwrn-
inquiry for a criterion or standard by which what is
ledge.
true in our notions may be distinguished from what (1) Gene-
is false. Since every kind of knowledge, no matter ral clmr-
aoter of
what be its object, must be tested by this standard, this
theory.
it follows that the standard cannot be sought in the

Sprachwissenschaft, i. 265-363 (Diog. 57) ; the \6yos has 5 parts,


Nicolai, De Log. Chrys. Lib. 31. called (TToixf'o by Chrysippus
This part of dialectic began tipofxa, irpoffrtyopia, fiVH-'^y trrSfSea''
with, inquiries into the voice jios, UpOpov to which Antipater
and speech. Voice is defined added the iietrdrTis, or adverb
to be sound and speech, to be {Diog. 57 ; Galen, De Hippoerat.
air in motion, or something et Plat. viii. 3 ; Lersch, ii. 28 ;

bearable A^p vfir\r}yfi.4vos % rh SteinthM, 29l). Words were
tSiov aicrdriThi' aKorjs ; the human not formed by caprice, but cer-
voice as ^vapdpos koL a-Kh didyoias tain peculiarities of things were
4icniixiroii.ev% distingtiished
is imitated in the chief sounds
from the sounds of other ani- of which they are composed.
mals, which are aiip vwh Sp/iris These peculiarities can there-
veTrXryyiiivos {Diog. 55 ; Simpl. fore be discovered by etymolo-
Phys. 97; Sext. Math. vi. 39; gical analysis ( Orig. u. Cels. i.
Gell. N. A. vi. 15, 6). That the 24 ; Aii^gustin. Dialect, c. 6 ;
voice is something material is 0pp. T. L Ap. 17, c). Chry-
proved in various ways {Diog. sippus, however, observes (in
55 ; Phtt. Plac. iv. 20, 2 ; Galen, Varro, L. Lat. ix. 1) that the
Hist. Phil. 27). The voice, in same things bear different
as far as it is ivapBpos, or com- names, and vice vers^, and (in
posed of letters, is called Ki^is ; Gell. N. A. xi. 12, 1) that every
in as far as it expresses certain word has several meanings.
notions, it is Xiyos (JJiog. 56 See i^mpl Cat. 8, C- Five ad-
Sext. Math. i. 155). A
peculiar vantages and two disadvantages
national mode of expression of speech are enumerated Diog.
(Ac'fis Kex'P7M^'") ^OviKus re /tol 59; Sext. Mat. i. 210; and
'EWrji'iKwj il Ae'^is jroToirj)) was poetry (Diog. 60), various kinds
called Si<i\eKTOs {Siog. 56). The of amphibolia {Diog. 62 Galen, ;

elements of a4 are the 24 De Soph. P. Diet. c. 4), the for-


letters, divided into 7 (jmvTietna, mation of conceptions, and divi-
6 i<pava, and 11 semivowels sion, are treated of.
C THE STOICS.

Chap, subject-matter of our notions, but, on the contrary,


^''
in their form. The inquiry after a standard becomes
therefore identical with another the inquiry as to
what kind of notions supply a knowledge that may
be depended upon, or what activity of the power of
forming conceptions carries in itself a pledge of its
own truth. It is impossible to answer these ques-
tions without investigating the origin, the various
kinds, and the value and importance of our notions.
Hence the problem proposed to the Stoics is reduced
to seeking by an analysis of our notions to obtain a
universally valid standard by which their truth may
be tested.
Whether this inquiry was pursued by the older
Stoics in all its comprehensiveness is a point on

which we have no information. Boethus, whose


views on this subject were attacked by Chrysippus,
had assumed the existence of several standards, such
as Eeason, Perception, Desire, Knowledge. Others,
in the vaguest manner, had spoken of Eight Eeason
{opOo^ Tii^yos) as being the standard of truth.' Hence
it may be inferred that before the time of Chrysippus
the Stoics had no distinctly developed theory of
knowledge. Nevertheless there are expressions of
Zeno and Cleanthes still extant which prove that the
essential parts of the later theory were already held
by these philosophers,' although it is no doubt true

'
IKoff. vii. 54. theory of knowledge from
2 The statements of Zeno general principles respecting
and Cleanthes, for instance, in notions.They therefore started
reference to (pavTcuria, prove from the data supplied by the
that these Stoics deduced their senses. A passage in Zeno, ex-
;

THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE. 77

that it first received that scientific form in which Chap.


alone it is known to us at the hands of Chrysippus.
'

The' character of this theory of knowledge appears (2) Prami-


mainly in three particulars: (1) In the importance i^'t^'^"'*^
attached by the Stoics to the impressions of the t^teori/ of
^^'
senses. This feature they inherited from the Cynics '" "

and shared with the Epicureans. (2) In the exalta-


tion of expression into a conception a trait dis-
tinguishing this from either of the two other
contemporary schools. (3) In the practical turn
given to the question of a criterion or standard of
truth. We proceed to the expansion of this theory
in detail.
The origin of all perceptions {(pavTaaiai) may be (a) Per-

referred to the action of some object ((J3avra<7rov) on 'tkeresiitt


the soul,' the soul at birth resembling a blank page, ofimpres-
and only receiving definite features by experience mitlumt.
from without.* By the elder Stoics, this action of
plaining the relations of vari- ^aVTaaTUc6v, because no (pavra-
ous forms of knowledge, shows ffrhv corresponds to (payTa(rriK6v

that even Zeno required pro- it is Sidxevos eAKvcr/ihs, TrdBos iv


gress to be from perception to t^ i^u^p "' ohS^vhs tpavjairTov
conception and knowledge, and yiv6ii,vov
and the object of such
that he distinguished these an empty perception is a ^de-
states only by the varying racr/ia. Compare also Sext.
strength of conviction which Math. vii. 2il : Sidxeyos eXKvcrfihs
they produced. is called (pavraa-ia rcov 4v ^fxtv
' Phit. Plac. iv. 12. Biog. iraBav. Impressions wholly un-
vii. 50. Hemes. Nat. Horn. 76. founded, which give the im-
*oi/Tao-i'a is iriifloj h
rp 'i/vxi 1016- pression of being actual per-
fifvov^ iyBeiKvinevov savrS re Kol ceptions, are called by Diot).
rh in the same way,
irCT-oiT)K({s, 51,^/i(/)io'eisai<ra>'ela7r!)u7ropxii>'-

it added, that light shows


is -rav yivd/ievat. In a wider sense,
other things as well as itself (pavraala means any kind of
(pavraffrhv is rh iroiovy rijv (pay- notion.
rafflav, and therefore tray 8 ti * P&i.Plac. iv. 11: oiSnoiKot
tiv SiyrtTOt Ktveiy rije '('"X^"- <pa(Tiy 8toc yeyyrid^ 6 &y9panros
iayraaia is distinguished from Ix^i rh riyefioyixhy fiepos rris tfivxfis

THE STOICS.

Chap. objects on the soul was regarded as grossly material,


V.
Zeno defining a perception to be an impression
{jvnraxns) made on the and Cleanthes takingsoul,'

this definition so literally as to compare the impres-


sion on the soul to the impression made by a seal on
wax.^ Being himself a very exact pupil of Zeno's,
Cleanthes probably rendered the views of Zeno cor-
rectly in this comparison. The difficulties of this

view were recognised by Chrysippus, who accordingly


defined a perception to be the change {sTspoLaa-ii)
produced on the soul by an object, or, more accu-
rately, the change produced thereby in the ruling part
of the soul ; ^ and whereas his predecessors had only
Sxrirep x^^P'^VS (^x^P'^V^ ^^ Galen, many different forms, if it had
H. Phil. 24, vol. xix. reads), to retain different notions at
IvepyStv els airoypou^v, ets touto the same time avrhs ovv r^v
pXav eKatTTTiV rwv evyoiwp evoTro- TiiToiaLv eiprtfrdai inrb rod Z'fivoti'os

7p(^Tai TrpoTOS Se 6 ttjs aTroypa- vtrevdei avrl ttjs erepot^ffeais,


</)7Js TpSiros d Stii. Tw^ cutrd-ficreav. ofitrre elvat roiovToi' rhv \6yov'
See p. 79, 2, Orig. o. Cels. vii. 37, ^avraffia ioTlv ^Tepoiteffis ^vxvs.
720, b, says that they taught Objection had, however, been
aiffd'fio'et KaTa\a/M^civ(T6at Tct Ko- raised to this definition, on the
Ta\afi^av6^va Koi iraffav KardKr]^ ground that not every change
of the soul gives rise to a per-
' Plut. Comm. Not. 47: ^av- ception, and therefore the
ratrla riiraais iv ^XV- '^^^ Stoics had defined a perception
same in Diog. vii. 45 and 50. more accurately {payraala iarl
:

That this was also the view of T^nraffis ev ^vxo ^s tiv 4y ^"XPj
Diogenes appears from what which was equivalent to saying
follows. <pavra(rla iffrlif erepoiutris iv Tyye-
2 Scant. Math. vii. ,
228 : /jLoviK^ or else in Zeno's de-
KXtv9r;s fiiv "yhp ^Kovire rijv finition of (fiavTairla as TiJTroxns
Tivaxriv KOToi elffox'h'' Te Ka\ iv ^vxp they had taken ^vx^ in
a restricted sense for rh fiyefiovi-
Kliov yivo^4v7}y tov KTipov Tiiraa'tv. Kiv, which really comes to the
Conf. JUd. 372 viii. 400.
vii. ; same thing. Even this defi-
' Sext. vii. 229, continues : nition had, however, been found
XptJfftTTTros 5^ &TOTrov TjyeiTO rb too wide, and hence eTepolaxns
toioCtok
according to this was limited to mean change in
view, it would be necessary for feeling (eTepofwcis Karct trelffiv).
the soul to receive at once But the definition is still too
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE. 79

considered ensible things to be objects, he included Chap.


'

among objects conditions and activities of the


mind.i The mode, however, in which the change
was produced in the soul did not further engage his
attention.
It follows, as a necessary corollary from this view, (j) Con-

that the Stoics regarded sensation as the only source "t^^^


of all our perceptions the soul is a blank leaf, sen- fromper-
:

itwns.
sation is the hand which fills it with writing. But
this is not all. Perceptions give rise to memory,
repeated acts of memory to experience.^ and con-
clusions based on experience suggest conceptions
wjiich go beyond the sphere of direct sensation.
These conclusionsrest either upon the comparison, or
upon actual combination of perceptions, or else upon

wide, as Sextus already re- kclkiuv ouSe ji6vov x^P^s ^al euep-
marked for a perception is
; yetrtuv koL &\K(tiv ttoKKiov Karop-
not the only feeling of change a\Kk koI (ppovfiffeus Koi
dd>(rea>v,
in the soul. A more accurate avdpeta^ koI Tutv \onrmv aperup.
definition has already been This passage must not he under-
quoted, 77, 1. The statements stood to mean that the oonoep-
in Sext. Math. vii. 372 ; viii. tions of good and evil, as such,
400; Diog. vii. 45 and 50; are objects of sensation (^iter,
Alex. Aplvro. De Anim. 135, b ;
iii. 558). The only objects of
Boeth. De Interpret, ii. 292 that kind are indioidual moral
(Sohol. in Arist. 100), are in states and activities. The
agreement with the above re- general conceptions derived
marks. from them are, according to
'Chrys. in Plut. Sto. Rep. the Stoic theory of knowledge,
19, 8ti lifv yap alffSriTd eVri
2 : only obtained by a process of
rayadh Kol rci /caKO, koi roirois abstraction.
^Kiroiet \ey6tv' oii ycip ^6vov rh ^ P^wi. Plac. iv. 11, 2 attrOa-
:

tABij iarXv oiirSrjT^ ahv Tois vd/aevoi yap Tims olov AevhoD
eifSfffii', olov Kiwn ical <p6^ot Kol aTre\66vTos avTov fivtifiriv exotiirii',
rh irapavKiiaia, aWk ko! rKotttis 'irav Se bfmeiSets iroAA.ai imrjiiai
Kol iioix^ias leal twv ifioitnv effriv ytvwvrai -riTt (paffiv ^X^'" ^M'^''

tuffSeffBai Koi Ka66\ov iujypoaivris


piav.

naX SciXios Kol dXKwv ouK oKiyuv


: : ,

80 TEE STOICS.

Chap. analogy;' some add, upon transposition and contrast.^


V.
The formation of conceptions by means of these
agencies sometimes takes place methodically and
artificially, at other times naturally and spontane-
(a) Koival ously.' In the latter way are formed the primary

formed conceptions, -Tj-poXijyp'Sis or Koival svvoiai, which were


naturally. regarded by the Stoics as the natural types of truth
and virtue, and as the distinctive possession of ra-
tional beings.* To judge by many expressions, it

' Diog. vii. 52 ^ Se KaTcJAijil/is


: Sext. (Math. iii. 40 ix. 393) ;

ylverai Kar' avro^js aiadijtrei fjtev, also agrees with the Stoic doc-
usKevKau Koi fiehdycai/ Kal Tpaxeoii/ trine of the origin of con-
Kol \eiwv '
K^ytf 5e t&v Si' oiroSef- captions, in saying that all our
^eus txvvayofi^vav, oStnrep rh Beohs ideas arise either kot' ifxTrfKatnti
eTvai Kal irpovos'iv roirovs Ttev ' ruv ivapymv or koto; t)/v oirb tuv
yap voov^4l/av rh flhy Karct irept' iyapyov fifT&$a<nv (cf. Diog. vii.
Trraxriv (immediate contact) 53), and in the latter case
ej/o'fi67], Tct Se Kaff 6fjiOi6r7jTa, rk either by comparison, or actual
Se kvaXoyiav, to
/car' Se Kara combination, or analogy.
fierddeiTtv, T^ he /caret irvi/Oeaii/, ^ Diog. 1. c. Compare the
TO. 5e Kar' ^vavriatfftv pourai, passage quoted from Seneca,
. . .

Se Kal Kara fierii^acrit' (transition* 81,2^


'^
from the sensuous to the super- PTmt. Plac. iv. 11 twc S' :

sensuous) riva, i)S TO XeKTa Kal 6 ivvoiSav al lihv <pv(nKal ylrnvrai


T(iTros. Oic. Acad. i. 11, 42 Kara rovs tpr}fx4t'ovs rp6'irovs (ac-
Comprehensio [ = KaTd\ri\jiis'] cording to the context, this
facta sensibus at vera illi must mean by memory and
[Zenoni] et fldelis videbatur experience), but perhaps the
;

non quod omnia, qua2 assent in author of the placita has been, '

re, comprehenderet, sed quia careless in his extracts here,


nihil quod cadere in earn posset KoX aveirtrexoiirois al 8" fjSri 5i'

relinqueret, quodque natura Tifierepas Kal eVlfie-


SlSair/caAfer
quasi normam scientise et prin- Aeias auTOi fihy oZv Evvoiai Ka-_
cipium sui dedisset, unde postea Xovvrai ix.6vai, eKuvai, Se Kol
notiones rerum in animis im- irpok-fitj/fis. Diog. vii. 51 : \juy
primerentur. Hid. Fin. iii.lO, 'pavTaartai/']al /ueV eicri rexi'iKol,
3.8 : Cumque rerum notiones in al Se S-rexvoi.
animis fiant, si aut usu (expe- ' Plut. Plac. iv. 11 b S^ :

rience) aliquid cognitum sit, x6yos Kafl' %v iTpoaayopev6fi.(Ba


aut oonjunctione, aut simili- A071K0I 4k rav rrpoXii^iav cvji-
tudine, aut collatione rationis vATipovffdai \4yeTai Karh rijy
hoc quarto, quod extremum n-piirriv ejSSoMtiSo (the first seven
posui, boni notitia facta est. years of life). Comm. Not. 3,
:

THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE. 81

might seem that by primary conceptions, or Koival Chap.


V.
svvoiai,^ innate ideas were meant; but this view

would be opposed to the whole character and connec-


tion of the system. In reality, these primary con-
ceptions, or Koival hvoiai, are only those conceptions
which, by reason of the nature of thought, can be
equally deduced by all men from experience ; even
the highest ideas, those of good and evil, having no
other origin.^ The artificial formation of conceptions

1, says that to the Stoics be- tiam boni pervenit. Similarly


longed Th irapSt Tcks ivvolas Kal Sea. Ep. 120, 4, replying to the
T&s vpo\'ri^eis tos koii/Sls tjyiho- question, Quomodo adnos prima
ao^eiv, &ip' Siy pLdKiffTariiv a'ipefftv boni honestique notitia per-
. . . Kal fidvTjv bfioXayeiv tt? ^tJfref venerit ? observes, Hoc nos
\iyovinv. Sen. Epist. 117, 6: natura docere non potuit: se-
multiim dare solemus prEesum- mina nobis scientise dedit,
tionl(irpiSxrul'is) omnium homi- scientiam non dedit nobis
. . .

num apud nos argumentnm


; videtur observatio collegisse
yeritatis est, aliqnid omnibus [speciem virtutis], et rerum
videri. J'requent instances will SEepe f aotarum inter se collatio :

occur of appeals to communes per analogiam nostri intellec-


notitias and consensus gen- tum et honestum et bonum
tium. . judioant. The notion of mental
' Diog. vii. 53 (\>vcnKSis Si : health and strength has grown
voeiTou SlKaiSv ri Koi ayaJdSv. 64 : out of the corresponding bodily
effri S' Tj Trp6\Tiiliis ^vvoia tpvaiKTi notions the contemplation of
;

Tuv KaB6\ou. In the same strain virtuous actions and persons


Chrysippus (in Plut. Sto. Kep. has given rise to the conception
17) spealss of ^^tpvroi vpoKijil/ets of moral perfection, the -good
of good and evil, lii Phit. points being improved upon,
Frag. De Anim. vii. 6 T. V. and defects being passed over,
487 Wytt., the question is the experience of certain faults
asked, Hov? is it possible to which resemble virtues serving
learn what is not already to make the distinction plainer.
known? The Stoics reply, By Even belief in a God was pro-
means of ipviriKoi ivvoiai. duced, according to Diog. vii.
^ Compare Cic. Fin. iii. 10 52, by airiiS|ij. See p. 80, 1.
hoc quarto [coUatione rationis] Conf Stoh. Eel. i. 792 oi niv
. :

boninotitia facta est; cum enim ISroJlKoi Keyovtrt fiey eiidvs 4ix(pve-

ab lis rebus, quassunt secundum trdairhv \6yov, Utrrepot/ Be avva-


naturam, adscendit animus col- SpoiCeaBai inrh rav ai(fdi\aeav kuX
latione rationis, turn ad noti- (pavTaffiuv vepl SeKarefftrapa ctt;.
:

82 TEE STOICS.

Chap, gives rise to knowledge, which is defined by the


Stoics to be a fixed and immoveable conception, or
(3) Xmm- gyst^m of such conceptions.' Persistently maintain-
formed ing, on the one hand, that knowledge is a system of

'ally'
artificial conceptions, impossible without a logical
process ; on the other hand, occupying the ground
they did, they must have felt it imperative that
knowledge should agree in its results with primary
conceptions,^ agreement with nature being in every
department their watchword. For their system,
moreover, it was as natural to derive support from a
supposed agreement with nature, as it was easy for

their opponents toshow that their agreement with


nature was imaginary many of their assertions, on ;

the contrary, being wholly opposed to general


opinions.'

() Rela- Perceptions, and the conclusions based upon


tlie''' l^eing thus, according to the Stoics, the two
^e^Unr'
' Stoh. Eel. ii. 128 elcai Se : to Zeno.) oukii/iv 8^ t^s Sta\eic-
T^v KaTdKtj^iv ot.ff(paKTJ
intffTfjfiTiv tikijs Beatpias rhv (To^hv &TrTarov
Kai aixerdiTTiCTOv itirb \6yov ' erepav ^treffOai 4v \6ycf),
5e iiriffriifniv ffiffTTjfia i^ iiriffrv- ^ See p. 80, 4.

fj.uv to(oi5twi/, otoy ^ rSy Kar^ ^ This was the object of


fiipos \oyiKii iv rif (TTrouSai^ vTrdp- Plutarch's treatise irep! tuv
Xovffa
&\K7iy 5e fficrrTifia ^| koiv&v iwoiwv. In the same
i-rrLffTiiiiciii TEX"}""'' ^ auToD ex"" ''^^7, the Peripatetic Dioge-
rh $4Paiov wj exotiffiv al aperal nianus (in hiseb. Pr. Bv. vi. 8,
S\\i;vSc( knowledge in a relative 10) casts it in the teeth of
sense) {ic </>a>>Ta<riui/ SeKTinJ)!' Chrysippus that, whilst ap-
ajucTaTTToiToi' tnrh \6yov, %vTivi pealing to generally-received
i^cunv iv -rivif Kal Swifxti (so. T^r opinions, he was always going
ijiux^s) Keio-fla'. Diog. vii. 47 contrary to them, and that he
aiTT^K TE tV eiriiTT^/ijii' i^aaLv i) considered all men, with one
KaTa\ri\S/iv tur^akri ^ ejiy iv (pav- or two exceptions, to be fools
TairiMi' 5rpo(rSe|ei d/ieTtCirTaiToj' 6irh and madmen.
\6yov. (This explanation, which *
IMoff. 52: fi Si KOTa\i)i(J
Herillns used according to yiverat bbt' aliroiis oiVB^ffei iifv
iWo^. vii. 165, certainly belongs \evKav, k.t.K. \6yip Si tuv SC
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE. 83

sources of all notions, the further question arises. Chap.


How are these two sources related to each other?
'

It might have been expected that only perceptions <^ -

would be stated to be originally and absolutely true,


since all general conceptions are based on them.
Nevertheless, the Stoics are far from saying so. Ab-
solute certainty of conviction they allow only to
knowledge, and therefore declared that the truth of
the perceptions of the senses depends on their rela-
tion to thought.' Truth and error not belonging to
disconnected notions, but to notions combined in the
form of a judgment, and a judgment being produced
by an effort of thought, it follows that sensations,
taken alone, are the source of no knowledge, know-
ledge first arising when the activity of the under-
standing is allied to sensation.^ Or, starting from

atroSei^ews tTvvayo[j,4yuv, Siffirep rh SrwiKol Koivus eV \eKT^ rh ct\7j0es


6iohs elvai, k.t.X. efyat Kal rb \^evSos KeKrhv Si

Sext. Math. viii. 10


' ol Si : viripx^iv (Jxwri rh Kara \oyiKiiv
awh TTJs aroas Keyovfrt juey Twy re ipavraffiav v<filtTTAfjiei/ov XoyiK^v

aiffdriTuy Tiva Kal twv voriTwv Si elvai tpavraaiav Kad' %v t6


h\Ti&ri, ovK 4^ ei/deias Si rot aitrflTjTo, tpatfraffSiv etrrt \6yt^ irapaffTriiTat.
aWa, avoupophv t^v ws ^tti
icoTCt twv Se XeKTWC tA fxiv iWiTrri
Tct irapaKflfieva roirois vo7]Tti. KaKoviri retouroreA^ (con-
5e
' fSext.l. c. continues .a\vi6is ceptions and propositions ; conf.
ydp etrri kot* airobs rh v-rdpxov Diog. vii. 63) irpotrayopeiovtri
. . .

Kal avTiKeifiev6v rivi, Kal }^evSos Se rtvaray auTOTcXoSv Kala^i(&iJ.aTa,


rd /ii) iiripxov Kal /i^ (this fiJ) is iiirep Keyovns iJToi itKriBetlo/uv t)

obviously redundant as appears \fievS6ij.iBa. IMd. 74 ; Bwg. vii.


from Math. viii. 85, 88 xi. ; 65 : a|(M;UO 5e iariv, 8 Io-tik

220, where the same definition aKi)6is ^ ^ciSos (see Cie. Tuso.
is given without the /i^j) avn- I. 7, 14) ^ Trpay/ia (better KfKrhy

Keiii,ev6v Tivi, inep affufiaToi' as Gell. N. A. xvi. 8, 4 reads)


a^iu/ia KaOecrriis votiriv eli/oi

avrmeKis hro<l>avThv iaov i(f>'
every sentence containing an laur^ is i Xpv<rnnr6s (pTicnv 4i/

assertion ornegative, and there.- to7s Sia^iKTiKoTs Spois. Aristotle


fore being opposed to every had already observed that the
other. Ibid. viii. 70 ii^iow ot : distinction between false and

a 2
84 THE STOICS.

Chap, the relation of thought to its object, since like can


V.
only be known by like according to the well-known
adage, the rational element in the universe can only
be known by the rational element in man.^ But
again, the understanding has no other material to
work upon but that supplied by sensation, and gene-
ral conceptions are only obtained therefrom by con-
clusions. The mind, therefore, has the capacity of
formally working up the material supplied by the
senses, but to this material it is limited. Still, it can
progress from perceptions to notions not immediately
given in sensation, such as the conceptions of what is

good and of God. And since, according to the Stoic


teaching, material objects only possess reality, the
same vague inconsistency may be observed in their
teaching as has been noticed in Aristotle ^
reality
attaching to individuals, truth to general notions.
This inconsistency, however, is more marked in their
case than in that of Aristotle, the Stoics so far ad-
hering to the Cynic nominalism' as to assert that no
reality attaches to thought.^ Such an assertion

true first appears in judgment. * Siog.


61 : ivii6t)ii.a (object
See Zeller, Philosophie der of thought) 5e ian <f>dvTairiia
Griechen,vol.ii.b, 156, 2; 167,1. Siavoias, oBtc ri %!> oirf itothv,
' Sext. Math. vii. 93 ; as rh axrovel Si rl iv xal ixravel iroiiiy.
fih ipws, ^naiv S Hoo-eiStii'ios rhv Stob. Bel. i. 332 rh ei/Ko^juoTO
:

VKiToivos Tlfiatov iitiyoiiievos, (pnffl n-f]Ti rivi, ehai ^-fiTi iroii,


iirh Tijs ^oJToeiSoCs &ifiea>s Kara- ImravA Si rtvh koL iiaavfi iroii
ka)t.Pi,viTai, ri 5e tj>iev^ imh rrjs </>oi'T(ff/ioTa i/vxrjs
tuCtb 5s inri
aeposiSoSs oko^s, oBtw kbI fj ruv tSiv apxalfv IStas irpoa-a-yopcie-
S\av ipvffis uirb crvYyeiiovs 6<j>dXei aSai . . . TaSra [raiiTOs] Se oi
KwraKa)i.$6.V<79aiTov\6yov. Conf. 2Tm"iKol <pt\6(ro^oi (paaXv avmip-
Plato, Kep. vi. 508, B. kt ovs eivai, koXtSv pii/ iwoi\ni,Tav
^ See Zeller'g Philosophie /leTexeiK vims, t&v Si Trrdia-eay,
der Griechen, vol. ii. b, 231. &s SJ; irpoffiryoplas /caXoDtri, ruy-
' Hid. ii. a, 211. Xt^"""- Although defended by
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE. 85

makes it all the harder to understand how greater Chap.


V.
truth can be attributed to thought, unreal as it is said

to be, than to sensations of real and material objects.


Do we then ask in what the peculiar character of
thought consists, the Stoics, following Aristotle, reply
that in thought the idea of universality is added to
that which presents itself in sensation as a particular.'
More importance was attached by them to another
feature the greater certainty which belongs to
thought than to sensation. All the definitions given
above point to the immovable strength of conviction

Prantl, Gesch. d. Log. 1. 420, 63, tion of ideas, but that they
the last words as they stand asserted that these ideas were
do not appear capable of any only ivvo^naTa an assertion
tolerable meaning. They are which had also been made by
more probably corrupt. Phd. Antisthenes. Compare what is
Plao. i. 10, 4 oi i,irh Ziivavos: said on p. 92 respecting the un-
reality of the \(kt6v, likewise
tSms eipa(rai>. ^mpl. Categ. 26, what Sext. Math. vii. 246,
e ; X/;iJffnr7ros aTropet nepi t^s quotes, as belonging to the
ideas, elT6SeTL ^Biifferai, av/jLira- Stoics ot'Te 5^ aKtiSets otfre ^ev-
;

'
pakfjUTeov 5e Kal riiv ffvvijdetajf Seis elaiv at yeviKal [tpayrairiat]
Tuv ^TwiKuv irepl ruv yeviKav Sc y^p tA rota ^ rota roWav
etSr]

TToiwv iras at intjoffets kot' aiirovs ri yeyij oSre roia otfre Tola if

irpo(p4povTai Kal rh iry oijTtva mankind be divided into Greeks


Koiv^irap'-avTohKeyeTai. Syrian and barbarians, the yepiKhs
on Met. p. 59. (In Petersen's &v6pa!TTos will be neither one
Philos. Chrys. Fund. 80): &s nor the other. The further
&pa tA elfSr) aire irphs ri)ii
. . . therefore a conception is re-
^(Tiv TTis ruv ovoiidTuv avuTtOiias moved from individual limi-
vapiiyero, iis Xpiaiinros Kal 'Apx^- tations, the further it is removed
Sji/jios Kol 01 irXeious riSv STuiKav from truth.
SiTTfpov (f4]Sn(rav . . . ou ^tJi/ouBe ' Diog. vii. 54 : ecrrt S' fi irpS-

voiiiMTi liffi Trap' airois at iS4ai, ATji/zts ivvota ^vfftK^ ruv Kad6\ov.
&s KKedi/BTis liffTcpov etpiiKe. Exc. e Joam. Damtase. (^Stob,
Prantl, 1. c. takes objection to rioril. ed. Mein. iv. 236), Nr.
what StobKUS and Plutarch 34 : XptJffiTnros rh ptev yeviKhv
here say yet this view is not
;
7]bb voTjrhv, rh Si eiStKdv Kotl

that the Stoics regarded their irpoinrlirTOV ^Si) (^Petersen, 83


conception of the imdri/ia as without cause suggests ^84)
identical with Plato's concep- aiV8i)T(ic.
;

86 THE STOICS.

Chap. as the distinctive feature of knowledge ;^ and of like


V.
import is the language attributed to Zeno,^ compar-
ing simple sensation with an extended finger, assent,
as being the first activity of the power of judgment,
with a closed hand, conception with the fist, and
knowledge with one fist firmly grasped by the other.
According to this view, the whole difference between
the four processes is one of degree, depending on the
greater or less strength of conviction, on the mental
exertion and tension.^ It is not an absolute difference
of kind, but a relative difference, a gradual shading
off of one into the other.
(_d) Tlie From these considerations it follows that in the
standard
of truth.
last resort only a relative distinction is left whereby
(a) Prac- the truth of notions may be tested. Even the gene-
tical need
ral argument for the possibility of knowledge proceeds
of such a
standaird. with the Stoics by practically taking something for
granted. Without failing to urge intellectual objec-
tions against Scepticism, as was indeed natural, par-
ticularly since the time of Chrysippus^ and often
most pertinent ones' ^the Stoics nevertheless speci-

See p. 82, 1.
' pied an intermediate place
dc. Acad. ii. 47, 145.
' between two of the most im-
' Stdb. Bel. ii. 128 Know- : portant Sceptics. Plut. Sto.
ledge is defined to be e{ij ^av- Eep. i. 4, p. 1059. Diog. 198
raffiav Ssktik^ ^fieriiirTUTOS inrh mentions a treatise against
K6yov, r/iVTivd. <j}ouriv iy rSyc^ Kol Arcesilaus.
Svvd,/jLec K^iffOai. ' Here may be noted the
Chrysippus opposed Arce-
* objection mentioned by Sext.
silas, with such success, ac- Math. viii. 463 Pyrh. ii. 186
; :

cording to the view of the The Sceptics cannot deny the


Stoic School, that Carneades possibility of arguing without
was refuted by anticipation proving their assertion and
and it was considered a special thereby practically admitting
favour of Providence that the the possibility. Also another
labours of Chrysippus had occu- one urged by Antipater against
;

THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE. 87

ally took up their stand on one point, which was this, Chap.
V.
that, unless the knowledge of truth were possible, it
would be impossible to act on fixed principles and
convictions.' Thus, as a last bulwark against doubt,
practical needs are resorted to.
The same result is obtained from a special inquiry (/3) Irre-
'*'***'*
into the nature of the standard of truth. If the
percej)-
question is raised. How are true perceptions distin- tions the
.-LTj^ n 1
guished from false ones
ni.T- 1'
the immediate
i?
I t
reply given of truth.
standard

by the Stoics is, that a true perception is one which


represents a real object as it really is.^ You are no
Carneades ( Cic. Acad. ii. 9, 28 ToSra. Following also the Stoic
34, 109) : He who asserts that line, Cic. Acad. ii. 1 0-12, makes
nothing can be known with Antiochus argue that Scepticism
certainty must, at least, believe makes all action impossible.
that he can with certainty 2 In Sext. Math. vii. 244,
know this. The replies of the aKTjOe'is ipavTafriat are, first of
Sceptics to these objections, and all, literally explained to be
the way they turned them in <pavra(riai, Zy effrii/ a\7i67J kottj-
their own favour, will be found yoplay troiiiffaff&at ' then, under
in Sext. Math. 1. c. and vii. 433. the head of true (jiavrairlai, the
' Plut. Sto. Bep. 10 (see p. KaTaKtiirriKal and oi Kara\TiKTif{ai
66, 1) ; lUd. 47, 12 koX : iv mV are distinguished, i.e., notions
ye Tois "wphs Toiis 'AKaSyifJLa'LKoijs which are accompanied by a,
aywaty d TrAeTtrros out^ re Xpvff- clear impression of being true,
Ittvcii Kal ^Avrmdrptp ir6vos yeyove and such as are not; and, in
Trep\ Tov jU^Te irpirreiv [xiire ipfiav conclusion, <pavratTlaKaTa\7j7rTiK^
&avyKara64T(os, oWai TrKafrfiara is defined tj airb rod inrdpxovTOS
:

\4yeiv KoX Kevas vTroOeffets tovs Kal Kar' aiirh rh virdpxov 4vawo~
a^iovvTas oiKcias ^ovTOffios yeyo- tieixay/jievT] Kal 4va'ireff(l>payta'fi4vr]y

fiev7}s eitdvs dpfi^v ^^ ^avras fiv^k &iroiaovK iiy y4votra cCTri [ir) imdp^
avyKaTaTtdefi4vovs. Ibid. adv. XO'Tos. This definition is after-
Col. 26, 3, p. 1122: rrivSi repl wards more fully explained:.
vdvTwv iwoxh^ oiiS^ 01 TToWa Ttpay- The same explanation is given
fiaTeutrdfiivoi Kol KaTanlvavTes els lUd. 402 and 426; viii. 85;
TovTO ffvyypdfi^Ta Kol \6yovs Pyrrh. ii. 4 ; iii. 242 ; Augustin,
iKlvtiaaii i.K\' in t^s StoSs auTTJs c. Acad. ii. 5, 11 ; Cic. Acad. ii.

reKemwvres HaTep Topyiva t^v 6, 18. Diog. vii. 46 : t^s Sc sjiav-

iLirpa^lav hrdyoyres kiniyipevffav. Tafflas r^v /iey KajTdKTjlTTiK^v t^v


JEJpiet. (Arrian. Diss. i. 27, 15) 5e ^KaTdXtjiTTOv KaTa\TyKTiKi]v
quietly suppresses a Sceptic by fxev, %v KptThptoe elvat tuv irpay-
saying ; obK &yu <rxo?^v rphs lidrav (pacrl,, tV ywon4vi\)i AJi
88 THE STOICS.

Chap. further with this answer, and the question has again
V.
to be asked, How may it be known that a perception
faithfully represents a reality ? The Stoics can only
reply by pointing to a relative, but not to an abso-
lute, test the degree of strength with which certain
perceptions force themselves on oxir notice. By itself
a perception does not necessarily carry conviction or
assent {av^KardOsais) ; for there can be no assent
until the faculty of judgment is directed towards the
perception, either for the purpose of allowing or of
rejecting it, truth and error residing in judgment.
Assent therefore, generally speaking, rests with us, as
does also the power of decision ; and a wise man dif-

fers from a fool quite as much by conviction as by


action.' Some of our perceptions are, however, of

vvapxovTos KttT* atirb rb Hirapxav positam et Toluntariam. Ibid.


evaireffippaytfr^evriv /col evajro^e- ii. 12, 37; De Fato, 19, 43,
fiayiJ.4vT]V ' aKarAKiiTrrov 54 t)?!//*^ Chiysippus affirms: visum ob-
anh inrdpxovTOSf ^ airh imtipxovTQS jectum imprimet illud quidem
fihr, fi^ kot' ai/rh 5e rb {nrdpxoVj et quasi signabit in animo suam
tV juj; Tpapy) /iiiSe iKTViroy. Ibid. speciem sed assensio nostra erit
50. in potestate. Plut. Sto. Eep.
'
Sext. Math. viii. 397 itrn : 47, 1 : tV
yhp ^avToiriav $ov\6-
fiev oiv 7j diroSe(|ts, &s eCTi trap' liems [A Xpitrmros'] oiiK oScroi'
tunuv oKoieiVj KaTaKijnTtKTJs tpav- oSTOTeXi) TTJs avyKaTtiSeiTfus
Tairlas trvyKaTiBecris, jJtis 3it\ovv curiav aTToSetKvietv ^pijKev Sri
^oiKev elvai trpayfia fcal rh ixiv ri $\d^ovtriv ol (Totpol i^6u56ts tjiavra-
IXd' aKoiffioPf rf) 54 cKoitriov Ka\ trlas i/iTToiovvTeSf hv at fpavraffiat
^Tri Tp Tiiierepif Kpiffei Kel^ivov. rb irotuffiv avTOTcKus ris ffvyKara-
fihv yap tpaviatntoBrivaL a^oiKijTov ffeo-eis, K.T.X. Id. 13: avBis Se
^v Kcti oi/K 4irl tQ irtiffxovTt cKeiTO <p7^(ri Xpvo'L'tnroSf KaX rhv Behv
&AV ivt r^ (pavrcurtovvTt rh ovraxrl ijifuSfis cjun-oicu' (pavratrlas Kol
StaTeQ^yai . , . rh Se ffvyKara- rhv ffo<phjf . Tjfias 54 tpavXov^
. ,

64ir6ai Toirtp ry Kivfj^art Ikcito SvTas truyKaTarlBetrBai Tois TOi-


4ir\ T^ TapaSexofiej/tp t)ji' ^fflyra- airais tpavrafflais. Id. Fragm,
<r(av. XHog. vii. 51 Acad,
; (kc. De An. 2 : oi/x vi ^vxh TpeTrei
i. 14, 40 : [Zeno] ad hseo quB kavr^iv els r^v twv irpay^rtov
visa sunt, et quasi acceptasensi- KaTi\n<fiiv Kol airdTTiv, Karii robs
bus assensiouem adjungit ani- airh TTJs tTToas. Mpictet, in Gell,'
morum quamesse vxilt in nobis
: N.A. xix. 1,15: visa animi, quas
: ;

THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE. 89

such a kind that they at once oblige us to bestow on Chap.


V.
them assent, compelling us not only to regard them
as probable, but also as true ' and corresponding with
the actual nature of things. Such perceptions pro-
duce in us that strength of conviction which the
Stoics call a conception they are therefore termed
;

conceptional perceptions. Whenever a perception


forces itself upon us in this irresistible form, we are
no longer dealing with a fiction of the imagination,
but with something real but whenever the strength
;

of conviction is wanting, we cannot be sure of the


truth of our perception. Or, expressing the same
idea in the language of Stoicism, conceptional or ir-
resistible perceptions, ^avracriai KaTaXriimicai, are

the standard of truth.^ The test of irresistibility

(pavTaaias philosopM appellant Cic. Acad. i. 11, 41 : [Zeno]


. . . non voluntatis sunt neque visis ( = (pavraaiais) nou omnibus
Arbitrarise,sed tI quadam sua adjungebat fidem, sed iis solum,
inferunt sese hominibus nos- quEe propriam quandam habe-
citandse ; probationes autem, rent deolarationem earum re-
quas auyKaraBiaiis Tocant, qui- rum, quae viderentur id autem :

bus eadem visa nosountur ao visum, cum ipsum per se cer-


dijundicantur, voluntariEe sunt neretur, comprehensibile (koto-
fiuntque hominum arbitratu XtivriKii <j>avTa(ria). Ibid. ii.

the difference between a wise 12, 38ut enim necesse est


:

man and a fool consists in lanoem in libra ponderibus im-


B-uyKaTaTiBeffBat and wpoireiriSo^d- positis deprimi, sic animum
fell'. The freedom of approba- perspicuis cedere non po- . . .

tion must, of course, be so test objeotam rem perspicuam


understood in harmony with non approbare. Conf. Fin. v.
Stoic doctrine of the freedom 26, 76 percipiendi vis ita de-
:

of the vrill. finitur a Stoiois, ut negent'


'
On the difference between quidquam posse peroipi nisi '

the conception of etfXoyo* and tale rerum, quale falsum esse


that of KaraKirirriKii <pavTa(ria, non possit. Siog. vii. 54
consisting as it does in the fact Seart. Math. vii. 227 : xpirlipiov

that the latter alone is unerring, toivw (pairiv o\jj9eias elyBi oi

see At/ien. viii. 354, e ; Diog. &vSpes ovroi tV KaraXijirTiKV


vii. 177. (jiayrairiav. It was a deviation
* Compare besides p. 87, 2, from the older Stoic teaching,
no THE STOICS.

Chap. ( KaTd\r}-\lns) was, in the first place, understood to


V.
apply to sensations from without, such sensations,
(7) Pri- according to the Stoic view, alone supplying the
mary con-
ceptions a material for knowledge. An equal degree of cer-
standard
tainty was, however, attached to terms deduced from
as well as
irresistible originally true data, either by the universal and natu-
percep-
tions. ral exercise of thought, or by scientific processes of
proof. Now, since among these derivative terms
some the primary conceptions (^Koival iwoiat), for

instance the
serve as basis for deriving others, it
may in a certain sense be asserted that sensation
and primary conceptions are both standards of truth.'
In strict accuracy, neither sensation nor primary con-
ceptions (jrpoKrj-^sis) can be called standards. The

to refuse, as the later Stoics verat KaTaairojffa Tifias as ffvyKa-


did, to allow a conoeptional rdBefftv Kol &Wov iJ.riSevhs Seofieyq
notion to be considered a test of els T^ roiavTT] TrpoffirlTrreiv, k.t.K.
truth, except with the proviso Hence Simpl. Phys. 20, b:
that no argument could be ad- av^pow TCt &K\a . . . Tr\iii' t^
duced against its truth. Sext. ivapyi].
253 aA\a yhp 01 fx^v apxat^TepoL
: ' Diog. vii. 54 Kpir^piov Si :

TWV "ZTu'iKav KptT'fiptSv ^offtv slvai T^s a\7ideias ^ao*! Tvyxdireiv tV


/coToA.TjirTiK^y tpavTaalatff tovt-
raiTTjv (pavraalav oi be vstinepoi etTTf r^v virdpxov70s, KaBd
aTrb
jrpotreTiGeiray Kal rh firjbiy exovaav ^ricri Xpiatinros ip rfi ScoSeict^Ti;
fv<TT7]fia, cases could be
since Twv (pvffiKiiv Kal 'AvTlvarpos Koi
imagined in which a faulty 'AiroW6dupos. 6 ^ev yi^p Bor]6hs
view presented with the
itself Kpirijpia nKelova &Tro\eiTri, vovv
full force of truth. This was KOI aiaStiaiv
Kal &pe(iv koi iirM-
equivalent to overthrowing the (this looks like an ap-
Titia\v
whole doctrine of a criterion ;
proximation to the teaching of
for how could it be known in the Peripatetics) iSi'X.piai-mras
;

any particular case that there Siatpepdiieyos vpis ai-rhv 4y t^


was not a negative instance ? Tp^Ttfj irepl \6yov xpiriiptii ^TjaLV.
But it is quite in harmony with cleat c^aSriffiv Kal irp6\7}^tv . . .

the Stoic teaching for a later oAAot 8e Tives tuv apxatOTepwv


Stoic (Hid. 257) to say of con- StojVkwv rhv opBhv \6yov KptT'lipiov
oeptional perception oBttj yip : 07roAeiirou(nj/, is 6 UoffeiBtivLos iv
iyapy^s oiira ol ttXtiktik^ fiovo- Tp Tepl KptTTiplov ^rjartv. See
mv^i tUv Tfixuv, (paai, Ka/tPi- above p. 76.

THEORY OF KNOWLEBGE. 9l

real standard, whereby the truth of a perception is Chap.


V.
ascertained, consists in the power, inherent in certain
perceptions, of carrying conviction ro KaTaXrjiniKov
a power which belongs, in the first place, to sensa-
tions, whether of objects without or within, and, in
the next place, to primary conceptions forraed from
them in a natural way koivoX swoidi or TrpoXtjyJrsis.
On the other hand, conceptions and terms formed
artificially can only have their truth established by
being subjected to a scientific process of proof. How,
after these statements, the Stoics could attribute a
greater strength of conviction to artificial than to
primary conceptions ;
' how they could raise doubts
as to the trustworthiness of simple sensations,^ is
one of the paradoxes of the Stoic system, proving the
existence, as in so many other systems, of a double
current of thought. There is, on the one hand, a
seeking for what is innate and original, a going back
to nature, an aversion to everything artificial and of
human device, inherited by Stoicism from its ances-
tral Cynicism. On the other hand, there is a desire
to supplement the Cynic appeal to nature by a higher'
culture, and to assign scientific reasons for truths
which the Cynics laid down as self-evident.
The latter tendency will alone explain the care

'
See above p. 82, 1. had inquired into the truth of
''
See above p. 89, 2, and the perceptions of the senses,
do. Acad. ii. 31, 101: neque and of the notions derived from
eos (the Academicians) contra them, in his treatise irepi a-uyij-
sensus aliter dicimus, ac Stoici, Silas, without, however, satis-

qui multa falsa esse dicunt, factorily answering the ob-


longeque aliter se habere ac jections which he quoted against
sensibus videantur. Chrysippus the theory. Sse p, 46, 2.

92 THE STOICS.

Chap and precision which the Stoics devoted to studying


'

the forms and rules which govern intellectual pro-


cesses. Attention to this branch of study may be
noticed in Zeno and his immediate successors at the
first separation of Stoicism from Cynicism.' Aristo
is the only Stoic who is opposed to it, his whole
habit of mind being purely that of a Cynic. In
Chrysippus, however, it attained its greatest de-
velopment, and by Chrysippus the formal logic of
the StoieS attained scientific completeness. In later
times, in proportion as Stoicism reverted to its origi-
nal Cynical type, and in connection therewith ap-
pealed to the immediate suggestions of the mind, it

lost its interest in logic, as may be observed in


Musonius, Epictetus, and others. For the present,
however, let it sufi&ce to consider the logic of Chrysip-
pus, as far as that is known to us.
C. FormaTr~ The term formal logic is here used to express

(V) TTtter- those investigations which the Stoics included under


ance m tjje doctrine of utterance.'' The common object
of those inquiries is that which is thought, or, as

the Stoics called it, that which is uttered (Xe/cToz/),

understanding thereby the substance of thought


thought regarded by itself as a distinct something,
differing alike from the external object to which it
refers, from the sound by which it is expressed, and
from the power of mind which produces it. For
this reason, they maintain that only utterance is
not material ; things are always material ; even the
process of thought consists in a material change
> See p. 60. See p. 73, 3.
. ;;

FORMAL LOGIC. 93

within the soul, and an uttered word, in a certain Chap.


V.
movement of the atmosphere.' A question is here

' See Seast. Math. viii. 11 : oi ycip imirr'liiiii irivTuy a\ij9S)y airo-
aith rrts (Ttoos, Tpia <pdfieyot ffv^U' tpavriK^, 7j 5e iviffr-fifiti Tris ex*'*'
yfiv a\\ii\ois, t6 te arifuuv6ii.ei'0v Tiy)ioyiK6y (Id. Math. vii. 38,
Kol rb arnioimv Kal rh Tvyxtivov. a similar statement is expressly
wv (TTifiaivoyiieyeivai r^v (pwj/^v . . attributed to a Stoic) likewise ;

atjfjMtvifievoy 5e tt&rb rh npay/xa a similar statement which Sen.


rh inr* avTTJs 57J\otJjuei/oy Tuy- . . . Ep. 117, discusses, and at length
X^vov a
-rb ixrhs iTroK^l/ifVov . . . declares to be a mere quibble,
roirwv Sh Sio fihv eTyat (rdfiaTa, but not till after a lengthy re-
KaBdirep t^v (f)av^y koX rh Tvy- f utation sapientiam bonum
:

X^-vov, %v 5e Sta^iiwroVf &(nrep rh esse, sapere bonum non esse.


ffTj^aivSfievov irpciyfia Kal \eKT6y. The statement on the as-
rests
Sen. Bp. 117, 13, giving it ex- sertion that nothing can be a
pressly as the teaching of the good which does not make it-
Stoics, not as his own: Svmt, self felt, and nothing can make
inqnit, naturae corporum . . . itself felt which is not material
has deinde sequiintur motus wisdom is material, because it
animorum entmtiativi corporum is mens perfecta, but sapere is
for instance, I see Cato walk incorporale et accidens alteri,
corpus est, quod video. . . . i.e. sapientise. Accordingly,
Dico deinde : Cato ambulat. \cKTby (as Am/mon. De Inter. 15,
Non corpus est, inquit, quod b, remarks) is a fieffov tov re
nunc loquor, sed enuutiativnm yoiifjiOfros koI rod irpdyfiaros' if,

quiddam de corpore, quod alii however, y6rifia be taken to ex-


effiatum vocant, aliienuntiatmn, press the thought itself, and
aliiedoctum. Compare also on not the process of thinking, it
the \fKT6v Semt. Math. viii. 70 becomes identical with \ticT6y.
(above p. 83, 2) Pyrrh. iii. 52.
; Conf. Slmpl. Cat. 3, a, Basil.
Various arguments are used by rk 8e \ey6fieva Kal KKra rh voii-
the Stoics to prove that the juaT({ ^(TTiv, ws Kal rots ^rutKo7s

voice as opposed to utterance i56Kei. In Pint. Plao. iv. 11, 4,


(XeKrby) is material, as has been a definition of ydriiia or iyySr/fia
said, p. 74, 5. Illustrative of is given similar to that of \k-
the distinction between utter- rby in Semt. Math. viii. 70 (jidv- :

ance and the process of thought rafffia hidvoias \oyiHov ^tpov. See
is the assertion (in iSeiBt. Pyrrh. above p. 84, 4. The statement,
ii. 81) that certainty as being however, of PhiUp. Anal. Pr.
a definite condition of the soul Ix. a, Schol. in Ajr. 170, a, 2,
is material, but that truth it- cannot be true, that the Stoics
self is not material XeycToi
; called things rvyxi.yoyra,
Siaipepeiv T^r ctA7)9fos rb ci\r]Bes thoughts iKipopiKa, and sounds
rpix^s, oviTt:f, <rv(rrd<Tei, Swifief \eKra, whereas ixtpopiKby may be
ovaitf liiy, iirel rb fiiv a\5)6es a(r^- used of thoughts in the same
liardv iffTty, ct^iufjia ydp itXTi KoX sense as \eKr6y.
\iKTby, i) Se oKifBeia ffSiiui, ian
94 THE STOICS.

Chap. suggested in passing, which should not be lost sight


V.
of, viz. How far was it correct for the Stoics to speak
of thoughts as existing, seeing they are not material,
since, according to their teaching, reality only belongs
^
to material things ?
Utterance may be either perfect or imperfect.' It
is perfect when it contains a proposition ; imperfect
when the proposition is incomplete.^ The portion
of logic, therefore, which treats of utterance falls

into two parts, devoted respectively to the considera-


tion of complete and incomplete expressions.
(2) In- In the section devoted to incomplete expressions,
complete
expression. much is found which we should include under gram-

{a) The mar Thus all incomplete


rather than under logic.
grammwr
expressions are divided into two groups^one group
of words.

> See p. 84, 4. This question Te\r). Various kinds of proposi-


was raised in the Stoic School tions are then enumerated as
itself at least Sextus, not hesi-
; being avTore^Tj. Follovring the
tating to attack the Stoic teach- same authority, (Diodes ? see
ing from this side (Math. viii. IHog. 48) Mog. 63, says : (>io(ri

262), speaks of an ayiivvTos liaxn Se rh \eKThv eivai rh Karct ipav-


in reference to the Svap^is of Toa'iav ?^oyiK^p itpLO'Tdfievof. r&v
Kexra, and he remarks (viii. Se A6KTWC rh fiev \4yovffiv flyai
268) dpu^^v Se ois eiffl rives oi
: auTOTeX^ 01 StmikoI, tb Be iWnrri.
hvypjiKdres t^v virap^tv tS>v \k- iWiirfi fiiv o5c effri Tk ayairdprt-
TUV, KOi OVX ot Tep6So^Ot fJi6j/0V, (TTOV e^fOi/Tci TJ)K iK(popav, olov
oTov ol ^ETTtKo^peLOL, aK\ot, Kal ot Tpd(l>ei 7rifi)ToC|Ue>/ yip, Tls au-
;

STwtKoVws oi Treplrhv BafffXefSijx', TOTeA.^ 5' iffrl t^ aTr-f}prt.op.ivT\v


ois ^So^e jUTjSev elvai atrtifiaTov. exoyra t)\v 4K(popiiti, otov Vpdfei
Probably the question was first 2QJKpaT7js. Prmitl in saying, p.
raised by later Stoics, when 438, that the Stoics divide judg-
pressed by their opponents. ments (afiioyuoTo) into complete
Basilides was the teacher of and incomplete, is inaccurate.
Marcus Aurelius. Otherwise Only AektA are so divided, but
the existence of XcktA was" KiKThv has a wider meaning
spoken of as quite natural. than that of a logical judgment.
" Sext. Math. viii. 70, see a^idS^ara are only one form of
above p. 83, 2 tUv Si XcKTwy to AeKTci abTOTeK^.
:

fiev ikhiWTJ Kahovo'i ret 5e auTO-


,

FORMAL LOGIC. 05

including proper names and adjectives, the other in- Chap.


V.
cluding verbs.' These two groups are used respec-
tively what is essential and what is
to express
accidental,^and are again divided into a number of
subdivisions and varieties.' To this part of logic
'
Plut. Qu. Plat. X. 1, 2, p. otfrg Si/ otfre aSifxa, aWa trv^^ffirj'
1008. A judgment or (irpiiToiris Khs Kol KaT7j7(Jprj/xo. Hence for
a|u/ia) e| 6v6fLaTos Koi ^p-aros the latter the names aijx&aim
(rvviffTTjKeUf av rb p.kv irrwaiv ot and trapaaiSfjL^apuz, See follow-
5ia\eKTtKol, rh Se Kar7iy6p7ip.a ko- ing note.
\ov(Tiv. The terms irTaais and xa- ' In nouns the cases were dis-

nfyip^lio.belonging to the Stoic tinguished, the nominative, ac-


terminology, the Stoics must be cording to Ammon. 1. c. being
meant by of SiaXtK-nml, In the called ivoiia, and the other five
first class of words they dis- cases irr^aeis a statement, how-
tinguish iiKO/ua and irpoffriyopla, ever, which does not agree with
limiting Svoiia to proper names, the usual use of those terms.
and understanding by irpoirri- In Siog. 65, the oases (yevtKii,
whether
'yopia all general terms, SoTiKJ), ttlTiaTixii') are called vKd-
substantives or adjectives (Diog. /Lai TrTwcreis. Chrysippus wrote
58; BeMer's Anecd. ii. 842). a distinct treatise on the five
According to Stol. Eel. i. 332, cases, IHoff. 192. Similar were
tttSitij was only used to -express the divisions of the KarriySprnia.
irpoirriyopia. Diog. 192, mentions According to Diog. 65, the Stoics
two books of Chrysippus irepl distinguished between transi-
Tuv irpoffTiyoptKuv. For the mean- tive verbs (op9cii), such as dp^,
ing of KaTj)y6pt]p.a or ^jua, the Sta\eyeTat passive verbs (Birrio)
verb, consult jKog. 58 and 64 ; such as ipSi/iai' neuter verbs
Sext. Pyrrh. iii. 14 ; do. Tusc. (oifSeTepa), such as tppovety, irept-
iv. 9, 21 ; PorpTiyr. in Ammon. TTKriiv and verbs which, with
De Inter. 37, a. According to a passive form, do not express
Apollon. De Construct, i. 8, a passive relation {avTnteaovM-
was used in strict accuracy
pripia Ta), Kelpeffdat, trelBearOat, &c.
only for the infinitive, other Consult on this point Phih. De
forms being called Kariiyop'lipMTa. Cherub. 121, c Orig. 0. Cels.
;

The distinction between


' vi. 57. On the opBh, and utttio,
om/ia and KarriySprifia was some- also Monys. TTirax. 15, p.
what bluntly referred to this 886, Bekk. ; Sim.pl. Categ. 79,
logical and metaphysical anti- u, f Diog. 191 ; and respecting
;

thesis by the Stoics, as may be all three divisions, Lm-soh. ii.


seen in Stob. Eel. i. 336 : atriov 196 StemtlwX,
; Gesch. der
S' S Ziivwv (jiTiolv fhai 5i' t, o5 5c Spraohw. i. 294. They also dis-
oifTJoi' (ru;ii/3e/37jK<!s Kal rh p.h tinguished between o-iJjii/Sa^uaand
ov Si aXriov KaTJiy6p7i-
ofTioj/ ffSina, irapacripPaita
a verb, when used
fia. TloireMvLOt
. . . rhiiiv . . . with a nominative, being called
atriov %v Kat aSifM, o? Si airtov aifiL^aiia or Kimi\y6pi>jM, and
: ;

90 TEE STOICS.

Chap. investigations into the formation and division of


V.
conceptions, and the doctrine of the categories, pro-
perly belong but it cannot be said with certainty
;

what place they occupy in the logic of the Stoics.'


Certain it is that these researches introduced little
new matter ; all that is known of the Stoic views in
reference to the formation, the mutual relation and
the analysis of conceptions, differing only from the
corresponding parts in the teaching of Aristotle by
the change of a few expressions, and a slightly
altered order of treatment.^

Trapaaiii.paii.a when used with an the meaningless Aov t!i 8iA ttc-
oblique case ; TrepiTroTc* is a ffiJ/t-
Tpas TTAeti' T& 5e Trapatrifi.^aiJ.aTa,
/Sa^ia, iierajjuiKei a Trnpaaifi^ajMi,, which at least gives a better
irepiTraTeirequiring a nominative meaning than the proposals of
(SoiKpoTTis), jiteTa^tteAei requiring R. Schmidt, Sto. Gramm. 66, 91,
a dative If an ob-
(Sw/tpt^Tei). ajid Lersch. 1. c. 33. Apollon.
lique case was necessary to com- De Const, iii. 32, p. 299 Bekk. ;

plete a sentence, besides the Suid. aipLfiaim (very inaccurate);


subject, the verb was called Prisoian, xviii. p. 1118, who, in
iXwTTOV fl <riii$aim or f\aTTOv f) his equally inaccurate account,
KaTjjy6pnij.a, as in the sentence has SLffvfi^d/xaTa. The example
Tlxdruv <j>i\e7, such, for instance, which Imciam,. Vit. Auot. 21
is fiXei, for these words only- employs to laugh at the Stoic
make a complete sentence by hair-splitting anent crii^Paiia
the addition of an object thus and TTapaaiiifiajia, of course
n\(Twr (/\el Aiuya, If this was proves nothing.
necessary with a irapao'vfjifiafi.a, 'There is nothing whatever
it was called lAoTToy ^ irapa- on record which serves to show
ai/ifiaiia ; such, for instance, is the position held by the cate-
the word /ic'Aci, for to complete gories. By several, definition
the sentence it is not enough and division were treated of
to say ^ancpdm iii\ei, but the ob- most improperly under the head
ject must be added, as in the sen- of language.
tence ^coKpAret juTa/l6Xei 'A\Ki-
: * Accordingto Diog. 60,
fiidSovs. This difference is ex- Beltker, Anecd. 647, Spoj was
ii.
plained by Pm'phyr. in Am.mon. defined by Ohrysippus as iSfou
1. c, 36, b, whom Lench. ii. (which must be read in Diog.
31, misunderstanding, blames. in place of xal) kviioais by

See Biog. 64 where the text is Antipater as \6yQS Kar" avdKvffiv


evidentlycorrupt. Without great (Anecd. iwiyieqv) airapTi^6vTa>s
temerity we mightsubstitute for 4K4)fp6iievos, i.e. a proposition in
FOUMAL LOGIC: TOE CATEGORIES. 97

Of greater importance is the Stoic doctrine of the Chap.


V.
, categories,' In this branch of logic, the Stoics again
follow Aristotle, but not without deviating from him (*) .^'''

in three points. Aristotle referred his categories to genes.


no higher conception regarding them severally as

whiolL the subject and the col- (IKog. 61). Lastly, if iSe,vt.
lective predicates may be inter- Pyrrh. ii. 213 (the previous de-
changed. 'Opurfihs gives in de- finition of dialectic is found
tail what Sm/ia gives collec- (as was stated on p. 73, 3), in
tively (Simpl Categ. 16, (8). Alcinmis Isag. 8, and he also
An imperfect 8pos is called mentions c. 5 three of the four
iiroypaipri. Instead of the Aris- kinds of division, instead of
totelian Ti ^v fTvai, the Stoics the fourth he gives two others),
were content with the rl ^v of refers to the Stoics, four kinds
Antisthenes (Alex. Top. 24, m). of division are enumerated.
Like Prodicus, they laid great The reference of the 8 hoApi-
stress on distinguishing accu- ffs mentioned by Prantl, p.
rately the conceptions of words 423, on the authority of Belt-
of similar meanings, X"P^. '''^p- Iter's Anecd. ii. 679 to a Stoic
i(iis, rjSovh, ticppoffivv (Alex. Top. source is much more doubtful.
96). The relation of yevos to There is a little that is new
f?8os is also explained yeyos is: in the Stoic discussion of Op-
defined to be the summing up position, and the same may be
of many thoughts (avoupaipeTojv said of what Simpl. (Categ. 100,
emoiiiidTav
which might mean /3 and S ; 101, e ; 102, ;8) quotes
thoughts which, as integral from Chrysippus (Trepl twv Kwrk
parts of a conception, cannot frrdpTjtriv Xeyofxevtcv') on the sub-

be separated from it only this


; ject of <rT4pn<ris and efis. Conf.
explanation would not agree JHog. vii. 190.
' See Petersen, Philos, Chrys-
with what follows, according
to which one would more likely ipp. Fund. pp. 36-144, invalua-
think of the different species ble for its careful collection of
included in the genus. Pramtl authorities, but in its attempt
p. 422 suggests avaipopTfrSiv, to build the Stoic system on the
which, however, requires ex- categories giving way to many
planation)elSor as tJ iirh tov
;
capricious combinations. Tren-
yivovs irepi^x^l'^'""' C-^*"?' ^^)' delenbwrg, Hist. Beitr. i. 217;
yeimcdraTOv is t> yevos hv yhos Pramtl, Gesch. der Logik, i.
oix exEi' elSi/nSroToy 6 elSos %v 426. Our authorities for the
elSos avK ?x' (.I>iog- 61 oonf. !
knowledge of the Stoic doctrine
Sext. Pyrrh. i. 138). As to of the categories are besides a
Siai'peiris, tnroSialpfais, and av- few notices on other writers
TiSialpeiris (division into contra- principally Slmplicius, on the
dictories) nothing newis stated; Categories, and Plotmm, En-
but liepiff/j-hs has a special notice nead. vi. 1, 25-30.
:

98 THE STOICS.

Chap. class-conceptions; the Stoics referred them all to


V.
one higher conception. Aristotle enumerated ten
categories ; the Stoics thought that they could do
with four,' which four only partially coincide with
those of Aristotle. Aristotle placed the categories
side by side, as co-ordinate, so that no object
come under a second category in the same
could
respect in which it came under the first one ^ the ;

Stoics placed them one under the other, as subordi-


nate, so that every preceding category is more
accurately determined by the next succeeding one.
{a) mgh- The highest conception of aU was apparently by
est Con-
ception the older Stoics declared to be the conception of
an in- Being. Since, however, speaking strictly, only
definite
Something, what is material can be said to have any being,
and many of our notions refer to incorporeal and
therefore imreal objects, the conception of Something'

' The Stoics attack the Aris- less than by the inquiry (Phys.
totelian categories for being V. 2) into the various kinds of
too numerous, and endeavoured
motion this inquiry being en-
to show that they do not in- tirely based on the idea of their
clude every kind of expression co-ordination.
(as if rejoined SMnplioiMS,C&teg.
,
' It will thus be understood

5, a, this was the point at all). how the ancients could at one
Compare Simpl. Categ. 5, o 15, ; time speak of iv, at another of
5 ; 16, S, who quotes these as t, as being the highest concep-
objections raised by Atheno- tion of the Stoics. The former
dorus and Coruutus, the former is found in Diog. 61 y^viKdra.-
:

living in the time of Augustus, To^ Se ^ffrtv h yivos hv y4vos ovk.


the latter in the reign of Nero. 6Xi, olov rb iv. Sen. Ep. 58, 8
Observations of these writers Nunc autem genus illudprimum
on some of the Aristotelian quEerimus, ex quo ceterse species
categories are given, Tbid. 47, C, suspensaj sunt, a quo nascitur
91, o. omnis divisio, quo universa
That such was the intended
* comprehensa sunt ;after notic-
position of the Aristotelian ca- ing the distinction between
tegories appears by the way in what is material and what is
which they were introduced, no immaterial, he proceeds quid :
FORMAL LOGIC: TSE CATEGORIES.
was in later times put in the place of the conception Chap.
V.
of Being. This indefinite Something comprehends
alike what is material and what is not material in
other words, what has being and what has not being:
and the Stoics appear to have made this contrast
the basis of a real division of things.' When it

becomes a question, however, of formal elementary


conceptions or categories, other points are emphasised
having no connection with the division into things
material and things not material. Of this kind are the

ergo erit, ex quo hc dedu- quibusdam videtur quid, for in


cantur ? illud quod est [ri . . . rerum, inquiunt, natura qusdam
iv'\ . . quod est aut oorporale
. sunt, qusedam non sunt ex- :

est aut incorporale. Hoc ergo amples of the latter are cen-
genus est primum et antiquissi- taurs, giants, and similar no-
mum et, ut ita dicam, generale tions of unreal things. Eitter,
[rh yevLKtiraTOv']. It is, how- iii. 566, remarks, with justice,
ever, more usual to find rl. that the older teaching must
Thus Plotin. Enn. vi. 1, 25 koi- : have placed the conception of
vhv tX koX imX irdyroiv %v yevos Being at the head; otherwise
Kaiifiivovai. Alex. Aphrod. Top. the objection could not have
155; Schol. 278, b, 20: o been raised, that what has not
^GiKviiOis %.v '6ri fjtij KaXus rh r\ ot being is thus made an object of
airh (Troas yevos rod Sj'tos (t( as thought. Probably the change
the genus, of which ip is a was made by Chrysippus, al-
species) TiflevTac et y^prl, SriKov though it is not de Snitely proved
'6ri KaX %v a\?C 4Keivoi vo-
. . by Stob. Bel. i. 390. Petersen
liodTii<raifTes aiirois rh hv Kara confuses the two views, in
txoiix6.TWV fi6vo>v KeyeffBat 5ia(|>eu- thinking (p. 146) that the
yoiev hf rb ^optiflhov Sia rovro Stoics divided Something into
ykp rh r\ yeviKclirepov avrou (paffiy Being and Not Being, subdivid-
etvai Kar7iyopo6fiVoi/ ov Karci ffa- ing Being again into what is
ftdruv ^6vov aWet Kal a(ru)fjiartiDV. material and what is not ma-
Schol. in Arist. 34, b, 11. Sesst. terial. In other respects, too,
Pyrrh. ii. 86 : rh rl, Sirep (f>a(riy he confounds the Stoic teach-
elvai irdprtav y^viKdirarov. Math. ing with the consequences,
X. 234 : The Stoics afiirm rSiv whereby Phtinms 1. c. and Plut.
rivuv to; [xiv e^vai fffitiiara ra 5e Comm. Not. 30, sought to refute
aatifMara. Sen. I.e. 13: Stoicivo- it.

lunt superpouere huio etiam- ' See previous note and p.


nunc aliud genus magis princi- 92,2.
pal . . . primum genus Stoicis
H
;

100 THE STOICS.

Chap.
V.
four highest conceptions,' all subordinate to the
conception of Somethiing, viz. subject-matter or sub-
stance {to vTroKSi/isvov), property or form {to ttoiov),
variety {to Trms sxov), and variety of relation (to
TrpOS Tt -TTOIS S^OV).^

(j8) Cate- The first of these categories ^ denotes the sub-


gory of ject-matter of things in themselves (to viroKsifievov),
matter or the material of -which they are made, irrespective of
substance.
any and every quality,^ the something which under-
lies all definite being, and which alone has a
substantial value.^ Following Aristotle, the Stoics

' The Stoics appear to have iffTirov imoKeifievov trrfiJLatySfjievov.


regarded them as yevM^Ton-a or Plot. 588, B ; imoKeifieva fikv yhp
vpSra yivri, rather than as cate- trpuTB. rd^avres Kal r^p v\rff ev-
gories. Conf. Simpl. Categ. ravBa rwy &\\wy wpoTd^avTes.
16, S (in other places as 51, /3 ;
Galen. Qu. Qual. S. Incorp. 6,
79, /3, he is speaking for him- xix. 478 \eyovin n6vriv rijv irpii-
:

self and not of the Stoic cate- TTjy S\riv aidtoy t V


&iroLov. Com-
gories) McM-c. Awel. vi. 14
; ;
pare following note. It would
Karriyopia did not suit them so seem to follow, as a matter of
well because of ^heir use of course, from the Stoic belief in
See p. 95, 1.
KaTiiy6prina. immaterial properties, see p.
^ Simpl. 16, 8 : oi Sf ye SrwV- 106, 4, that tiie Stoics also
Kol els 4KdTToya irvffreWeiv ^^t- believed in immaterial sub-
ovfft rdv Tcov irp^Tojv yevwv api6fj.6y stances (Petersen, 60) but
;

. . . TTolovprat ykp rijv TOfiijf els contradicting as this would


reffffapa els virOKeiiieva, KOl "noia their belief that reality only
Kal exovra koX irpbs Ti iriiiS
TTiiis belongs to material things,
MxovTa. Plot. En. vi. 1, 25 and being mentioned by no
Phit. Comm. Not. 44, 6. p. 1083. authority, although obviously
' Instead of vtroiceifievov^ the so open to the criticism of op-
Aristotelian category of being, ponents, it is safer to suppose
oiffia, was substituted by some, that they never went so far as
not only without the School, to state the belief in words.
but also by Posidonius, who in ' Simpl. 44, 5 ?oiKe Stoiik^
:

Stoi. Bel. i. 434 distinguishes Tivi ffwrideit^ ffvi/e-jreadai, ouSev


ovaia and Troibs the change of &\Ko ^ rh inroKeifievov elvat vopX-
the one and the other. Simi- ^wf, T^s 5e irepl aiirh 8iatpophs
larly his fellow-disciple Mnesar- ayvnoffTiiTous Tjyoifievos. Diog.
chus. 150. Stol. Eel. i. 322 (see be-
* PorpTiyr. in Simpl. 12, 5 : low 101, 2) and 324 e<pn<re 5e i:

7) Te yvtp &irUK Baii . . . irpurdv XloffeibtStvLos rrjy rwv bKtav ovfflav


: :

FORMAL LOGIC: THE CATEGORIES. 101

distinguish,' in this category of matter, between Chap.


V.
matter in general, or universal matter, and the par-
ticular matter or material out of which individual
things are made. The former alone is incapable of
being increased or diminished. Far otherwise is the
material of which particular things are made. This
can be increased and diminished, and, indeed, is ever
undergoing change ; so much so, that the only-
feature which continues the same during the whole
term of its existence^ constituting its identity, is its

quality.

KoX vK-riv ^-KOiov /cal &fiop(pov elvai, TaiSrTJs oiiK ael tovto Sianeveiif,
Kaff iitrov ovSkv
airoTerayfieuov &,\\a SiaLpetffBat Kal ffvyx^iffBai.
iSiov ex^i ffXVI^^ ouS^ TrQidrrtTa The same was held by Chrys-
(car' av7-f}v [fcaS' afir^r] ' ciel S' ly ippus, according to Stob. Eel. i.
Tici irxhM-^'^^ 1^^ TroidrriTi ejvai, 432, who says Posidonius held
:

Staipepetf Se T^v ohfriav t^s SXt^j, that there were four varieties
t)}v oZtrav Katk r^v imSffTcurty^ of change, those Karct Siatpeaiv,
iwimltf/iivov. <9i4pZ. Phys. 50 Kar' aWolaunv (water to air),
rh &iroioif <Ta/xa rijp irponlffTt\v kotA ffvyxvffiv (chemical com-
iXilv elvai <pa<riv. Further par- bination), Kar' avd\viriVf the
ticulars on matter hereafter. latter also called riiv 4^ 3\ai'
' Porphyr. in Simpl. Cat. 12, /iCTajBoA^v. ToirtDV S^ r^v Kar'
5 : 5itt6v i(TTL rh vTroKelfnyov ov aWoiaffiy Trepl rijv ovffiav yiyvs-
fi6vov KaTOL robs aTrh rris <rToas crfloi (the elements, according
oA.\a Karh robs Trpea^UTepovs. to the Stoics, changing into each
Deoeipp. See following note. other) ris Si iWas rpeis trepl
^ IHug. 150 oicrlav Se (piuTi
: rovs iroiobs \yo/i4povs Toi/s 4vl
Tuv tyrav airdvTwy t^v Kp^Ti)v rrjs ovffias yiyyo[ievovs. arcoAoiJ-

iSk-i\v. So thought Zeno and Bas Si Toirois Kal rhs yeviaas


Chrysippus v\7) Se iariv { ^s
: (Tvfi$aiveiv. T^v ykp ovaiav otfr'
^TtSTjTTOTOuv yiyerai. KaKe^rat 5e a^^eoBai o&re fieiovaOai . . 4vl .

Sixas ovffia re Kol ii\7], tJ re twi/ Si Twv (5toT Ttotuiv (which may
nivTuy Kal fuv 4ir\ fiepos. ij
tj be understood, not of individual
fih' oZv Twv h\av oihe TrKelaf properties, but of individually
oi/TE iKdrrtev ylverat, ri Sk tuv determined things) olov Aiavos
hrX fiepovs Kol irKiiav Kal iKdrrwi'. Kal &e(avos, Kol av^iiffets Kal fj.eLci-
Stob. Eel. i. 322: {Ziivuvos-) ams yiyveaBai. (These words are
ovaiav 8e eivai t^ii rav ivrav explained by Pramtl, 432, thus
irdvrav vpeiTTiv S\tiv, rairriv Se qualitative determination ad-
vSurav itSioj/ Kol oSre irKelia -yiyvo- mits increase or decrease of
fifinjv oine iKdrro), ra 5e juepj intensity but the use of the
;

102 THE STOICS.

Chap. The second category, that of property' or form,


V.
comprises all those essential attributes, by means of
(7) T/ie
category of terms ait,i\(ns and fidoKris, and ras [juei/] iv f^^P^^ Trdtras ovffias
property indeed the whole context no pitp KoX 0pe(T6aL, ra fiev i^ avrwp
or form. less than the passage quoted fiedelffas, ra Se no6ep iirt6pra
from Diogenes, prove that they "TrpoirSsxo^iipas oTs Se irpiffGitrt

refer rather to the increase or Kal &7rei<nv apiBfiois Kol TrA^fleffic,

diminution of substance in the TaDra ju?) Siafj[.4petp, aKK* erepa


individual thing.) Sih Kal vapa- yiypeirdat rats eiprifiepais Trpo(r6-
fi^Vilv rijv eKdffTOu iroi6T'rjTa ajr^ Sois, 4^aWay^p rrjs ot}(rlas KafjL-
TVS yepeffeci}^ H-^XP'- "r^^ avaipeaeais. ^apoicTis. That of this per-
. . . raf iSiats irotuy 5i5o
eiri 5e petually changing material it
/xev t^ SeicTiKO, fi6pta
ilvai (pOfTi should be said /h<)t' av^6i),ipov
(individual things have two fi^Te iiewifisvop may appear
component parts, which are strange but the meaning is
;

capable of change), -ri ii.h n this it can only be said of an


:

Kara r^y t^s ovaias \nr6(no.<Tiv t!) individual thing that it in-
/Se Ti Karct t^jv tov iroiov, rh yap creases and diminishes in so
[ISiuS TTOlhv'] its TTOWdKiS Kiyoji^v far as it remains as one and
T^u aii^riaiv Kai ttiv fi^iuxriv hriSe- the same subject, an iS'ms iroihp
Xeo'floi. Porphyr. See previous during the change but the ;

note. Dexipp. in Cat. 31, 15, material itself, which is ever


Speng. : ws itni rh uiroKeifievoi/ changing, cannot be regarded
SirrhVy oi/ fiSfOv Kar^ robs airh rris as the one identical subject, of
trrocis ciWh Kal KarciTohs irpea^v- increase and dlimiuution. This
repovSf ev ^61* rh \ey6fievov irpa- idea is expanded by Alea;.
rov imoKeifiei^ov, ois ^ &Troios SA-tj ApAro. Quffist. Nat, I. 5.
. Seiirepoj/ Se {nrokel[xevov rh ' TTOibp or "TToidrTjSf and also
Tfoibv fe Koivws % (Siws v^iararai^ Troths (sc. \6yos'). According to
VTToKcificyov yb.p KoX 6 ')(a\Khs KoX Simpl. 55, o, many Stoics assign
i iwKpdrTjS. Pint. Comm. Not. a threefold meaning to iroidp.
44, 4, p. 1083 (the Stoics assert) The first, which is also the most
us 5i5o Tiiiwv iKoffrAs iffnv viroKei- extensive meaning, includes
fiepa,rh fiiv ovffia, rh 5e [7rOi(J|/]. every kind of quality, whether
Kal rb jU6V cLcl ^ei Kal if>4peraL, /jiiir essential or accidental the tt&s
av^6fivoy fiijre i^eiQiifj.evoi/^ jU^t ixop as well as the rroiip. In
'6\(i>s otSu iffrt ^tafievov, rh Se the second meaning -nothp is
SittjUeret Kal au|civ6Tai Kol jUeiourai used to express^e?-OTfflerei quali-
Kal 'j:6,vra Trrftrxet ravavriaQhriptf ties, including those which are
(TVfinefpvKhs Kal trvvripfiofffiej/op Kal derivative and non-essential
ffvyKexvfiei'OV, Kal rTJs dia(f>opasT^ the (TxeVeij. In the third and
ai<r6'{i(reifi7jSafiovTrap4xoy oi^airBai, narrowest sense it expresses
The latter is the individual Toils airapri^opras (KOTct r^p ^K(/)o-
thing Itself, the former the mate- php) KaX 4ij.fj.6pas iipras Kar^
rial thereof, in reference to Sia<j>opcii' iroiohs, i.e. those quali-

which Plutarch had just said : ties which faithfully represent


roi Xiififiara (Tvyxupovaiv oSrof, essential attributes in their
:

FORMAL LOGIC: THE CATEGORIES. 103

which a definite character is impressed on matter Chap.


V.
otherwise indeterminate.' If the definite character

distinctive features. The sub- the nature of the object to which


stantive iroidTTis is only used in they belong: rets fiiv ycip ffxe'ceij
the last sense. TOLS iiTLKTfjTois KaTaffTdfTeffi xpc[-
' Sim.pl.
57, 6 (the passage KTvp^CetrBuL rhs Se e'|6is Tais i^
is fully discussed by Petersen, eavTcov ivepyelais. A
more limited
85, and Trendeleiibwrg, 223) meaning, that of local position,
is given to o-xeVis in Stob. Eel.
TTjros rh liri riav ffoifjAroiV Xeyovci i. 410.
Siocpop^v elj/ai Qi}alas oijk &n-oSta- The distinction between
Atjtttt;!' (separable, i.e., from and (rvva<j>ii also belongs
Eveoffis

matter) Ka6' eaurV, "^^' ^^^ ^^ here. Only that, the oneness of
P(Jj]/Aa Kal idt6T7ira [sc. fiiav'] which depends on an essential
avoXiiyovffav ovre XP^^V ^^"^^ quality is i)vujji.ivov everything
else is either (fvrt\ii}i,ivov or ix
aVTTIS T0!0UT(Jt1JTI, Kad' %V TTOLOV Sieo'TtJTO);'. Sext. Math. ix. 78
In place of
v((}i(rTaTai yevetris. (also in vii. 102) : twx re ffufid-
p Petersen, 85, with the
v6riij,a Tiay tA jueV iffTiv Tjvwfieya, res 5e 4k
approval of Trendelenhwrg and ffwanTOfievuv Tol.Se 4k SieffTciTajf '

Prcmtl (433, 96), reads 4m6i\i).a. Tli/ufjLeira fievohv effri to virb fiias
To me, Brandts Schol. 69, a, e|e&)y KpaToifiefa, KaOdjrep tffvrol
32, appears to retain it with Kal f&ja (rvi/d<pia applies to

reason, the meaning being that chains, houses, ships, &c. ; com-
iroi(JTT)r constitutes no indepen- bination 4k BieffTciirwy to flocks
dent unity, but only a unity of and armies. Seneca, Ep. 102, 6,
conception. Non-essentialqnali- Nat. Qu. ii. 2, says the same.
ties were by the Stoics excluded Conf. Alex. Be Mixt. 143:
from the category of iroibv, and ai/dyK-q 5e rh ev ffufia vnh fiias &s
reckoned under that of viis tpafftv e^ews ffvveXea'dat [1. avve-

eX<"'- XeffBaf]. Simpl. 55, e rhs yap :

The same distinction be- ttohJttjtos eKTck Xeyovres oSto [of


tween what is essential and ^TCaiKoV\ 4tr\ rWV TJUCilfjLiVUP fiSfO^J/

what is not essential is indi- iKTCt.&Tro\eiTroviTtv itrlSeTuv KaTa


cated in the terms 6|is and avvaip^v, oiov veois, Kal iirl rtev
Gx^ffis ttokJttjtcs, or essential
' Karii Sidaraaiv, olov irrpaTov, /xii-
properties, being called essen- Sey elvai sKrhv )ii7]Se evplffKeo'dai
tial forms (ejeis or l/crtS) ; non- TTvevpMriKdv Ti v iir' ainwv fitiSe
essential qualities being called cVa \6yoU '^xov Sxne ^m riva
features or varieties (irxe'ireis). virdtrraffiv 4\6etv [iias exeats.

See Simpl 54, y ; 55, e. In de- Those e|eis which admit of


termining essential attributes, no increase or diminution (eVi-
these, according to Simpt 61, Toirij, and Syeffis) are called 8io-

j3 (Schol. in Arist. 70, b, 43), Beffets or permanent forms.


are declared to be essential, not Virtues, for instance, which,
when they happeii to be perma- according to the Stoics, always
nent, but when they spring from exist in a perfect form where

104 TEE STOICS.

Chap. be one which belongs to a group or class, it is called


V.
a common quality Koiv&i -irocov or, if it be some-
thing peculiar and distinctive, it is called a distinctive
quality IhCtos ttolov.^ Properties therefore combined
with matter constitute the special materials out of
which individual things are made;^ and quality in
this combination (Trotov), corresponds, as Trendelen-
burg has well shown,' with the form {ethos) of
Aristotle.* It may, in fact, like that, be described

they exist at all, are SioflEcreis, avrcLs -KQiay afielyous, ojs /jLovffiK^

but arts are only ?|6ij. Simpl. They also dis-


fiouirMov, K.r.\.
Categ. 61, 3 72, 5 ; 73, /3 Sohol.
; ; tinguish between a thing and
in Arist. 70, b, 28; 76, a, 12, its oiiiria. Stob. Eel. i. 436 : fiii

24 ; StoT). Eel. ii. 98 and 128. elvai Tc ravrhv t6 ri iroibv l^lws


Conf. Petersen, 91. A different KoX TTij/ ouciay ^1 ^s ^(TTi rovro, ju^
view was takfen by Aristotle IxevTOi ye fi'fiS' erepov, aWa /xdvov
of the relations of these ex- ov Tavrhy, Sik rh kclI ^4pos elvat

pressions. TTjs oiifflas Kol Tbv at/rhv e-n-e'xeii'


' SyrioM. on Arist. Metaph. T^irov, TO 5' eVepa rivuv \ey6fieya
21 p. 90 in Petersen: koI ot StmikoI
,
detv Kai TSncft Kex^pfo'dai xoi jU^S'
Se Tovs Koivoijs ^otovs vph Tav IZiwv h ii4pei Seapt'ia'Bai. Conf. Sea^.
TToiav airoTlBevTai. Sfob. Eel. i. Pyrrh. iii. 170 ; Math. ix. 336 :

434 see above p. 101,


; 2. Simpl. at 5f ^tatKol olJTe erepov tov b\ov
De An. 61, a, explains iSfcus Toibs rh fiepos o^re rh avT6 tpaaiv
by ctTo^tu^ei' etSos. Diog. vii. vTrapX^iy and Seneca, Ep. 313,
138 ; Phit. 0. Not. 36, 3. 4. Mnesarchus, a fellow dis-
' Besides the passages already ciple of Posidonius, accordingly
quoted in note 2 on p. 101, from compares the relation of an
Plutarch and Stobseus, see Sext. individual thing to its (ouo-io)
Pyrrh. i. 57 tol Ktpvdfifva (the
: with that of a statue to the
intermingling materials, the material of which it is com-
question here is the possibility posed. Since the iSdos iroibs
of mingling) e'f oiirias kh! iroio- distinguishes a thing from
ri}Tuv irvyKuaBal <l>atriv. Por- every other, there follows as a
phyry in Simpl. Categ. 12, S matter of course, what is as-
contests this view himself. serted circumstantially and in
The therefore, clearly
Stoics, detail by Chrysippus (in PMla,
distinguish e{r, or essential Incorrupt. M. 951, B), Sn Suo
form, from the subject to which eiSoiroioiis [ = iSwi iroioij] tjrl T^s

it belongs ; and Philo must ouT^s QVffias ont.i\-)(avov ffutTT^-


have been following the Stoics vai.
when he said (Nom. Mutat. ' L. c. 222.
1063, D) ejeis yitp rav /for'
: * This may be seen from the
:

FORMAL LOGIC: THE CATEGORIES. 105

as the active and efficient part of a thing.' Aristotle's Chap.


V.
form, however, expresses only the non-material side
of a thing, whereas quality is regarded by the Stoics
as something material in fact, as an air-current.^
Hence the mode in which a quality is conceived to
reside in matter is that of an intermingling of ele-
ments.' The same theory of intermingling applies of
course to the union of several properties in one and
the same matter,* and likewise to the combination of

passages quoted in note 2 on iy To7s Trepl e^twp o^Stv &\\o ris


the previous page. ir\^v &pas ehai tftijaiv' inrh
e'leis

Pha. St. Rep. 43, 4, p. 1054


' rovTotv yctp tru^exeTat refc (rtj^fiara,
r^v }i\T\v ap')hy 4^ eavTTJs Koi Kal 70V TTOihv iKaffrov eli/ai aXriOS
a.Kiv7iT(yy itiroK&ifTdanaisiroiSTijiTiv 6 ffvv4xt^v a-fip effTiv, hv ffKKiip6-
airotpaivovatj rks 5c Trot6T7yras TTjTa i^kv 4v (nZiip(^, TrvKfirriTa S' ^

infeiifj.aTa oVtras Kal t6vovs aepc- iv \i8tp, \evK6TTiTa S' 4v apyvpcfi


5eis ots Uv iyyevtovrat t^4fie(ri ttjs Ka\ov<nv. Simpl. 69, 7: n tSsv
UA-t/s eiSoTTotelv eKaffra Kal ffxn]fia.- ^TULKuv StJ^a KeyovTuv, (rdfAara
Ti(fLV.It is a carrying out of dlj/at ri (rx'tlfiara Sxrirep ra &\\a

the Stoic teaching (as Simpl. TToii. Ibid. 67, e ; 56, S : vas 5e
57, remarks) for Plotinus to
e, Kal TTPeu/xariK^ r) ovffia eaTai tuv
reduce -noihiis to the class- atufiariKwy irotoriircav aitov rou
conception of Sivafus (Enn. vi. irue^ifiaTos (rvvBerov ivros, k.t.\.
1, 10, 574, P). But the Stoic ' AleoB. Aplvr. An. 143, De
definition of Svvafiis (quoted by b : irws Se <xta^6vTwv eVri ttiv irepl
Si/nvpl, 58, a
^ TrKiUvuv iirot- Kpdaews KOtv^v :rp6\'r]>iitv rh Keyetv
ariK^ ffv/jLTTTQifitirav, with the ad- Kal T^y e|ii/ TOW exovatu avr^jv
ditional words KaX KaraKparodaa fj-efiixdat KoX 7i]V (f>iffiPTo7s (t>VTOts

ruv iyepyeLuii/ does not directly Kal rh ^U)S T^ aepi Kal Ti]y ^vx'h^
refer to iroi6rTjs. ITokJttjs may Tip aiiiiaTi. Ibid. 144, a, the
also be connected with the saying is quoted against the
Aoyos (TirepjuaTi/cds. See Plotin. Stoics : fisfux^at rf vKy rhy
i.29, 593, A
ci 8e rh. iroio S\-i\v
: et6v.
votav Keyoiey^ irpurov fjikv ol \6yoi Plut. C. Not. 36, 3
* : K4yov-
auToTs em\ot aW' oiiK iv ii\ri civ ovToi Kal Tr\drTovtTiy iirl fiias

yevifievoL frvvBeTov Ti TtoiT\troii(Ti.v ovHas Bio Wiais yei/4(r6at Troiovs


. . . ovK &pa avTol etSn oiSi \6yoi. (this follows from their hypo-
Diog. vii. 148 : tan ii <piats ef is thesis, but it is distinctly denied
[ =
7roi(iT7)s] ^1 avTrjs KiVOvpLivi), by Chrysippus in thesis. See
KaTcb ffTTfptiaTiKOv^ \6yovs airoTe- p. 104, 2) Kal T^v aiiT^v ovffiav eva
hovai Te KaX awix"'""'' ^ ^5 iroihviSius exovaaf 4vt6v7os erepov
niir^s, K.T.\. SeX^'''^^^ '^^^ Siaxpuh&TTtiif dftoias
2 Plut. Ibid. 2 (Xpiamnos')
: afMporepovs.
;;

IOC THE STOICS.

Chap. several attributes to produce a single conception of


V.
quality.' In all cases the relation is supposed to be
a materialistic one, and is explained by the doctrine
of the mutual interpenetration of material things.^
This explanation, indeed, could not apply to every
kind of attributes. Unable to dispense entirely with
things not material,^ the Stoics were obliged to admit
the existence of attributes belonging to immaterial
things, these attributes being, of course, themselves
not material.* What idea they formed to themselves

' Simpl. 70, e koI oi StcoikoI


: said to be material and in all ;

5e TroUTTyras noioTt]T(av iroiovtrLv cases when they are combined,


tavTuv (? iKT&v) iroiovvres cktols each property retains its own
e|eis [1. 6KTO Koi e|efs or e|ets peculiarity, and yet is inherent
only]. The context shows that in the subject-matter and in
the meaning of these words is every other property belonging
that given above. The con- to the same subject-matter
ception of a property is com- it follows that this relation can
pounded of several attributes, only be explained by supposing
and, therefore, a property of a mutual interpenetration of
several subordinate properties. properties with each other and
If hevKhv is a xp^M* ^^^ ^^"" with their subject-matter.
KpiTiKiv t^fus is the e|is, or form ' The proof of this will be

of \iVKbv. given subsequently. Meantime


^This follows of necessity, compare the remarks, p. 92, 2
quite independently of the 94, 1 on the \^kt6v.
above quoted language of Alex- * Simpl. 56, S, and, 54, (3 : oi
ander, from the Stoic doctrine Se 'Ztu'CkoX rwf fikv awfidrwy ffoi-
of the material nature of pro- ^arirc^s, rap Se aaufidrav aatcixd-
perties and of the mingling of Tovs elyai \4you(rt ras TroiiTTjras.
materials. B'or if that inter- Only the ffaifiariKol tokJttjtes
mingling of materials in which are TrveinaTu, see p. 105, 2 ; in-
each one retains its properties corporeal properties are called
(juifis and Kpaffis in contrast to IktS, to distinguish them from
chemical combination icapdei(ns e|6 (essential forms). Dexipp.
and defined to be
ffiiyxyc's') is in Cat. 61, 17, Speng.: eaviidfa
the complete interpenetration Si Twv "SirmKuv X'^P^C^^'^^*' "^^^
of one material by another, e|eis airh rSav eKTWv
iurtifiara yap
without passing into a third IJiil irapaSix^iievoi Kaff eavTh, Srav
(^Stoi. Eel. i. 376; Alex. De ipefrx^^eii/ Sedv fi ^irl ris roiairas
Mixt. 142, a Plut. C. Not. 37,
;
SioX'^i)(eis epxovrai. But this use
2) ; if, moreover, properties are of terms appears not to have
FORMAL LOGIC: THE CATEGORIES. 107

of these incorporeal attributes, when reality was con- Chap.


'

sidered to belong only to things corporeal, it is, of


course, impossible for us tq determine.'
The two remaining categories include everything (5) The

which may be excluded from the conception of a ^fi-^'etl

accidental.
ITT
thing on the ground of being either non-essential or
In so
r
far as
11-
such things belong to the
,1 -,
""/^
variety nf
relation.

object taken by itself alone, they come under the


category of variety {ttcos %oi/) ; but when they belong
to it, because of its relation to something else, they
come under the category of variety of relation (yrpo9
Ti TTtos s%ov). Variety includes all accidental quali-
ties, which can be assigned to any object indepen-
dently of its relation to any other object.^ Size,
colour, place, time, action, passion, possession, mo-
tion, state, in short, all the Aristotelian categories,
with the exception of substance, whenever they apply
to an object independently of its relation to other
objects, belong to the category of variety' (ttci)? e%ov).

beenuniversalamong the Stoics (rutj.d'Tuv erepas Se iirt toiv atru-


(Simpl. Categ. 54, 7), with fnaTov aSrij i^etrrriKs.
whom different views prevailed ^ Simpl. 44, S: b Se ttji'
touching tlie extent of the con- ar6.(nv koI t^v Kdditrti/ fii] irpoff-
ception of 4kt6i>. According to voiovp.evof (including sc. rois
this passage it was Antipater oSo-ic) eoiite 'StusU^ tiki a-vvriOela
who wished to include under nweTrfaBai ovSiv &K\o 1j t!i

e/CTO, the KOivh nvjorTiiiaTa {nroKel/isyoi' ris Se


^ivcu vofiiQav,
(Ta^iiToiv Kol affwp.6,Tt>iv. Trepl avrh Stmpophs ayvTroaraTovs
'
Conf. Simpl. 57, e, who iiyoifievos Kal iriij exovra, outoc

after giving the definition of airoxaKuv lis iv rots viroKeifieyois


quality, quoted p. 103, 1, con- ex""'^'^ ""'^^ toSto rh iriis exeiy.
tmues : iy Si Toirois, ft fii) oX6v 'Dexipp. in Cat. 41, 20,
Tc Korh rhv ixeivaiv \6yov Koivlv Speng. ei Se tij eij t!) iris %xov
.

fivat ffifiirrafia ffufidruiv re koX ffvyrdrroi ras trKearras Karii-


aaaiiirav, oiiKert effrat yhos fi yoplas, Sffirep oJ Sraii/col iroiovffiv.
TroKJTTjs, 4^^' ^repais /liv inl ruv Plotin. vi. 1, 30, 594, A : iraJs Si
1C8 THB STOICS.

Chap. On the other hand, those features and states which


V.
are purely relative such as right and left, sonship
and fatherhood, &c. come under the category of
variety of relation {irpos rl ttws sxov) ; a category
from which the simple notion of relation (jirpos rl)
must be distinguished. Simple relation {-rrpos tI) is

not spoken of as a distinct category, since it includes


not only accidental relations, but also those essential
properties (ttokz) which presuppose a definite rela-
tion to something elsesuch as knowledge and
perception.*

ev Th TTihs
^x^> iroWrjs Btatpopas Simpl 42, e ot Si StidikoI
' :

^v avTots oijffiis ; ttws yhp rh iivfffvhs yepovs Svo Kara rhv t6-
Tpi-JTTI^VKal T^ \evKhu 6tS tv TQV TOVTOV apidfiOVVTOl, TBL fiCV y
[y4vos Bereov'], rov fiev ttouov tov T0is'jrp6s Ti TLdevres, Tct 8' ey toTj
Se TTOiov liyros ; ttws 5e tI ttotc vp6s ri irojs ^xovo't, koI t^ /iev
KoX nov
rh irSts 5e ; '6\tiis irits Trp6s Ti avriSiatpout/res rots Koff
exovra rh x^*s '^^ '^^ trepvffi Kal aina, to 5e irpcis t irois eX"'"'''*
rh 4v AvKelip Kol ec ^AKaSriyiif; Tols Kara. Statpitpdv, (Ibid. 44, j8 :

Kal '6\us TrSbs Se 6 -xp^vos iris 01 StwVkoI l/O^t^outn TTliffTlS TT}S

^X^ ; . . . ri Se Troietv irSis iris KaTct Siafpop^v iStdrrjTOs ainjX-


^Xoy . Kl *5 irdffxoy ov ir&is \6.xQo.i Kp6s rl ircijs ^x*"''^"')
Tcfc

1x01/ . . .iffwsB^ h.v fi6vovapiJi6iTt Sweet and bitter belong to to


^irl TOV Heiffdai
^X^ '^"^ ^'^^ rh Trits sp6s Ti to the other class belong

TOW ^X^^^ ^^^ ^^ ''"*'" exeiv ov irdjs


' Se^ihs, irar^p, &c., KdTa dta(f>opau
fXof kA.A.4 eX""- Simpl. Oateg. 94, 5 ^afft TO. Kard Ti elBos x^P^'^'
: The Stoics included ex^'>' TTipi^d/ieva. Every Kafl' out!) is
under Tris ^X""- ^ saying as also kutA Sia</>opdK (determined
Simpl. 16, S, does that the Stoics as to quality), and every irp6s rl
omitted time, and place,
iroahv, iras ex"" is also a Trpis Ti, but
it must be meant that they did not conversely. Conf. 43, /3. ft
not treat these conceptions as Si Set ffatpeffrepoy fjLera\afieiy rcL
separate categories. What they KeyS/j-eva^ Trpds ri fiiv Xiyovffiv
did with them Simpl. explains 5o"a KttT' oiKeior x-P'^'^^P^ ^'""
1. c. 61 yhp rh TT^s ^X^** voiti^ovaiv KeifievA TTtos anoyevei irphs frepov
avTQts roiavra Trepihafj-^dveiif.
Tct (or,according to the definition
Trendelenbwg, 229,withjustice, in Sext. Math. viii. 454 irp6s :

observes that, wherever the Ti ^o'Ti rh Trpbs ereptp yooifievov'),


species-forming difference lies irpds Ti 5e irus exovfa bira TreipvKe
in iroffhv as in mathematical fTVfi^aiveiv rivl kal }ii] avfi^aivetv
conceptions, there woahv comes &vev T^s wepi ouret fiera^oKris Kal
under ttoi6i'. &\Koiiiffeus jUETct ToD TTphs rh iKrhs
FORMAL LOGIC: THE CATEGORIES. 109

The relation of these four categories to one another Chap.


V.
is such, that each preceding category is included in
the one next following, and receives from it a more (f)
^'''''-

definite character.' Substance never occurs in reality categories

without property, but has always some definite quality *" ""^
another.
to give it a character. On the other hand, property
is never met with alone, but always in connection
with some subject-matter.^ Variety presupposes
some definite substance, and variety of relation sup-
poses the existence of variety.' It will hereafter be

ojrojSXeiretv, Sffre ^av jttey kotA the addition of a fresh deter-


Bia(l>opdv T( BiaKeifxevov irphs erepov mination a better name for
;

Vk{)ffriy vp6s Ti ^6vov rouTO tffrai, the second category would be


&s 71 e^ts Ka\ 71 iTria'T'tiiJ.rj Koi 7] {moKei^iva iroii- for the third,
aiffSTjcris ' Srav Se fi^ Kara riji/ iixoKeifleya Trotd irus exoyra for '

iyovffai/ Sia(f)ophp Karh i/ziA^l/ Se the fourth, inroKeifieya Troii Trp6s


tJjc irphs erepoy (rx^(^tv deoipTiTat, tI ttws exocTtt. In support of
'iTp6s Ti TTws exayra earai S yhp ' this, he refers to Simpl. 43, a :

vihs Kal 6 5e|iis ^aOev Tiywv irpoff- rb


eirerai Se avrols KaKelyo 6.tottov
SetJcTOi, TTphs TTJV v7r6ffTafTLV ' 5tb (TvySeTa noieTyrAyeyri eKirporepuy
KoL (i7\Bepiia.s ytyofjL4v7]S irepl aifrct, Tiy&y Kal SeuTepcuy a>s t6 T^p6s rt
fieTa$o\7Js y^voLr' hy 0VK4ri iror^p, iK TTotoO Kal 70V 7rp6s ri. Plut.
Tov vtov a'iroday6yTOSj 6 Se Se|tis C. Not. 44, 6 rerrapd ye iroiouffiy
:

rod irapaKeifjLevov fjLeraartiyTos ' rh mrOKiifliva Trepl iKaffToy, piaWov


Se yKvKv naX nmpby hv aWoia oiiK Se Terrapa eKa'jroy Plot. 7}/j.wy.

yivoLTO el /x^ ffvufxera^dWot koIti Bnn. 593,


vi. 1, 29, droiros v A :

irepl avTo, Siyafus. In this sense, Siaipeats iyBarepCfiTuy eiSwy


. . .

therefore, 7rp6s ti belongs to t6 erepoy Tideiffa, Hairephy [elfj riy


Troihy, being composed (as Sim^l. Siaipwy TTjy ^Tri(rri]p.7]y r^y fiky
43, o, says) of Troihv and 7rp6s ti. ypafifiaTiK^v Kiyoi, r^y Se ypafina-
On the other hand, wp6s rl irws TLK^v Kal &\\o Tt
if iTotd are to
exo" only expresses, to quote be Bat) ttoiA, they are composed
Seriart, an accidental relation. of 8Ar| and See
eTSos or \6yos.
PrcmtVs quotation (I. 437, 108) p. 48, 2.
from Simpl. 44, ;8, we have no See p. 103, 1.
2

special reason to refer to the See p. 107, 2 Plotin. vi. 1,


' ;

Stoics. 30 "Why are iris exoyro enu-


:

Trendeleribwg, 220, con- merated as a third category,


siders that these genera are in since Trdyra irepl rijy vKrjy irtDs

so far subordinate to one ano- ixovTo. the Stqics would pro-


;

ther, that the previous one bably say that 7rai& are irepl TTjy
continues in the next, but with u\7iy Triis ^xoyra, whereas the
110 THE STOICS.

Chap. seen how closely these deductions, and, indeed, the


V.
whole doctrine of the categories, depend on the meta-
physical peculiarities of the Stoic system.

(3) CoTii- Passing from incomplete to complete utterance,


jilete ut-
we come, in the first place, to sentences or proposi-
terance.
(a) Jutlg- tions,' all the various kinds of which, as they may be
vient.
deduced from the different forms of syntax, were enu-
merated by the Stoics with the greatest precision.^
Detailed information is, however, only forthcoming
in reference to the theory of judgment (a^lcofia),
which certainly occupied the greatest and most im-
portant place in their speculations. A judgment is

a perfect utterance, which is either true or false.'

TriisexovTo, in the strict sense efi())Epijs i! Po'm6\os ! by Sextus


of the term, are irepl tA iroia. called n\eiov fl a^taiia), Ammon.
Yet since the woict themselves in Waitz, Arist. Orig. i. 43,
are nothing more than SAtj ttws speaks of ten forms of senteijces
%%'>'""'> ^11 categories must be held by the Stoics, mentioning,
ultimately reduced to liKi). however, only two, irpoaTaKTMis
Prantl, Gesoh. d. Logik, i.
' and e^KTUids (so reads the MS.
440-467. "Waitz suggests 4(piKriKds, more
2 In Diog. 66 Sext. Math, ; probably it is cvktikos). Diog.
viii. 70; Ammon. De Interp. 4, 191, mentions treatises of
a (Schol. in Arist. 93, a ; 22, b, Chrysippus on interrogatory
20) ; Sim.pl. Cat. 103, o ; Boith. and hortatory sentences. On
De Interp. 315 Cramer, Kneci.
; the relation of an oath to df lu/^a
Oxon. iii. 267, conf. I. 104, a light is thrown by Simpl. 1. c,
distinction is drawn between also by Chrysippus' distinction
at^tafM (a judgment), ip(iTr]ii.a (a between h.KT\QopKeiv and ^vopKiiu
direct question, requiring Yes ^^vSopxeiy and iiriopKe^v in Stoi.
or No), TtiffjM (an Inquiry), Floril. 28, 15.
irpoffTaKTLKdy, dpKLiiiy, apariKdv ' JHog. 65 a^lmfia Si effriv 3
:

(wishes), (VKTiKhv (a piayer), itrjiv a\Tj9esfi ^evBos. Questions


iiroSetiKhv (a supposition), eK9- and other similar sentences are
tik6v(qs 4KKiiT6Q} svdeia ypttfifi^'), neither true nor false (Ibid. 66
irpoirayopevTiK^v (an address), and 68). This definition of a
6av^.aaTiK6v, ^^KTiichv, hrairoprj- judgment is constantly referred
TiKdv, afjyqytj^TtKiiv (explanatory to, see p. 83, 2, by Simpl. Cat.
statements), '6p.otoy afn^fiari (a 103, o do. Tuso. i. 7, 14 De
; ;

judgment with something ap- Tato, 10, 20 Gell N. A. xvi. 8,


;

pended, as : &s Upia/iiSriinv 8; Schol. in Arist. 93, b, 35.


;; .
;

FORMAL LOaiC: JUDGMENT. ViV

Judgments are divided into two classes : simple Chap.


judgments, and composite judgments.' By a simple
'

judgment the Stoics understood a judgment which is

purely categorical.^ Under the head of composite


judgments are comprised hypothetical, corroborative,
copulative, disjunctive, comparative, and causal judg-
ments.^ In the case of simple judgments, a greater (n) Simple
'" '^'^"^ '

or less definiteness of expression is substituted by the


Stoics in the place of the ordinary difference in re-
spect of quantity s"* and with regard to quality, they

The purport of the expression (Schol. in Arist. 44, a, 9


h^yos aTro<pavrLK6s, T^KTiv aivo- Prantl, 446, says this passage
(pavriv (in Dioff. 65 ; Gfell. xvi. is not quite correct ; it only
8, i ; Amman. De Interp. 4, a implies that the term a-vfm-XoKi]
Sohol. in Arist. 93, b, 20) is the was confined to a copulative
same. judgment); for the aiViSSej,
I
Seiet. Math viii. 93 : t&v which is characterised by a
yap a^tw[j.aT<aj/ TrpaTriv (TxeSiy Kal SiiiTi, and therefore is not iden-

KupitordTTiv iKtpepovffi Sicupopaf ot tical with the TTapa(rutfT]fj.^vov,


Bta\eiiTiKolKafl' ^y rd li-^v iffriv Diog. 72 and 74; for the 5ia-
avTuv airKa ret 5' ovx airAa. IMd. (TOfpovv r^ ^a\}\ov and the Sio-
95 and 108. Diog. 68 gives the eraipovv tA ^ttov, Diog. 72 ; conf
definitions of both. Crcumer, Anecd. Oxon. i. 188
^ Sext. 1. c., by whom Biog. Apollon. Synt. (iJcAier's Anecd.
must be corrected, see p. 113, 3. ii.), 481. These are only some
^ Diog. 69 : iv Se rols ovx of the principal forms of com-
atrKots Th ffvvriy^^hov koX rh napa- posite judgments, their number
avvTififievov Kal rb ffvinreirXeyfievoi^ being really indefinite. Chrys-
Kal rh alriwdes Kal rb SieCevyf/.eyov ippus estimated that a million
Kal rb Biaffaipovv -rb iui.K\op Kal combinations might be formed
rb rb ^ttov. Further
Siacra(j>ovii with ten sentences. The cele-
details presently respecting the brated mathematician, Hippar-
(rvvriiJLii.hov and Ste^evyjiivov. For chus, however, proved that only
the i!apa<rvvr\iJiiihov a condi- 103,049 affirmative and 310,952
tional sentence, the first part of negative judgments could be
which is introduced by eVeiS); formed with that material (Pint.
see Diog. 71 and 74 for the ;
Sto. Eep. 29, 5, p. 1047; Qu.
(rvfiireTrKeyfLevov, the charac- Symp. viii. 9, 3, 11, p. 732).
< There no notice of a
teristic of which is the Kal and is

Kal, see Diog. 72 Sext. Math, ;


division of judgments into
viii. 124 Gell. N. A. xvi. 8 and
;
general and particular. Instead
9 Ps. Galen, EiVay. SioK. 13
;
of that, Sext. (Math. viii. 96)
Dexipp. in Cat. 27, 3, Speng. distinguishes oipiff/neVa as oStos
112 THE STOICS.

Chap. not only make a distinction between afErmative and


V.
negative judgments,' but, following the various forms
of language, they speak of judgments of general
negation, judgments of and
particular negation,
judgments of double negation.^ Only affirmative
and negative judgments have a contradictory relation
to one another all other judgments stand to each
;

other in the relation of cojitraries.' Of two proposi-


Kd6ir]rai, aSpiffra as rh KddTjrai, dictory ayritpcuns, a contrary
and fieira as &v6p(onos KtiBr/Tai, fvavTiirns, putting both under
^coKpdTTJS irepliraTeL. theWhen the class conception of avrmei-
subject stood in the nominative, lieva. The Stoics reserved av-
were called Trarayopev-
ojptfjfi4va rLKfl/ieva -for contradictories
TiKo QBwg. 70) the others kuthi-
; (^Simpl. Cat. 102, S and 102, C,
yopiKti a KarayopevTiKbv is ovtos
'
a Stoic discussion intended to
TrepnraTeT* a kaivqyopiKiv, Aicay show that the conception of
TreptiraTel. ivavTiov is not applicable to
' An affiimative judgment negative sentences and con-
was called Kara^aTiKiv, a nega- ceptions), which is after all
tive a7ro</>oTiKiJv, by Chrysippus only a difference in termi-
in the fragment about to be nology. ''Eva.vrlov they also call
quoted, and Simpl. Cat. 102, 8, liaxififvov{Apolhn. Synt. 484,
C Apul. Dogm. Plat. iii. 266, Bekk.). Otherwise, following
Oud. renders these terms by de- Aristotle, they distinguished
dicativa and abdicativa. For between ivavTiov and iyavrltos
the manner in which they ex- ixov tvavrla are conceptions
pressed negative sentences, see which are in plain and imme-
JBoith. De
Interp. 373 ; Schol. diate contrast, such as ipp6vriais
in Arist. 120. and a<pp6vrnTis iyavrlus ^xoyra

^ Biog. 69 gives an example are those which are only con-


of apvTjTiKdVj ovSels irepitrarei * trasted by means of the ^mvrla,
one of particular negation, such as (j>p6vLfios and &tppa)y
ffTepTyriKov a(i}i?ijiv9pwn6s etrriv (Simpl. Categ. 98, 7). The
OVTOS one of double negation, former, therefore, apply to ab-
inrepaTTOcpaTtKbl' as, ovxl 7ifi4pa stract, the latter to concrete
ovK iarl. notions. That every negative
' Seait. Math. viii. 89
; Mot/. judgment has an affirmative
73 : avTiKeiiifva are Sc t^ eVepov judgment opposed to it is
Tov irepov iffrltf anro'tiaTlKij' elaborately proved by a series
or (according to' the outward of quotations from poets, each
treatment of these determina- one of which is four times re-

tions) aTrO(/)({ffl -TrKeoyAC^l as. It peated in the fragment wep! oiro-
is day, and It is not day. Aris- {pariKiSv first edited hyZetronne-
totle called such a contra- (Fragments in6dits,Paxis, 1838),
^ ;

FORMAL LOGIC: JUDGMENT. 113

tions which are related as contradictories, according Chap.


V.
to the old rule, one must be true and the other
false.

Among composite judgments the most impor- (^) Com,-


posite
tant are the hypothetical and the disjunctive. As judgments.
regards the latter, next to no information has reached
us.^ A hypothetical judgment (crvvrjiiiisvov) is a
judgment consisting of two clauses, connected by the
conjunction ' if,' and related to one another as cause
and effect ; the former being called the leading
{fjiyovfievov), and the latter the concluding or inferen-
tial clause {Xrj<yov).^ In the correctness of the infer-
ence the truth of a hypothetical judgment consists.

and subsequently emended, ex- ' Divg. 71 ; Seast. Math. 109


;

plained, and with a great degree Qalen, De Simpl. Medicamen.


of probability referred to Chry- ii. 16, vol. xi. 499 ; Ps. Galen,

sippus by Bergk (De Chrysippi EiVa-y. Sio\. p. 15. The Stoics


libro ir/>l airocpaTiKai/, Cassel, distinguish most unnecessarily,
1841, Gymn. progr.). In ex- but quite in harmony with
plaining the fragment Pi'antl, their ordinary formal punc-
Gesoh. d. Log. I. 451 appears to tiliousness, the case in which
have hit the truth in one point, the leading clause is identical
where Bergk is not satisfied. with the inferential clause (ei
' Simpl. Categ. 103, /3 Cic. ; ri/ifpa iarXv, vnepa eirrij') and the
De Fato, 16, 37 ; N. De. i. 25, case in which it is different (el
70. Further particulars above riiiepa iffrlv, ipSs ea-riv). Con-
p. 83, 2; 110, 3. ditional sentences of the first
" Viz. that the members kind are called iupopoiiuva
of a disjunction, as well as their ffui-ri/i/ici/a. Sext. viii. 281 ;

contradictory opposites, must 294; and 466; Pyrrh. ii. 112;


also be contraries (adversa or conf. viii. 95; Diog. 68. That
pugnantia), and that from the in all these passages Sujiopoi-
truth of the one the falsehood fievov must be read, and not
of the other follows. A dis- Suupopoifiemv, appears according
junction which does not satisfy to ProMtVs (p. 445, 122) very
one or the other of these con- true observation from the re-
ditions is false (iropoSiefeiry^tte- marks of Alex. Top. 7, a Anal. ;

vov). Gell. N. A. xvi. 8, 12 Pr. 7, b, on Supopoinivoi avWo-


Sext. Pyrrh. ii. 191 ; Alex. yifffioi.

Anal. Pr. 7, b.
; ;

114 THE STOICS.

Chap. As to the conditions upon which the accuracy of an


V.
inference rests, different opinions were entertained
within the Btoic School itself.' In as far as the

' Sext. Math. viii. 112 But, in any case, the meaning
KOttiws fxej/ ydp ^oativ &jrq.vm oi appears to have been {Diog. vii.
AiaA.KTiKoi vyies eivai ffvpijfifievoVf 81), that, in the cases men-
Srtiy aKo\ot;0^ t^ ev avT^ ryyou- tioned, conditional sentences
fi,4vcf) rh iy uiiT^ X^yoif. irepl Se may be right, not that they
must be right.
^ovtTi Trp6s aW'fiKovs Kal p-ax^fi-^va Others more appropriately
Trfs ttKoXovBias iKriBevrai Kpiriipta. judged of the correctness of
do. Acad. ii. 47, 143 In hoc : conditional sentences by the
quod in elementis dialec-
ipso, connection of their clauses,
tici dooent, quomodo judicare either requiring, for a con-
oporteat, rerum f alsumne sit, si ditional sentence to be right,
quid ita connexum est, ut hoc : that the contradictory opposite
Si dies est, lucet ; quanta con- (ivTiviiiiivov') of the inferential
teutio est aliter Diodoro aliter
I clause should be irreconcileable
Philoni, Chrysippo aliter placet. with the leading clause, or that
(The further remarks on the the inferential clause should be
points of difference between potentially (Suvei/icj) contained
Chrysippus and Cleanthes have in the leading clause (^Sext.
no reference to hypothetical Pyrrh. ii. 111). The first of
judgments.) The Philo here these requirements, which is

alluded to ^the same Philo mentioned by IHog. 73 as the
against whom Chrysippus wrote only criterion of the Stoic
his treatises (^Diog. vii. 191 School, was due to Chrysippus,
and 194), the well-known dia- who accordingly refused to al-
lectician, and pupil of Diodorus low sentences in which this was
had declared all conditional not the case to be expressed hy-
sentences to be right in which pothetically ( Cio. DeFato, 6, 12
a false inferential clause is not 8, 15) it was not right to say,
:

drawn from a true leading Si quis natus est oriente cani-


clause. According to this view, cula, is in mari non morietur
conditional sentences would be but, Nonet natus est quis oriente
right, with both clauses true, canicula et is in mari morietur.
or both false, or with a false It may be observed, in con-
leading clause and true in- nection with the enquiry into
ferential clause (jSteiKi. 1. u. viii. the accuracy of conditional
245 and 449 Pyrrh. ii. 110).
; sentences, that a true con-
According to Sext. Pyrrh. ii. ditional sentence may become
104, the view of Philo appears false in time. The sentence,
to have gained acceptance If Dion is alive now, he will
among the Stoics, perhaps continue to live, is true at the
through ZenOjf or whose coimec- present moment; but in the
tion with Philo see Diog. vii. 16. last moment of Dion's life it
FORMAL LOGIC: JUDGMENT. 115

leading clause states something, from the existence of Chap.


V.
which an inference may be drawn as to the statement
in the concluding clause, it is also called an indica-
tion or suggestive sign.^
The modality of judgments, which engaged the (7) -Hfo-

attention of Aristotle and his immediate pupils so judgnietts.


much, was likewise treated by the Stoics at consider-
able' length ; but, from the sphere of these enquiries,
so much only is known to us as relates to possible and
necessary judgments,- being the outcome chiefly of
the contest between Chrysippus and the Megarian
Diodorus.^ It is in itself of no great value. Great

will cease to be true. Such ' Diodorus had said that


sentences were called cLirepiypi- Only what is, orwhat will be,
^wy fieTairiiTTovTaf because the is possible. The Stoics, and
time could not be previously in particular Chrysippus, define
fixed when they would become Swarhii as what is capable of
false {Slmpl. Phys. 305, a). being true (rh ^mSeKriKhv rov
Chrysippus also wrote on thcMc- a\ri9hs efj/ai), if circumstances
TairETTTOra, according to Dionys. do not prevent 'ctSivarov as 6
;

Oomp. Verb. p. 72 Schaf er. Diog. 4(niv itriSeKTiKhp rod oi.\Tj6is


fi'fj

vii. 105, mentions two treatises thai. From the Swariv they
of his on the subject, cha- distinguish the ovk ivayxatov,
racterising them, however, as which is defined as t xa) a\iriB4s
spurious. 4aTi Kol ^evSos oT6v re etvai ruv
' According to Seait.
Pyrrh. ixrhs fiT^Sev ivayriovfiivuif (^Phit.
ii.100, Math. viii. 143 and 156, Sto. Eep. 46, p. 1055 Biog. 75 ; ;

the Stoics distinguished be- Boeth. De Interp. 374, Bas.


tween (TTifieia and
virofjivria'riKa The same thing is also stated
artiieiahSeiitTiKi. The definition in Aleas. Aphr. De Fato, c. 10,
of the latter was ivismTucbv p. 30. SuyaTbi/ efvai yev4ff9ai
a^lufia ev iryieT (rvyrififievcft Ka6ri- rovTO S' uir' oh^Gvhs KoiX^sra lyeyc'
yoificpov (or TrpoKoBnyoiiievov') a&ai Khv fiii yevTjTai.') On the
iKKaKimr iKhv rod \-fiyoVTos the ' other hand, ivayxmoi' is, what
vytes (Tui'Tj^juevoi/ being a sentence is both true and incapable of
with both the leading and in- being false, either in itself or
ferential clauses true. Sext. owing to other circumstances.
Pyrrh. ii. 101 106 ; 115 ; Math.
; IHog. and JBoeth. There was
viii. 249. probably anothe definition of
116 TRE STOICS.

Chap. value was, nevertheless, attached to it by the Stoics,


V.
in the hope thereby to escape the difficulties neces-
sarily resulting from their views on freedom and
necessity.'
(J) In- In their theory of illation,^ to which the Stoics
ference.
attached special value, and on which they greatly
prided themselves,' chief attention was paid to hypo-
thetical and disjunctive inferences.* In regard to
these forms of inference, the rules they laid down are
well known;" and from these forms they invariably
took their examples, even when treating of inference

ovK hvayKaiov, as 6 if/euSof ot6v re thoides preferred to attack


eivat Tav ^Krhs fiij 4pavTiovfi4yoftf

another leading clause of Dio-
so that it might be said (Boeth. dorus, the clause that Every
429) that the ovk avayKatov was past occurrence must neces-
partly possible and partly im- sarily be true (JEpictet. Diss. ii.
possible, without contradicting 19, 2 and 5). The Aristotelian
(as Boeth. and Prantl, p. 463 position in reference to a dis-
believe) their other statement, junction, that When the dis-
that the Smirhv was partly junction refers to something
necessary and partly not neces- future, the disjunction itself is
sary. The conceptions of the true, without either clause be-
Possible and the Not-necessary ing necessarily true, was not
are thus made to overlap, the accepted by the Stoics {Simpl.
former including the Necessary Cat. 103, j8).
and Not-necessary, the latter ' Pltit. Sto.
Bep. 46, p. 1055,
the Possible and the Not-pos- justly insists on this point.
sible. Premtl, pp. 467-496.
''

To defend Ms definition of '


Biog. 45 ; Sext. Pyrrh. ii.
the Possible against the Kvpniiov 194, see above p. 65.
of Diodorus, Chrysippus denied * Both were included by the

the statement, tvvar^ a^vvarov Peripatetics under the term


fiil liKo\ov6iv, without exposing hypothetical. In the same way
the confusion contained in it the Stoics include both among
between sequence in time and the five oyoirdSfiKTOi. See below
causal relation {Alex. Anal. Pr. p. 119,2.
57, b ; Philop. Anal. Pr. xlii. bj ' Chain-argrmient seems to

Schol. in Arist. 163, a ; Cie. De have been also treated of in the


Fato, 7, 13 J Bp. ad Div. ix. 4). categorical form. See p. 120,
Cleanthes, Antipater, and Pan- 3.
;

FORMAL LOGIC: INFERENCE. 117

in general.' According to Alexander,'^ the hypotheti- Chap.


V.
cal and disjunctive forms were considered the only
regular forms of inference,* the categorical form () Sypo-

being considered correct in point of fact, but defective inference


in proper syllogistic form.''1 In hypothetical infer- the 09'i-
ginal
form.
As shown by Prantl, 468,
' pressed in definite terms, for in-
171 on Diog. 76 Seari:. Pyrrh.
; ; stance. If it is day, it is light.
ii. 135 Apul. Dogm. Plat. iii.
; The arrangement of the clauses
279, Oud. The latter rightly (which were designated by
refers to the fact, that Chrysip- numbers, and not by letters, as
pus discussed the main forms the Peripatetics had done), was
of hypothetical inference at the called TpSiros for instance, ei

Tery beginning of his doctrine rh vpwTOff rd Seirepov. A con-


of inference, Seaat. Math. viii. clusion composed of both forms
223 of expression was a XoyirpoTros

Anal. Pr. 87, b Si" {moei-


2 : for instance, ei UKdraiv, ava- Q
aeus 5e &W7is, ws ehrev (^Arist, TTpei Tixdrtov &Wa fjiijv t6 irpW'
Anal. Pr. i. 23, 41, a, 37) tUv & Tov Tii &pa deirepoy. The pre-
KaX o&s ol veiliTepot (ruKKoyi(TfjLoijs misses were called KitiiiuiTa (in
fiSifous ^oiXovTai Xeyetf oStoi S* contrast to &|f(u/ia which ex-
eUrlv 01 5iefc rponiKou, ws (pcurl, koX presses a judgment indepen-
Trjs irpoKiiy^ews yiv6fiuot, rov rpo' dently of its position in a syllo-
TTtKov ^ ffvi/rjfifievov (conditional) gism); or, more correctly, the
6vTos tl SiEfei/y/neVou (disjunctive) major premiss was aVm", the
fl trvfiTtivXiyiiivov (a copulative minor irp6(!\if^is (hence the par-
judgment suggesting partly ticles 5e ye were vpoaKtyirTiKos
hypothetical judgments like the (rivSe(Tiios, Apollon. Synt. p. 518,
aviiireTrKiyiiivov in Sext. Math. Bekk.). The conclusion was
viii. 235, partly negative cate- hritpopd, also itritpoptKol (rvySefffiol,
gorical judgments which have Itid. 519. The major premiss
the force of hypothetical judg- in a hypothetical syllogism was
ments, such as it is not at the
: called TpoTTiKhv, its two clauses
same time A
and B. Conf. being called, respectively, r/yoi-
Siog. 80. Semt. Pyrrh. ii. 158 fievov (as by the
Peripatetics)
Math. viii. 226. Cic. De Fato, and \9iyov (by the Peripatetics
vi. 12). By
the vednepoi, the iirdiiivov'). Diog. 76 ; Seont.
Stoics must be meant,
for the Pyrrh. ii. 135 ; Math. viii. 301,
terminology is theirs and the ; 227 ; Aless. 1. c. and p. 88, a
Peripatetics, to whom it might 109, a ; 7, b ; PMlop. Anal. Pr.
otherwise apply, always con- Ix. aSchol. in Arist. 170, a, 2
;

sidered the categorical to be Amman, on Anal. Pr. 24, b, 19


the original form of judgment. Arist. Orig. ed. Waitz, i. 45
See Prantl, 468, 172. Apul. Dog. Plat. iii. 279, Oud.
' an inference was
Such Ps. Galen, Eltray. iiaX. p. 19.
called \iyor when it was ex- < Aleo!. Anal. Pr. 116, b, after
;

118 THE STOICS.

Chap. ences a distinction was also made between such as are


V.
connected and such as are disconnected.' In con-
nected inferences the Stoics look principally at the
greater or less accuracy of expression,^ and partly at
the difference between correctness of form and truth
of matter.' They also remarked that true conclusions
do not always extend the field of knowledge ; and
that those which do frequently depend on reasons
conclusive for the individual, but not on proofs
universally acknowledged.'* The main point, how-
ever, to be considered in dividing inferences is their

mentioning aiJ,eB65as Trepaivoirrei fljjs) when not only the illation


inferences in-
ffvWoyicTfiol, or is correct (iytiis), but when
complete in point of form, such the individual propositions, the
as: = B,B = C,.-.A=C, which
A premisses as well as the con-
issaid to want as its major pre- clusion, are materially true.
miss Two things which are
: The \6yoi itucoktikoI may there-
equal to a third are equal to fore be divided into true and
one another. On these ane- false. Seicf. Pyrrh. ii. 138;
86Sus irepalvotnes of the Stoics Math. viii. 310 and 412 ; Diog.
see 1. c. 8, a ; 22, b ; Aleai. Top. 79.
10, Ps. Galen, Eis. Sid\. 59. He * Sext. Pyrrh. ii. 140 and
then continues ois 8ti /ih nil : 185 Math. viii. 305 313 and
; ; ;

Ktyoviri trvWoyuTTiKas (rvj/dyetv, 411 True forms of inference


:

vytas \4yovffi [ot ve^repoi] . . . are divided into airoSeMTticoi and


Sti Se TjyovPTat dfioiovs av7oiis oi/K airodGiKriKol. avoBeiKTiKol =^
elvai Tois KaTTiyopiKfHS avWoyi- 01 $1^ npaSi]\a>v &57i\6v ri avvd-
iTfiQis . . . ToO iraj'T^s Bta/iaprdvov- yovres' oiiK atrobeiKJiKol when
ffiv, this is not the case, as in the
^ (TvvaKTiKol or TiepavriKoX, and inference : If it is day, it is
imwanTiKoi or cmipavroi, or i(rvK-
light It is day, .. It is light
' \6yurroi. Sext. Pyrrh. ii. 137 ; for the conclusion, It is light,
Math. viii. 303 and 428 JMoff. 77. ; is known as well as it is known
2 Syllogisms which are con- that It is day. The airoSeiKTiKol
clusive in point of fact, but may proceed either iipoSevTMus
wanting in precision of form, from the premisses to the con-
were called irepavrtKot in the clusions, or e<^oSevtik<i>s fi^a /cat

narrower sense those complete ; 4Kica\vTrTtKas itpoSevrmas when


also in form, crvWoyiVTMoi. the premisses rest upon belief


Diog. 78; Ps. Galen, E'uray. (TrfffTlS and^V^/tl)) ; ^KKoAinTTIKUS
IioX. 58. when they are based on a scien-
* An inference is true (&Xi- tific necessity.
;

FORMAL LOGIC: INFERENCE. 119

logical form. There are, according to Chrysippus,' Chap.


V.
who herein adopted the division of Theophrastus,
five original forms of hypothetical inference, the ac- (iSJ Tlw
jwie sympU
curacy of which is beyond dispute, and to which all forms
(rf

may be referred and


other forms of inference thereby hypotheti-
cal in-
tested.^ Yet even among these forms, importance is ference.

attached to some in which the same sentence is re-


peated tautologically in the form of a conclusion,'
proving how mechanical and barren must have been
the formalism in which the Stoic logic so abounds.
The combination of these five simple forms of in- (7) Com-
posite
ference gives rise to the composite forms of inference,^
forms of
all of which may be again resolved into their simple inferenee.

forms.* Among the composite forms of inference,


' According to i)i<ii^.
79, Sext. conclusion and minor premiss
Pyrrh. ii. 157, others added are identical. The first class are
other forms of avmr6ietKToi. called SitpopoiifjLemt If it is day, it

Oic, in adding a sixth and is day ; It is day, .'.It is day. The


seventh (Top. 14, 57), must second class, it,5icup6pci)s trepaivoy-
have been following these au- Tes It is either day or night
thorities. It is day, .". It is day. The
'Consult, on these five ava- latter term is, however, applied
iriiSeiKToiof Chrysippus (which to both kinds. See Alex. Anal.
need not be given here more at Pr. 7, a 53, b ; Top. 7 ; Schol.
;

length, being absolutely iden- in Arist. 294, b, 25 ; CX,c. Acad,


tical with those of Theophras- ii. 30, 96 ; Prantl, 476, 185.

tus) JHog. 79-81 (on p. 79 we * Oic. Top. 15, 57 ex his :

must read trvWoyiffriKav for modis conolusiones innumera-


avWoyuTiiav. See p. 118, 2) ; biles nascuntur. Sext. Math.
Sext. Pyrrh. ii. 156-159; 201; viii. 228, in which passage it is
Math. viii. 223-227 ; Cie. Top. striking that avairdSeiKToi should
13 ; Simpl. Phys. 123, b ; Ps. be divided into aw\o7 and oux
Qalen, Zltray. Sia\. 17 ; Prwntl, a-ir\o7.It has been suggested
473, 182 ; on the ^efmros ava- that ^TToBeiKTiKuv should be sub-
Tr6SiiKTosSi^Tr\it6iiai/ Sext. Pyrrh! stituted for avairoSelKTav, but it
i. 69; Cleomed. Meteora, pp. is also possible that the latter
41 and 47 ; Prcmtl, p. 475. word may be used in a najrow
^ Two such cases are distin- as well as in a wider sense.
guished, one in which all three " IHog. 78 auWoyKTrucol [\6-
:

clauses, the other in which the 701] nev olv eiaiv oj ^toi ivavd-
THE STOICS.

Ohap. those composed of similar parts are distinguished


V.
from those composed of dissimilar parts ; in the '

treatment of the former, however, such a useless


formality is displayed, that it is hard to say what

meaning the Stoics attached to them.^ If two or


more inferences, the conclusion of one of which is
the first premiss of the other, are so combined that
the judgment which constitutes the conclusion and
premiss at once is omitted in each case, the result is

a Sorites or Chain-inference. The rules prescribed


by the Peripatetics for the Chain-inference were de-
veloped by the Stoics with a minuteness far trans-
cending all the requirements of science.' With these

SetKTOt 0VT6S ^ aLifay6fievoi ^irt Tohs teticexpression. The same


avairodeiKTOvs Kami ri tw 6e^-. meaning must attach to iTn^iK-
Toiv rl Tivd. According to Galen, Aovt4s t6 Kal ifrtfiaWd/ji.epoi,
Hipp, et Plat. ii. 3, p. 224, which are to be found eV rais
Chiysippus had taken great tri/i/6xws Kafi^avofievats Trporoureai
pains io resolving the composite X^p'^s Twy ffvfivepaa'fiii'fuv for
forms of inference (Diog. 190 instance, A is a property of B,
and 194). Antipater suggested B of C, C of D ; .", is a pro- A
still simpler modes. perty of D. iinfiaWifiei/os means
8ea;t. 229-243, borrowing
' the inference, the conclusion of
the example used by iEnesl- which is omitted; iirifiaWtnv,
demus, bat no doubt following the one with the omitted pre-
the Stoic treatment. Prantl, miss. These inferences may be
479. Such a composite infer- in either of the three Aristote-
ence is that mentioned by Sex- lian figures kotA ri iropoSeSo-
tus 1. c. 281. yiivov avvBcTiKbv Beiipriiia. t ol
^ Sext. ; Prmtl, p. 478. flhp irepl 'ApltrTOTiKTiJ/ 7^ XP^^^
' Alex, on Anal. Pr. i. 25, 42, irapafierpiiffayTes TrapeSatroi/, 4<p*

b, 5, after speaking of the Sor- Sffou ouT^ ciTrpTei, ot Se airh t^s


ites, continues (p. 94, b) : iv rp Tov [ffToas] irap' ^Keivoiv \a^6vTiS
Toiairri ruv vporilireoav trvvex^iif Kttl die\6uTes 4iroiTj(rav e4 avrov rh
r6 T trvvderiKSv ^ffrt det^pTifia KoKoifxivov Trap* avrois Seirepoy
. , . KaX ot KaKo{/^evoi writ twi' Kal rpirov Be/xa Kal riraprov, a/te-
vut4[jqiii4iri^\KovTes re Kal 4irt~ M\aavTes fiiv rod xp^'^'^f.^v, trav
^awifievoi. The ffuvScTiKhv Sh rh dirtoiTovv Svydfievav \4yeadat
Bfiipriiia (or chain-argument), 4v rfi toioiJti) Beupl^f, k^v AxpV'ros
the meaning of which is next jj, 4ire^eK66yTes re Kal (ii\i(ravres.
investigated, must be a Peripa- Bef eieoce is made to the same
;

FORMAL LOGIC: INFERENCE. 121

composite forms of inference Antipater contrasted Chap.


V.
other forms having only a single premiss,' but it was
an addition to the field of logic of very doubtful C^) -^-

worth. On a few other points connected with the from a sin-


Stoic theory of illation, we have very imperfect in- ?^f i"'*-
formation.^ The loss, however, is not to be regretted,
seeing that in what we already possess there is con-
clusive evidence that the objections brought against
the Stoic logic were really well deserved. It was in-

tMng in Sivtpl. De Ccelo ; Schol. refer to such composite infe-


in Arist. 483, b, 26 v StroioiiTri
: rences.
avdKvaiS tov \6yoUf 7] rb (TVfi- ^ Called fioi/QK-fifi(iaToi ffvWo-
irepafffjLa KafjLfidi'OVffa Kai Trpo(r\afj.- ytaiiol. Such were r]ji.ipa inTi,
^dpovtra iA\7iv Trpdraa-tv, kotA rb tpus &pa %(TTiv and avairviis, Cps
rpijov \ey6fjLevop irapot, jots 2Twi- &pa. See Aleai. Top. 6, 274;
Kois Bi^a Trepaiverai, the rule of Anal. Pr. 7, a, 8, a ; Sext. Pyrrh.
which is, that when a third pro- ii. 167 ; Math. viii. 443 ; Apul.

position can be concluded from Dogm. Plat. iii. 272, Oud.


the conclusion of an inference Prrnitl, ill, 186.
and a second proposition, that ^ Compare the remarks of
third proposition can be con- Prantl, 481, on Sext. Pyrrh. ii.
cluded also from the premisses 2; Alex. Anal. Pr. 53, b; GaUn,
of the inference and the second 1. c. ; Ps. Galen, Haay. Sia\.
proposition. Both these pas-
' 57. If Posidonius, according
sages appear to have escaped to the latter passage, calls ana-
the notice of Prantl in his logical conclusions (rvvaKTi-
summing up, otherwise so ac- Kovs KttTct BivofjLtif d^iiiifiaTos, and
curate. Or else the irpSiTov, the Stoics also, according to
deirepov, rpWov andTeVapToy 0/ia Schol. in Hermog. Bhet. Gr. ed.
mentioned by Galen, Hipp, et Walz, vii. 6, 764, spoke of a Kara
Plat. ii. 3, vol. v. 224. Alex. diivafiLv TpoTTtubv, we have already
Anal. Pr. 53, b, would hardly met with the same thing, p.
suggest to him the various 119, 1, where an analogical con-
forms of the AfoiriiSciKToi instead clusion was included in the
of the formulae for the resolu- a^e96Scas irepaivovres, which, by
tion of composite conclusions. the addition of an oi|fcii^a, can
The expressions Sih Sio TpoTri/cwc, be changed into regular con-
Si4 rpiuv rpoTTiKwy, and the title clusions. In the doctrine of
of a treatise of Chrysippus irepl proof the riiiroj jrapiiBofos was
TOV Sict TpitOV (SC. TpOTTlKWU Or also treated of, according to
\i\HjjAtuv conf, p. 3) in 117, ProM. in Euclid, 103, being
Biog. vii. 191; {Galen, I.e.; probably suggested by the ethi-
Seast. Pyrrh. ii. 2), appear to cal paradoxes of the Stoics,
122 THE STOICS.

Chap, deed a petty carefulness to trace, as they did, even


the most worthless logical forms ' to the end.
(e) Me/'u- Next to describing the inferences which were valid,
TaiCcifs.
a^otlier subject engaged the careful attention of the
Stoics, and afforded an opportunity for vindicating
their dialectical subtlety. This was no other than
the enumeration and refutation of false inferences,^
and in particular the exposing of the many fallacies
which had become current since the age of the
Sophists and Megarian^. In this department, too,
as might be expected, Chrysippus led the way.* Not
that Chrysippus was always able to overcome the
difficulties that arose ; witness his remarkable atti-
tude towards the Chain-inferences, from which he
thought to escape by withholding judgment.^ The
fallacies, however, to which the Stoics devoted their
attention, and the way in which they met them, need
not occupy our attention further.*

' Conf Alea;. Anal. Pr. 95,


. ab iis dioitur rjavxi^eiv. The
a Galen. See above p. 120, 3.
; same remark is made by Seiet.
According to Ps. Galen, 1. o. p. Math. vii. 416 ; Pyrrh. ii. 253.
58, Chrysippus wrote these trea- The same argument was em-
tises on 'ZMWoyurrmal Sxpio'TO'. ployed against other fallacies
^ Siog. 186, mentions falla- (^Simpl. Cat. 6, 7). With this
cies due to Chrysippus, which \6yos ri<Tvx^in>v (JDiog. 198),
can only have been raised for Prantl, p. 489, connects apyis
the purpose of being refuted. \6yos {Cic. De Pato, 12, 28),
^ The list of his writings regarding the one as the prao-
contains a number of treatises tical application of the other,
on among them no
fallacies, but apparently without reason,
than five on the i^i/5(J/x6i/os.
less The apy})s K6yos, by means of
de. Acad. ii. 29, 93 Placet
: which the Stoic fatalism was
enim Chrysippo, cum gradatim reduced ad absurdum, could
interrogetur, verbi causa, tria not of course commend itself
pauca sint, anne multa, ali- to Chrysippus, nor is it attri-
quanto prius, quam ad multa buted to him.
perveniat,quiescere,idest,quod ' Prantl,
pp. 485-496.
ESTIMATE OF STOIC LOGIC. 123

In all these enquiries the Stoics were striving to Chap.


find firm ground for a scientific process of proof.
Grreat as was the value which they attached to such D- -^sii-

a process, they nevertheless admitted, as Aristotle had stoio

done before, that everything could not be proved, f^i^l


Here, then, was the weak point. Instead, however, slurrt-
"'"""'?*
weak point by means of induction,
of filling up this
and endeavouring to obtain a more complete theory
of induction, they were content with conjectural data,
sometimes carrying their own truth in themselves, at
other times leaving it to be established by the truth
of their inferences.' Thus, their theory of method,
like their theory of knowledge, ended by an ultimate
appeal to what is directly certain.
No very high estimate can therefore be formed of (2) lu
'"'^ ""'
the formal logic of the Stoics. Incomplete as is our
knowledge of that logic, still what is known isenough
to determine the judgment absolutely. That the
greatest care was expended by the Stoics since the
time of Chrysippus in tracing into their minutest
ramifications, and referring to a fixed type, the forms
of intellectual procedure, we see indeed. At the same
time, we see that the real business of logic was lost
sight of in the process, the business of portraying
the operations of thought, and giving its laws, whilst


Sext. Math. viii. 367 : oW tov ifi^SaSai tV iir^eea-w -rh
oil Sei, (patrl, Tritirav ajr6Sei^tv a\T\Bh eiplcrKeadai ixeii/o rh tois
alruu, Tii/A ii KoX i^ fnroBiaws i^ tmoBitrws \-ii<pSeiaiii iiruS>ep6-
Suyfifferai npo-
\afjLfidi/iy, iirel oif fiej/ov el yhp rb to{itois clkoKov-
Palveiv iiiuv i \6yoi, iav /ij) SoBfi Bovv iarw fryiM, KaKcri/o ofs oko-
Ti iruTThv ii alnov Tuyx'^''*"'- ^ovBfi aKi)Br) Kol avaiupiKeKra
lUd. 375 : ciWl' eiaBaaiv fmoTvy- KaBiarriKiv.
X^vovres Ae-ygiv iri trlffTis ecri

124 THE STOICS.

Chap, the most useless trifling with forms was recklessly


'

indulged in. No discoveries of importance can have


been made even as to the logical forms of thought,
or they would not have been passed over by writers
ever on the alert to note the slightest derivations from
the Aristotelian logic. Hence the whole contribution
of the Stoics in the field of logic consists iu this,
in clothing the logic of the Peripatetics with a new
terminology, and developing certain parts of it with
painful minuteness, whilst other parts were wholly
neglected. Thus it fared with the part treating of
inference. Assuredly it was no improvement for
Chrysippus to regard the hypothetical rather than
the categorical as the original form of inference.
Making every allowance for the extension of the field
of logic, in scientific precision it lost more than it
gained by the labours of Chrysippus. The history of
philosophy cannot pass over in silence this branch of
the Stoic system, so carefully cultivated by the Stoics
themselves, and so characteristic of their intellectual
attitude. Yet, when all has been said, the Stoic

logic is only an outpost of their system, and the care


which was lavished on it since the time of Chrysippus
indicates the decline of intellectual originality.
STUDY OF NATURE. 125

CHAPTER VI.

THE STtTDT 'OF NATURE. FUNDAMENTAL POSITIONS.

Or far more importance in the Stoic system than the chap.


study of logic was the study of nature. This branch ^^
of learning, notwithstanding an appeal to older views,
was treated by them with more independence than
any other. The subjects which it included may be
divided under four Fundamental
heads, viz.: 1.

positions 2. The course, character, and govern-


;

ment of the universe 3. Irrational nature and 4.


; ;

Man.'
The present chapter will be devoted to consider-
ing the first of these groups the fundamental posi-
tions held by the Stoics in regard to nature ; among
1 Natural Science was by the mathematician (astro-
divided by the Stoics them- nomy. Posidonius in Svmpl.
selves (^Diog. 132) (1) eiSikiSs
: Phys. 64, b, discusses at length
into iraiiiTwv Kal irept
-rlrnoi irepl the difference between astro-
apxuv Kal tTTOix^iav Kal O^oiv Kal nomy and natural science) and
;

nepdraiv Kal r6irov Kal Kevov (2) the third, ground which is
yevMas into three
divisions, shared by both the physician
TTtpl KSaiiov, irepl atotx^lav, and and the mathematician. The
the aiTioXo7iK(ir. The first of precise allotment of the subject
these divisions covers ground into these divisions is not
which is partly peculiar to known. At best, it would be a
natural science and is shared very uncomfortable division.
'

126 TSE STOICS.

Chap. which three specially deserve notice their Material-


VI.
ism ; their Dynamical view of the world ; and their
Pantheism.
A. Mate- Nothing appears more striking to a reader fresh
rialism.
from the study of Plato or Aristotle than the startling
(1) Mean-
ing of the contrast presented thereto by the Materialism of the
Stoic ma-
terialism. Stoics. Whilst so far following Plato as to define a
(a) Mate- real thing' to be anything possessing the capacity of
rial or COT-
acting or being acted upon, the Stoics nevertheless
objects.
restricted the possession of this power to material
(a) Reality objects. Hence followed their conclusion that no-
belongs to
material thing real exists except what is material or, if they ;

objects could not deny existence in some sense or other to


only.
what is incorporeal, they were fain to assert that
essential and real Being only belongs to what is ma-
terial, whereas of what is incorporeal only a certain

modified kind of Being can be predicated.' FoUow-


' Soph. 247, D. (see p. 95, 2) and 338 Xpianriros :

2 Plut. Com. Not. 30, 2, p. tdriov iivai \eyei 5i* ii. Kol rh
1073 iyra yhp fi6va Tct trdfiaTa
; fiev oUriQV %v Kal ff Sofia, k.t.A.
Ka\ovcriv, eiretS^ Svtos rh iroteTv ri HoffsiS^vios Se OT^Ttas. alriov S'

Kol iriiTx^iy. Plao. i. 11, i: of ^(TtI twos h 4K^tvo, fl rh apxv-


5i*

STwi'Kol TTfivTa Tct oYtio ffafiariKd yhv TTOiiiiTews, Kal rh fi^j/ atrtov tv
TTvev^ara ydp. iv. 20 : ot 8e StwI'- Ka\ ffafia, ou Si atriov oUre Sy oUre
Kol ffw^a T^v tpcoviiv' TTav yap rh ffcHfia, aWci ffv^^e^Khs Kol Kanj-

Spdijxevov ^ Kai 'kolovv (Tufia "


rj Si y6priii.a. See p. 95, 1 and 2.
(paiv^ irotei KaiSp^ fri ttoi/ . . . Ding. vii. 56 :According to
rh Kivovv KoX ivox^ovv ffwfiii ^ffiiv Chrysippus, Diogenes (see
Ti fray rh Kivovfievov trcD/xa Simpl. Phys. 97, a), and others,
i<TTiv. dc. Acad. i. 11, 39: the voice is material, vav yhp
[Zeno] nullo modo arbitrabatur Tb TroioCx iraiid iari. Ibid. 150:
quidquam eflSci posse ab ea oiiffiav Si tpaffi tuv ^vruv andvTaiv

[natura] quas expers esset cor- T^v irpdoTT]!/ iS\riy, us Kal Xpvtrtir-
poris nee vero aut quod
. . . tros iv T7? Trpdrji tv (pvffiKav Kal
efficeret aliquid aut quod effi- Zi]vuv S\7i Se iffTiv, ^| ?s driSi)-
ceretur (more accurately in : iroTOvv yiyerai . irufia Si iffri
. .

quo effioeretur aliquid. Conf. Kar' ai/Tobs 7] ovffia. Sippolyt.


Bitter, iii. 677) posse esse non Eefut. Haer. i. 21 : alifl.a^a S\
corpus, Seneca, see below p. wdyra {nriBevro, k.t.\.
128, 1 ; 129, 1 Stob. Eel. 1. 336
;
:

STUDY OF- NATURE: MATERIALISM. 127

ing out this view, it was natural that they should Chap.
regard many things as corporeal which are not gene-
rally considered so ; for instance, the soul and virtue.
Nevertheless, it would not be correct to say ' that the
Stoics gave to the conception of matter or corporeity
a more extended meaning than it usually bears. For
they define a body to be that which has three dimen-
sions,^ and they also lay themselves out to prove how
things generally considered to be incorporeal may be
material in the strictest sense of the term. Thus,
besides upholding the corporeal character of all sub-
stances, including the human soul and Grod,^ they
likewise assert that properties or forms are material
all attributes by means of which one object is dis-

tinguished from another are produced by the exist-


ence of certain air-currents,* which, emanating from (fi) Theory
-""'>'
the centre of an object, diffuse themselves to its "-f
'^'f

extremities, and having reached the surface, return


again to the centre to constitute the inward unity.*

' As do Bitter, iii. 577, and Plut. Com. Not. 50, 1, p. 1085 :

Sclileiermaclier, Gesch. der tois Ttoi6TT)ras ovalas /col a-iiiiaTa


Philos. 129. TToiomiv, and Ibid, ii, i, the
^ Diog. vii. 1.35 : a-iSim 5' effTi statement discussed on p. 101, 2.
(<()rj(rlc 'AiroXXiiSwpos 6^ T5 if)U(riKp) ^ Philo, Qu. De S. Immut.

rh rpixv Sioo'TOTii', k.t.K. p. 298, D (the same in the


' See p. 98. The corporeal spurious treatise 'De Mundo, p.
nature^ of deity and the soul 1154, E) r\ Si [e|is = iroi(iT7js"|
:

will be subsequently discussed, iari T!Vvfi,a avnarpi^ov 4ip' laurd.


' See
p. 105. Sen. Bp. 102, 7, Spx^oi nev yap iarb rav fleaav
remarks, in reference to the ^irl ri irepara TeiveaSai., ifiaii<rav

difference of %vai)i.iva (see p. Se t,Kpas 4Truj>ayelas amxdfiVTH


103, 1) nullum bonum putamus
:
Tr6.\iv, Sxpis &v M rhv aurhv &<pt-
esse, quod ex distantibus con- /cijTai TcSTroi/, cup' oV rh irpuTov
Stat uno enim spiritu unum
:
iipfiitrSn. e^eais S amexhs olnos
bonmn contineri ac regi debet, ilavKos &(pSapTos, k.t.A. Qu.
unum esse uniusboniprincipale. Mund. S. Incorr. 960, D [De
Hence the objection raised in Mundo, 1169, A] : ^ 5' [e|is] Io-tI
.

128 THE STOICS.

Chap. Nor was the theory of air-currents confined to bodily-


VI.
attributes. It was applied quite as much to mental
attributes. Virtues and vices are said to be mate-
rial,' and are deduced from the tension imparted to
the soul by atmospheric substances therein subsisting.^
For the same reason the Good is called a body, for
according to the Stoics the Grood is only a virtue, and

tSvos.
9ri/u/iaTiKds There can thes, in Plut. Sto. Rep. 7, 4, p.
be no doubt that Philo is des- 1034 : irKTiy^ irvphs 6 t6vos eVrt
cribing the Stoic teaching in Khv iKavhs iv ry ^vxfi y^yjjTai
these passages. Tphs rh 4iri$iiWovTa
e7riT\eTi/ Tcfc

The same idea is also used iVxf's KaAeiTai Kol Kpdros. Stob.
to explain the connection be- Eel. ii. 110 Sxnrtp Iffxiis rod
:

tween the soul and the body. trdtfiaros rSvos 4(TtIv iKavhs Iv
The unity of the universe is veipots, oiiroj KaX rj ttis "^vxris
proved by the fact that the Iffx^s t6vos 4<n\v iKavhs iv t^
Divine Spirit pervades it. Fur- Kpivetv Koi irpdrreiv Kal n4\. All
ther particulars hereafter. Conf properties may be classed under
Alea;. Apkr. De Mixt. 142, a: the same conception of tension.
Tivuirdat fikv vTroriBeTai [Xp^ffiir- See p. 127, 5 and Plut. Com. Not.
iros] tV ffijxtraffav ohaiajf -kv^v- 49, 2, p. 1085 7^v jji.ev yap tcraa-i
:

fiarSs TLvos Si^ avr^s 5t^-


Trdffris Ka\ tSSwp oijTe ouTct (Xuvex^tv otfre
Koi/TOs, 6(^' ov ffwdyerai re Koi eVepa, irt'evfiarlKTis Se /*eT0Xf7, Kol
auT^
avfifievei Koi ff^inraQh iffrtv Kvp^dovs Svvdfieais r^v kv6ri\Ta
rh irav, (That must be the Sta<pvKdTTeiv' a4pa Se Ka\ irvp av-
reading, the next sentence con- riov t' elj/ai 5i* iVToviav SKTartKa
taining Tmv Se, K.T.\. Conf. Ka\ TOis Svfflv iKeivois eyKSKpaiJ-eva
143, b). Alex. 143, b, carefully t6vov irap^x^iv kol rh fidvtfi'ov Kal
denies the statement, that the ouiriSSes. Ps. Censorin. Fragm.
all penetrating Breath keeps c. 1, p. 75, Jahn Initia rerum :

things together. eadem elementa et principia


> Plut. Com. Not. 45. See diountur. Ea Stoici credunt
p. 129, 3. Sen. Ep. 117, 2: tenorem atque materiam; ten-
Placet nostris, quod bonum est, orem, qui rarescente materia
esse corpus, quia quod bonum a medio tendat ad summum,
est, f acit quidquid f acit corpus
: eadem conoresoente rursus a
est . . sapientiam bonum esse
. summo referatuT ad medium.
diount: sequitur, ut necesse Here tenor or t6vos is made
sit illam corporalem quoque equivalent to iri/eOfia. Seneea,
dicere. Conf. p. 129, 1. however, Nat. Qu. ii. 8, conf. vi.
' This is the conception of 21, endeavours to show that
t6vos, upon which the strength intemHo belongs to spwitus
of the soul depends, as well as more than to any other body.
the strength of the body. Clean-
STUDY OF NATURE: MATERIALISM. 129

virtue is a definite condition of that material which Chap.


VI.
constitutes the soul.' In the same sense also truth
is said to be material, personal and not independent
truth being of course meant,^ that is to say, know-
ledge, or a property of the soul that knows. And
since according to the Stoics knowledge consists in
the presence of certain material elements within the
soul, truth in the sense of knowledge may be rightly
called something material. Even emotions, impulses,
notions and judgments, in so far as they are due to
material causes, the air-currents pouring into the
soul (n-vevfiaTo), were regarded as material objects,
and for the same reason not only artistic skill but
individual actions were said to be corporeal.' Yet

'
Sen. Ep. 106, i: bonum Xe. Kol eMrus, (pacrl. tovtI /iiy
f aoit, prodest enim quod f acit yap a^i(iifj.d e(rTi,Th 3e a^iu/Mi\eK-
corpus est bonum agitat ani-
: t6vj t6 5e KiKrdv hffdifxarov ' avd-
mum et quodammodo format et naKiv 5e rj ahiiBsia (rufid itrriy
continet, quse propria sunt cor- Trap' iffov ^TTiffT^/AT/ -K^vrav a\ri6ut/
poris. Quie corporis bona sunt, airo(l>avrtK^ SoKetTvyxdveii/
iratra
corpora sunt: ergo et quse 5e iirifTTiifiTt Ttiis %x^ ^fnXv Tjye-
animi sunt. et hoc cor- Nam fjLoj/tKdv . . . t6 Se Ttye/jLoviKdv
pus. Bonum hominis necesse (T&fiaKara to^tovs imripxe. Simi-
est corpus sit, cum ipse sit cor- larly Pyrrh. ii. 81. See p. 92,
poralis si adf actus corpora
. . . 2.
sunt et morbi animorum et Plut. Com. Not. 46, 2,
^

avaritia, crudelitas, indurata p. 1084 6.roTrov yap eS /xcA.a, ras


:

Titia .ergo et malitia et


. . operas Kai r&.s KoKias, irphs Se
species ejus omnes . ergo et . . rairais r&s rexvas Kal rb.s fiviifias
bona. It is then specially re- Jtdffas, en S^ tpavraaias Kal irdBrj
marked that the Good, i.e. vir- Ka\ dp/ias Ka\ trvyKaTa6e(reis
tue, works upon the body, (Td^fiara irotov/ievovs iv ^rjSevl
governing it and representing (pdyai Ke'tffBat, K.r.K. ol^' ov . . .

itself therein. Conf . p. 128, 1. liimv rhs kperhs Kal rhs Kaxtas
2 Sext. Math. vii. 38 rh' 5e
: f^Ja etvai \eyovffiy, oiiSh Tct ndOri
a\iiBetav olovrai rives, Kal jidKurTO, fiSvov, opyhs KoX <ftd6vovs Kai Kiiras
01 ciTrb -rris (TTOas, Sia<p4peiv toA.))- Kal iirixatpeKOKlas, ou5^ KaraXij-
6ovs Karcb rpeis Tp6'Kovs . oirffny . . ^ets Ktu tpavrafflas krI ayvolas ovSe
fifv Tap' Ztrov v nev SX^ffeia a&iid riisrexyas f^a, r^p aKurorojuKitv,
iart rb Se &\ii9hs turdiiuerov inriip- tV X"^"'"''"''"'^'' 4A.\i vphs
E
:

130 THE STOICS.

Chap. certain actions, such as walking and dancing, can


VI.
hardly have been called bodies by the Stoics, any
(7) The more than being wise was called a body ' but the ;

eawses of
actions objects which produced these actions, as indeed
material.
everything which makes itself felt, were consideired
to be corporeal. To us it appears most natural to
refer these actions to the soul as their originating
cause ; but the Stoics, holding the theory of subject-
matter and property, preferred to refer each such
action to some special material as its cause, consider-
ing that an action is due to the presence of this
material. The idealism of Plato was thus reproduced
in a new form by the materialism of the Stoics.

TouToty (fol rets ivifr^^ias ffdaiiara profiteer esse. Quas sint . .

KaX^^aTToiovai, rhvieepiTraTov ^^of, ergo que antiques moverint,


t))v 6pj(7jffiUjvK60efftt'^ t^v riiv dicam, Animum constat animal
irpoaaySpeviTiv, r^v \oiBoplav. esse. . . . Virtus autem nihil
Plutarcli is here speaking as aliud est, quam animus quo-
an opponent. Seneca, however dammodo se habens ergo :

(Ep. 106, 5), observes Non : animal est. Deinde : virtus


pnto te dubitaturam, an ad- agit aliquid : agi autem nihil
fectus corpora sint tan- . . . sine impetu (4p/tJ() potest. If
quam ira, amor, tristitia si : it is urged : Each individual
dubitas, vide an vultum nobis win thus consist of an innu-
mutant: Quid ergo 1 tam
. . . merable number of living
manifestas corpori notas credis beings, the reply is that thtese
imprimi, nisi a oorpore? See animalia are only parts of one
p. 129, 1 Stob. Eel. ii. 114
; animal, the soul ; they are ac-
The Stoics consider virtues to cordingly not many (multa),
be substantially identical (rcks but one and the same viewed
ouTai Kofl' m6aTaaiv) with (the from different sides : idem est
leading part of the soul (^7/to- animus et Justus et prudens et
viKhv), and consequently to be, fortis ad singulas virtutes quo-
like it, ffdiiara and fiya. Seneca, dammodo se habens. From the
Ep. 113, speaks still more
1, sameletter,p. 23, wegatherthat
plainly : Desideras tibi scribi a Cleanthes explained ambulatio
me, quid sentiam de hao quses- as spiritus a principali usque in
tione jactata apud nostros an : pedes permissus, Chrysippus as
justitia, an fortitude, prudentia prinoipale itself.
ceterseque virtutes animalia ' See p. 92, 2, the extract
sint. ... Me in alia senteutia from Sen. Ep. 117.
STUDY OF NATURE: MATERIALISM. 131

Plato had said, a man is just and musical when he Chap.


'

participates in the idea of justice and music ; the


Stoics said, a man is virtuous when the material pro-
ducing virtue is in him ; musical, when he has the
material producing music.
Moreover, these materials produce the phenomena (*) Wide
of life. Hence, not content with calling them bodies, g/ mate-
the Stoics actually went so far as to call them living "^^"
beings. It seems, however, quite as startling to hear
such things as day and night, and parts of the day
and parts of the night, months and years, even days ,

of the month and seasons of the year, called bodies.'


But by these unhappy expressions Chry-
singularly
sippus appears to have meant little more than that
the realities corresponding to these names depend on
certain material conditions by summer is meant a :

certain state of the air when highly heated by the


sun by month tbe moon for a certain definite period
;

during which it gives light to the earth.^ From all

' Phit. Com, Not. 45, 5, eaXT!6ji(vov, k.tA. Stoi. Eel. i.

^. 1084 Xpva'nntov livrnioveiovres


: 260 Chrysippus defines tap
:

iv Tif irp^Ttfi ray (pvffmwv ^tjttj- ctovs &pav KeKpafiipTtv iK x^^H-^^os


ouTto TrpoffdyovTos
fi.a/Twv oitx V ' a'jroK'fiyoyTos Kal Oepovs apxofieyov
tihv ui^ ffwfid iffriv, r] 5' effirepa , . . 6epos Se Spay T^y /xt\iO'T' a^'
Kal 6 op6hs Hal rh fxetrov ttjs vvKrhs ijKiov diaKsKov^evriv fieT6Tro)pov Se
adofiaTa ovK %ffTllf '
ouSe t\ fiip &pav %tovs t^v fierh 6epos fiiu trph
Tip.4pa ffufjA iffTlv^ o^xi Se Kal ^ x^i/zufos 5e KcKpafieyriv x^^t*-^^'
voviifivia (Toi^a, Koi t] SckaJt?], koI 5e &pav ^rovs r^v fj.ti\itrTa Kare-
TreVTeKaiSeKdrri Kal fi rpia/c&f Kal 6 '^uyfi.ivftv, ^ riiv t$ ircpl yriv aepi

fxrfv ffcop^d 4irTL Kal rh 64pos Kal rh KaT^vyfjL4vt]v, Ibid. : According


(t>6tv6vtiipov Kal 6 iviavrSs. to Empedocles and the Stoics,
' IHog. 151 x^'i"'"'""
: I"" ^^^ cause of winter is the pre-
elvai rhv Oirkp yrjs &epa Kare-
(fiatrt ponderance of air, the cause of
^vyii4mv Sici r^v -rov ri\iou irpdaa summer the preponderance of
itfrnSoi', eop 8e t^iv fiKpairlai> toB fire. JMd. 556 : fi-els S' iirrl, (fniirl

arpos KaTcfc T71P irphs Tjftas iropeiav, [XpiSffiiriros] rh tpaivSfieyov rris tre-
9epos ii rhv fnrip pis aipct Kara- Kiivris irphs t\ims, % atKiivf] fiipos

TL 2
132 THE STOICS.

Chap, these examples one thing is clear, how impossible


'

the Stoics found it to assign reality to -what is not


material,
{l) The in- In carrying out this theory, they could not, as
Z^^-"^ might he expected, wholly succeed. Hence a Stoic
material, could not deny that there are certain things which
it is absurd to call material. Among such include
empty space, place, time, and expression (Xsicrov)-^
Admitting these to be incorporeal, they still would not
allow that they do not exist at all. This view belongs
only to isolated members of the Stoic School, for
which they must be held personally responsible.^
How they could harmonise belief in incorporeal
things with their tenet that existence alone belongs
to what is material is not on record.
(2) Comes The question next before us is: What led the

Xce<i tie' Stoics to this materialism ? Jt might be supposed


Stoic ma- that their peculiar theory of knowledge based on
sensation was the cause ; but this theory did not pre-
clude the possibility of advancing from the sensible
to the super-sensible. It might. quite as well be said
that their theory of knowledge was a consequence of
their materialism, and that they referred all know-
ledge to sensation, because they could allow no real
being to anything which is not material. The pro-
bability therefore remains that their theory of know-

%Xowa (f>aw6ii.ivov jrphs TiiiMs. something immaterial.


Cleomedes, Meteora, 112, dis- ' 7>itf^. vii. 140 Stob.'Ecl.i.
;

tinguishes four meanings of 392; Sexf. Math. x. 218 and


livv. In the two first it means 237 viii. 11 vii. 38 Pyirh.
; ; ;

something material in the


; ii. 81 iii. 52.
; See p. 92, 2.
others, as a definition of time, * See p. 94, 1.
STUDY OF NATURE: MATERIALISM. 133

ledge and their materialistic view of nature both Chap.


indicate one and the same habit of mind, and that
both are due to the action of the same causes.
Nor will it do to seek for these causes in the in- (a) The
fluence exercised by the Peripatetic or pre-Socratic ^^^^"
philosophy on the Stoic School. At first sight, indeed, not am, ra-

it might appear that the Stoics had borrowed from '^p^2te-


Heraclitus their materialism, together with their tio views.

other views on nature ; or else it might seem to be


an expansion of the metaphysical notions of Plato
and Aristotle.For if Aristotle denied Plato's dis-
tinction ofform and matter to such an extent that
he would hardly allow form to emat at all except in
union with matter, might it not appear to others
more logical to do away with their distinction in
thought, thus reducing form to a property of matter ?

Were there not difficulties in the doctrine of a Grod


external to the world, of a passionless Keason ; were
there not even difficulties in the antithesis of form
and matter, which Aristotle's system was powerless to
overcome ? And had not Aristoxenus and-Dicsearchus
before the time of Zeno, and Strato immediately after
his time, been led from the ground occupied by the
Peripatetics to materialistic views? And yet we
must pause before accepting this explanation. The
founder of Stoicism appears, from what is recorded of
his intellectual growth, to have been repelled by the
Peripatetic School more than by any other; nor is there
the least indication in the records of the Stoic teach-
ing that that teaching resulted from a criticism of
the Aristotelian and Platonic views of a double origin
184 THE STOICS.

Chap, of things. Far from it, the proposition that every-


'

thing capable of acting or being acted upon must be


material, appears -with the Stoics as an independent
axiom needing no further proof.
(J) iTie The supposed connection between the Stoics and
Stnic Via-
Heraclitus, so far from explaining their materialistic
not Aue to views, already presumes their existence. Yet long
ttig. before Zeno's time the philosophy of Heraclitus as a
living tradition had become extinct. No historical

connection therefore, or relation of original depend-


ence, can possibly exist between the two, but at most
a subsequent perception of relationship can have
directed Zeno to Heraclitus. Zeno's own view of the
world was not a consequence, but the cause, of his
sympathy with Heraclitus. In short, neither the
Peripatetics nor Heraclitus can have given the first
impulse to Zeno's materialism, although they may
have helped in many ways to strengthen his views on
that subject, when already formed.
(c) Prae- The real causes for these views must therefore be
nought elsewhere, and will be found in the central
^oftheStoio
philosophy idea of
the cause.
the whole system of the Stoics the practical
character of their philosophy. From the first devot-
ing themselves with all their energies to practical
enquiries, in their theory of nature the Stoics occu-
pied the ground of common views, which know of no
real object excepting what is grossly sensible and cor-
poreal. Their aim in speculation was to discover a
''firm basis for human actions.' In action, however,
men are brought into direct and experimental contact

> See p. 66, 1.


STUDY OF NATURE: MATERIALISM. 135

with objects. The objects then presented to the Chap.


'

senses are, we must know, regarded in their naked


reality without concealment, nor is an opportunity
afforded for doubting their real being. Their reality
is proved practically, inasmuch as it affects us and
offers itself for the exercise of our powers. In every
such exercise of power, both subject and object are
always material. Even when an impression is con-
veyed to the soul of man, the direct instrument is
something material the voice or the gesture. In
the region of experience there are no such things as
non-material impressions. This was the ground
occupied by the Stoics : a real thing is what either

acts on us, or is acted upon by us. Such a thing is


naturally material ; and the Stoics with their practical
ideas not being able to soar above what is most obvi-
ous, declared that reality belongs only to the world
of bodies.
Herefrom it would appear to follow that only in- (3) Con-

dividual perceptions are true, and that all general ^qf-u^^oic


conceptions without exception must be false. If each "inate'
.
riaUsm.
notion (XsKTOv) is incorporeal, and consequently un- (a) j.

much higher ^w*^"*^


real,*
'
will not absence of reality in a
_
'
percep-
degree belong to the notion of what is general ? tims alone
Individual notions refer directly to perceptions, i.e.
^^j^^f
to something incorporeal ; nevertheless they indirectly trutk as-

refer to the things perceived, i.e. to what is material, general


But general notions do not even indirectly refer to ??-
. twm.
anything corporeal; they are pure fabrications of
the mind, which have nothing real as their object.
> Seep. 93; 182, 1.
136 THE STOICS.

Chap. This the Stoics explicitly maintained.' To attribute


'

notwithstanding to these general conceptions, to


which no real objects correspond, a higher truth and
certainty than belongs to the perceptions of individual
objects, was a gross inconsistency, but one which the
Stoic system made not the slightest attempt to over-
come.
(J) Tlieory The materialism of the Stoics likewise led to some
"salinter- remarkable assertions in the matter of natural science.
If the attributes of things, the soul and even the
powers of the soul, are all corporeal, the relation of
attributes to their objects, of the soul to the body, of
one body to another body, is that of mutual inter-
mingling.^ Moreover, inasmuch as the essential
attributes of any definite material belong to every
part of that material, and the soul resides in every
part of the body, without the soul's being identical
with the body, and without the attributes being
identical with the material to which they belong, or
with one another ; it follows that one body may
intermingle with another not only by occupying the
vacant spaces in that body, but by interpenetrating
all its parts, without, however, being fused into a
hoinogeneous mass with it.* This view involves not
only a denial of the impenetrability of matter, but it

' See p. 84, i. Now, if each attribute is due to


' See p. 105, 3. the presence of some material
Let a piece of red-hot iron
' producing it, there is no avoid-
be taken, every part of whiph is ing the conclusion that there
heavy, hard, hot, &o. Not one must exist in the iron, and in
of these attributes can be con- each part of it, as many various
founded with another, or yyith materials as there are attributes,
the iron itself, but each one without any one of them losing
runs through the whole iron, its own identity.
;';

STUDY OF NATURE: MATERIALISM. 137

further supposes that a smaller body when mingled Chap.


VI.
with a greater body will extend over the whole of the
latter. Tt is known as the Stoic theory of universal
intermingling (^Kpaais So oKwv), and is alike different
from the ordinary view of mechanical mixture and
from that of chemical mixture. It differs from the
former in that every part of the one body is inter-
penetrated by every part of the other; from the
latter, because the bodies after mixture still retain
their own properties.' This peculiar theory, which

' IKog. vii. 151 : koI tos union of substances, in which


Kptl(reis Se SiS\ov ylv(r6at, KaOd each retains its olKeia. ovtrla or
<j>ri<Ttp d XpitriiTTros iv rfj Tptrp itohJttjs Kara rijv irepiiypwpiiv j
TUV fj}V(riKUUf KOl fX^ KOTCt TTepi- aiyxvais, in which both sub-
ypo^Tjv Kal TTopdOefriv Koi yoip els "
stances, as well as attributes,
ireKayos oAiyos ohos ^Kridfls ^irl are destroyed ( ipSeipeadai ),
iTffffoi' avTiirapeKTad^fTeraL etra giving rise to a third body
irviiip9ap'l)ff(Tcu. According to KpaffLs = 5vo ^ Kal irXeidvuv tiv&v
Sfoi. Bel. i. 374, the Stoics ffotfA.d'caiv tiKaiv 5C SXx}p avTiirape-

more accurately distinguish Kraaiv aWiiKais oStois, Sttrre


jui^ts, KpouTis, vapddeffis, ffvyxvffts. (rdi^eip eKoxTTov avrSJv 4v rp fii^ei
napoLdeCis is trafjtdrwp awaip^ Karh Tp roia^Tr] r^v tc oiKeiav oltriav
T^s iiTKJiavelas ; for instance, the Koi T^s ef auTji 7roi6T7iras. Mate-
combination of various kinds rials thus united can be agairt
of grain. Mili; is Siio fl Kal separated, but yet are they so
TrKcL^Vfjov tratfidTuif avTiirapeKTatTis united ws fi-rtSev n6piov iv aurots
:

SC HXaVf vno^evovaav ruv trv^t^vSiv Ti/oi ju^ fierexov vdvruv tuv iv t^

KipX owTct TTOioT^Tftiy for in- ; fjdyfjiart.


stance, the union of fire and For such a union to be pos-
iron, of soul and body. Such a sible, (1) it must be possible
union is called juijis in the case for one body to penetrate every
of solid bodies, Kpams in the part of another, without being
case of fluids. "Siyxvan is Sia fused into a homogeneous mass.
ijKa\ 'ir\ei6vuv iroiOT'hTuv wepi rh, Hence the expression aafia Sio.

fTf^/xara jUTa)3oX^ els erepas Sta- fftifiaros eLvriirap^Keiv, trufia ffd^a-


tpepoifftjs toiStwi' jtokJttjtoj yeve- TQs elvat riirov Kal ffw/Aa x^P*'^^
aw, as in the making up salves 5th c(ifjt,aTQS K6j/aujUT}6cTcpov trepie-
and medicines. Very much in XOVTOS a.\7\A Tov TTh-iipovs tU T^
the same way according to K\T\peS iv5uOfiVOV {^Plut. C Not.
Alex. Aphr. De Mixt. 142, a, 37, 2, p. 1077 ; Alex. 142, b
Chrysippus distinguished three Themist. Phys. 37 Svmpl. Phys. ;

kinds of /**f t? KapdQemsy or ; 123, b ; Hippolyt. Eefut. Haer,


;

138 TBE STOICS.

Chap. is one of the much debated but distinctive features of


VI.
the Stoic system,' cannot have been deduced from
physical causes. On the contrary, the arguments by
which Chrysippus supported it prove that it was ulti-
mately the result of metaphysical considerations.*

i.21) (2) it must be possible


;
capable of extension, whilst re-
for the smaller body to extend taining their own properties ;

over the whole size of the frankincense, for instance,


greater. This is affirmed by when burnt, and gold. (3) The
Chrysippus : ouSey dirfxew xpi- soul penetrates every part of
fiepoSf olvou a-raXayfibv va Kepatrai the body, without losing its
r^v fliXoTToy, or even eh iKov properties. So (pirns does in
vhv K6(rfiov Stareveiif rp Kpdffei rhv plants, and ?{ does in all which
trraKayfiiv (^Phct. 10; AUx. 142, it connects. (4) The same
b; IMog.). The greater body is holds good of fire in red-hot
said to help the smaller, by metal, of fire and air in water
giving to it an extension of and earth, of poisons and per-
which it would not otherwise fumes in things with which
be capable. Nevertheless, the they are mixed, and of light,
bodies so united need not which penetrates air.
necessarily occupy more space The first of these arguments
than was previously occupied clearly does not embody the
by one of them {Alex. 142, b real reason in the mind of
Platin. Bnn. 463, C.
iv. 7, 8, p. Chrysippus ;it might, with
Fie. 860, 14, Or.). The ab- equal justice, have been used to
surdities which this theory in- prove anything else. Just as
volves were already exposed by little does the second for the
;

Arcesilaus (^Phit. 7), and in phenomena to which it refers


detail by Alexander, Plutarch, would be equally well explained
Bextus, and Plotinus, by the on the theory of simple inter-
latter in a whole treatise (Enn. mingling (iropdSeffjs) or com-
ii. 7) irepi rrjs Si* cf\i' Kp^reus. plete mixing. Nor
((ni7xi'0'ii)
* IloXXe^
ix^v yhp Xeyerat Trepl does the fourth argument, taken
Kpitreais Kal trx^^^v ai^vvroi irepl independently of the theory of
Tov irpoKiifiiVov tTKefifiards eltn the corporeal nature of pro-
trapa Tois AoyfiartKOis ffrrfo'ets. perties, necessarily lead to the
Sext. Pyrrh. iii. 56. See pre- idea of Kpaa-is as distinct from
vious note. Trapiieffis and ffiyxviris. For
According to Alex. 142, a,
^ heat, according to the Peri-
the following arguments were patetic view, might be regarded
used by Chrysippus (1) The
argument from Koival Imoiai
:

as a property of what is hot,
light as a definite property of
our notion of xpaais is different a transparent body (conf.
from that of <riyxv<rcs or irap<- Alex. 143, a), vapdSeiTts and
Seffij. (2) Many bodies are (riyxiHTis sufficing for other
DYNAMICAL VIEW OF NATURE. 139

We have, moreover, all the less reason to doubt this Chap.


fact, inasmuch as the materialistic undercurrent of
the Stoic system affords for it the best explanation.
Although the stamp of materialism was sharply B. Dy-
cut, and its application fearlessly made by the Stoics,
^f^,"'^
they were yet far from holding the mechanical theory nature.
of nature, which appears to us to be a necessary con- andfm'er.
sequence of strict materialism. The universe was
explained on a dynamical theory ; the notion of force
was placed above the notion of matter. To matter,
they held, alone belongs real existence;
characteristic of real existence they sought in causa-
but the
^
tion, in the capacity to act and to be acted upon.'
This capacity belongs to matter only by virtue of
certain inherent forces, which impart to it definite
attributes. Let pure matter devoid of every attribute

.things. Even the fact, greatly of God to the world, can hardly-
insisted upon by the Stoics, be otherwise explained than as
that things so mixed can be Chrysippus did, if once mate-
again separated into their com- rial existence be assigned to
ponent materials (Alex. 143, the soul, to ((>i}ir(s, to e|ij, and to
a Stob. i. 378) was not con-
; God. We have, therefore, here
elusive. As long as the know- the real ground on which this
ledge of the actual composition theory of Kpdais was based and ;

depended on isolated cases and Simplioius rightly deduces it


crude experiments, like the one herefrom (Phys. 123, b) rh Se :

named by Stobseus (into a mix- croi/ia 5iA adifikwros j^apeiv ol iiiv


ture of wine and water, put an apyaioi as ivapyis aronov i\dn-
oiled sponge, it will absorb $avov, oi 5e ani rris ffroas Strrepoif
the water and not the wine), vpoffiiKavTO ws ctKoKovBovv rais
and as long as the substantial (npZv airav inro6e<reaiv . . .
change of elements, advocated aiiimra yap \4yeiv irivra SoxoSy-
by the Stoics as well as by the res, koI tos iroidxTiTos koI riiv
Peripatetics, was clung to, it if/ux^"; <"' ^^^ vavThs Spuvres toC
was no difficultmatter for an ffd/ia/ros ical t^iv 'fivxhv xwpoSo-oi/

opponent to reply. On the koI tAs iroiiiTijTar iv ra!s Hpiaeiri,


other hand, the relation of the avvcxtipow crufM S<4 adifiaToi
soul to the body, of property to x'"f"'''-
gubject-matter,of <(ii(risto<()uTiv, ' See p. 95, 3; 126, 1.
140 THE STOICS.

Chap, be considered, the matter which underlies all definite


'

materials, and out of which all things are made ;


^ it

will be found to be purely passive, a something


subject to any change, able to assume any shape and
quality, but taken by itself devoid of quality, and
unable to produce any change whatsoever.^ This
inert and powerless matter is first reduced into shape
by means of attributes,^ all of which suppose tension
in the air-currents which produce them, and conse-
quently suppose a force producing tension.* Even
the shape of bodies, and the place they occupy in
space is, according to the Stoics, something deriva-
tive, the consequence of tension ; tension keeping the
different particles apart in one or the other particular
way.^ Just as some modern physiologists construct
nature by putting together a sum of forces of attrac-
tion and repulsion, so the Stoics refer nature to two
forces, or, speaking more accurately, to a double kind
of motion expansion and condensation. Expansion
works outwardly, condensation inwardly condensation ;

produces being, or what is synonymous with it, mat-

' On &voms 8X17, as the uni- 8J) rcTTapa (TTOixeia fti>ai A^oS riiv
versal inoiceifieyov or ovffia koiv^, &itoloi/ ovaiav ttji/ lihijj/.

see p. 100. Sext. Math. x. 312 :


4 ' See p. 141, 2.
awoiov fiiv oiv Kol eyhs adifuvros ' Pint. Sto. Rep. 43. See p.
T^v Tuv ^Kuv inreffT'tiffavTO yevstriv 105, 1.
oJ SrwiKot. ct.pxh 7ckp TUP &t>' * See p. 105, 1 and 2 ; 127,
ot' OAiTois iffTiv 7) &iroios v\ri Koi 5 ; 128, 2.
Si' b\av rpexT^, iKTafiaXKoiant Simpl. Cat. 67, e (Schol.
'

T6 Tairns yCveTai rcl Teaaapa 74, a, 10) Th Toivvv ffXW" ol


:

ffTOixeio, -irvp, k.t.\. Pint. C. 2to)ikoI riiv Titriv irapexeaBai


Not. 48, 2, p. 1085 : ri SXij Kofl' \4yov(riv, Sia-vsp tV m^toJu tuv
avriiv li\oyos oSffa Kal &iroios. iTTifieimv SidtTTaffiv. Sih Kol ivSelav
M. Awel. xii. 30 : iiia ohaia dpi^ovrai ypa/iii^v riiv els &Kpoy
KOLvii, Ktui Sielpynrai ISites iroiois Teranivriv.
tr^fiari fuipiois. Diog. 137: t4
;:

DYNAMICAL VIEW OF NATURE. 141

ter ; expansion gives rise to the attributes of things.' Chap.


VI.
Whilst, therefore, they assert that everything really
existing must be material, they still distinguish in
what is material two component parts the part which
is acted upon, and the part which acts, or in other

words matter and force?


The Stoics, however, would not agree with Plato (2) The
nature of
and Aristotle so far as to allow to formal and final force,
(a) Force
causes a place side by side with this acting force or
Utitited to
efiBcient cause. If in general anything may be called the notion
of efficient
cause.
Simpl. Cat. 68, : oi Z\ Archedemus, and Posidonins.
2tco{Ko1 Ziiva^jLiv^ ^ \tJaXKov KivriffLv Sext. Math. ix. 11 oi airii t^s :

cFToas Sva Kfyoi/res apx^s^ Behv Kal


rideVTaij r^v fiey 4irl tA effw, T'qv &noiOf S\71P, rhv fikv 6ehy iroiety
Be eirl to I|(M * koL t^v juev ' Tov {tnei\ii(l>atn, ttjv Sk S\t]v trila'xetv
elyatj rijv Be rod trothf eJvat voiji- re Kal TpeVetrflot. Similarly
(ovaiv aWiap. Nemes. Nat. Horn, Alex. Aph. De Mixt. 144
c. 2, p. 29 et SI \4yoifv, KaBdnep oi
; AcUll. Tat. Isag. c. 3, 124, E ;

^TutKol, roviKTiv riva eivai Kivtjtrty PMt. PI. Phil. 89 Stob.


i. 3, ;

trepi Tct (Tdofiaraj ets ri etrw Sjua Bel. i. 306 322, according to the
;

Koi els Th e|(u KtvovjxlvTiv, KaX rijy passage quoted, p. 101 2, from ,

^ev eisrh |ft) fieyeOiai/ Kol itoi6t7]- Zeno respecting B\7) Sia toiJttjj :

Ttav aitoreAeffTiKiiv ilvtu^ T7?v 5e 5i Siadeiv rhv rod navrhs \6yov ftv
eU rh %(Tui ev^aeas Koi oiialas. eyioi elfiaptieviiy KdKovffiv, ot6vtrep
This remark is confirmed by iv rp y6vri t6 ffTrepfia. Sen. Ep.
what is quoted, p. 128, 2 from 65, 2 Dicunt, ut scis, Stoici
:

Censorinus, and by the language nostri, duo esse in rermnnatura,


of Plutarch (Def. Orac. c. 28, ex quibus omnia fiant causam :

Schl. p. 425), in reference to et materiam. Materia jacet


Chrysippus TroWdKis etpjKtiiy,
: iners, res ad omnia parata, ces-
8ti tois CIS rh airrjs iieaov ri ouffia satura si nemo moveat. Causa
Kai rats ctirb Tov avTTJs fxetrov Stoi- autem, i.e. ratio, materiam
KeiToi Koi avvix^'^^^ Kiiffifffffi. format etquoconquevultversat,
- Diog. vii. 134 ; So/cei 5' ex ilia varia opera producit.
avTois &px^^ elyai rwp B\av SvOf Esse ergo debet, unde fit aliquid,
rh TTOtovv Kal rh vdffxoy. fh fiej/ deinde a quo fiat. Hoc causa
odf w&a'xoy slvaL t^v tiirotov oi/fflay est, illud materia. Tbid. 23
r^v liKrtVy rh Se iroiovv rhp iv avrri Universa ex materia et ex Deo
\6'Yov rhv di&v, Tovrov yiip Hyra constant potentius autem
. . .

&tSiOv Sii irdffns aiiTfjs Srifuovpye^v est ac pretiosius quod facit,


e/caiTTo. Such is the teaching quod est Deus, quam materia
of Zeno, Cleanthes, Chrysippus, patiens Dei.

142 THE STOICS.

Chap. a cause which serves to bring about a definite result'


VT.
and various kinds of causes may be distinguished,
according as they bring about this result directly or
indirectly, by themselves alone or by the help of
others' in the highest sense there can be, according
to the Stoics, only one acting or efficient cause. The
form is due to the workman, and is therefore only a
part of the efficient cause. The type-form is only an
instrument, which the workman employs in his work.
The final cause or end-in-chief, in as far as it repre-

sents the workman's intention, is only an occasional


cause ; in as far as it belongs to the work he is about,
it is not a cause at all, but a result. There can be
but one pure and unconditional cause, just as there

' Sen. Ep. 65, 11: Nam si, time, place, and motion, ought
quocumqne remote quid effici to be reckoned as causes, since
non potest, id causam judicant nothing can be produced with-
esse faciendi, &c. Sext. Math. out these. He allows, however,
ix. 228 :aXrdv i<TTiv ov irap6v-
ei that a distinction must be made
Tos yiverai ri &TroT6\6(r)UO. This between causa efficiens and
appears to be the most general causa superveniens. This agrees
Stoic definition, That given by with what Cicero (De Fate,
Seiet. Pyrrh. iii. 14 tovto, Si' h 18, 41) quotes from Chrysippus
evepyovv yiverai rh aTroreXeff/xa relative to causEe perfectse et
and by him said to express the principales, and causae adju-
views of several schools, ex- vantes et proximae, and with
presses a narrower conception the Platonic and Aristotelian
the conception of efficient distinction of alnov Si' h and oS
cause, which, however, for a oiiK Si'cu. See teller's Philo-
Stoic, is the only essential sophic der Griechen. In the
one. same way, Plut. Sto. Kep. 47,
^ Seait. Pyrrh. iii. 15, dis- 4, p. 1056 distinguishes between
tinguishes between irweKTMh, alria auroTeXV and npoKarap-
avvalria, and ffivepya aXrta, all of KTiKii, Alex. Aph. De Fato, 72,
which are, however, subordi- blames the Stoics ir/irji/os yhp
:

nated to the Si' i, which he is anitov KaTdKeyovfft, Tct fievirpoKa-


there alone discussing. Seneca TapKTLK^, Tct Si iTvvairta, tA Se
1. c. maintains that, according eKTiKd, Tot Se irvpeKTtKci, ret Se ^\Ao
to the definition given above. Ti. Conf. Orelli ad locum.
DYNAMICAL VIEW OF NATURE. 143

can be but one matter ; and to this efficient cause Chap.


everything that exists and everything that takes place ^
must be referred.'
In attempting to form a more accurate notion of (V) CIm-

this efficient cause, the first point which deserves ^y^g g^.
^'''"*
attention is, that the Stoics believed every kind of
cause.
action ultimately to proceed from one source. For
hovr could the world be such a self-circumscribed
xmity, such a harmonious whole, unless it were
governed by one and the same force ?^ Again, as
everything which acts is material, the highest efficient
cause must likewise be considered material ; and since
all qualities and forces are produced by vapour-like
or fiery elements, can it be otherwise with the highest
acting force?' Everywhere warmth is the cause of
nourishment and growth, life and motion ; all things
have in themselves their own natural heat, and are
preserved and kept in life by the heat of the sun.
* 1. c, after enu-
Seneoa, irparov irotoOv fi Th apxvy^" ttoi'/j-

merating the four causes of <reais.

Aristotle, to which the Platonic ^ C^c. N. De. ii. 7, 19, after

idea is added as a fifth, con- speaking of the consentiens,


tinues This turba causarum
: conspirans, oontinuata cognatio
embraces either too much or rerum ((ru/iTrcEfleio ray SAaiy),
too little. Sed nos nunc primam continues: Hsec ita iieri om-
etgeneralemquserimusoausam. nibus inter se concinentibus
Hebo simplex esse debet, nam et mundi partibus prof ecto non
materia simplex est. Quserimus possent, nisi ea uno divino et
quse sit causa, ratio scilicet continuato spiritu contineren-
faciens, id est Deus. Ita enim, tur. See Semt. Math. ix. 78.
qusecumque retulistis, non sunt The same view is further ex-
multse et singulse causse, sed ex panded in Sext. Math. ix. 78.
una pendent, ex ea, quse faciet. Couf. the quotation on p. 127,
Conf Stob. Eel. i. 336 ofrioi' S'
. : 5,from Alexander.
S Z^i/wi' ^alv ehai 5i' * . . .
' According to the remarks,

XpifftTTiros oitTiof ilvai \eyei 81' t p. 105 and 126, this requires no
. . . noiTt^{ij/ios 5e oSraiy '
cCiTioi' proof,
5' iari twos 5i' t ineho, fi ri
:

144 THE STOICS.

Chap. What applies to parts of the world must apply to the


VI.
world as a whole ; hence heat or fire is the power to
which the life and the existence of the world must be
referred.'
This power must be further defined to be the soul
of the world, the highest reason, a kind, beneficent,
and philanthropic being ; in short, deity. The uni-
versal belief and the universal worship of God prove
this, as the Stoics think, beyond a doubt ^ still more ;

accurate investigation confirms it. Matter can never


move or fashion itself; nothing but a power inhe-
rent as the soul is in man can produce these results.'

The world would not be the most perfect and com-


plete thing it is unless Eeason were inherent therein ; *

'
ac. N. D. 23 (oonf.ii. 9, ea et ipsa tota natura fervida
ill. apparently
14, 35), gives it est, et cjeteris naturis omnibus
as the view of Cleanthes, who salutarem impertit et vitalem
alone is mentioned, 9, 24. All calorem.Ex quo concluditur,
living things, plants, and ani- cum omnes mundi partes sus-
mals, exist by heat nam omne : tineanturoalore, mundum etiam
quod est calidnm et igneum ipsum simili parique natura
cietur et agitur motu sno. in tanta diutuinitate servari
Digestion and circulation are eoque magis quod intelligi de-
the result of heat ex quo in- : bet, oalidum ilium atque igneum
telligi debet, eam caloris natu- ita in omni fusum esse natura,
ram vim habere in se vitalem ut in eo insit procreandi vis,
per omnem mundum pertinen- &c.
tem. Moreover omnes partes :
* On the argument, ex con-

mundi . calore fultse sus-


. . sensu gentium, consult Pint.
tinentui. There must be fire Sto. Rep. 38, 3 Com. Not. 82,
;

in earth and stones, else it 1 ; Oic. N. D. ii. 2, 5 Seneca, ;

could not be extracted there- Benef. iv. 4 Sex:t. Math. ix.


;

from. Water, especially fresh 123 and 131, where different


spring water, is warm, more varieties of it are given, even a
particularly in winter, and as particular one from Zeno.
motion warms us, so the roll of " Sext. Math. ix. 75.
the waves does the sea. From N. D. iii. 9, 22 Zeno
Oie. :

water likewise as it evaporates, enim ita ooncludit quodratione :

air derives its heat. Jam . . . utitur, melius est, quam id,
vero Teliqua quarta pars mundi, quod ratione non utitur. Nihil
'
:

DYNAMICAL VIEW OF NATURE. 145

nor could it contain any beings possessed of conscious- Chap.


VI.
ness, unless it were conscious itself.' It could not
produce creatures endowed with a soul and reason,
unless it were itself endowed with a soul and reason.^
Actions so far surpassing man's power could not
exist, unless there were a cause for them in perfection
equally surpassing that of man.' The suhordination
of means to ends which governs the world in every
part down to the minutest details would be inexplic-
able, unless the world owed its origin to a reasonable
creator.* The graduated rank of beings would be
autem mundo melius. Katione (Tuyepar^ rb -Trpoiefievoy (Tirepp.a
'

igitur mundus utitur. The KoyiKov Kol aiiTh \oytK6v sffTiv 6 Se '

same, ibid. ii. 8, 21, and 12, K6tTfios vpoleToi tTTrepfia \oytKov,
34. Sext. Math. ix. rh 104 : ei Koymhr &pa effrly d Kdffftoj. The
XoyiKhv Tov fvti KoyiKov Kpetrrdv same proof in Sext. Math. ix. 77
iffTLV, ouSej' 5e ye K^fftiov KpuTT6j/ and 84 ; Conf ibid. ii.
(Mo. 1. c. .

4(TTi, \oyiKhv &pa d kSitijlos . . . 31, 79; 6, where also the


18,
ri yap poephp rod fi^ voepov K(d passage in Xenophon, Mem. i.
^fifl/vxov TOV fi^ ifiyjtixov KpstrT6if 4, 8, quoted by Sext. ix. 94, is
4ffTiv oi/Bev S4 ye K6(riJL0v Kpeirrov referred to.
voephs &pa KaX ^pApvx^s ifftiv 6 ' Cfic. 1. c. iii. 10, 25 : Is.
K6(riios. Likewise Diog. 142, [Chrysippus] igitur : si aliquid
says that Chrysippus, Apollo- est, inquit, quod homo efScere
dorus, and Posidonius agree non possit, qui id effioit melior
that the world is Cfov xal \oyMhv est homiue. Homo autem hsec,
Ktd efirl/vxof Kol voep6v rh yap ' quae in mundo sunt, effioere non
C^Oy TOV p.^ Q4^ KpetTTOV ouSei/
potest. Qui potuit igitur, is
Se TOV KAffflOU KpslTTOV Cv^ ^P* '
praestat homini. Homini autem
6 K6(Tp.0S. prsestare quis possit, nisi Dens 1
' ao. N. D. ii. 8, 22 Zeno : Est igitur Deus. The same,
affirms : NuUius sensu carentis only a little more fully. Hid..
pars aliqua potest esse sentiens. ii. 6, 16. To this argument^
Mundi autem partes sentientes another favourite one of the
sunt. Non igitur caret sensu Stoics, based on the fulfilment
muudus. of prophecy, belongs.
^ Diog. 143 : ip.-^vxov 5e [Thv * Cleanthes made use of
K6ffp.oy\ 6ts StjXoc ck ttJs rifieTepas arguments from final causes to.
ij/vxvs iKetdev oHfTris airofftrda'- prove the existence of God.
(noTos. Sext. Math. ix. 101 Of this nature are all the f our>
Z^vofv 5e d KiTTiehs airh "Bevo^Siv- arguments which he employs in
Toy T^f iKpop^'l)V ha^iiiV' ovrwffl do. N. D. ii. 5, but particularly
; ;
:

146 THE STOICS.

Chap. incomplete, unless there were a highest Being of all


VI.
whose moral and intellectual perfection cannot be
surpassed.^ Although this perfection belongs, in the
first place, to the world as a whole,'' nevertheless, as
in everything consisting of many parts, so in the world
the ruling part must be distinguished from other
parts. It is the part from which all acting forces
emanate and diffuse themselves over the world,'
whether the seat of this efficient force be placed in
the heaven, as was done by Zeno, Chrysippus, and
the majority of the Stoics;* or in the sun, as by

the fourth, based on the regular See p. 143, 2 ; 144, 1-4

order and beauty of heaven. A 145, 1 and 2.


building cannot exist withoub = Sext. Math. ix. 102, ex-
a builder no more can the
; panding Zeno's argument given,
building of the world exist p. 145, 2 ir(ff7js yhp (p^itreus Kol
:

without a ruling spirit. There- i//ox^* V Karapx^ Trjs Kivifffstas


with Cicero connects the above- ylvfffSat 8oKe( ^LTrh TiycfioytKou koX
named argument of Chrysippus. vaffat at iirl t^P-^PV tov B\ov
The same writer, N. D. ii. 32-66, 4^aTro(rTe\\6iJievat SvvdfieLS s oirii
gives very fully the physical Tiyos Tnjyris tov riyefiavtKov |oiro-
theological argument for the (TTeWoKTai. Cie. N. D. ii. 29
existence of providence, which according to Cleanthes, omnem
is given in a shorter form by enim naturam necesse est, quse
Cleomedes, Meteora, 1 Seneca,
; non solitaria sit, neque simplex,
De Provid.i. 1, 2-4 Nat. Qu. i.
; sed cum alio juncta atque con-
Sesut. Math. ix. Ill conf. Ps.
; nexa, habere aliquem in se
Censorvn. Fragm. i. 2, p. 7.5, principatum [ = Tiyf/iovLKiv] ut
Jahn ; Phit. Plao. i. 6, 8 belief
: in homine mentem, &c. . . .

in gods grows out of consider- Itaque necesse est illud etiam,


ing the world and its beauty, an in quo sit totius naturas prin-
argument also quoted by Sext. cipatus, esse omnium optimum.
Math. ix. 26. See following note.
' See the expansion of this * Cic. Acad. ii. 41, 126:
thought by Cleanthes (in Sext. Zenoni et reliquis fere Stoiois
Math. ix. 88-91) and the Stoics Eether videtur summus Deus,
(in Cic. N. D. ii. 12, 33). Cicero mente prsditus, qua omnia re-
distinguishes four kinds of gantur. N. D. i. 14, 36 : (Zeno)

beings Plants, Animals, Men, aethera Deum dicit. 15, 39:
and that being which is alto- ignem prsterea et enm, quem
gether reasonable and perfect antea dixi, aethera (Chrysippus
deity. Deum dicit esse). JHog. vii.
: :

DYNAMICAL VIEW OF NATURE. 147

Cleanthes;' or in the centre of the world, as by Chap.


VI.
Archedemus.^ This primary source of all life and
motion, the highest Cause and the highest Reason, is

G-od. Grod therefore and formless matter are the two


ultimate grounds of things.'

138 : ovpavbs Se iffTiv i) io'xd'TV considers the original deity;


TT^pKjjfpeia, ^ trdv i'Spurat rh
4v for this does not exclude the
Bf'iov. IMd. 139 rhv i\ov Kdfffiof: other. No doubt he identiiied
^^ov 6vra /cai ^fi^vxov Kal \oyiKhv o(8))p with calor (see p, 144, 1),
exeiv TjyefioyiKhv fiev rov al64pa, believing that it emanated from
KaBd <jyi\atii 'Aprlirarpos . . . the sun. Biog. 139: KAcdvflijs
Xpiffnrjros S' , , . kc^ Xloaeih^vios 5e [rh TyytptsviKiv fpTifft] rhy TfjXiov.
. . T^v ovpav&v
. (pafTi rd iiyefio- Ar. Didyrmis, 1. o. TiyepLOPiKhv
vixbv ToC K6iTiiov. He continues : Sh Tov K6fffjLov KKedvdei fiev ^pf(re
6 ficyrot XpifatinTos Siatpop^repoi rhv ^Kioy eiyat 8io rh ix4yi3Tov
irii\iv r6 Kadaptirepov rov alOepos rav dnrpav imdpx^tv KaX irKeiffTa
iv ravr^ "''V
ovpdycp] A koI
[ ffvpL&dKKiffQai nphs t^v tuv &\uv
irpoTou dedv Keyovfftv, aUrdrjTiKus SioIktktiv, k.t.\. Stob. Eel.
&(Tircp KEXupT^KeVai 5icb rSiv 4v a4pt i. 452 Ps. Cemorin. Fragm. i.
;

Kal SicL rwv ^tp^v a-nivTaiv koI 4. According to Epiphait. Exp.


ijtvT&i/j Sict S^ Trjs yijs ai/TTJs Kad' Fidei. 1090, c, he called Ihe
eJu'. Arius Didymus, in Ens. sun the ScfSovxos to the universe.
Prsep. Bv. xv. 15, 4 Xpva-lwirip :
^ Stoh. 1. c. 'Apx'5aoj (leg.
:

Se [7]yefiovtKiv rnv K6(rf/.ov etvai A


with Cod. 'Apxe'Sw") Ti ^7e-
rov alBepa Tbv KaBapdyraTov
iipeffe] fioviKhv TOV K6(rijLou iv y^ utrdpx^iv
KaX elKtKptvetTTaTOV, are TrdvTUf dirc^ilvaTO the same statement
:

evKtyryrSTaTOV Svra Kal t^i' 3a.ij/ without mentioning rthe name


irepidyoVTa rov Kiaputu tpiffiy. in Ar. Didymus, 1. c. This re-
Ibid. XV. 20, 2 According to : minds one somewhat of the
the Stoics, the air surrounding Pythagorean doctrine of a cen-
sea and earth is the soul of the tral fire, and the view of Speu-
world. Cornut. Nat. De. 8 Os. sippus. The resemblance to
Zeus dwells in heaven, iirti iKei the Pythagoreans is greater, if
iffTi rd Kvpi^arov fiepos rrjs rov SlMpl. De Coelo, Schol. in Ar.
K^ffpiov >livxfis. TertulUa/n (Apol. 505, a, 45, is correct in saying
47 ; Ad Nat. ii. 2, 4) inaccurately Archedemus denied with the
attributes to the Stoics the Pythagoreans that the earth
belief in a God external to was in the centre of the world.
nature. 'See p. 141, 2; 143,1. Aris-
' Acad. 1. c.
die. Clean- : tooles, in Eus. Pr. Ev. xv. 14
thes solem dominari et
. . . ffToix^'iov eivcd tpairi [of ^tw'CkoI']
rerum potiri = Kpareiy twv ^vrtev Twv ivTiav ih irDp, KaS&irep 'HpdK-
putat. He speaks with less AeiTOS, TOiirov 5'
&px.^s ii\T]v Kal
accuracy {KrUehe, Forsch. 428) 6ehv, ats nhdruv.
in N. D. i. 14, 37 ether he :

L 2
148 THE STOICS.

Chap. The language used by the Stoics in reference to


VI.
the Deity at one time gives greater prominence to
(3) Deity, the material, at another to the spiritual side of their
(a) The
conception conception of God. As a rule, both are united in ex-
of Deity when taken
pressions which only cease to be startling
mvre ac-
curately in connection with Stoic views in general. God is
defined.
spoken of as being Fire, Ether, Air, most commonly
as being -n-vsvfMa or Atmospheric-Current, pervading
everything without exception, what is most base and
ugly, as well as what most beautiful.' He is further
is

described^ as the Soul, the Mind, or the Eeason of

Fuller particulars p. Hi,


' rSiy ari/iardTuv. Tei'tulUan,
1 ; Hippolytus, Eefut.
146. Ad Nation, ii. 4: Zeno makes
Haer. i. 21 Chrysippus and : God penetrate the materia mun-
Zeno suppose apx^^ 1^'^^ ^^^^ '^^^ dialis, as honey does the honey-
jriinwy, ffufia Svra rh KaSaptiraToy combs. See p. 105, 3.
(aether). Diog. 148: Antipater Clemens, Strom, v. 691, A:
calls the ov(rla 6eov aepoetS^s. <paffi yap ffw^a lyat Tby Bfity oi

Stob. Eel. i. 60 : Mnesarchus (a ^Tto'iKol Kai iry^vfia Kai' ovaiav,


pupil of Panastius) defines God &tnrp aij.4\i nai r^v ;|w;^i'.
Ibid.
to be rhv tc6(r^ov rijv npuirrii' OV' i,295, C: {oi Stw/jtoI) ffwfia 5>^a
(riav ^xoyra eirl irvei^aros. Sciet. rhy fleiy 5i& rris aTtfi(ndn\i ^\7js
Pyrrh. iii. 218 StwikoI 5J [A.e'- : Tretf>otT7iit4vat Keyovffiv ou KahSts.
yovtri Sebc] Tri/eGjUO Si^/cov Kai Sicfe Protrept. 44, A: toiis airb T?r
rav fiStxBHv (the adverse). (TTOas, 5ict irdtrris ii\7js, Kai Siek Ti)y
AUx. Aphr. on Metaph. 995, b, a.Tifj.OTdr'ijs, rh Buov StijKetv \4-
31 (Schol. in Ar. 607, a, 19) : yovras. Orig. Cels. vi. 71:
u.
Tols atrh ttjs (Ttous So|ey 5 Bibs Tuy '^rtaiKuty (paffitlyrwv Sri & Bebs
Kai rb iroifiTiKiiV oXnov iv ttj v\ri nvevfiA 4tti 5(i ir dyroiv Sie\Ti\vBhs
elmi. Ibid. De Mix. 144, gives Hal irdyr' 4y eavT^ trepiex^y. Op-
them credit: xi/oJ^ari as 5ii ponents like Origen,. 1. c. and
TfdvTioy Zii\Kovri av6.'miiv t6 t i. 21, Alexander, De Mixt. 1. c.

ivai eKdiTTOv Kai rh e^QeffBai Kol and Plutarch, Com. Not. 48,
avixixiviiv. Compare the quota- naturally attack them for their
tions p. 127, 5 and De An. 145 : materialistic views.
[rb^ vovv^ Kai 4v ro7s tpavKordrots = 6toJ. Ecl.i.58. See follow-
eivai Beiov 6yra, us toTs airb Trjs ing note. Diog. 138 (according
iTToas eSo^fv. Lvcicm, Hermot. to Chrysippus and Posidonius) :
81 : aKovofi-sy Se avrov KeyovTos, rby S^ K6afiov oiKGitrBai Kara vovv
ws iia\ 6 deh^ ovk 4v olpav^ effrty, Kai TrpSvoiav . ely &iray avrov
.

dX\& Sih TTiivTQiy 7re(f>oTJ]Kei', oToy fipos SffjKovTOs ToD pov KaBdiTep
iihaiy >rol \i8aiy Kol f<f I0^', &xpi '"'
: ;

DYNAMICAL VIEW OF NATURE. 149

tlie world ; as a united Whole, containing in Him- Chap.


VI.
self the germs of all things ; as the Connecting

Sy /tey fiaWov, 5(* Sv 5J ^ttov. mur et sensibus, on which ac-


More popularly, iJi(J. 147: Scbv count the mens mundi is called
^Iva.t C^av aB6.vaTov hoyinhv TeAetoi/ irp6voia. M. Awrel. iv. 40 iis ev :

^ voepbl' ^p ebdaifiovi^, KUKOV iraf- Q^ov rhv K6ffiMV fiicLV ov(riav KcA
rbs avexiieKTOV, irpovoriTlKhp K6ff- ^vX^^ f^^^^ ^jrexov truyexus
fiov re teal ruv eV Kfjfffi^, ^u^ tlvai hrivoeiv' -nas ew a'iadt]ffLy [liavT^v
fi.4yT0t iaidponcSiiap^ov. eivai 8^ to6tou TTtivTa dLyaSWoTcu icai vws
Thv fi9 Srifiiovpyoi/ twv Hkcuv icai ipfi-ri fii^ irdvTa irpdiriTei. HeracUt.
Sxrvep vanpa. Trmrrtnv Koivui re Alleg. Hom. 72. TertvMan,
Kal rh fiepos avTov rh Si^Koy 8ick ApoL 21 Hunc enim (Xirfo'y)
:

vdfTwv, ft ToWcus irpoffTiyopiais Zeno determinat factitatorem,


jrpovovafiti^effdtu Karot ras ivifdfieis. qui euncta in dispositione for-
Phmd. Nat. De. (JPhilodem,. irepl maverit, eundem et fatiun
ei(r0ei<is) Col. 1 and Oio. Nat. voeari et Deum et animum
De. i. 15, 39, quoting from him Jovis et necessitatem omnium
According to Chrysippus, Zeus rerum. Haec Cleanthes in spiri-
is Kotvij 0d(rjf, eiftappi^yTj, ctra7K7;, tum congerit, quem permea-
K.T.X. Hid. CoL 3 : He con- torem imiversitatis affirm^t.
sidered ySjios to be deity. (Me. Similarly Laetant. Inst. iv. 9,
1. 0. : legis perpetute et aeterrse L, 5. Epijjlian,. Haer. v. 1, p.
vim .. Jovem dicit esse.
. 12: According to the Stoics,
Themist. De An. 72, b : toTj ciTrli God is vovs, residing in the
Tffiifaivos ... 8i^ TrdtTTis oi/irlas world as its soul, and permeat-
iretpoiTtiKevoL rhv Behv TiQefievais^ ing the fj-epucal ovcrlai. Zeus is
Kal 'K9V iLiv eivax povv, ttov Se tfrif- also spoken of as being the soul
X^jv, 1C9V Se tpiiftv, TTOV 8 e^iv. of the world by Carnutus, Nat.
Oic. Aead.ii. 37, 119: No Stoic De. 2 by Plut. Sto. Eep. 39, 2,
;

can doubt hune mundum esse p. 1052 and by Chrysippus,


;

sapientem, habere mentem, iHd. 34, 5, p. 1050: t 8" t,


quae se et ipsura fabricata sit, Koiv}} t^6ffis Kal6 Koivos ttjs ipi-
et omnia moderetur, moveat, trews \6yQs KoA rpSyota
elfiapfjLevTj

regat. Id. N. D. ii. 22, 58: Kal Zeis iffrtv owSe roijs ayTitroSas
ipsius vero mundi . . natura . K\ri0' Travraxov yhp ravra 6pv'
non solum sed plane
artificiosa AezTOi ine* avTuy. Stoi. Eel. i.
artifex ab eodem Zenoue diei- 178: Ziivwv . . . [t)\v elfiap^ivTjy'^
provida utili-
tur, consuitrix et Swd/iiy KivTjTtic^iv T^s v\7]s Kari
tatum opportunitatumque om- TavTa Kal ^trairtos, ^yrtva fi^ Sia-
nium. ... As every nature tpfpeiy np6yotay Kal tpiLfffiy Ka\e7y,
develops from its stock, sic Ar. Sidymns, in Eus. Pr. Ev.
Natura mundi omnes motus XV. 5, 2
] God cares for man
:

habet voluntarios oonatusque He is kind, beneficent, and loves


et appetitiones, quas ipnhs men. Zeus is called K6trnos as
Grseoi vocant, et his consen- oiiTios ToC fpi/, ei/iap/ieyri, because
taneas aetiones sic adhibet ut Koytp SioiKet all things,
eipofiiV(p

nosmet ipsi, qui animis move- iipdareni, 8t( oliSky larty airby
::

150 THE STOICS.

Chap. element in all things; as Universal Law, Nature,


VI,
_ Destiny, Providence as a perfect, happy, ever kind
;

and all-knowing Being nor was it hard to show that ;

no conception could be formed of God without these


attributes.* Both kinds of expression are combined

a'no^iSp6.ffKeiv, irpSvoia, hrt vphs nolle: non possnnt. Farther


Tft XP^*''*/"*"' olKovofiet cKaffra, details respecting the beneficent
AristocJes (Ibid. .xv. 14): Pri- nature of the Grods in Sen.
mary fire contains the causes Benef. i. 9 ; 3-9 and 25-28 ;
iv.
and \6yoi of all things; the Clement, i. 7 ; Nat. Qn. v.
5,
unchangeahle law and destiny 18, 13. On the divine omni-
of the world supplies their con- science Ep. 83, 1 ; "V. Beat. 20, 5.
;

nection. Sen.' Benef. iv. 7, 1 ' According to CUc, N. D. ii.

Quid enim aliud est natura, 30, 75, the Stoics divided the
quam Deus et divina ratio toti argument as to God's providen-
mnndo et partihus ejus inserta? tial care of the world into three
. . Hunc eundem et fatum si
. parts. The first part went to
dixeris non mentieris. (Simi- establish that if there existed
larly Frag. 122 in iaof. Inst. ii. Gods, there must also be a care
8, 23). Id. Nat. Qu. ii. 45, 2 of the world; for Gods could
God or Jupiter may be equally not exist without having some-
well spoken of as Destiny, Pro- thing to do, and to care for the
vidence, Nature, the World. world is the noblest thing that
Stob. Eel. i. 178: 'AvriiraTpos & can be done. If, moreover,
^Tu'iKbs 6e6p tLTTetp^voTO T^v elfxap- deity is the highest being, the
ftevTiv. Zeus
called Koivhs v6-
is world must be governed by
fios by IHog. vii. 88 ; by Clean- deity. The same conclusion is
thes at the end of his hymn arrived at from the wisdom and
(Stab. Bel. i. 34) ; likewise ae. power of deity, which must
N. D. i. 14, 36 says of Zeno always busy itself with what is
Naturalem legem divinam esse best and highest. Lastly, it is
censet, eamque vim obtinere stated, that inasmuch as the
recta imperantem prohibentem- stars, heaven, the universe, and
que contraria. Plict. C. Not. all powers in the world are
32, 1; Sto. Eep. 38, 3 and 7 divine, it is clear that every-
(here following Antipater): God thing must be governed by
must be conceived of as naxdpios, divine reason. The second part
einroiTjTiKbSf ^ikavSpcewoSf KTjSe- proved that the force and skill
fiopixhs, Mkstm. (in
a>^4\ifios, of nature prodnced and sustains
Stob. Floril. 117, 8) God is the : all things. All the more reason
type of every nTtue,iieya\ippav, that a universe so skillfully
itfepyeriKOSf fl>i?uiv8pBinos, if.T.X. formed and so harmoniously
Sen. Ep. 24, 49 Quae causa est
: arranged must be directed by a
Dis benefaciendi ? Natura. natura sentiens. And since, in
Errat, si quis iUasputat nocere its parts, it could not be more
DYNAMICAL VIEW OF NATURE. 161

in the assertion that God is the fiery Eeason of the Chap.


VI.
World, the Mind in Matter, the reasonable Air-Cur-
rent, penetrating all things, and assuming various
names according to the material in which He resides,
the artistically moulding Fire, containing in Himself
the germs of everything, and producing according
to an unalterable law the world and all that is
therein.'

beautiful or adapted to its pur- Kei hi' '6\ov TOV K6a'fiov' 6 Beds els
pose, it must be true of it more KOT* avTobs, Zebs juep KaT& rb C^ov
than of any human work of T^s SKtjs ovofia^6iiej'os, "Hpa Se
art, that it owes its origin to a KaTct Tdv hepa Kal ra Komh. Ka&'
forming reason. The third eKtKTTOV TTJS SAtjs fiepos, St' ^s
part aims at proving, on phy- Ksx^P^ite, KaXoiixevos. The latter
sico-theological grounds,quanta passage explained by Biog.
is
sit admirabilitas ccelestium 147, whothus continues Ai'o :

rerum atque terrestrinm. fi.ev ydp <paa'i Bt ftv t^ irdvra'


' Stob. Eel. i. 58: ^loyivits Zrjifa Se uaKovtri trap' ^ffov tov ^yv

KoL KKeavBtis Kul OtvOTriSrjs t^v C^Tl6s iffTtV fl Sict TOV ^^V K^X^pTi'
Tov K6aftov i^vxhv [Oehv \eyovtri\ Kev. (This, too, in Stob. Bel. i.
. . noo'ei5c6p(os iri/eCjUa voephv
. 48.) 'AdTjvav Se Kara t^v eis
Kol irupwSes, ovk ^x^ t^^ iiopip^v aldepa StiTOffij/ tov TjyefjLoviKov
fiera^dAKoj/ 5e els t ^oiKerai Kat avTov.'*Hpav Se Kara T^y eis aepa.
(Tuve^QfioiotSfiej/ou iraffLU . . . TA]- Kat "Hcftata'Tov/caret t^jv els t6

vwv 6 "SrwiKhs vovv k6<tplov ir^pL- TexvtKhv Trvp. Kal noffetSwya Kari
vov. lb. 64; Plut. Plac. i. 8, T^v els rb vyp6v. Kal AijfiiiTpav
17 : 01 StooikoI mep'ov (^Plwt. Karii T^y els yvv Sfiolots Se koI
KQiv^repoy) 9ehy aTcotpaivovTOi irup T&s ^\Aas npoa'Tyyopias ^x*^M^^o
TcxyiKbi' iS$ $a5i(ov ytviaei, M Ttvos 6iioi6T'iiros aireSoffav. Plut.
K6<riiou (a similar definition of C. Not. 48, 2, p. 1085 rbx Behv:

nature is given by Zeno in (Me. . . trcDjua voephv Kal vovv 4v SAp


.

Nat. De. ii, 22, 57) iiJ.TTpiiX.Ti<f>6s TroiovfTes. M. Awel. 5, 32: rif
re irdvras robs ffirepfiariKoiis \6- 5i& ovffias SiijKOVTa \6yoVj
Trts
yovs, ots civavra {PI. ixaanC)
icaff K.T.A.. PorpTiyr. in Bus. Pr. Bv.
Kaff eliiapiiiviiv ylvi-rai, Koi vvevfia XV. 16, 1 rbv Se Qebv .
: . irvp .

^kSi^koc, tov k6(Tijlov, ris


Si' '6\ov voephv elirSvTes. Orig. c. Gels,
5^ irpo<Ti\yopias furaXafi^&vov Sii vi. 71 Kara fjiev oZvTobs hub rris
:

Toil rris vKvs, Si.' ?s (teXf^Pltf M^- GToas . . . Kal & \6yos tov Oeov 6
TaA.\tf|eis. Following the same }iexpt avBpda-nuv KaX tuv i\axiifTuv
source, AtTienag. Leg. pro Christ. KaTa$alvav ohSev &\\o eiTTlv ^
c. 5, Sehl : a y^p S fi^' Sths irvp irvevpa <r(ji>fiaTtic6v. The same
TfXviKbv, K.T.K. (the same down combination of nature.and mind
to ylverai) rh Se TrveSfia avrov Bi^- in the conceptions of God is

152 THE STOICS.

Chap. As used in the Stoic system, these expressions


'

generally mean one and the same thing. It is an


unimportant difference whether the original cause is
described as an Air-Cun-ent or as Ether, or as Heat
or as Fire. It is an Air-Current, Air-Currents being,
as we have already seen, the causes of the properties

of things, giving them shape and connection. It is


also Fire, for by fire is only meant the warm air, or
the fiery fluid, which is sometimes called Ether, at
other times Fire, at other times Heat,' and which is

expressly distinguished from ordinary fire.'' More-


over the terms, Soul of the world, Eeason of the
world. Nature, Universal Law, Providence, Destiny
all mean the same thing, the one primary force pene-
trating the whole world. Even the more abstract
expressions. Law, Providence, Destiny, have with the
Stoics an essentially gross meaning, implying not
only the form according to which the world is ar-
ranged and governed, but also the essential substance
of the world, as a power above everything particular

found in the hymn of Cleanthes 137 : hiunirai fikv oZv ttvai ri irvp
(in Stot. Eol. i. 30), Zeus being tv iii atS'epa KaAeio-floi.

described as the ipxny^s <j>v<ras, ' Stob. Eel. i. 538, on the


who directs the Koivhs \6yos is authority of Zeuo ; Ckc. N. D.
Sm irivTuv 0(jit^, by means of ii. 15, 40, on that of Cleanthes.

Trvp iei^uiov. Both state that the diSerenoe


' Stoi. Eel. i. 374: Chiysip- consists in this: Ordinary (Stcx-
pus teaches clvoi ri tn iri/cDjua yoc) fire consumes things; but
KLvovv ^aurhvphs eauriicol i^ 4au- the vvp rexvtKhv, which consti-
Tou, fi TTvevfia eauT^ Kiifovv irprffrw ,tutes (piais and >iivx\ preserves
KOI owltru iryevfKi Be ^KryiTTai 5ia things. Heraclitus, too, in
rh \4ye(T0ai avrh aepa etvai utyoi- making primary fixe the basis
jievov ^vti\oyov Sk yiyveaQai of things, did not mean fiame,
eireiTo [? perhaps : aurf), or: TTupis but warmth, which may be
fj'] aWephs, fiirre Kai tis Koivhr equally well described as at-
?i.6yov Treffeic airii. Diog. vii, mospheric substance or as ifnix^.
;

DYNAMICAL VIEW OF NATURE. 153

and individual.' If Nature must be distinguished Chap.


TI.
from Destiny, and both of these notions again from
Zeus,'' the distinction can only consist herein, that
the three conceptions describe one original Being at
different stages of His manifestation and growth.
Viewed as the whole of the world it is called Zeus
viewed as the inner power in the world, Providence
or Destiny;' and to prove this identity at the close
of every period, so taught Chrysippus, Zeus goes back
into Providence.''
Upon closer examination, even the difference be-
tween the materialistic and idealistic description of
Grod vanishes. God, according to Stoic principles,
can only be invested with reality when He has a

Seneca, De Benefic. iv. 7,


' Heine, Stoic. De Fat. Doct. p.
2 God may also be called
: 25, apparently without reason,
fattim nam cum fatnm nihil
: conjectures Kal Tiji fiiy ati/iari
:

aliud sit quam series implexa rhv KSfffioy), rp Se ^vxy T^y ""prf-
causarum, ille est prima om- yoiay Srav oZv ix ir-dpuffis yevTjTai
nium causa, ex qua ceterse pen- fi6yov &^9apTuy oyra rhy Aia rSiy
dent. Nat. Qu. ii. 45, 1 Vis : 0ewy avaxapiXv ^irl ttiv 'irp6yotay,
ilium fatum vocare ? Non erra- elra 6jxov yepofjieyovs iir\ fitas TTjs
bis. Hie
ex quo suspensa
est, rov aidepos ovirlas SiaTe\e7y ap.<pQ-
sunt omnia, causa causarum. repovs. To this maxim of Chrys-
The same applies to the name ippus, reference is made by
of providence and nature. See Phih, Incorrup. M. 951, B,
p. 162, 2. where, too, irpdyoM is equiva-
^ iStob. Eel. i. 178 (Plut. lent to ^vxh TOU KdffflOV.
Plac. 28, 5) i.Hocr(iS<iyios [t^k
: ' According to Chrysippus.
elfiap^emjv^ rplTTjy airh Ai6s. A different view is taken by
vpSrrov fiev ykp eTvat rhv Aia, Sed- Posidonius. "With him Zeus
Tepov Sk T^y (pv(riy, rpWiiV Se tt]v stands for the original force,
elpiapiiiintv. Conf. do. Divin, i. ^tliris for its first, and ei/iapi^evii

55, 125, where prophecy


is de- for its second production.
duced, according to Posidonius, * Plut. 1.0. &. Bp. 9, 16:
(I) a Deo, (2) a fato, (3) a Jovis, cum resoluto mundo et
natura. Plut. C. Not. 36, 5, p. Diis in uuum confusis paullis-
1077 \76i yovv Xpvanriros, 4ol-
: per cessante natura acquieseit
Kivai Tw fiev kvQpdiirtj) rhv Aia Kal sibi cogitationibus suis tradi-
rby K6(Tiioy (instead of which tur.
154 THE STOICS.

Chap, material form. Hence, when He is called the Soul,


VI '

the Mind, or the Keason of the world, this language


does not exclude, but rather presupposes, that these
conceptions have bodies ; and such bodies the Stoics
thought to discern in that heated fluid which they at
one time call the all-penetrating Breath, at another
Ether, or primary Fire.' Each of these two deter-
minations appeared to them indispensable,^ and both
became identical by assuming, as the Stoics did, that
the infinite character of the divine Eeason depends on
the purity and lightness of the fiery material which
composes it.' Seneca is therefore only following
out the principles of his school when he calls it quite
indifferent whether God is regarded as Destiny or as
an all-pervading Breath.'' Those who charge the

Compare, besides what


' noster calor, quo hsec qn^ nota
has been already quoted, Oic. nobis sunt, retinentur et vigent.
Acad. i. 11, 39 (Zeno) statue-
: Absurdum igitur est dicere,
bat ignem esse ipsam naturam. cum homines bestiaeque hoe
Siog. vii. 156 Sokci 5e auroij
: calore teneantur et propterea
riiv iiei> <pi<riv elvai irvp Tex"*!"' moveanturacsentiant,mundum
6S^ PaSi^ov eij yiveijiv, Sirep 4itt\ esse sine sensu, qui integro et
vvevp-a TTupoeiSes Kol Tex'"'E'5ej. puro et libera eodemque acer-
Stob. Eel. i. 180 : Xpu(rnr7roj rimo et mobilissimo ardore te-
Sivaiuv TTvevfMTiKiiv tV oi<rlav neatur. Conf. Ar. Bidymus, in
T^s eifiapfievris Td^ei toS iroyrbs the passage quoted, p. 146, 4,
SioiKTiTmi\v according to
; or, p. 105, 127.
another definition eifiapfievri : < Consol. ad Helvid.
8, 3 Id :

^crrly S ToB xSanov K6yos, ^ K6yos actunl est, mihi crede, ab lllo
ruv if rif K6iT)i(f vpovolif SioiKoi/- quisquis formatio universi fuit,
/levay, k.t.a. Instead of \6yos, sive ille Deus est potens om-
he also used iX^Seia, ^iaks, nium, sive incorporalis ratio
aiVfo, avdyien, &c. ingentium operum artifex, sive
2 See p. 143. divinus spiritus per omnia
Oic. N. D. ii. 11, 30 : Atque maxima ac minima Eequali in-
etiam mundi ille fervor puiior, tentione [ = rdvoj] diffiusus, sive
perlacidior mobiliorque multo fatum et immutabiliscausaxum
ob easque causas aptior ad sen- inter se cohaerentium series,
sus commovendos quam hio Conf. p. 153, 1.
DYNAMICAL VIEW OF NATURE. 155

Stoics with inconsistency for calling God at one time Chap.


'

Eeason, at another Soul of the universe, at another


Destiny, at another Fire, Ether, or even the Universe,'
forget that they are attaching to these terms a mean-
ing entirely different from that in which they were
used by the Stoics.^
The more the two sides of the conception of Grod (J) 6od
^the material and the ideal are compared, the ^'^^^
clearer it becomes that there is no difference between
Grod and primary Matter. Both are one and the same
substance, which, when regarded as the universal
substratum, is known as undetermined matter but ;

when conceived of as acting force, is called all-per-


vading Ether, all-warming Fire, all-penetrating Air,
Nature, Soul of the world, Eeason of the world, Pro-
vidence, Destiny, Grod. Matter and power, material
and form, are not, as with Aristotle, things radically
different, though united from all eternity. Far from
it, the forming force resides in matter as such ; it is

in itself something material it is identical with


;

Ether, or Fire-element, or Breath. Hence the dif-


ference between eflBcient and material cause, between
Grod and matter, resolves itself into the difference
between Breath and other elements. This difference,
too, is no original or ultimate difference. According

' de. N. D. i. 14 Zeno calls


: reason, the soul of the world,
natural law divine, but he also and ether ; Chrysippus to rea-
calls the Ether and the all-per- son, to the soul of the world, to
vading Eeason deity. (We ruling reason, to communis
shall come back presently to natura, destiny, fire, ether, the
what he says as to the divinity universe, and etemil law.
of the stars.) Cleanthes gives " Xrische, Forsoh. i.
365.
the name of deity to the world,
156 THE STOICS.

Chap. to the Stoic teaching, every particular element has


VI.
in process of time developed out of primary fire or
God, and to Grod it will return at the end of every
period of the world.' It is therefore only a deriva-
tive and passing difference with which we are here
concerned. But taking the conception of Deity in
its full meaning, it may be described as primary

matter, as well as primary power. The sum total of


all that is real is the divine Breath, moving forth
from itself and returning to itself again." Deity
itself is primary fire, containing in itself in germ
both God and matter;^ the world in its original

gaseous condition ;* the Universal Substance changing


into particular elements, and from them returning to
itself again, which regarded in its realform as God
includes at one time everything, at another only a
part of real existence.^
C. Pa/a- From what has been said it follows that the Stoics
tlieism.
admitted no essential difference between God and
(1) God
identical the world. Their system was therefore strictly pan-
with the I
world. I
theistic. The' world is the sum of all real existence,
and all real existence is originally contained in deity,
which is at once the matter of everything and the
creative force which moulds this matter into particu-


See pp. 153, 2; 153,4. \iy6vT<t>v ff&fia Tpeirrhv hi6\ov /cal
^ Chrysippus. See p. 152, i.KKoiwT'bv Koi jjLeTafiKiiTbv Kaf
note 1. 7roT trtivTa <l>6eip6yrai/ koX fiiifov
* AHstocles. See p. 147, rhv dehv KaTaKiirSvTuv. Ihid. iv,
note 3. 14 6 rav ^tu'^kuv debs Sre ir&fia
:

' Mnesarehus, in Stob. i. 60. Tvyxavuv Sre itkv riycfioviKhv ?x"


See p. 148, 1. T^i/ iiKr]v oittrlav Urav ij iKirOpuffis
Orig. c. Cels. iii. 75, p.
'
^
3t6 Se inl ficpovs yiverat aitTTJs
497, A Xtu'Ikuv 9fhv ^BapThr
: iraf ^ SiaK(!ir/ir)(ris.
flaa-yipTuv Ka\ ^^v ohalav avrov
: ;;

PANTHEISM: GOD AND THE WORLD. 157

lar individual substances. We can, therefore, think Chap.


VI.
of nothing which is not either immediately deity or
a manifestation of deity. In point of essence, Grod
and the world are therefore the same indeed, the ;

two conceptions are declared by the Stoics to be ab-


solutely identical.' If they have nevertheless to be
distinguished, the distinction is only derivative and

partial. The same universal Being is called God


when it is regarded as a whole, World when it is re-

garded as progressive in one of the many forms

Besides the quotations al-


' oKoy Kdfffioi/ Kai rhv dvpaviv. Ar.
ready given from Chrysippus Bidym. in Eus. Pr. Ev. xv. 15,
on p. 153, 2, and Cleanthes on 1 and 3 i\ov Se T'bv K&ff^ttv
: iriiv

p. 155, 1, compare Phrsdr. Nat. rols eauTov fifpeiTi Trpoaayope{iov(rt


De. {Philodem. irtpl 6uo-c0cas), 6e6y. . . . Sih S^
/col Zevs \4yirat

Col, 5 ^ioy4vr)s
: 6 Ba^vX^vios
5' d K6tTixos. Orig. o. Cels. v. 7
iv T^ trepl TTJs 'Adtjvas Thv Koafiov o'a</)cDs 5^ Til/ i\ov h6(rfjiOV Ae-
ypd^et Tq} Alt rhv avriy virapx^tf^ yovffLV ilvcLL B^hv 'S.Tw'iKol fisv rb
tj irepicxeiv rhv Aia xaBdirep i.v- npuTov. The arguments given,
Bptairov ^vx^v. Cic. N. De. ii. p. 144, for the existence of God
17, 45 : Nothing corresponds are based on the supposition
better to the idea of God, quam that God is the same as the
ut primum himc mundum, quo world. The existence of God
nihil excellentius potest,
fieri is proved by showing the rea-
animantem esse et Deum jndi- sonableness .of the world.
cem. Ibid. 13, 34 Perfect : Aratus gives a poet's descrip-
reason Deo tribuenda, id est tion of the Stoic pantheism at
mimdo. Sen. Nat. Qu. ii. 45, 3 ;
the beginning of the Phseno-
Vis ilium vocare mundum ? mena: Zeus is the being of
Non falleris. Ipse enim
est whom streets and markets, sea
hoc quod vides totum, suis par- and land, are full, whose off-
tibus inditus et se sustinens et spring is man, and who, out of
sua. Ibid. Prolog. 13 Quid : regard for man, has appointed
est Deus? Mens universi. signs in the heaven to regulate
Quid est Deus? Quod vides the year. The same idea is
totum et quod non vides totum. contained in the well-known
Sic demum magnitude sua illi lines of Virgil, Georg. iv. 220
redditur, qua nihil majus ex- iEn. vi. 724. The round figure
cogitari potest, si solus est of the Stoic deity, Sen. Bp. 113,
omnia, opus suum et extra et 22 De M. Claud. 8, 1, has also
;

intra tenet. Diog. vii. 148 reference to the world as God.


ohaiav Se 0Eot) 7A}vuv fiev ^at rhy Conf. ao. N. D. i. 17, 46.
158 THE STOICS.

Chap. assumed in the course of its development. The dif-


VI.
ference, therefore, is tantamount to assigning a
difference of meaning to the term world, according as
it is used to express the whole of what exists, or only
the derivative part.'
(2) Oif- Still this distinction does not depend only upon

tw^Go'd ^'- ^'^y ^ looking at things, but it is founded in the


and the nature of things. Primary primary
worUonly
relative,
^
.
^/*.
nre, primary reason, constitute
force, as such,
i, I
what

is
^
primarily n /
Grod.
Things into which this primary substance has changed
itself are only divine in a derivative sense. Hence
deity, which is ultimately identical with the whole
of the world, may again be described as a part of the
world, as the leading part (to '^ys/j,ovtKbp), as the
Soul of the world, as the all-pervading fiery Breath.^

' Stoi. Eel. i. Hi : K6<rfiBv S' ing) &s tpTjtrt IloffeiS^vios . . .

etj/al ^Tjffiv 6 XpitTiirnos (riffrtifw. fftJffTr^/AO 4^ ovpavov xal yrjs ical

e| ovpavov koI yi^s Kal rSn/ iv Toii- tSiv iy TO^TOis ip^ffeoay, % (third
rois (piffeuv
' ij rh iK Beuv Kal av- meaning) aitrrrnia ix 6f&v Kal
Bpilmav aiarniia koX Ik tUv Jve/ta afSpdonoiy Ka\ Tuy eyexa roirtay
TO^rwv yeyovSrotv. \4yeTat S' yeyovitity. Ar. Didym. in Eus.
^r4pus Kdff^os 6 &ehs, Ka& tv 7j Pr. Bv. XV. 15, 1 KiSff/tos is the
:

SiaK^O'fnto'ts y'lverat koL TeXetovrai. name for rb ck jriffirjs ttjs ovaias


JMog. vii. 137 \fyovin Se xdafiov
: iroihy, and for rh xaTh, -r^y Sia-
Tpixus avTiiv T rhv dehi/ rhif ix
' ic6aii.riaiy rijy roiairriy leal Stdra^iv
TTjs andffTjs obtrlas iSiws troihvj ts exoy. In the former sense, the
S^ &(pdpapT6s iffrt KoX ayevyttTos world is eternal, and the same
STj^iovpyhs &)V TTJs SiaKoa-p/qiretas as God in the latter, created,
;

Karctxp^v^v Tij/iy nepi6Sovs h.va- and subject to change. Com-


MffKuv els eauT^i' r^v airaffav pare also the quotations from
oiitriav Kol 'jrfiKiv e| eavrov yevvStv. the mathematician Diodorus,
KaX aiir^i/ Se r^y dtaicScT^'no'tv tuv in Ach. Tat. Isag. c. 6. p. 129,
a<TTip<jOV KdiXflov sli/aL Keyovffl KOt, b.
rplrov rh truyeCTTjK^s ^| afitjyoiy. See p. 148. The two ideas
-

ol etrri xiff/ios f; (according to blend into each other. Thus


the first meaning of the word) S Seneca, Nat. Qu. Prol. 13, says
tStws Troths Tristwv HKwv ovfflas, God must be the Eeason of the
(universal substance in its de- world and must also be the
finite quality) tj (second mean- universe itself; and he con-
;

PANTHEISM: EXCEPTION OF BOETHUS. 169

The distinction, however, is only a relative one. "What Chap.


VT "

is not immediately divine is nevertheless divine de-


rivatively, as being a manifestation of primary iire

and if the soul of the world is not identical with the


body, at least it pervades every part of that body.' It
is a distinction, too, which applies only to a part of
the conditions of the world. At the end of every
period, the sum of aU derivative things reverts to the
unity of the divine Being, and the distinction be-
tween what is originally and what is derivatively
divine, in other words, the distinction between God
and the world, ceases.
Boethus alone dissented from the pantheism of (3) Goe-

the Stoics by making a real distinction between Grod ^glnu^run


and the world. Agreeing with the other Stoics in tkepan-

considering deity to be an ethereal Substance,^ he ^j^e Stoics.

would not allow that it resided, as the Soul, within


the whole world, and, consequently, he refused to call
the world a living being.^ Instead of doing this, he
placed the seat of deity in the highest of the heavenly
spheres, the sphere of the fixed stars, and made it

operate upon the world from this abode.'* The oppo-

tinnes Quid ergo interest in-


:
' Diag. 143 : BiJr/flos S4 ^riaiv
ter naturam Dei et nostram 1 ouk cTi'oi Qifov tiv K6criiov. The
Nostri melior pars animus est, words of Pliilo, Incorrupt. M.
in illo nulla pars extra animum 953, c ^^vxk Se tov k6(tp.ov kutA
est. Totus est ratio, &c. robs dvTi5o|oSj'Tas 6 Behs imply
'
The connection of the two, the same, but these words evi-
like the connection between dently are not taken from Boe-
soul and body, and the argu- thus.
ment quoted by TertuUian from * Siog. 148: BMos Se iv ifi
Zeno on p. 148, 1, is a xpaa-ts Si' irtpl ^ia-etas ohiriav 6eov t^v tuv
%Kav. See p. 135. &irAai/Si/ (r<()ar|Da)' which must be

Stot. Eel. i. 60
= : BiiTjflos tIiv understood in the same sense
aXBipa Bilv are(j}iimTO. as the corresponding statements
160 THE STOICS.

Chap. site view detracted, in his eyes, from the unchange-


VI.
able and exalted character of the divine Being. How
anxious he was to vindicate that character will also
be seen in the way in which he differed from his
fellow-Stoics in reference to the destruction of the
world.

of other Stoics the iiyeiiovtKhv of


: rup. M. 953, B, God is described
the world resides in the purest as the charioteer guiding the
part of the ether. Yet, inas- world, and irapifrrcJ/ieros the
much as the world is no living stars and elements. But this
being, nor is deity the soul of passage, beginning at koI /u^ttot'
the world, it must, according eiKiiTtos, is evidently Philo's
to the view of Boethus, act upon own expajision of what he has
it from without. This is ex- just quoted from Boethus.
pressly stated in Philo, Incor-
;

GENEMAL COURSE OF THE UKIVERSE. 161

CHAPTEK VII.

THE STUDY OF NATUKE. COITESE, CHARACTER, AND


,

GOTERNMENT OF THE UNIVERSE.

Bt virtue of a law inherent in nature, Primary chap.


Being passes over into particular objects; for, in- ^^^

volving as it does the conception of a forming and A. The


creating force, it must as necessarily develope into a
^gJ^J^f
universe, as a seed or ovum must develope into a *' *-
plant or animal.' Primary fire so taught the Stoics, (i) OHgin
following Heraclitus first goes over into vapour, "f *^
then into moisture ; one part of this moisture is pre-
cipitated in the form of earth, another remains as
water, whilst a third part evaporating constitutes
atmospheric and air, again, enkindles fire out of
air,

itself. By the mutual play of these four elements


the world is formed,' built round the earth as a

Diog. vii. 136 kot' 4px^*


' : 13, 1 : Rre will consume the
likvoZv Hoff aiirhi/ Syra [rhr 6ehv~\ world : hunc evanidum con-
rpeveiv rijv iracrav oiaiav 5i' dtpos sidere, et nihil relinqui aliud in
as Kol Sffirep in tj 701^ rb
S!<op rerum natura, igne restinoto,
(nrep/ui irepiExcToi, o8tib koI toS- quam humorem. In hoc futnri
TOP ff'KepfjiariKht' \6yov Svra rov mundi spem latere. JStob. Eel.
K6(Tfiov ToioflSe viroKtir4(r9ai h t$ i. 372 and414, 5. See pp. 161, 2
vyp$ ivepyhv ourqj iroiovvTa ri]V 164, 2.
Sktiy Trpii! riir ray iljris yiyfffiy, ^ Stob. i. 370 : Z'^i/ura Se oBras
K.T.X. Seneca, Nat. QuEest. iii. wiroi^idvtaeiu Sio()/i^8i)v
TomiTijy
M
162 THE STOICS.

Chap. centre;' heat, as it is developed out of water,^ mould-


VII.
ing the chaotic mass. By the separation of these

'
Se^trei eivat iv irepio^c/t ttiv rod Tptir6fiivov &vbi tpiifflv aii^etrOai

iiXov Siajc6(Tfnj(riv ix rris outrias. Kal ipx^o'dai SMKOiTfietv Tb '6\ov,


Srav itf TFupbs rpoTT^ ets SSap 8i* Kal TotauTrjy TfpioSov ael Kal Star
aepos yevTjTai rb juev ti u^iffTatrfloi K6a'iir](rLi' 'jroiov/ievov tov iy tjj
Kal yrjv (rvviffraffQou, 4k tov \onrov T&v H\ay oifffia t6vov (for this fa-

fie rh fihv Stofieyeiv SSup^ iK Se tov vourite expression of Cleanthes,


aTfii^ofieyou a4pa yiveffdai, i rivos see p. 127, 5 128, 2) m^ -"aieaBat
:

5^ TOV aepos irvp ^^dwreiv. Diog. rStaKO(r^oiJ)Uef3i/ to SXovJ. Sxnrep


vii. 142 ylyeirBaL Se rhv k6<!)iov
: yhp kv6s Tivos Th fiepif] irtJfTO
tirav ix trvphs ^ olffia rpair^ St* tpierai eK ffirep^Ttov 4v toIs KaBi}-
p,4pos els vypSTTira, elra rh TraX"- KOVfTL XP^^OLSf OVTOl K(^ TOV iKou
juepes avTov tTvffTh.v d.TTOT\eirB^ yij TO, jiepT], Sip Kal TO fijJo Kal t4
rh Sh ^eTTTOjLiEpes i^aepuB^ Kal ^vTk ovTa Tvyxiiyei, iv Tois KaQi)-
tovt' iirtTrXeov \enrvif9ky Trvp airo- KovTt xp6vois tp{reTai. Kal fiffjrcp

yevv'fjtrTi eJra Karit fii^iv iK T0i5-


; Tives \6 yoL fxepuy eis oirepfia
TU)V
Tuy tpurd, T Kal ^^a Kal &\\a yimj. trvviSvTes ixiyvvyTai Kal a^dts 5;o-
Chrys. in Plut. St. Eep. 41, 3, KpiyovTat yevofiej/ue tuv fiepuf,
p. 1053 Ti Se vvphs ineTafioXii
: oStus i^ ev6s Te trdfTa yiyyeirBai
iffTi TOia&rri St' &4pos els SSwp
' Kal 4k irdyraiv ets %v trvyKplveadai,
rpeirerat kolk* roirov 7^s &<ptff- (conf Heraclit. in vol. i. 467, 1),
.

Tafihlis A^p ivOvtiiarai Keirrv- ' dS^ Kal ffviitpiiivais Sie^tovtTTjs ttjs
vofieyov Se tov aepos 6 ai8i]p irepidSoi). A few further details
TrfptxeiVai KiKhtp. The same are supplied by Macrob. Sat. i.
writer observes, in the Scholia 17. The myth respecting the
on Hesiod's Theogony, v. 459, birth of Apollo and Artemis is
oTi Kadiypaip SvTuv twv '6>mv koL referred to the formation of the
ofiBpaiv KaTatpepofjtevuv voWuy sun and moon. Namque post
T^jv eKKpifftv ToiiTav Kp6vov avo- chaos, ubi primum coepit con-
fjLiia-dai. Oonf. Cleinens, Strom. fusa deformitas in rerum
V. 599, c, and
Stoi. i. 312. formas et elementa nitescere,
' Eel. i. 442, also
StoJ). terrseque adhuc humida sub-
affirms that the creation of the stantia in molli atque instabili
universe begins with earth. sede mutaret convalesoente
:

2 Stoh. 1. c. KA.ct^pflTis Se
: paullatim setheres calore atque
ovTOi irds <p'ri(Tty iK^KoyiffOevT os
'
inde seminibus in earn igneis
TOV TtavThs ffvui^eiv tI> fieffov auTov defluentibus (the connection of
TTp&TOfj eira to: ix^t^^ya airoofiey- Zeus, i.e., of Ether, with Leto,
vvfrQai St' ^\ov, tov Se Trofrbs the Earth) hasc sidera edita
i^vypavSevTos, ri ecxaTov tov esse credantur et solem maxi-
;

TTuphSf kvTiTV'K'i)travTos avTtp tov ma caloris vi in suprema rap-


fi4<Tov, TpiireffQai irtiKiv ets TOvvaV' tum lunam vero humidiore et
;

Tt'oy (the probable meaning is, velut femineo sexu naturali


that the last remains of the quodam pressam tepore infe-
original fire begin a motion in riora tenuisse, tanquam iUe
the opposite direction) effl' outm magis substantia patris con-
:

GENERAL COURSE OF THE UNIVERSE. 163

elements, a distinction between the active and the Chap.


passive powers of naturebetween the soul of the VII.

world and the body of the world becomes apparent.


The moisture into which the primary fire was first
changed represents the body, just as the heat' latent
in it represents the soul ;
^ or, taking the later four-
fold division of the elements, the two lower ones
correspond to matter, the two higher ones to acting
force.*

As the distinction between matter and force has (2) Mul of


the world:
stet, hseo matris. The state- St6\ov fj.v yap &i/ 6 K6ffixos -nvpdi-
ment that besides other things Stjs u0uy Kol i^ujf^ 4(rTtif SauTou
plants and animals had their Kol 7iyefiovtK6v. 8t Se fieTafia\&)V
origin in the intermingling of eis Th {r/pbv KoX t^v ivairoXeKpdeT-
elements {Stob. and Siog.) must aav ^vy^v rp6i:ov Tivh, eis ffwfjia
be understood in the sense of Kal ^vx^l' fJ-ere^aKev &(TTe av-
generatio sequivoca. Lactmit. l^etnivaL ^k TO^TWtf, &\\ov rty^
Inst. vii. 4, says the Stoics sffx^ \6yoy,
make men grow like sponges ' Nemes. Nat. Horn. C. 2,
out of the earth, and Sext. p. 72 : Keyouffi di ot Srwi'/coi, twv
Math. ix. 28, says the Stoics (TTOix^iccv Tct flic elt/at SpatrrtKcL
speak of the earth-born men of Ttt 56 iraOriTiKii ' SpaiTiKct p.f
prehistoric ages. aepa KOt iriJp, wadfiTtKh Se yriv Kal
There must always be some
' SSwp. Pint. Com. Not. 49, 2.
remainder of heat or fire, See above p. 127, 5. From this
as Cleanthes and Chrysippus passage a further insight is
avowed, or else there would be obtained into two points con-
no active life-power from which nected with the Stoic philo*
a new creation could emanate. sophy, which have been already
Philo, Incorrupt. M. 954, C, discussed. It can no longer
observes that, if the world appear strange that the active
were entirely consumed by fire power, or deity (and likewise
at the iKTiipinais, the fire itself the human soul) should at one
would be extinguished, and no time be called Fire, at another
new world would be possible. Air-Current, for both represent
5i6 Kai TLj/es Tuv diri ttjs trroas equally the acting force and ;

. , , e<j)a(xav, hri fier^ t^v e/cjriS- the statement that properties


puCiVj iireibav A peos K6afjiOS fieWrj are atmospheric currents as,
Si]fiioupyetff9ai, aifiTvaj/ jxiv rh irvp indeed, the whole distinction
ob (r/Sei/yi/Toi, irotr^ 5e ris abrov of subject-matter and property
fio7pa viro\inerai. follows from this view of
' Chrys. in Plut. 1. c. 41, 6 things.
M 2
;

164 THE STOICS.

Chap. its origin in time, so it will also have an end in time.'


VII.
Matter which primary Being has separated from itself
to form its body is being gradually resolved into pri-
mary Being again; so that, at the end of the present
course of things, a general conflagration of the world
will restore all things to their original form, in which
everything derivative will have ceased to exist, and
pure Deity, or primary fire, will alone remain in its

original purity.^ This resolution of the world into

' The Stoics, according to (according to Nwmenius : see


Diog. 141, where, however, Ens'. Pr. Ev. xv. 18, 1) : Zivuvt
there apparently a lacuna
is Koi KAecifdei Koi Xpvffltrvtii apeiritei
in the prove that the
text, r^v fiera^&Wety otov eis
oi/triav
world (5io(ci(fffH7iris, not K6<rfws, tTTrep/ia rh(Philo, Incorrupt.
irvp
in the absolute sense, see p. M. 956, B, expresses himself
158, 1) will come to an end, against this description) koI
partly because it has come into 7rd\tv iK TovTov Toiahrtfli &iroTe-
being, and partly by two not KeiffQai T^jy SioKSfffiTiirtv oTafrpdre'
very logical inferences ot to : pov ^v. Seneca, Consol. ad
[vulgo o5 Te T&, Coiet: oStit6] Marciam, gives a graphic de-
fiefnj (pOaprd iffrL, KaX rh ^\oif ' rcL scription of the end of the
Se fiepTj Tov K6fffiov (pOaprctf els world, which recalls the lan-
&K\it\a yoip fieTa$ilK\ei
^Baprhs guage of the Revelation. Com-
fipa d k6cthos and (1 ti iwiSeucTir pare, on the subject of iiaripatris,
forrl rijs ivl rh x^'po" ii^Ta$o\9is, Diog. vii. 142, 137 (see above
<l>6apT6v iiTrt
KaX 6 K6ff^os &pa p. 158, 1) Ar. Didym. in Eus.
;

^^avxiMtyrat yap Koi i^vSarovTai. Pr. Ev. XV. 15, 1 Plut. Com. :

Conf. AlesB. Meteora, 90. In Not. 36 (see p. 153, 2) ; Hera-


Plut. Sto. Rep. 44, 2, p. 1054, ettt. Alleg. Horn, c, 26, p. 53
Chrysippus asserts that the Cie. Acad. ii. 37, 119 N. D. ii. ;

oi(ria is immortal, but to K6a^os 46, 118 Sen. Consol. ad Polyb.


;

belongs a &airfp a.<p9aptria. i. 2 Alex. ApTvr. in Meteor. 90,


;

Plut. Sto. Eep. 39, a. In the last-named passage,


2, p.
1052 [XpiitnTTTTOs] iv t^ Trpdrep
: it is urged by the Stoics, in
5rcpl irpovoias -rhv Ma, ipijalv, support of their view, that even
ai^eadat iiexpis tivch airhv oirayra now large tracts of water are
KaTavaAiiari. iirel yctp i BdnaTos dried up or else take the place
fxev iffTi ^vx^^ x^P^^f^^s ^^^ TOW of dry land. Sirniyl. Phys. iii.
(rdpLaTos, tj S^ tov Kdfffiou ypvx^ oh b ; De Coelo ; Schol. in Arist.
Xwp'CcTai likv, atf{6Tai Se iruj/exSs 487, b, 35 and 489, a, 13;
/tfXP" *" f's a{ni]v ^avaXtiffy Justin. Apol. i. 20 ; ii. 7 ; Orig.

tV i^Atji/, oh ^tjTeov atrodviiffKeiv c. Gels. iii. 75, 497, a ; vi. 71.


jhv Kda/ioii, Stoi. Eel. i. 414 Since at the iKvipaiais every-
GENERAL COURSE OF THE UNIVERSE. IGo

fire or ether,' the Stoics thought, would take place, Chap.


'

through the same intermediate stages as its genera-


tiou from the primary fire.^ Cleanthes, following
*
his peculiar view as to the seat of the governing
force in the world, supposed that its destruction
would come from the sun.''

No sooner, however, will everything have re- (3) Cycles


in tlie
turned to its original unity,' and the course of the
Korld's

thing is resolved into deity, ^aKeiu CIS iavriy,


Pint. C. Not. 17, 3, p. 1067, * expressly asserted
It is
says ^av iKirvptetratrt rhv xdcfiov
: that everything, without ex-
oi/TOtf Kouchy fiiv oiiSt* driovv airo' ception, is liable to this des-
Keiirerat, rb 5' ^\av ipp6vijjL6t' iari tiny neither the soul nor the
;

TqvMa.vTa Kol ffot^ov. Gods are exempt. Conf. Sen.


'
Numen. in Bus. Pr. Ev. xv. Cons, ad Marc. 26, 7 Nos :

18, 1 : ap^tTKei Sh rdti irpea'^urd- quoque felloes anlmse et jetema


Tois ruv ctjri t^s atp4ffeas tkiStt/j, sortitse (the words are put in
i^aypovffOat trivra KaroL ireptdSovs the mouth of a dead man), cum
Tivas Tcis fieylffraSf els-irvp aldepu- Deo visum sit iterum istamoliri,
Ses avotKvofievuv wdfrav. Ac- labentibus cunctis et ipsas parva
cording to Philo, Incorrup. M. ruinae ingentis accessio in
954, B, Cleanthes called this antiqua elementa vertemur.
fire ipA.i|, Chrysippus avyh. Re- Chrysippus says of the Gods, in
specting &pBpa(, 0A.(if, aiyli, see Plut. Sto. Bep. 38, 5 Some of :

ibid. 953, B. The observations the Gods have come into being
on p. 151 respecting the iden- and are perishable, others are_
tity of irDp, TTxeujua, aWiip apply eternal Helios and Selene,"
:

here. and other similar deities, h'av6


^ This is, at least, the im- come into being Zeus is ;

port of the general principle eternal. In Philo, Incorrupt.


(assigned to Chrysippus by M. 950, A, Orig. c, Cels. iv. 68,
Stob. Bel. i. 314) expressed by Plut. Def. Or. 19, p. 420, Com.
Heraolitus, that, in the reso- Not. 31, 5, p. 1075, it is objected
lution of earth and water into that, at the general con-
fire, the same steps intervene, flagration, the Gods will melt
in a retrograde order, as in away, as though they were
their generation. made wax
or tin. According
of
See p. 147, 1. to PMlodem. deuv Stayuyiji,
Trepl
* Plut. Com. Not. 31, 10: Tab. i. 1, Vol. Heroul. vi. 1,
iirayaviC^fievos d K\eiv9ris rg in- even Zeuo restricted the happy
Trvpixru \4yei tV irf\'i\rnv, KaX rh. life of the Gods to certain
Xonra. (uTTpa rhv liXloi/ i^o/ioiliffai lengthy periods of time.
peg. -'] TrdpTu fttvT^ Kol liera-
:

166 THE STOICS.

Chap. world have come to an end, than the formation of a new


VII.
world will begin,' so exactly corresponding with the
previous world that every particular thing, every
particular person, and every occurrence will recur in
it,' precisely as they occurred in the world prece-

' Ariug, in Eus. Pr. Ev. xv. longer, and that therefore
19 : ^nl TOffovTo Se Trpo7^6itv & Apollo, who represents the state
Koivhs \6yos Koi Koiv^ ^itris fiei- of perfect unity was honoured
^wj/ Koi 'ir\eiaiv yevo^ejrq reKos nine months with the paean,
ava^vptivaffa Traz/ra Koi eis lauT^ whilst Dionysus, torn to pieces
avoKa^ovtra iv ry ircitrp ovffla by the Titans, the emblem of the
yivfTtti (itoccupies the room of present world of contraries, was
the whole substance) iirave\- only honoured for three with
6ovffa eU rhif TrpSyrov ^devra the dithyramb, some mistake
\6yov Koti ils avAaraffiv [? koto- seems to have crept in. Pro-
ffiv ?3 eKeivTjv r^v troiovtrav bably we ought
either to read
iviaurbv rhv fieyiffiov, Koff %v air' or to transpose
8jrep irphs rpia Ik,
aiiTTJs fjtivrii ets avr^v miXivyiyerai the passage from Bioic(i(r^7)(riy to
7} airoKaTdffTcuris (the same in ifcnvpatriv.
Pliilop. Gen. et Corr. B. ii. * The belief in changing
Schl. p. 70), TravfXeov<ra 8J SiSi cycles is a common one in the
T6.i^iv a^' o?as SiaKofffieiv ojfratJrws older Greek philosophy. In
Ijp^aTo Kara \6yop irtiKiv t^v av- particular, the Stoics found it
r^v Sie^aycoy^v irotetrat. See in Heraclitus. The belief, how-
p. 161. According to Nemes. ever, that each new world
Nat. Horn, c, 38, p. 147, conf. exactly represents the preceding
Censorin. Di. Nat. 18, 11, the one is first encountered among
iisTripainstakes place when all the Pythagoreans, and is closely
the planets have got back to the connected with the theory of
identical places which they oc- the migration of souls and a
cupied at the beginning of the periodic year. Endemus, in a
world, or, in other words, when passage which has generally
a periodic year is complete. been lost sight of in describing
The length of a periodic year Pythagorean teaching, had
was estimated by Diogenes taught (in Simpl. Phys. 173)
(^Plut. PI. i. 32, 2 ; Stul. Eel. ( Se Tts iritrreiaeie rots IlvBayo-
i. 264) at 365 periods, or 366 x pelois, us TT(i\ij/ T^ ainci aptdfup
18,000 ordinary years. Pint. Kayi: itv9o\oyi)aai rh ^a$Siov ex""
De Ei. ap. D. 9, g, E, p. 389 ifiiy KaBJi/ievois oStoi koi ri &\ha
mentions the opinion, hnp rpia wdfra S[iiola>s ejei, wal riv XP^"""
trphs tv, rovTO r^v BmKdff^Tiffijf iiKoyiv imi ^t)v airhv flvca (in
XP^^V ^pbs r^v iKiriipuaif efvai. that case the time must be the
Inasmuch as it had been pre- same as the present time). The
viously said that the duration Stoics appear to have borrowed
of Kdpos (i. e. iKiripaurts) was tne this view from the Pytha-
; :

GENERAL COURSE OF THE UNIVERSE. 167

ding. Hence the history of the world and of Deity Chap.


as, indeed, with the eternity of matter and acting
VII.

force, must necessarily be the case revolves in an


endless cycle through exactly the same stages.' Still

goreans (unless with other who would appear in the future


Orphic-Pythagorean views it world would be numerically
was known to Heraclitus), and identical (efj h.pS)uf) with the
it commended itself to them as present Socrates or not ? {Simpl.
being in harmony with their 1. c.) the answer being, that
theory of necessity. Hence they could not be numerically
they taught ^hetA riiii iniripatrtv
: identical, since this would in-
'7rd\iv Trdvra TavroL iv rtf Kitrfxtf volve uninterrupted existence,
yeveffQai /car' apLdfihv, iis Koi rhv but that they were alike with-
iSitios rhv avTby r^
TTOthy TrdKiif out a difference (dirapiiAAoKTOi).
re koX ylveffOai eKeiycp
iip6ffdev eTval Others, however, chiefly among
r^ K6<Tnif {Alex. Anal. Pr. 58, the younger Stoics, appear to
b). toiJtou 5e o^Tftjy exovTos, have held that there could be
hrt\ov, as ovZiv aStJi/arov, Koi jj/xas noticeable differences between
fier^ rh TeKevTTJaai Trd\iv ircpU^uv the two. {Oi-ig. v. 20, 592, c.)
Ttvwv elXrjfifjLeyojy xp6vov iis hu This remark appears to have
vvv ^fffiey KaTaffT-fiffetrBcu (rx^jtta given rise to the false notion
(Chrysippus, -irepl Uponlas, in \Mvppohft. Eefut. Hser. i. 21 ;
Zactant. Inst. vii. 23. Conf. Epiphan. Hser. v. p. 12, b) that
Seneca, Ep. 36, 10 Veniet : the Stoics believed in the trans-
iteram qui nos in lucem reponat migration of souls. The remark
dies). This is to apply to every made by Nemes., that the Gods
fact and to every occurrence in know the whole course of the
the new world, at the irnAi77E- present world, from having sur-
Viffia or aTroKariffTaffis (as the vived the end of the former one,
return of a former age is called) : can only apply to one highest
thus there will be another God, who, however, does not
Socrates, who will marry ano- require such empirical know-
ther Xanthippe, and be accused ledge. The other deities will
by another Anytus and Meletus. not have survived the general
Hence M. Awel. vii. 19, xi. 1, conflagration.
deduces his adage, that nothing ' Ar. Didym. 1. c. continues
new happens under the sun. 1WV ToiotSrcoi/ "mpiShav ^| ai'Siou
Simpl. Phys. 207, b; PMlop. yivofjUvwv hKarairaiiiTTus. oire
Gen. et Corr. B. ii. Schl. p. 70 yiip ioxh^ ahlav Kol [del.]
rrjs
Tatian. c. Grseo. c, 3, 245, d jraiTiv ot6v T6 ytv4(r$ai, otfre rod

Clemens, Strom, v. 549, D ; SiotKovvTos airrd. oiiciav re yhp


Orig. c, Cels. iv. 68 ; v. 20 and Tois ytvo/i4j/ots ^tpeffrdvcu SeiTeipv-
23; Nemen. 1. o. Plut. Def. ; Kviav B^vaSex^'^Bat ras fifraPoKks
Or. 29, p. 425. Amongst other irdffas Koi rh SrnxiovpyTJffov e|
things, the Stoics raised the oJt^s, K.r.\. Conf. Phihp.:
question. Whether the Socrates airop^iTeie S" &v tis, lis <fni(nii

1G8 THE STOICS.

Chap. there were not wanting, even in comparatively early


vir.
times, members of the who entertained Stoic School
doubts on this teaching and among the most dis- ;

tinguished of the later Stoics some gave it up alto-


gether.' Besides the periodical destruction by
. fire.

'AXe'^avSpos, Trpbs ^Api(rror4\'r]. ci much empty space outside the


y^p 7] S\fj Tj auT^ cti SLafi4vif world as was necessary for the
^(TTi Si rtai T^ iruiririKhi/ tdriov ri world to be dissolved in at the
ayrb ael, airlav ovxl
Sib. troiav ixTtipaiTis. The diilerence be-
KOTCt TcepioSdv TLva tT\slovos xp^vov tween view and the older
his
tt TTJS avTTiS ^\1JS TCL aiiTot irii\iv Stoical view which Bake (Po-
tear* aptBfjLbv utJ ray avr&v %ffrat j
sidon. Rel. 58). deduces from
OTTip rii/es {/)affi t^v iraXiy^
icoTct Stub. i. 432, is purelyimaginary.
yeyeffiav Kal rhp fieyav ivtavrhv Antipater, according to Dio-
ffv^^aiveiVf iv ^ -jrdvTav Tuv ainuy genes, also believed in a future
airoKOTtJiTTaffis yivtrai. See M. conflagration. Little import-
Aurel. V. 32. ance can be attached to the
' According to Philo (In- statement in (ac. N. D. ii. 46,
corrup. M. 947, C), besides 118, respecting Pansetius, addu-
Posidonius and Pansetius, his bitare dicebant ; whereas the
instructor {Diog.
vii. 142 Stob. ; words of Stob. are irieaianipav
:

Bel. 414), Boethus asserted,


i. vofii^ei riiv il'SKJTrjTO toS KSfffiOu
;

in opposition to the ordinary and those of Diog. &<f>8apTov-.

Stoic teaching, the eternity of airetp'livaTO rhv k6(T^ov.


the world. Philo adds that Boethus emphatically denied
this was
also the view of Dio- the destruction of the world,
genes of Seleucia, in his later his chief reasons (in Philo, 1. c.
years. Moreover, Zeno of 952, 0) being the following :

Tarsus, on the authority of (1) If the world were de-


Numenins (in Buseh. Preep. Ev. stroyed, it would be a de-
XV. 19, 2), considered that the struction without a cause, for
destruction of the world by fire there is no cause, either within
could not be proved (i/>a(rh' or without, which could pro-
T^s iKnvpc&treus rav
^TTtffx'^'iv Trepl duce such an efiect. (2) Of
3\ai</). But these statements the three modes of destruction,
are elsewhere contradicted. those Kari Siaipeaiv, Karh ivaSpe-
Diogenes mentions Posidonius ttokJttjtos (as
<Tiv rrts ^irexoiffTii

as one who held the destruction in the crushing of a statue),


of the world by fire. The kbtA aiyxuffiv (as in chemical
testimony of Diogenes is con- resolution), not one can apply
firmed by Phit. PI. Phil. ii. 9, 3 to the world. (3) If the world
{Stob. Bel. i. 380; Eus. Pr. ceased to exist, the action of
Ev. XV. 40. See Achill. Tatian, God on the world, in fact. His
Isag. 131, c), who says that activity would altogether cease.
Posidonius only allowed so (4) If everything were con-
;:

GENERAL COURSE OF THE UNIVERSE. 169

periodical destructions by floods ' were also assumed; Chap.


VII.
there being, however, a difference of opinion as to
whether the whole universe, or only the earth and its

inhabitants, were subject to these floods.^

sumed by fire, the fire must go flood is to purge away the sins
out for want of fuel. With of mankind, ut de integro totse
that, the possibility of a new rudes innoxiaeque generentur
world is at an end. [res humante] neo supersit in
The resolution of the world deteriora praeceptor (29, 5)
into indefinite vacuum, attri- peraoto judicio generis humani
buted by Phct. Plao. ii. 9, 2, to exstructisque pariter feris . . .

the Stoics in general, is no antiquus ordo revocabitur.


doubt the same as the con- Omne ex integro animal gene-
densation and expansion of rabitur dabiturque terris, homo
matter. Hitter, iii. 599 and inscius scelerum but this state:

703, supposes it to be a mis- of innocence will not last long.


apprehension of the real Stoic Seneca (29, 1) appeals to Bero-
teaching.' How Hegel, Gesch. sus, according to whom the
d. Phil. ii. 391, and SchUier- destruction of the world by fire
macher, Gesch. d. Philos. p. 129, will take place when all the
in view of the passages quoted, planets are in the sign of the
can absolutely deny that the Crab, destruction by water
its
Stoics held a periodic destruc- when they are in the sign of
tion of the world, is hard to the Capricorn. Since these
comprehend. signs correspond with the
' The fiood and its causes summer and winter turns of
are fully discussed by Sen. Nat. the sun, the language of Sene-
Qu. iii. 27-30. Eain, inroads ca agrees with that of Censonn.
of the sea, earthquakes, are all Di.Nat. 18, 11, evidently quots d
supposed to contribute. The from Varro, conf. John, p. viii.
chief thing, however, is, that Cujus anni hiems summa est
such a, destruction has been cataclysmus sestas autem
. . .

ordained. in the course of the eopyrasis. Conf. HeracUt. AUeg.


world. It comes cum fatahs Hom. c, 25, p. 53 When one ;

dies venerit, cum adfuerit ilia element gains the supremacy


necessitas temporum (27, 1), over the others, the course of
cum Deo visum, ordiri meliora, the world will come to an end,
Vetera finiri (28, 7); it has by iKiripaKTis, if the element is
been fore-ordained from the fire ei S* &6pow SBwp iKpayelri,
;

beginning (29, 2; 30, 1), and KaraKKvtrii^ rht/ k6<t^ov aTToKeiff'


is due, not only to the pressure 90.1.

of the existing waters, but also ' For the former view, the

to their increase, and to a language of Heraclitus and


changing of earth into water Censorinus tells, for the latter
(29, i). The object of this that of Seneca.
:

170 rjm STOICS.

Chap. One point established by the generation and de-


^^'
struction of the world the uncertainty of all par-
B. Govern- ticular things, and the unconditional dependence of
wm-ld. everything on a universal law and the course of the
iVjNatwre
of Destiny,
uniygrse is throughout
one in the Stoic
a leading
(a) Bes- enquiries into nature. All things in nature come

PmX' ^^^*^^y virtue of a natural and unchangeable con-


dence. nectiou of cause and effect, as the nature of the
universe and the general law require. This abso-
lute necessity, regulating all Being and Becoming,
is expressed in the conception of Fate or Destiny
(ij siiMipiisvr))^ Viewed from the point of view of
natural science, Destiny is only another name for

primary Being, for the all-pervading, all-producing


Breath, for the artistic fire which is the Soul of the
world.2 But again the activity of this Being being
always rational and according to law. Destiny may
also be described as the Eeason of the World, as
universal Law, as the rational form of the world's

1 JHog. vii. 149 : naff etixapiii- se gignat. Sen. Nat. Qu. ii. 36 :

vi)v ? </)oiri -rh irivTO, ytvea'Bai Quid enim fatum ?


intelligis
X/)rfirr7ros, k.t.K. fan 8' iup- existimo neoessitatem renim
jueV?) aWia Tav fivTwv eipojihri f) omnium actionumque, quam
K6yos Kaff iiv i (tiiff/ios Stf^dyerai. nulla rumpat. De Prov.
vis
A. Gell. vi. 2, 3 : (Chrysippus) 5, 8 : Irrevocabilis hrauana pa-
in libro irepl irfovolas quarto riter ac divina cursus vehit.
flliapii.ivi\v esse ^vffixiivdicit Hie ipse omnium conditor et
Tiva aivTa^iv tuiv '6\av ^j aXSiov rector scripsit quidem fata, sed
TMi' iripav roTs Irepoij ettoko- sequitur. Semper paret, semper
\oudoivTO)V Kal /icTct iroKii fihv odv jussit.
ItTTapafiirov oS(ri)s Trjs Toiaims ' p. 152 and Stoi.
Conf.
avixirKoKTis. Divin. i. 55,
Cio. Bol. 180 (P/*. Plao. i. 28),
i.

125 (according to Posidonius) Xpiamiros Sivafuv irvevinarm^v


Fatum, or diMpiiitn], was called tJjv ovaiav t^s ei/mpfifi/ris TtJJei
ordinem seriemque oausarum, toG vavThs Sioikjjtik^i'.
cum causa causae nexa rem ex
GOVERNMENT OF THE WORLD. 171

course.' When regarded as the groundwork of na- Chap.


vn.
tural formations, this primary Being or general Law
is called Nature ; but when it appears as the cause of
the orderly arrangement and development of the world,
it is known as Providence ;
^ or in popular language it
is called Zeus, or the will of Zeus ; and in this sense it
is said that nothing happens without the will of Zeus.*

Hence Chrysippus' defini- cJvai t5 4v(Triiff6fjievoy rf} otKovofiiif

tion (Plut. and Stot.) fluapiiivn : fi'i]Te Tuv iiepaif ixri^ii/ ex^iv 'd-Trtos

iffrXv 6 rov K6fffi.ov K6yos ^ \6'yos Kiniflijo-eToi tl ffx^"'" SX\ms [^]


(^Plut. vAjios^ ruv 4v r^ KSiTfAtp Kara r^if Koiir^v (pitriv. Cleanthes,
vpovoltf SioiKovfi4fo)y ' ^ \6yos wafl' Hymn, (in Stoh. Eel. i. 30) v.

tv rh fihv yeyovora yiyovs, Tci hi 12, 18 ; M. Aurel. ii. 3. See p.


ytyvS/ieva yiyv^rat, rh Se yevt^ffi- 161, 1.
Instead 'of X(J7os,
fievayevfiaerat. It has been already de-
''

Chrysippus also used a\7)6fia, monstrated that all these ideas


alrla, (^iais, aydyKv. TTieodoret. pass into one another.
Cur. Gr. Afi. vi. 14, p. 87: Phit. Com. Not. 34, 5,
Chrysippus assigns the same p. 1076 et Si, Sis : <j)ri(n Xpiaiinros,
meaning to eitiapiieyov and KaxTj- ou5 Tov\iixio'T6y ian tuv fiepuv
vayxaaiiinv, explaining et/jLop- txftv i.KKfas aW' fiKara tV ^*is
fi4v7j to be Klvrjffis aibios avvex^s $ov\Ti(riv, K.r.\. Conf. Sto. Eep.
Kol TeTayiiiim ; Zeno defines it 34, 2 : o^TQ) Si rrjs tuv SAwi*
(as Stob. i. 178, also says) as oiKOvoiiias Trpoayovfrris, avayKoiov
dvvafiii Kij'rjTiK^ ttjs ii\7is also ;
Kara TaiTrjy, &s &y iroT* %xvi^V,
as tl>6ffis or irpivoia ; his suc- ex^tv Tiixcis, e^TC trapa fftviriv r^v
cessors as \6yos t&v iv rif Koa-ficp iSiav votTovfTeSy elfre TrfirTjpwfievot,
vpovoit^ hLoiKovfi4vaiPj or as etpfibs elre ypafifiaTiKoX yeyov6res %
all lav. (The same in Plut. fi,ovtnKo\ . . . Karh, rovrov Si rhv
Plac. i. 28, 4. Nemes. Nat. Horn, \6yov Tck jrapavX'fuTia ipovfiev Kal
c. 36, p. 143.) Even rixv, he irepl T^s aperris T}fi.53v fcol irtpl rris

continues, is explained as a KOKlas Ka\ rh i3\ov Twv t^xv&v Kal


deity (or as Simpl. Phys. 74, b, Twv OTe^cviwr, s %<p7)v . . . ov6iv
has it as a detov koI haiiJ.6viov) ;
yhp iffTtv i.\Kois T&v Kafk fiepos
but this supposes it to be yeceffflol, oiiSi rob\dxi(rTOVy &\V ^
essentially identical with ilinap- Kara ttj*' Kotyijv <l>iffiv Koi Karh
fievTl. Chrysippus in Piict. Sto. Tbc iieelpiis \6yov. Hid. 47, 4
Eep. 34, 8, p. 1050: rrjs yap and 8. Cleamtli. Hymn. v. 15 :

KoiPTJS (piffstas ls irtfi'Ta 5la- ohSi Ti yiyvitai ifr/ov iiti xfloi/l

TeivotSffTis Se^irei vav rh dTrwffovv aov Slxa, Soufiov,

yipAfievov ipT^ 3A^ koI twv [xopiatv o^e Kar* aidepiov 6e7ov tiSKov oijT*
drtiiow Kar' iKelvvv yevf<r6ai Ka\ 4vl ir6vTCi>f

Thv ixeiviis \6yov kotA t! 4Ji)s irAiii' iirdffa ^i{ou(n kokoI aiperf/itf-
ffiv avolais.
; :

172 THE STOICS.

Chap. In action as the creative force in nature, this uni-


"

versal Keason also bears the name of Generative


(J) See- Eeason (X670S aTrsp/iariKOs). It bears this name
generative more immediately in relation to the universe, not
reason.
^^^ ^^ being the generating power by v?hich aU
things are produced from primary fire as from seed
according to an inner law, but because in the pre-
sent condition of things all form and shape, all life

and reason, grow out of it, in short, because pri-


mary fire and reason contain in themselves the germ
of all things.' In the same sense, generative powers
in the plural, or \070t airspfiaTiKol, are spoken of
as belonging to Deity and Nature ; and in treating
of man, X0704 o-irspfj-aTiKol denote the generative
powers as a part of the soul, and must be thought of
as bearing the same relation to the individual soul
as the generative powers of Nature do to the soul
of natiue.'' By the term Generative Eeason, there-
fore, must be understood the creative and forming
forces in nature, which have collectively produced
the universe, and particular exercises of which pro-

' See the quotations on Phtt. Atlwnag. ; M. Aurel. ix. 1


p. 161, 1 161, 2 164, 2 144,
; ; ; SpuTicrei/ [i, (fiats'] eVl r^ySe t))*
1 ; 148 145, 2, from Diog. vii.
; Sia^(r;iir)<Tii/ cruWa^oi'O'a rii/as
136 ; Stoi. Bol. i. 372 and 414 ;
}^6yBus tuv Iffoiiivav koI Suvdftfiy
do. N. D. ii. 10, 28 ; 22, 58 yoi/i^ous aixcpiaaaa, k.t.K. Ibid.
Sext.Math. ix. 101 : M. Aurel. vi. 24 Alexander and his groom
:

iv. 14 : ivtKf>avt(T0iitrii T( yevvi]- iK-titpdrnrav th robs ai/Tohs rov


(ravTt, /xa\Aoi/ 5^ avaKfjipOiitrji els KSafiou inrepfiaTiKoi/s K6yovs.
Tbv \6yov ai/Tou rhv o-trepfxaTtKhv Diog. vii. 148 : ^(Tti Se tpitris
Karck iiera^oKfiv. IHd. 21 : ot e^is 4^ auTijs Kiuovfieyrj xar^ ffirep-
i/zuxal . . . cty rhp twv (i\wv fiariKohs Kdyovs, K.r.K. Ibid,
ffnepiJMTiKhv Kiyov hfO;Ka^^av6- 157 : jLt^piJ 5^ ^v^s Keyovtrtv
/levai. oKTti), ras irevre rohs
altrd^n fis Kai
'^
See on p. 151, 1, the de- iv iiixiv trvepfiaTiicovs \6yovs koL rh
finition of deity from Stob. (pavriTiKhv koX rh hoyuTTMiv.
GOVERNMENT OF THE WORLD. 173

duce individual things. These forces, agreeably with Chap.


the ordinary Stoic speculations, are spoken of as the '

original material, or material germ of things. On


the other hand, they also constitute the form of
things the law which determines their shape and
qualities, the \6yos only we must beware of trying
to think of form apart from matter. Just as the
igneous or etherial material of primary Being is in
itself the same as the forming and cheating element
in things, the Eeason of the world or the Soul of
nature ; so in the seeds of individual things, the
atmospheric substance, in which the Stoics thought
the generative power (air^pfjui) alone resides,' is in
itself germ out of which the corresponding thing
the
is produced by virtue of an inherent law.^ The in-
ward form is the only permanent element in things
amid the perpetual change of materials.' It consti-
tutes the identity of the universe ; and whereas
matter is constantly changing from one form to
another,* the universal law of the process alone con-
tinues unchangeably the same.
All parts of the Stoic system lead so unmis- (2) Argu-

takeably to the conclusion, not only that the world favowr of


as a whole is governed by Providence, but that every -P-

'
As the primary lire or Qusest. Conviv. ii. 3, 3 and 4, it
ether is called the seed of the is defined as y&ms eVSe^ij yfvi-
world (p. 161, 1), so, according o-euj.

to Chrysippus (in Biog. 159), See p. 101, 2.


the (Tirepfui in the seed of plants *This is particularly mani-
and animals is a irMu/ta kot' fast, not only in the history of
oinriatf. the world, but also in the
' a-irepimT mhs \6yos is also doctrine of the constant change
used to express the seed or the of the elements,
egg itself. Thus, in Mut.
;

174 THE STOICS.

Chap, part of it is subject to the same unchangeable laws,


'

that no definite arguments would appear necessary


to establish this point. Nevertheless, the Stoics lost
no opportunity of meeting objections to their views
(a) Argvr jn tij^ fullest manner.' In the true spirit of a Stoic,
ment from ^, . . , , . .
thegeneral Ohrysippus appealed to the general conviction of
cotime-
mankind, as expressed
' ^ in the names used to denote
twns of
manUnd. fate and destiny,^ and to the language of poetry.'
Nor was it diflBcult to show* that a divine govern-
(i) Argti- ment of the world followed of necessity from the
Stoic conception of the perfection of God. Besides,
llTp^-"^
faction of in proving the existence of a Grod by the argument
drawn from the adaptation of means to ends, a pro-
(c) Argti- vidential government of the world was at the same

Tke^tJwmj ^^ proved.* Chrysippus also thought to defend his


ofneaes- theory of necessity in the same strictly logical man-
ner. For must not every judgment be either true
or false ? ^ And does not this apply to judgments
which refer to future events, as well as to others ?
Judgments, however, referring to the future can only
' Seine, Stoicorum de Fato also Ps. Arist. De Miindo, c. 7.
Doctrina (Naumb. 1859), p. 29. The argument for Providence,
' Compare what the Peri- drawn from the consensus gen-
patetio Diogenianus (in Hus. tium in Sen. Benef. It. 4, fol-
Pr. Bv. vi. 8, 7) and Stob. lows another tack.
(Bol. i. 180) observe on the ' Homeric passages, which

derivations of et/iap/ievri, jrewpiD- he was in the habit of quoting


jueVr), Xpe&y {Heine, p. 32, 1, in Eus. 1. c. 8, 1.
suggests on the strength of * See do. N. D. ii. 30, 76.
TAeofZwci, Cur. Gr. Affect, vi. 11, = The two are generally
p. 87, 4, who transcribes the taken together. Compare the
quotation from Eusebius rhv quotations on p. 145, 4.
Xpivov Kara rb xp^up. We ought = See p. 83, 2 110, 3 Aris-
; ;

rather to read, according to totle and the Peripatetics


Tlieod. Gaisf. rh xp^^" ""t^ rh thought differently. See Simpl.
XP^os), ^olpai, KKuBii : and the Cat. 103, (3.

quotations p. 170. 1 ; 171, 1


; :

GOVERNMENT OF THE WORLD. 175

be true when what they affirm must come to pass of Chap.


'

necessity ; they can only be false when what they


affirm is impossible ; and, accordingly, everything
that takes place must follow of necessity from the
causes which produce it.'

The same process of reasoning, transferred only (a) Argu-


"j-en.tfrom
from the outer world to the inner world of mind,
fore-
underUes the argument from the foreknowledge of knon-ledge
^''^'
God.'' If in the former case it was handed down that "'

whatever is true, before it comes to pass, is neces-


sary, so in this case it is said to be necessary, if it

can be truly known before it comes to pass.

To this argument may be added a further one (e) Argu-


towhich the Stoics attached great importance-^the '^f'^tfrom
'
the easu-
argument from the existence of divination.' If it is tence of

impossible to know beforehand with certainty what ^*^'^'


is accidental, it is also impossible to predict it.

But the real kernel of the Stoic fatalism is ex- (3) T7ie

pressed in the maxim, that nothing can take place ^*'* ?/"

without a sufficient cause, nor, under given circum- dence de-


*''*"*
stances, can happen differently from what has hap-
pened.^ This were as impossible, according to the (a) Provi-
dence as
**2'-
Oic. De Fato, 10, 20. 3, 1) : Chrysippus proves, by
' Alex. l)e Fato, p. 92, the existence of divination,
Orel. : rb Se Xeyeij' eli\oyoi> etyai that all things happen Kaff et-
roiis fltoJis ra eiro/ucco irpoeiSeVoi ixapixiin)v for divination would

. . . Tovro Xayt^avovTas koto-


KoX be impossible, unless things
(T/ceuiifeiv irupaaSai Si' airov rh were foreordained. Alem. De
Tidyra 4^ &vdyKris re yivea-Qcu Kal Fato, c. 21, p. 96: 01 S^ vfiifovvres
Ka.9' tt/iapiieyril' oStc a\Ji6is oire tV fUiVTMriv /cal kotA rhy avrav
eij\oyoy. \6yov ii6vov ffdj^effOat Keyovres
' Oic. N. D. ii. 65, 162 ; De ainiiy koX toiIti? irlarei toC iravTO
Fato, 3, 5 (unfortunately the naB' (luapiiiv-nv yfwo-floi xpi^li^yot,
previous exposition is wanting) k.t.X.

JMogeniaii (in Mis. Pr. Ev. iv. Plut. De Fato, 11, p. 374
'

176 THE STOICS.

Chap. Stoics, as for something to come out of nothing ;

VII.
were it possible, the unity of the world would be
at an end, consisting, as it does, in the chain-like
dependence of cause upon cause, and in the abso-
lute necessity of every thing and of every change.*
The Stoic doctrine of necessity was the direct con-
sequence of the Stoic pantheism. The divine power
which rules the world could not be the absiolute uni-
ting cause of all things, if there existed anything in
any sense independent of it, and unless one unchang-
ing causal connection governed every thing.
(J) Prom- (Hence divine Providence does not extend to in-
denee di-
dividual things taken by themselves, but only in
rected im-
their relation to the whole. Everything being in
to the uni-
verse, in-
every respect determined by this relation, and being
directly to consequently subject to the general order of the
duals. Kuril 8e rhy ii/amlov [^K6yoy] nd\i- inrh tpitreas SiotKoifievov ^utiktjs
crra fifv kolI TCpurov ehai S6^eie rb Te KoX JwyiKTi^ Kol voepas ex^tv
fiTiSiv avaiTius yiyeffdat, aW^L t)\v rwv tji/Tav BiolKritnv
otBiov
/caret irpoTjyov^4yas alrlas ' SeiS- Karct etpu6v Tiva KaX rd^iv Trpo'iov-
Tpoy 8e rb ^iffei SiotKeiffdcu tSvSc aav so that everything is con-
;

rhv KiSfffioc, aiimvom (tol (Tv/iirBfl? nected as cause and effect, i.Wa
aiirhv avrt^ iiyra. Then come iravri re t(|j ytvofieytfi erep6y ri
the considerations confirmatory iiraKoKovdeiv, fiprijfievov i^ avrov
of that view divination, the oir' aviyKTis Sis airlov, khI irav rh
wise man's acquiescence in the ytv6fievov exetv n irph avrov, ^ its
course of the world, the maxim airltp ffvyiiprijTai' firiSev yhp avat-
that every judgment is either riots ii4\re elyai /i-fire yiveadat rue
true or false. JVemeg. Nat. Horn. 4p T^J K6(rfji.(jt Sict rh firiS^v eJvai 4v
C. 35, p. 139 el yhp tuv avruv
: avr^ aTro\e\ufjLevtjy re Kol Kex^pi-
alrluv irepieffTTiKSTUVf &s fpaffiv cfievov rap TrpoyeyoySrtov andpruv

avTol, iraffa avdyKTj ra ai/ra ylve- StatnraffOat yap Kal SiatpeiffBai Kal
irBtti. /iilKeri rbv Kiiir/xoi' eva fueyeiv ael,
' Alea;. Tie Fato, u.22, p. 72: Kara /iiav rd^iv re Kal olxoyoiilav
ifjiiu6v T6 fivai tpcuTi Kol 6fiol(as StoiKo{ifievoy, ei iiyairi6s ris elud-
aSvvaToy rh d.vaiTiws Ttp yiveffBal yoiro Klyrjiris. See (Mo. Divin. i.
Tt 4k fir] ivTOs. 65, 125 ; De Fato, i,7;M. Aurel.
' Alex. 1. 0. p. 70 : ipturl 5^ rhv X. 5.
K&ffyiQv rivSe '4va tvra . . . K(ii
.

GOVERNMENT OF THE WORLD. 177

world, it follows that we may say that Grod cares not Chap.
vn.
only for the universe, but for all individuals therein.*
The converse of this may also be asserted with equal
justice, viz. that God's care is directed to the whole,
and not to individuals, and that it extends to things
great, but not to things small.^ Directly it always
extends to the whole, only indirectly to individuals
throughout the whole, in so far as they are contained
therein, and their condition is determined by its

condition.^ The Stoic notion of Providence is there-


fore entirely based on a view of the universe as a
whole ; individual things and persons can only come
into consideration as dependent parts of this whole.
The Stoics were thus involved in a difficulty (c) mffi-

which besets every theory of necessity the diflS- cutties


connected
culty of doing justice to the claims of morality, and niAth the
themij of
of vindicating the existence of moral responsibility.
necesidty
' In Cic. N. D.the ii. 65, 164, in our hemisphere, and for the
Stoic says Nee vero universo
: men in each city. The argu-
generi hominum solum, sed ment may be superfluous, but it
etiam singulis a Diis immorta- serves to show that the care of
libus consuli et provideri solet. individuals was the result of
Sen. Nat. Qu. ii. 46 Sin- : God's care of the whole world.
gulis non adest [Jupiter], et M. Ati^el. vi. 44 ci niv oiv i0ov-
:

tamen Tim et causam et KdffavTo irepi ifiov Kail r&v 4^^ol


manum omnibus dedit. do. ffv/ji^rjvai b(l>Gi\6vTuv oi fleol, Ka-
N. D. 66, 167 Magna Dii cu-
: \oJs e$ou\eiitravTO . . . u Si fi^
rant, parva negligunt. Itid. iii. ejSouAe^ffarro Kar' iSlav irepl ^juoi),

35, 86 At tamen minora Dii


: vepi ye tuv koiv&v irdvrus 4Pov-
negligunt ... ne in regnis KtiaavTo, oTs kot' iTaKoKoiBria-ui
quidem reges omnia minima Kol ravra aviifiaivovra hairi^eaBai
curant. Sic enim dioitis. Koi aripyeiv o</>eI\u. Similarly,
' Cicero uses the following ix. 28. It will be seen that the
argument to show that the pro- Stoics consider that the exis-
vidential care of God extends tence of divination, which
to individuals If the Gods
: served as a proof of special
care for all men, they must care providence, was caused by the
for those in our hemisphere, connection of nature.
and, consequently, for the cities
N
178 THE STOICS.

Chap, This diflSculty 'became for them all the more pressing-
VII.
the higher those claims were advanced, and the more
(a) State-
severely they judged the great majority of their fel-
ment of
several low-men.' To overcome it, Chrysippus appears to
difficul-
ties.
have made most energetic efforts.^ The existence
of chance he could not allow, it being his aim to
establish that what seems to be accidental has always
some hidden Nor would he allow that every-
cause.'
thing is necessary, since that can only be called ne-
cessary which depends on no external conditions,
and is therefore always true ;* in other words, what

is and unchangeable, not that which comes


eternal
to pass in time, however inevitable it may be.* And,
by a similar process of reasoning, he still tried to
rescue the idea of the Possible, little as that idea
accords with the Stoic system.

' As AlesB. c. 28, p. 88, fitly themselves they can take place,
observes. and 5ii toSto ipcurl /aiSh ri yev6-
" The great majority of the fieva Kaff ei/iapfi4vTjp, Kodrot &napa-
Stoic answers to itoKKi, iirti\iia,ra Piras yiv6iifva, i^ kviyirns ylvf-
(puffMd TC KaX ^SiKct Kol Sia\eKTih, irBai, 8ti ^(Ttiv o4toTs Svvarhv
which (according to Plut. De ytviaiai Kal t!i avjiKiliievov. (Me.
Fato, c. 3) were called forth by Top. 16, 69 Ex hoc genere
:

the theory of destiny, in all causarum ex seternitate penden-


probability belong to him. tium f atum a Stoicis nectitvir.
' See p. 171, 3, Chrysippus, Alex. De Fato, o. 10, p. 32 j
'

in Plut. Sto. Eep. 23, 2, p. 1045. Cic. De Fato, 17, 89; 18, 41,
He assigned as a general rea- and above, p. 115, 2. Hence
son rb yctp Itvairiov 8\ui i.vi- Pbit. Plac. (similarly .Nemeg.
TTopKTOv ejvai Hal rh aiirSfiaTOV. Nat. Horn. c. 39, p. 149) : & n^r
Hence the Stoic definition of yap eTvai war' iiviyicriv, & Sh Kofl'

rvxT} is atT^a 6.irpov6riTos Kal fi8;- & S^ xarct itpoaiptaiv,


eluapiiivriv,
\os hivBpbyirivtf \o-yifffi^ in Plut. & 8e Karh, "rixv, & Sk koto rh
De Fato, c. 7, p. 672 Plac. i.
; auTo/iaTbf, which is evidently
29, 3 {Stab. Eel. i. 218) Aleoj.
; more explicit than the lan-
De Falo, p. 24; i^mpl. Phys. guage used by Stob. Eel. 1. 176,
74, 6. Bee p. 171, 1. and the statement of Theo-,
' Alex. 1. c. The Stoics as- doret on p. 171, 1.
sert that things are possible ' See p. 116, 2. Opponents
wLich do not take place, if in such as Plut. Sto. Kep. c. 40,
; .

GOVERNMENT OF TBE WORLD. l~d

In reference to human actions, the Stoics could Chap.


^^^"
not allow the freedom of the will, in the proper
sense of the term ;
' but they were of opinion that (^) j^<-<lI

this did not prejudice the character of the will as a uiUy mn-
deciding-power. For was not one and the same ^'^"*^'f-
all-determining power everywhere active, working
in each particular being according to the law of its
nature, in one way in organic beings, in another in
inorganic beings, differently again in animals and
plants, in rational and irrational creatures?^ And
albeit every action may be brought about by the \

co-operation of causes depending on the nature ot \

things and the character of the agent, is it not still

free, the resultant of our own impulses and decision ?^ |

Involuntary it would only be were it produced by


external causes alone, without any co-operation, on
the part of our wills, with external causes,* Moral

and Alex., pointed out how il- fievov i-jrl toIs oiJtws iyepyovffiv
lusoiry thisattempt was. Ac- ehat. NeToes. appeals to Chrys-
cording to the latter, he fell ippus, and algo to Philopator, a
back on the simple result, Stoic of the second century,
maintaining that, in the case of A.D. Of bim he remarks, that
things happening Kofl' etimpnevny, he has consistently attributed t4
there is nothing to prevent eif' riiuv to lifeless objects.
the opposite from coming about, * De Fato, 18, 41 In
die. :

so far as the causes which pre- order to avoid necessitas, or to


vent this from happening are uphold fate, Chrysippus distin-
unkuown to us. guishes causae prinoipales et
' See above, p. 171, 3. perfecfeefromcaussBadjuvantes,
''
Chrysipp. in Gell. N. A. his meaning being that every-
vii. 2, 6; AUic. De Fato, o. 36, thing happens according to fate,
p. 112. not causis perfectis et principa-
' Gell.1. c. Alex. c. 13
; libus, sed causis adjuvantibus.
Nemei. Nat. Horn. c. 35, p. 138, Conf. Cic. Top. 16, 59. Although
140. Alex. c. 33 (on which see these causes may not be in
Seine, p. 43), gives a long ar- our power, still it is our
gument, concluding with the will which assents to the im-
words : irSi' rb Kofl' iffi'iiv yivi- pressions received. CEuomaus
H 2
180 THE STOICS.

Chap, responsibility, according to the Stoics, depends only


vn,
on freedom of the will. What emanates from my
will is my action, no matter whether it be possible
for me to act differently or not.' Praise and blame,
rewards and punishment, only express the judgment
of society relative to the character of certain persons
or actions.^ Whether they could have been different,

or not, is irrelevant. Otherwise virtue and vice must


be set down as things not in our power, for which,
.

consequently, we are not responsible, seeing that


when a man is once virtuous or vicious, he cannot
be otherwise ;' and the highest perfection, that of
the Grods, is absolutely unchangeable.* Chrysip-
pus even endeavoured to show, not only that his
*

whole theory of destiny was in harmony with the


claims of morality and moral responsibility, but that
it presupposed their existence. The arrangement of
the universe, he argued, involves law, and law in-
volves the distinction between what is convention-
ally right and what is conventionally wrong, be-
tween what deserves praise and what deserves blame.^

(in Eiu. Pr. Ev. vi. T, 3 and 10) TroioriiTuv /ij) iryyoov/iivuv, no!
charges Chrysippus with mak- hruvoi ^iv Kal ipciyot koI tiimX Koi
ing a 7iiilSov\oi> of the will, be- Ko\d(reis.
cause he laid so great a stress ' Aleso. c. 26, p. 82.
on its freedom. ' Alex. c. 32, p. 102.
' Cfell. vii. 2, 13 ; CXc. 1. c. ' The arguments usual
106, puts in
" Aleso. c. 34, p. among the Stoics in after times
the mouth of the Stoics t4 liiv : may, with great probability, be
ran (i^av ivipyiiffei iil6vov, rh i\ referred to Chrysippus.
irpilct -rii Ko-fiKh, KtHrii iHv aiuxf- 'Alex. c. 36: Xc7ou(ri 7<if>'
Tl^trerai, t^ S^ KaropBdafffi. Tavra obx ^(rrt rotairr} ft^y ij flfiapfi4v7jf
yiip Toirois Karh <pvffiv ju^y, tivrav ohK ^ari SJ vevpap.iv^ (It never

Se ffa! afiapTTifuiTuv KaX KaTopBufid- happens that there is a eifiapfiitni


tnov, Kill rwv Tomiruv piatuv kui but not a ircTrpw/iEf >)) oiSc iim

'

OOVBRNMENT OF THE WORLD. 181

Moreover, it is impossible to think of destiny with- Chap.


VII.
out thinking of the world, or to think of the world
without thinking of the Grods, who are supremely
good. Hence the idea of destiny involves also that
of goodness, which again includes the contrast be-
tween virtue and vice, between what is praiseworthy
and what is blameworthy.' If his opponents ob-
jected that, if everything is determined by des-
tiny, individual action is superfluous, since what
has been once foreordained must happen, come what
may, Chiysippus replied: There is a distinction
to be made between simple and complex predesti-
nation; the consequences of human actions being
simply results of those actions, those consequences
are therefore quite as much foreordained as the
'
actions themselves.^

second argument imh t^s oJttjj


Mint ii\v dXaaj ohx [ouSe] eCTi 5^ TraKaiffTpas is the following ;

i/etJieffts' OVK iiTTi liiv vtiieffis^ ovk oh irdpra fjiev ei^p^eyijVj


effri Kaff
tffri 8^ v6nos ovU HffTi iiip t/6ii0Sf
' oiiK iffri Se aKt^KvTOs KaX hrape^^
OVK etTTi 5e Xd^os op&bs TrpoffTOMTL- 'jr6dtffT0S Tl TOV Kdo'fJLOV SLOtKTja'lS
Khs fiiv Sv TTOtTjreov avayopevriKhs ovSe effTi fjL^v toCto, ovk Iffr* 5^
Se&poi/notrjTeov' aAAck ^irayope^e- K6ffiJLOs ' oitSe ^(TTi /Acy Kifffios, ovk
Toi jUei/ tA afiapTav6fieva, TtpofTrAr- eiVl Se Seoi(for K6a'iios, accord-

Terai Sh rot KaropBtifiara ' ovk &pa ing to the definitions of Chiys-
eo-Ti /iiv TOiairt) ii eluapiiivri, ovk ippus, is the whole, including
e<rn Sf a/uapr^^uara Kal KaropOii- gods and men. , See p. 158, 1)
Hara- iw' el iarai a^opT^juara e( Se eiffi deo!, eialv &rytt6ol ol 0eoi

KaX KOTopfldi/ioTO, ^ffTiK a.per'if koX &\?C TovTOf ^ffTiV aper-tj &X\' 1
ei

Koxia- 56 toSto, Iitti KaKhv Kol effTO/ aperii, %aTi ^p6vr)ais- &W'
iuaxp6v aX\ct ri liiv Ktt\hv ^irai- el rovTO tffTiy ri i'jriiTT'fjfiTj iron\-
verhi/, rh Bt cuaxpiv ^eKT6v ouK Tewv T6 KoX ov KoiTirewv
^Wb.
&pa iari Toiairji fiiv f) cijctop^nej/ij, TTOiriTea fiey effri Tcfc KaTopSt^fiara,
oliK iaji 8e iTiiuveriy Kol \fiiKT6v. ov TroiriTea Se TCi afiapriiixaTa, k.t K.
What is praiseworthy deserves OVK Upa irivra iiXv ytveTU Kaff
Tifiii or y4pas ijdiiirii, and what elfiupiievtiv, OVK iari B^ yepaipeiv
is blameworthy merits KdMtrts Ktxl iTrayopGovy.
or inavSpBaais. " ao. De Fato, 12, 28 ; Dio-
^AUx. c. 37, p. 118: A (itt Mis. Pr. Ev, vi. 8,
182 THE STOICS.

Chap. From all these observations, it appears that the


'.

Stoics never intended to allow man to hold a dif-


ferent position, in regard to destiny, from that held
by other beings. All the actions of man in fact his
/destiny are decided
by his relation to things one :

individual only differs from another in that one acts


on his own impulse, and agreeably with his own feel-
ings, whereas another, under compulsion and against
his will, conforms to the eternal law of the world.'
c. Natme Everything in the world being produced by one
mm-U. aid the same divine power, the world, as regards
its structure, is an organic whole, in respect of its

16) ; Sen. Nat. Qu. ii. 37. Things incorrect to say, perhaps you
which were determined by the will reap.
co-operation of destiny alone ' Sen. (after Cleanthes, whose

Chrysippus ' called irvyKaSfifiap- verses in Epicteit. Man. 52)


/ueVo (confatalia). The argu- Ep. 107, 11 Ducunt volentem
:

ment by which he was confuted, fata, noleutem trahunt. Hip-


which Prantl, Gesch. d. Log. i. polyt. Eefut. Haer. i. 21, has put
489, erroneously attributes to it very plainly: ri Kafl' eluap-
the Stoics themselves, went by fUvfiv dvai irivTti Sif$e$tuti<ravro
the name of apr^hs \6yos (ignava rapaSelynari xPV^f-ivoi roioirif,
ratio). Besides the oji^bs \6yi)t, 8ti &airep ix/Hicn-os Sty ?j l{|pTi)-
Plvt. De Fate, c. 11, p. 574, /ieVos Kiuv, ictv liiv jSo^ATrrai eirt-
mentions the iipl^av and the ir6ai, Kal IXKcrac koI lircTai ixiiv
-\6yos irapA t^v tifiapfi4vriv as fal- . . iav Si ^Jj $oi\7fr<u circirfloi,
.

lacies which could only be re- Trdvras i,vayK<ur8iitrfrat, rh airi


futed on the giound of the free- Siiirov Kai ^irl ruv ivBpiiirav icai

dom of the will. The last-named fi^ $ovK6iixvoi yip &Ko\ov9f!p&vaff-


one, perhaps, turned on the Kaa6i)aovrM urivras eis rh irerpcs-
idea ((Enomans, In JHus. Pr. Ev. The same idea
liivov flae\8eiy.
vi. 7, 12) that man might frus- is expanded by M. Awel. vi.
trate destiny if he neglected to 42: All must work for the
do what was necessary to pro- whole, ^K wepiovcrias Sk Kal 6 iiefi-
duce the foreordained results. (p6iievos Kal d a,VTi$iidvttv iteip^-
According to Amnum, De Inter. Heyos Kol iiyaipfiy rk yiydfieva, Kal
106, a, Luoia/n, Vit. Auct. 22, 7aip ToS roioiroii ^XPPJV" ' K<i<r;uo.
the Sfpl^av was as follows It is man's business to take
Either you will reap or you care that he acts a digniiied
.will not reap: it is therefore part in the common labour.
NATURE OF fHE WORLDPERFECTION. 1S3

constitution perfect. The unity of the world, a Chap.


"

doctrine distinguishing the Stoics from the Epicu-


(i).^^^
from
reans, followed as a corollary
mary substance and of primary force. It was further
,.,. IT.. the unity of pri-
pe^fee-
,
miity Olid

**""*"
proved by the intimate connection, or, as the Stoics
called it, the sympathy of all its parts, and, in par-
ticular,by the coincidence of the phenomena of
earth and heaven.* Its perfection followed generally

After all that has been


' 4\A^Xoij. Dioff. vii. 140 4v SJ :

said, this needs no fvirther con- T^ K6aiuf lurtSiv elvai Kevhv iW


firmation. Conversely, the T/yua'dai avThy^ tovto yhp hvay'
unity of the forming power is KiiC^iv T^v Ttov ohpaviuv vphs to.
concluded from the unity of 4irlyeia aifiirvoiav Kal avvTOviav,
the world. See p. 143, 1, 2. Ibid. 143 3ti ff ils 4arTi Ztivuv
:

Conf. Plut. Def. Orac. 29, p. ipitffltf 4v T^


Tov li\ov Kal
trepl
425. M. Awrel. vi. 38 itivra : XpifftvTTOs KaX ^AiroWiSupos . . .

iLKKiiKois iirnreir\eKrat Koti irdvTa Kol notreiSiivtos. Alex. De Mixt,


KarA TovTO iplKa 8[AA^\ow itrri 142, a, see p. 127, 5 ; ao. N. D.
. . TOVTO Si SiCi T^V TOyiK^JV
, ii. 7, 19 ; Bpictet. Diss. i. 14, 2:

KivTJITlt' KOti ffiflTTfOiai/ KoX T^V oh SoKft irot, ^<^7?, TjifutrBat Ta


cvuffiv TTjs oiKrlas. Ibid, vii. 9, irdyTa ^0Ke7, ^<jyr) t Se crvjuira-
; ;

2 Sext. Math. ix. 78 tSv : Beiv Ta 4nlyeia toTs ovpavlots ov


ffafx^Tav Tct /xcf iffTiv Tjvan^va, SoKel aot ; Aoke7, ^i^t;, Cicero
Tct Si ix avvanTopievav, ret SJ Ik mentions the changes in ani-
SiefTT^Tuv . . . htel oiv Kal 6 mals and plants corresponding
K6tT/ios ffwfid itrriy, ^TOi ^I'w^ to the changes of seasons, the
/Aevov ^(TtI ffufjia fj iK ffvva/KTo- phases of the moon, and the
fievuv ^ ^K SieffT^uw o6t Si 4k greater or less nearness of the
avva-KTofievuv oUtc 4k SteffTti^uv, sun. M. Awel. iv. 40. From
is Seixm/iev 4k tuv irepl airhv all these passages we gather
crujUirafleiSv
Karft yiip riy rrjs what the question really was.
ffeX^i^s ou|^(rei$ Kal tti&iffeis TroWefc It was not only whether other
Tuv T6 itriytiwv ^(fwp Koi BaXuffaiav worlds were possible, besides
<l>eiiiet re Kol at^eTcu, iiiwilnfis Te the one which we know from
Kai ir\T)/t/up(S6s (ebla and flood), observation, but whether the
irepi Tii/a litpri ttjs 9a\d(ra'ris yivov- heavenly bodies visible were in
Toi. In the same way, atmo- any essential way connected
spheric changes coincide with with the earth, so as to form
the setting and rising of the an organic whole (fv""! Hiog.
stars : 4^ wv avfitpayis, 3t* Tjyu- vii. 143).
liivov Ti aufia KoSinTiiKiv 6 xianui, The Stoic conception of av\i.-
4nX fiev yitp tuv 4k trvvavTOixei/ai' was not used to denote
ireSfleia

i) 5i6o:t<6tv o4 av/irriirxfi to /tepq the magic connection which it


;

184 THE STOICS.

Chap. from a consideration of their fundamental princi*


VII.
pies.' But the Stoics made use of many arguments
in support of it, appealing, after the example of
preceding philosophers, sometimes to its beauty, and,
at other times, to the adaptation of means to ends.^
An appeal to the former is the assertion of Chry-
sippus, that nature made many creatures for the
sake of beauty, the peacock, for instance, for the
sake of its tail ^ ;
and the dictum of Marcus Au-
relius, that what is purely subsidiary and subservient
to no purpose, even what is ugly or frightful in
nature, has peculiar attractions of its own ;* and the

expresses in ordinary parlance, SioiK&v KSyos ovSefAav iv lauT^


but the natural coincidence be- aiTiav ^x^^ '^'^^ KaKOTTOieiv KaKiav '

tween phenomena belonging to ykp QVK ex^t, oiiSe t( kokus iroiet,


the different paits of the world, oiiSk $\iiirTeTal Tt utt* ^kciVou.
the consensus, concentus, cog- vdfTa bh Kar' iKeTvov yii/eraL koX
natio, oonjunotlo, or continuatio vepaiveTOi.
naturse {Oie. N. D. iii. 11, 28 ' Diog. 149 TuiTiiv 8f [tV:

Divin. ii. 15, 34 69, 142).


; In (pifftv'^Kol rov ffVfKl>4pOVTOS (TTOxd-
this sense, M. Awel. ix. 9, ob- feirfloi Kol riSopris, as SijXov iK Tr/s
serves that like is attracted ToG hvBp^nov Srjiitovpytas.
by like fire is attracted up-
; ' Pint. St. Kep. 21, 3, p.
wards, earth downwards beasts ; 1044 : eiiriv [XplicriTTiros] 8t( , . .

and men .^ieek out each other's <pi\oKa\i'iv . . . T^v tbilTtV Tn


society e ven amongst the high-
; TroMiXlif x"-^?"^""-" f'^is iffTl,
est existences, the stars, there ravra Kar^ K4^lu fipjjKe ' ytvntro
exists a ivairis ix SieffrriKdraiv, a S" tiv /ui\urra roirov iyt^aais iirX
ffvfivddeLa ^v StfffTufft. Even the T?s xipKou 10V Taii. Conf. the
lastremark does not go beyond Stoic in Cic. Fin. ii. 5, 18 Jam :

the conception of a natural con- membrorum . . . alia videntur


nection ; nevertheless, it paves propter eorum usum a natura
the way for the later Neopla- esse donata . . alia autem
.

tonic idea of sympathy, as no nuUam ob utilitatem, quasi ad


longer a physical connection, quendam ornatum, ut cauda
but as an influence felt at a pavoni, plumse versicolores co-
distance by virtue of a connec- lumbis, viris mammse atque
tion of soul. barba.
' M. Awel. vi. 1 : ri ray iKuv * M. Aurel. iii. 2 It is there :

oiiria (the matter of the world) proved by examples, Sti ital to


iitiyiviiifva toTs (piird ytym/iii/ots
NATURE OF THE WORLD PERFECTION. 185

Same kind of consideration may have led to the .Chap.

Stoic assertion, that no two things in nature are alto- !^


gether alike.' Their chief argument, however, for the
beauty of the world, was based on the shape, the
size, and the colour of the heavenly structure.^
The other line of argument is followed not so
much in individual expressions. But owing no
doubt to the same reason the predominantly prac-
tical character of its treatment of things the Stoic
view of nature, like the Socratic, has ever an
eye on the adaptation of means to ends in the
world. As, on the one hand, this adaptation of
means to ends is the most convincing proof of
the existence of deity, so, on the other hand, by it,

more than by anything else, the divine govern-


ment of the world makes itself manifest.' Like
*
Socrates, however, they took a very superficial view-
of the adaptation of means to ends, arguing that
everything in the world was created for the benefit of
some other thing plants for the support of animals,
animals for the support and the service of man,^

iX^i Ti iSxapi naX iira-yuybv , . . has the most perfect form, that
trx^Sbv oiBw oux' ""' ''wv Kai' of a globe, with a sky the most
iTTaKO\o(iBrii7w avjxfiaa/dmuii ifiiilis perfect in colour, &c.
nus SuuTwiffrajBai. ' See the passages quoted

'Cie. Acad. ii. 26, 85 Sen. ; p. 145, 4, particularly CHo.S. D.


Ep. 113, 16. The latter includes ii. 32.
this variety of natural objects * PUd. Cin Porphyr. De
among the facts, which must Abstin. iii. 32) ctw" iKiivo ri]
:

fill us with admiration for the A/a toO XpualTnrm mBxvbi/ ^v, as
divine artifices. Viuis avrav koI aW^iKuu ol fleol
^ Plut. Plac. i. 6, 2 :KoXhs Si x'^P"' f'^oiiiaavTo, iiiiHv Si tA fi?a,
i Kdfftios StjKov S' ix toD ax'h-
aviiTroKeii.ftv /ih imrovs xai avvdri-

pLaros kolI tov xP^f^^"^^^ '^"^ '^'^^ pctJctv K^ivas, atfSpelas Si yvfivdtrta

fuyiSovs (tol T?s irepi ibv xdiTfiov vapSaAns ol &pKrovs KaiXcofTas,


Tuti aarepau iroLKiKias ; the world k.t.X. Cic. N. D. ii. 14, 37 :
186 THE STOICS.

Chap.
vn.
the world for the benefit of Gods and men '
not
^infrequently degenerating into the ridiculous and
pedantic, in their endeavours to trace the special
end for which each thing existed.'' But, in asking

Scite enim Chrysippus ut : bent. The earth with its plants


clypei causa inrolucrum, va- and animals was created for the
ginam autem gladii, sic praeter service of man. In Ori^. c.
mundum csetera omnia aliorum Cels. iv. 74, p. 559, the StoicS
causa esse generata, ut eas assert that Providence created
fruges et fructus, quas terra all things for the sake of ra-
gignit, animantium causa, ani- tional beings ; M. Awrel. v. 16
mantes autem hominum, ut and 30 Gell. vii. 1, 1. Hence
;

equum vehendi causa, arandi the defiiiition of Kia^ws quoted


bovem, venandi et oustodiendi on p. 158, 1.
canem. Id. OS. i. 7, 22 Placet :
* Chrysippus (in Phit. Sto.

Stoicis, quse in terris gignan- Rep. 32, 1, p. 1049) shows how


tur ad usum hominum omnia useful fowls are the horse is
;

creari. intended for riding, the ox for


' die. Fin. iii. 20, 67 : Prse- ploughing, the dog for hunting.
claj-e enim Chrysippus, cetera The pig, Cleanthes thought
nata esse hominum causa et (^Clemens, Strom, vii. 718, B),
Deorum, eos autem communi- was made to sustain man, and
tatis et societatls suse. N. D. endowed with a soul, in place
ii. 53, 133, in describing the of salt, to prevent its cor-
Stoic teaching Why has the: rupting (Oio. N. D. ii. 64, 160;
Tiniverse been made ? Kot for Fin. V. 13, 38 Pint. Qu. Con-
;

the sake of plants or. animals, viv. V. 10, 3 and 6, p. 685;


but for the sake of rational Porphyr. De Abstin. iii. 20);
beings, Gods and men. It is oysters and birds for the same
then shown (c. 54-61), by an purpose also {Porphyr. 1. c.).
appeal to the structure of man's In the same way, he spoke of
body, and his mental qualities, the value of mice and bugs, see
how God has provided for the p. 189, 1. The Stoic in Cic.
wants of man and the argu-
; N. D. ii. 63, 158, following in
ment concludes with the words. the same track, declares that
Omnia, quse sint in hoc mundo, sheep only exist for the pur-
quibus utantur homines, homi- pose of clothing, dogs for
num causa facta esse et parata. guarding and helping man,
Just as a, city, and what is fishes for eating, and birds of
therein, exists for the use of prey for divers uses. Epictet.
the inhabitants, so the world is Diss. ii. 8, 7, in the same spirit,
intended for the use of Gods speaks of asses being intended
and men. Even the stars quan- to carry burdens for this pur-
;

quam etiam ad mundi cohse- pose he must be able to walk,


.rentiam pertinent, tamen et and in order to walk, must pos-
spectaculum homiuibus pras- sess the power of imaginaMon.
NATURE OF THE WORLDMORALITY. 187

the further question, For what purpose do Grods and Chap.


men exist? they could not help being at length
'

brought beyond the idea of a relative end to the


idea of an end-in-itself. The end for which Gods
'^
and men exist is that of mutual society.' Or, ex-
pressing the same idea in language more philosot
phical, the end of man is the contemplation and
imitation of the world ; man has only importance
as being a part of a whole ; only this whole is per-
fect and an end-in-itself.^

The greater the importance attached by the {2)M<n-al


Stoics to the perfection of the world, the less were *J^^^y .'^

they able to avoid the diflBcult problem of recon-


ciling the various forms of evil in the world. By
the attention which, following the example of Plato,
they gave to this question, they may be said to be
Ihe real creators of the moral theory of the world.'
The character of this moral theory was already
determined by their system. Subordinating indivi-
duals, as that system did, to the law of the whole,
it met the charges preferred against the evil found
in the world by the general maxim, that imperfec-'\
tion in details is necessary for the perfection of the/
whole.* This maxim, howevet, might be explained'

' We gather this from the


' See p. 186, 1.
' do. N. D. ii. 14, 37 : Ipse comparatively full accounts of
autem homo ortus est ad muu- the Btoio theory of the moral
dum oontemplandum et imitan- government of the world. Phit.
,dum,nullo modo perfectus, sed Sto. Kep. 37, 1, p. 1051, says
estquaedam particula perfeoti. that Chrysippus wrote several
Sed mundus quoniam omnia treatises irepi toS itrfi^v 4yK\i)T}n/
complexus est, nee est quid- elmt /iijSe funirrhv K6iriup.
* See p. 187, 2, and Ghrys-
quam, quod non insit in eo,
; perfectus undique est, ippus (in Plmt. Sto. Eep. 44, 6)l :
188 THE STOICS.

Chap, in several ways, according to the meaning assigned


to the term necessary. If necessity was taken to be
physical, the existence of evil was excused as being
a natural necessity, from which not even deity could
grant exemption. If, on the other hand, the neces-
sitywas not a physical one, but one arising from the
relation ofmeans to ends, evil was justified as a con-
dition or necessary means for bringing about good.
Both views combined in the three chief questions
are
involved in the moral, theory of the world the ex- :

istence of physical evil, the existence of moral


evil, and the relation of outward circumstances to
morality.
{a) Exisst- The existence of physical evil gave the Stoics

"plmUal
little trouble, since they refused to regard it as an
evil. evil at all, as will be seen in treating of their ethical
system, It was enough for them to refer evils of

this kind diseases, for instance to natural causes,


and to regard them as the inevitable consequences
of causes framed by nature to serve a definite pur-
pose.' Still, they did not fail to point out that

TfKcov M^" i K6ffiios iTuiid iiTTiv, piincipale naturee consilium,


oi TfKea Sf Tcb K6trixov /jLtpri t^ ut faceret homines morbis ob-
vphs rh h\ov Ttas ex'"' ""' i"^ "o^' noxios . . . sed cum multa
oStA chai. Compare also the inquit atque magna gigneret
statement in Plut. Solert. An. pareretque aptissima et utilis-
c. 2, 9, p. 960, that animals sima, alia quoque simul agbata
must be irrational, because the sunt incommoda iis ipsis, quse
irrational must be contrasted f aciebat coharentia eaque non, :

with the rational. per natuiam sed per sequelas


' 6'eK. vil. [vi.] 1, 7: Chrys- quasdam neoessarias facta dicit,
ippus, in his treatise Treplirpoi/oior, quod ipse appellat hotA irapaKO-
discussed, amongst other things, KoiBriirir. . Proinde morbi
. ,

the question, ei oi rav ivSpdirav quoque et aegritudines partse


v6(roi Koxii ifiiaiv -/liiovTai. Ex- sunt dum salus paritur. M.
istimat autem non fuisse hoc Av/rel. vi. 36 : All evils are
NATURE OF THE WORLBMORALITY. 189

many things only become evil by a perverted use,' Chap.


"

and that other things, ordinarily regarded as evil,


are of the greatest value.*
Greater diflSculty was found by the Stoics as by (j) Exigt-

others to beset the attempt to justify the existence


^^.^{^i

of moral evil the diflSculty being enhanced by the
extent and degree of moral evil in the world ' accord-
ing to their views. By their theory of necessity
they were prevented from rolling the responsibility
for moral evil from natural law or deity on to man.
If, nevertheless, they did not altogether exclude this
\

course, inasmuch as they refused to allow to deity any


participation in evil, and referred evil to the free will
and intention of man,'' they only acted like other

itriyevviiiiaTci ruv trefij/uv Koi the house of nature all the


Ka\wp. Plitt. 6An. Procr. c. waste has its uses.
and 9, p. 1015: abrol 5i (the ' A circumstance which
Stoics) Kaxtav Kal Kaxotaifiovlav Plut. Com. Not. 19, p. 1067,
TOffaiir-iiv . , , RaT* itraKoKo^Bitffiv dexterously uses against the
yeyovivai \4yovfftv. Sen. Nat, Stoics.
Qu. vi. 3, 1. * Cleantheg, Hymn. v. 17
' Sen. Nat. Qu. v. 18, 4 and (see p. 171, 3) ; Plut. St. Eep.
13 Non ideo non sunt ista
: 33, 2 Chrysippus affirms, is
:

natura bona, si vitio male tS)V altyxp^^ ^i 6e7ov vapairiov


utentinm nocent ... si bene- yiveffBai ovk eii\oy6v iirriVf law is
ficia naturae utentium pravitate innocent of crime, God of im-
perpendimns, nihil non nostro piety. Id. (in Gell. vii. 2, 7) :

malo accepimus. Quanquam ita sit, ut ratione


^ Chrysippus. (in Plut. St. quadam necessaria et principali
Kep. 21, 4] remarks that bugs do coacta atque connexa siut fato
US good service by preventing omnia, ingeniatamen ipsa men-
us from sleeping too long, and tium nostrarum perinde sunt
mice warn us not to leave fato obnoxia, ut proprietas
things about. He also observes eorum est ipsa et qualitas . . .
{liid. 32, 2) that wars are as sua saevitate et voluntario im-
useful as coloni es, by preventing petu in assidua delicta, et
over-population. See the quo- in errores se ruunt. Hence
tations, p. 185, i 186, 2. M. ;
Cleanthes continues, in a pas-
Aurel. vui. 50, makes a similar sagequotedin Greek by Gellius;
remark in regard to weeds. In iis Tuv j3Aaj3uv exdirrois Trap'
' :

190 THE STOICS.

Chap. systems of necessity, ia not treating this solution as


VII.
final.' The real solution which they gave to the
difficulty was partly hy asserting that even the deity
is not able to keep human nature free from faults,'
and partly by the consideration that the existence of
evil is necessary, as a counterpart and supplement to,
good,' and that, in the long run, evil would be turned
by the deity into good.*
axtrois yivofteyuv Ka2 Kaff dpfi^v Eep. 35, 3 (C. Kot. 13, 2)!
ain^v afiapraySyruv re KctL ^Xair- yhp avrii tus [ii kbkIo]
7(i>CTai
TOfievuv Kal Kar^ t^v ahrSov 5ia- KOT^ rbv Trjs <p^iTftos \6yop Kol
Koiac KOI vpASitTiV. In Phit. Sto. Vva o0Tetfs elfjrw oiiK &XP^'^'^^^ yivf-
Rep. 47, 13, p. 1057, Chiysippus Tou vphs TO SAo, ovSk yhp ttv
says that, even if the Gods rhyoBbv ^v. C. Not. 14, 1 : As
make representations to
false in a comedy, what is absurd
man, it is man's fault if he contributes to the effect of the
follows those representations. whole, o0Ta i|'|io5 ttv axn^v 4<p*

Conf. Epictet. Ench. ^. 27: eavTTJs T^JK Kiuciav rots S' iiXXou
&<rvep ffKOTrbs irpbs rh itvorvx^tv oiK &xi">''''^' iarir. Similarly
ov rfderai, oiirus oiiSe KaKov (piffis M. Awel. vi. 42. Gell. vii.
(evil in itself) iv xAaiuf ylvercu. 1, 2 (Chrysippus) nihil est
:

Id. Diss. i. 6, 40. Such ob- prorsus istis, inquit, insubidius,


servations bear out in some qui opinantur^ bona esse po-
degree the statement of Phit. tuisse, si non essent ibidem
Plac. ii. 27. 3, that, according mala nam cum bona mails
:

to the Stoics, rh laiv tlnipBai, ri contrariasint, utraque neoessum


Sk avei/idpecu. See above p. 179, est opposita inter se et quasi
3,4. mutuo adverse quaeque fulta.
Chrysippus recogmsed nixu (HeracUtus' h,VT\\o\/ arvii-
this and hence he says (in
; consistere nullum adeo
(ftepov) :

Oell.) It has been also de-


: contrarium est sine contrario
creed by destiny that the bad altero. Without injustice,
should do wrong. cowardice, &c., could not we
^ Chrysippus in Phit. Sto. know what justice and valour
Eep. 36, 1 kukiW Se KaB6\ov
: are. If there were no evil,
Spot otfre hvvtvrov itrriv oih* Ix^' <pp6y7)tTLS as iirifrr^fiTi h.ya6wy (fol,

Ka\us ap6i)vai. Id, (in Gell. KOKup would be impossible


vii.1, 10): As diseases spring (Plut. C. Not. 16, 2, p. 1066).
from human nature, sic herole Cleanthes, Hymn. 18
inquit dum virtus hominibus aWh trh KciX rh irepurah iiriarairai,
per consilium naturas gignitur Aprta OetKat
vitia ibidem per affinitatem Ko) Koa-iieTv TO &Koirna, koI ov <piKa
contrariam nata sunt. ao) (pi\u iariv
' Chrysippus in Pltit. Sto.
:

NATURE OF THE WORLDMORALITY. 191

The third point in the moral theory of the world,! Chap,


vn.
the connection between moral worth and happiness,
enffaged all the subtlety of Chrysippus and his fol- (") Cbw-
1
lowers.
m J
To deny any connection l :
between iv.
them i.-^A
would
nectionhe-
tneen
"'"^
have been to contradict their ordinary views of the ';'*^"f

relation of means to ends. Besides, they were pre-


pared to regard a portion of our outward ills as divine
judgments.' Still there were facts which could not,
be reconciled with this view the misfortunes of the
virtuous, the good fortune of the vicious and which
required explanation. The task of explaining these
facts appears to have involved the Stoics in consider-
able embarrassment, nor were their answers altoge-
ther satisfactory.^ But, in the spirit of their sys-

St. Rep. 37, 2) in answer to thes


iff0\a KaKOifftv question, How the misfortune
&ffd* (va yiyveaBai irAvTuy \6yov of the virtuous is to be ex-
aiiv idvra, plained, says trdripop &jUc\ou-
:

Plut. Sto. Rep. 35, 1 rhv


' : fifvuy Tivuv KaGdnep iif olKlats
$eh KO\d(eiv ^trl r^v Kaxiav Kai fiei^otri irapairivret Ttva irlrvpa Kal
ToAXck 701611' iirl KO\dtrei rwv iro- iroaol nvpoi rives rwv ^\av c
vqpuv . , vori fifv ret Svff-
, oiKovofiovfievui/
fl Slol rh KoBi-
XpTjffTa (TvfjL^aivetv <pr]<rl rots ffrourdat 4Trl ray Totoirav Saifjt6via
ayaOots oitx Siffvep rots tpauKots tpav\a 4v oh rip 6vrt yivovrai
Kohitrfus '^^^^ "'"' SaAtjv
x^P^" iyK\nT4ai&fi.4\eiai; Similarly the
oiKovofiiav Sautref} iv rats Trd^eaiu Stoic in Oic. N. D. ii. 66
.[to Ka*ca] cfjrovefieTai Karcb
. Magna Dii curant, parva negli^

.

rhv Tov Aths Kdyof ^toi iirl KO\d- gunt, hardly satisfactory ex-
ffEi t) kot' SXAijc ^x'"""^"
""' planations for any theory of
vphs rh 3Xa o'lKoi/oiilav. Id. necessity. It is still more un-
15, 2: TaiTii<l>7i<n roiii Btobsvoieiv satisfactory to hear Seneca
Siraj Tuv irovtipuv KoKa^oiiivuv oi (Benef. iv. 32) justifying the
Kotnoi trapaSeiyfiatri roirots XP^ unmerited good fortune of th^
^fvoi ^TTOC iirtx^ip^trt rutQVT6v ti wicked as due to the nobility
iroieiv. At the beginning of the of their ancestors. The reason
same chapter, the ordinary assigned by Chrysippus (in
views of divine punishment had -nohh
Plut.') Ktti rb rijs hydyKtis

been treated with ridicule. HifuxOai does not quite ha^.^


Conf. Qoaast. Eom. 51, p. 277. monise with Plut. C. Not. 34,
' Thus Chrysippus (in Pint. 2 : ov yhp 5} 7e uAtj ri xanhv 4^
;

192 TRE STOICS.

Chap. ,tem, only one explanation was possible : no real evil


VII.
. could happen to the virtuous, no real good fortune
fcould fall to the lot. of the vicious.' Apparent mis-
ifortune will therefore be regarded by the wise man
j
partly as a natural conseq\ience, partly as a whole-
\some exercise of his moral powers f there is nothing
which is not matter for rational action everything ;

that happens, when rightly considered, contributes


to our good ; nothing that is secured by moral de-
pravity is in itself desirable.^ With this view, it

kamris itapitrxni^^^, Siruios yip Kal xp^trdai avr^ itp' oTov ttv KaV
iari Kol irrfo-ai Siros Se'xcToi 5tn- &pfjiTitrev.

Kii'oOi/Tos outJjc Kol ' Seneca's treatise, De Pro-


^ofhs inh ToO
<rX'!i'''''(foi/Tos Iffx^f. Just aa videntia, is occupied with ex-
liftle does Seneca's Non po- panding this thought. In this
test artifex mutare materiam 'treatise, the arguments by which

(De Prov. 5, 9) agree with his the outward misfortunes of
lavish encomia on the arrange- good men are harmonised with
ment and perfection of the the divine government of the
world. For, according to the world are (1) The wise man
:

Stoics, matter is ultimately cannot really meet with mis-


identical with reason and deity. fortune he cannot receive at
I

These contradictions do not, the hands of fortune what he


however, justify the doubt ex- does not, on moral grounds,
pressed by Seine, Stoic, de assign to himself (c. 2, 6). (2)
Fato Doct. 46, that Seneca is Misfortune, therefore, is an
here not speaking as a Stoic. unlooked-for exercise of his
For Chrysippus says very much powers, a divine instrument of
the same thing. See p. 190, training ; a hero in conflict
1,2. with fortune is a spectaculum
'
M. Awrel. ix. 16 : oiie iv Deo dignum (c. 1, 2-4. Conf.
veiaei, aKiC ivepyflif, rh toD Kayt- Ep. 85, 39). (3) The mis-
KoG (ifov KaKhy Kal iyaBhv, iffirep fortunes of the righteous show
oiiSi fi apcTJ) Kai Kaxla auroD iy that external conditions are
ireto-et, iWh ivepyiicf. neither a good nor an evil (c. 5).
' M. Aurel. viii. 36: %v (4) Everything is a natural
Tp6irov iKilvTi [v ^ims] irSi/ rh consequence of natural causes
ivuTTiiievoy icdl avrtPaimv int- (c. 5). Similar explanations in
irepiTpewet Kal KaTaTdfrffet cU r^y Hjpictet. Diss. iii. 17 ; i. 6, 37
etfutpiifpriv Kol ftc'poj Iout^s iroiet, i. 24, 1 ; Stoh. Eol. i. 132 M.
;

oSras Kal rh Koywhy f^joy Siyarai Awrel. iv. 49 ; vii. 68 and 54 ;


ray KdiKv/ia fi\iiy Ibi/toS iroieif X. 33.
NATURE OF THE WORLD: MORALITY. 193

was possible to connect a belief in divine punish- Chap.


vn.
ment, by saying that what to a goodman is an exer-
cise of his powers, is a real misfortune and conse-
quently a punishment to a bad man; but we are
not informed whether the scattered notes in Chry-
sippus really bear out this meaning.
The whole investigation is one involving much
doubt and inconsistency. Natural considerations fre-

quently intertwine with considerations based on the


adaptation of means to ends ; the divine power is

oftentimes treated as a will working towards a de-


finite purpose, at one time arranging all things for
the best with unlimited power, at another time ac-
cording to an unchangeable law of nature ;
* but all

these inconsistencies and defects belong to other


moral theories of the world, quite as much as they
belong to that of the Stoics.

' PMlodem. irepl BfZv Sio- ihiyx""' ''rieCiDi'Tai, Tifrc Kctra-


^ay^y, col. 8, Vol. Here. vi. 53: ((>eT)7ou(Ti>' ^irl ri Sii toSto i)i(r/ceii/

liioiTiKus AvavTos aitT^ [^f^] Taa'ui'oirT(Jjtti'a(whatis suitable)


Sdvafiiv waOevTes, 8toi' ^h rSov u^ iroieic, 3ti oh niyra Btivaro:,
1 94 THE STOICS.

CHAPTER VIII.

lEKATIONAL NATPEE. THE ELEMENTS. THE UNIVEESB.

Chap. Turning now from the questions which have hitherto


;_ engaged our attention to natural science in the
A. T/ie stricter sense of the term, we must first touch upon

ral ideas ^ ^^^ characteristic questions afifecting the general


on nature, conditions of all existence. Yet even here the Stoics
hold little that is of a distinctive character. The
matter or substance of which all things are made is
corporeal.' All that is corporeal is infinitely divi-
sible, although it is never infinitely divided.^ At the
same time, all things are exposed to the action of
change, sinpe one material is constantly going over

into another.^ Herein the Stoics following Aris-


totle, in contrast to the mechanical theory of nature,*

' See above, p. 126 ; 101, 2 ;


101,3 : FiuutoiimiaexomnibTis,
Diog. 135. Conf . Stoi. Eel. ex aqua aer, ex aere aqua, ignis
i. 410. ex aere, ex igne aer ... ex
^ In Swg. 150, there is no aqua terra fit, cur nou aqua fiat
difference made between Apol- e terra ? . omnium elemen-
. .

lodorus and Chrysippus. Stoh. torum in alternum recursus


Eel. i. 844 Pint. C. Not.
; 38, 3, sunt. Similarly Epictet. in
p. 1079Sext. Math.
; x. 142. Stob. Floril. 108, 60. Conf. p.
Similarly Aristotle. 101, 2 198, 3. This is borrowed
;

' PZm^.Plao.i. 9, 2 : 01 StoiikoI not only from Heraclitus, but


TpeTTTif Koi oWoicoTTji' Kol K6TO- also from Aristotle.
$\r[T')]VKa\piv(rr^vi\i\vSCiKovT^v * They only called the first
v\riv. Didg. 150. <Ss. Nat. Qu. iii. kind Ktmiffis. Aristotle under-

IRRATIONAL NATURE. 195

distinguish change in quality from mere motion in Chap.


VIII.
space. They enumerate several varieties of each
kind.' Nevertheless, they look upon motion in space
as the primary form of motion.^ Moreover, under
the conception of motion, they include action and
suffering.' The condition of all action is contact ;
^

and since the motions of different objects in nature


are due to various causes, and have a variety of
characters, the various kinds of action must be dis-
tinguished which correspond with them.' In all

stood by Klin)(Tu every form of 77, b, 33. Simplicius himself


change. contradicts this statement. It
Stoh. Eel. i.
> 404, 408, gives had, however, been already ad-
definitions of xlvrfais, of <poph,, vanced by Aristotle.
and of noirq, taken from Chry- ' Simpl. 1. c. 78, j8 (Schol.
sippus and ApoUodorus. Simpl. 78, a, 28) : The Stoics who, ac-
Categ. 110, P (Schol. in Arist. cording to p. 84, , Schol. 79,
92, 6, 30. Eespeoting the kinds a, 16, very fully discussed the
of /iera^oKii see the extracts categories, made the following
from Posidonius on p. 101, 2) Statpopal 76J/WC; rd i^ainwv Ktvei-
distinguishes between fifveiv, aOat, (Sis ij /j-dxaipa t6 refiveiv ^/c

ijpefieiv, Tiffvx^C^tVf oKiinjTiiv, but rijs otKitas Ix^t KaroffKey^s rd


this is rather a matter of lan- Si' eavTov ivepyeiy r^v kIvtj(tiv, its

guage. Smvpl. Cat. 78. fi, re- al tpiffeis KoX at tarpiKol Swd^eis
lates that the Stoics differed T^jv troiriatv for
inrepyd^ovTat ;

from the Peripatetics in ex- instance, the


in de- seed,
plaining Motion as an incom- veloping into a plant tA &<p'
plete energy, and discusses eavTov TToietVj or dird iSias bpfiris
their assertion that KivEio-Bai is iroie7v, one species of which is

a wider, kivuv a narrower, idea. rd ciTr6 \oyLK7is ip/ATJs rd Kar


2 Simpl. Phys. 310, b ol : U aperiiv ivepyetv. It is, in short,
anh T^s (TTOos kotA Ttaixav Kivr/frii/ the application to a particular
f\eyoy ^eivat ttiv toitik^v, ^ case of the distinction which
KOTct nfya\a Siarr'lifia.'ra fl Karci will be subsequently met with
\6y(f> dea;pT]Ta iKpKnaflivTjV. of |is, ifiiais, ij'ux^i and ^^ux^
&mpl. Categ. 78, j8 (Schol. Koyudi^ The celebrated gram-
78, a, 23) Plotinus and others
: matical distinction of opBit and
introduce into the Aristotelian vwTia mentioned p. 95, 3 is con-
doctrine the Stoic view rh : nected with the distinction
Kotvov Tov -rroiiiv KaX Trdffxeiv eXvM between ttol^Iv and ndirxftv.
Tas Kivhfftis, Conf. Simpl. p. 79, u, (; Schol.
1. y^. 77, ;8 ; Schol. 78, b, 17 and 30.
o 2
106 THE STOICS.

Chap. these statements there is hardly a perceptible devi-


vni.
ation from Aristotle.
Of a more peculiar character are the views of
the Stoics as to the intermingling of substances, to
which reference has already been made.' Even with
regard to Time and Space, they found some innova-
tions on Aristotle's theory to be necessary. Space
(tottof), according to their view, is the room occu-
pied by a body,^ the distance enclosed within the
limits of a body.^ From Space they distinguish the
Empty. The Empty is not met with in the universe,
but beyond the universe it extends indefinitely.^
And hence they' assert that Space is limited, like the
world of matter, and that the Empty is unlimited.*
Nay, not only Space, but Time also, is by them set

' See page 135. called x^P"- Hence rivos cor-


2 i. 382
Stab. Bol. : ZV"" kuI responds to a full, Kevhv to an
ol Att' avTov 4vt6s ^ev toO K6afwv empty, x<i>pa to a half -empty,
firi^ei/ eivat Kevhif ^|at 8' avTOv vessel. Setk. Math. x. 3, Pyrrh.
Sireipoi/ (conf Themist. Phys. 40,
. iii. 124, speaks to the same
b Plut. Plac. i. 18, 4 ibid. c.
; ; effect. Cleomed. Meteor, p. 2,
20, beginning ot SroiiKoi koX En- 4 ; Simpl. Categ. 91, S. Ac-
Kovpos). biatpfpetif Se Kev6v r6rtov cording to the Stoics, iropu^fir-
Xiipct" Kol Ti /iiv Kcvhv eivai TOToi Tois (rdtiiiuriv 6 riijros Koi
iprj/iiav ffd^aros, top ie rStrov t6 rhy hpov ciir* avruv trpoffKc^ifidvet
4Trex^P-^vov inrd (rcifiaros, r^v Si rhv t^^x^ roffovie, Ka06iroy irv^-
X^p^v tA 4k fiepous 4irx6iievop 7r\r]povvTat [-oCrai] uirb ray ffafid'
(Plut. adds, like a half-empty ray.
vessel). Stob.i. 390 Chrysippus : ' The Stoic idea of space is
defined tSttos = rh KaTex^fievov so understood by Themist. Phys.
5i' S\ov vird tyros, ij rh otov Kare- 38, b ^mpl. Phys. 133, a.
;

X^cdai 6irb tiVTos KaX St' Saou * See previous note and in

Karex^fJ-fvov elfre vwh rivhs eifre' Diog. 140 (where, however, in-
iirh rivuv. If, however, only stead of iur^ftaToy Si, we should
one portion of the oliv tc kote- read Keyhv Sk') definitions of
Xeirflai inrh ivros is really filled, Key6y.
the whole is neither Kev)>v nor * Stob. Eel. i. 392, quoting
rdtroSt but rfp6u ti oiiK uvo^ktvT- Chrysippus.
lifvov, which may possibly be
;

THE ELEMENTS. 107

down as immaterial and yet to the conception of


;
' Chap.
Time a meaning as concrete as possible is assigned, '_

in order that Time may have a real value. Zeno


defined Time as the extension of motion Chrysippus ;

defines it, more definitely, as the extension of the


motion of the world.^ The Stoics affirm the infinite
divisibility of Time and Space,^ but do not appear
to have instituted any deep researches into this
point.
In expanding their views on the origin of the B. Ele-
"^''**-
world, the Stoics begin with the doctrine of the
four elements,* a doctrine which, since the time of
Aristotle and Plato, was the one universally ac-
cepted. They even refer this doctrine to Heraclitus,
' See p. 131, 2. limited, the present is limited
* Simpl. Categ. 88, f. Schol. the present cannot be accu-
80, a, 6 ; twv 8^ "S^rnKfev Ziivatf rately determined, it is the
fiev ir(^7)s aTr\ws Ktvijffeus Sti- boundary between the past and
arrjiia Thv xpivov elire [ooii. Plmt. the future (Archedemus in
Plat. Qusest. viii. 4, 3) Xpiai-nitoi Phit. C. Not. 38, 6, p. 1081),
& Zi6,irri\iia rris tov K6ffiJLov Kivii' lying partly in the one, partly
o-eais. Conf. Ibid. 89, a, $ ; in the other (Chrysippus, iJi<i.
Simpl. Phys. 165, a. More fuU 38 8*)
'

is Stob. Eol. i.260 i S^Xpiffm-


: Semt. Math. x. 142 ; Plut.
JTOS xp&voy ejvai Kiviiffeus Sida- Com. Not. 41, p. 1081 ; Stob. i.
T7j/to Kofl" S iroTC Ae'yfToi iiirpov 260.
rdxovt T Kol PpaSirriTos, tj rh * For the conception of
irapaKo\ov8ouif Stdarriiw. ry toB <rroix'<w', which is also that of
KiJiT/iou Kivii<rei. The passages Aristotle (Metaph i. 3, 938, b, 8),
quoted by Stob. Ibid. 250 (_Pl/ut. and its difference from that of
Plac. i. 22, 2), 254, 256, 268, ipxh, see Diog. 134 ; 136. The
and IHog. 141, from Zeno, difference, however, is not
Chrysippus, ApoUodorus, and always observed. Chrysippus
Posidonius, are in agreement (in Stob. Bel. i. 312) dis-
with this. In the same places tinguishes three meanings of
occur several other observations irroix^hv. In one sense, it is.
on Time, which are, however, fire in another, the four ele-
;

of no importance, such as that ments in the third, any mate-


;

Time as a whole, and likewise rial out of which something is


the past and the future are un- made.
;

198 THE STOICS.

Chap. wishing, above all things, to follow his teaching on


VIII.
natural science.' On a previous occasion, the order
and the stages have been pointed out, according to
which primary fire developed into these elements in
the formation of the world.^ In the same order,
these elements now go over one into the other. And
yet, in this constant transformation of materials, in
the perpetual change of form to which primary mat-
ter is subject, in this flux of all its parts, the unity
of the whole still remains untouched.' The distinc-
tive characteristic of fire is heat ; that of air is cold

" Lassalle, Heraclitus, ii. fLiVyiyverat x*'"'" ' BSajp, Sei-


84. repa Se ^| SSaTos els a4pa, rpiri}
See p. 161. As is there
''
Se oi ^ffx^TTfi eis irvp. On ac-
stated, primary fire first goes count of this constant change,
over into water Si' ocpos (i. e. primary matter is called {IMd.
after first going over into air, 316, where, however, the text
not passing through air as an is obviously corrupt, and there-
already existing medium, as fore only partially intelligible)
Lassalle, Heracl. ii. 86 inaccu- 4 ipx^l KcQ 6 \6yos Kai ^ itStos
rately says), and water goes Sipafiis , 6(y avT-fiv re vdvra
. ,

over into the three other ele- KaTava\l<TKovcra Ka\ ri [4(] air^s
ments. In this process there iriAtv &,TroKaBtffTtt(Ta Teray/xevus
is, however, a difficulty. Fire KoiSS^. Bpictet. in Stob. Floril.
is said to derive its origin from 108, 60: Not only mankind and
water, and yet a portion of animals are undergoing per-
primary fire must have existed petual changes, oAAtb icai ri
from the beginning, as the soul fleio, Kai cj) Ai' avrll tA, Terrapa

of the world. Nor is it correct oToixeio &va Hal k&tu TpiiteTOi


to say, that actual fire is never ttal nerafiiXKei- Kal y^ re 8Sp

obtained from water in the yivpTtu KoX iiSap aj)p, oStos Se


formation of the upper ele- iniKiv CIS ai64pa fUTaPiKKfi- Kal
ments (as Lassalle, p. 88, does). 6 avrhs rpdiros ttjs fiera^oX^s
' Chrysippus, in Stoi. Bel. i. HvaSev Kdrai. On the flux of
312 : irpdJTTjs /nS* yiyvofieviis t^s things, see also M. Awrel. ii. 3 j
iK TTvphs KOTtk ffviTTOLatv eis ie'po vii. 19 ; ix. 19 ; 28. Ous. N. D.
jW6Toj3o\iis, SeuT^pas S' kirh To6rov ii. 33, 84 : Et cum quatuor sint

eis CSap, rplTTjs S' ^rt fiaWov Karck genera coiporum, vicissitudine
rh afdKoyov (TwiffrajiivovTOv ffSct- eorummundioontinuata ( = am-
Tos <ds Yijv, Tr6.Ktv Se otTrb rairris tx^s conf Sen. Nat. Qu. ii. 2,
; .

SiaXvO|ue'i/i)i Kol Smxfoiieprisnp^TT] 2,oontinuatio est partium inter


;

THE ELEMENTS. 190

that of water, moisture ; dryness that of the earth.' Chap.


VIII.
These essential qualities, however, are not always
found in the elements to which they belong in a pure
state,^ and hence every element has several forms

and varieties.' Among the four essential qualities


of the elements, Aristotle had already singled out
two, viz. heat and cold, as the two active ones, call-
ing dryness and moisture the passive ones. The
Stoics do the same, only more avowedly. They con-
sider the two elements to which these qualities pro-
perly belong to be the seats of all active force, and
distinguish them from the other two elements, as
the soul is distinguished from the body.* In their
se non intennissa con]'iinotio) each element as its distin-
natura est. ex terra Nam guishing feature, assigning cold
aqua, ex aqua oritur aer, ex to water, moisture to air.
aere aether deinde retrorsum
:
2 Thus the upper portion of

vicissim ex aethere aer, ex aere the air, owing to its proximity


aqua, ex aqua terra infima. Sio to the region of fire and the
natura his, ex quibus omnia stars (iSsm. Nat. Qu, iii. 10), is
constant, snrsum, deorsum, the warmest, the driest, and
ultro oitroque commeantibus the rarest but yet owing to
;

mundi partium conjunctio oon- the evaporation of the earth


tinetur. See p. 194, 3. and the radiation of heat,
' Diog. 137 eTrai Si -rh likv
; warmer than the middle, which
irvp rh Sep/ihv, t!) 5' SSup rh iyphv, in point of dryness and density,
t6i/ t* oiepa t^ i^vxp^vr^v yij;' tiii isbetween the two, but exceeds
ri iTip6v. Pint. Sto. Rep. 43, 1, both in cold. See p. 146, 4.
p. 1053. The air is, according ' Chrysippus, in Stob. i. 314 :

to Chrysippus, ipiaei foifepbs and KeyetrBai 5e vvp rh wp&des irav


vpdyras ipvxp^^- ^^' De Primo KoX aepa rh aepuSes kolI dfioitos t&
Frig. 9, 1 ; 17, p. 948, 952 1, \onrd. Thus PMlo, Incorrupt.
Galen, Simpl. Medic, ii. 20, M. 963, E, who is clearly fol-
vol. xi. 510. Sen. Nat. Qu. iii. lowing the Stoics, distinguishes
10 i. 4 Aer
; : frigidus per
. . . three kinds of fire fivflpal,
:

seetobscurus natura enim


. . . <t>\i^, avyii. He seems, however,

aeris gelida est. Conf. Oie. only to refer to terrestrial fire,


N. D. ii. 10, 26. Of the four which, after all, forms only one
properties by the pairing of small portion of fire.
which elements arise, even Pp. 128,
2; 148, 2; 151,1:
Aristotle had attributed one to 163, 2.
: :

200 THE STOICS.

Chap. materialistic system, the finer materials as opposed to


VIU.
the coarser, occupy the place of incorporeal forces.
The relative density of the elements also deter-
mines their place in the universe. Fire and air are
light ; water and earth are heavy. Fire and air
move away from the centre of the universe
;
' water
and earth are drawn thereto and thus, from above ;
'^

to below
or, what is the same thing, from without

to within
the four layers of fire, air, water, and
earth are formed.' The fire on the circumference

This statement must be


' Stoics maintain that the world
taken with such modification continues in empty space, irel
as the unity of the world ren- ndvTa ai/Tov ra /Ae'pij iirl rh iiiffov
ders necessary. If the upper rhevKe. The same reason is
elements were to -move alto- assigned by CUomedes, Meteor,
gether away from the centre, p. 5.
the world would go to pieces. Stol. Eel. i. 346 {Pint.
2

Hence the meaning can only PI. 12, 4).


i. Zeno, lUd. 406
be this that the difference of
: oh TTiivTus 8e ffupM 0(ipos ex^'^i
natural motions can only take ciAA* a^aprj elvai aepa koX Trvp
place within the enclosure hold- . . , tp^fTii y^p aviifpotTa tout'
ing the elements together, and eivai Sicfc rb fni^evhs fierex^^v
so far a natural motion towards pipovs. Phii. Sto. Eep. 42,
the centre can be attributed to p. 1053 : In the treatise trtpX
all bodies as a distinctive Kivi](Tias, Chrysippus calls fire
feature, anterior to the con- apapes and ci,v(o(pepes koI roirtp
trast between heaviness and irapa':r\7itrlus rhv aepa, tov juev
lightness. Conf. Chrysippus, in SSaros T^ 7p fiaWoy npotjyeiiO'
PM. Sto. Rep. 44, 6, p. 1054 iUEj/ou, TOV 5' aepos, Tip irvpi. (So
The striving of all the parts of too in Ack. Tat. Isag. i. 4 in
the world is to keep together, Pet. Doctr. Temp. iii. 75.) On
not to go asunder. oSra Sh rod the other hand, in his *u(rucal
^\ou TGtvofjievov eis ravrh Koi Kt- Tcxfoi, he inclines to the view
vovfievov Kal tuv ^opiuv Ta{m\v that air in itself is neither
heavy nor light, which how-
tr^fiaTOS 0iffGais, iriBavhy^ natTt ever can only mean that it is
rots a^fjLoaiv elfat r^v ir/je^TTjc neither absolutely, being heavy
KOTck (piffui Kivriaiv irpis rh toC compared with fire, and light
KOtT/JiOV flCffOV, rif ft.\v K6tTtJitp OV- compared with water and
Tutrl Ktj/ounevtp Trphs avrhvj rots earth.
de as tiv fi4pe(riv odaiy. * Diog. 137: avar&Ta
fiipetriu ft.\v oZp
Aoldll. Tat. Isag. 132, A.: The HvM "ri vvpi 5^ aiBfpa KoKtiffBai,^
; .

THE ELEMENTS. 201

goes by the of Ether.' name


Its most remote por- Chap.
VII]
tion was called by Zeno Heaven ^ and it differs ;

from earthly fire not only by its greater pmity/ but


also because the motion of eartSily fire is in a straight
line, whereas the motion of the Ether is circular.''

A radical difference between these two kinds of fire,


which Aristotle supposed to exist, because of this
difl'erence of motion, the Stoics did not feel it neces-
sary to admit.* They could always maintain that,
when beyond the limits of its proper locality,

fire tried to return to it as quickly as possible,

= In Ach. Tat. Isag. 130, A,

(Tipaipap yj/i/a(r6aij elrat^v tuv he defines ovpavhs as aiBepos rb


vKavw^ei/wv. fxeff ^v rhy aepa, IffXttToic, ^1 oh H.a\ 4v ^ ^(TtI
etrarh SSoip, imofTTidfirivBk iriivTUV vdvTa ifitftavus. Similarly Diog.
rijy yv^y [i.i(n\v aTctii/Tuv oZfrav. 138 CUmmd. Met. p. 7.
;

lUd. 156; 3ee p. 202, 3. To Otherwise the term is used in a


these main masses, all other wider sense.
smaller masses of the same ' See
p. 146, 4.
element in difEerent parts of * Stob. i. 346 rii fAv wepl- :

the world are attracted, be- yetov (ftas kot* evQe7av, t6 S' ai64-
cause all seek to reach their piov irepitpepus Kivilrai, See p.
natural place. Conf M. Awel. . 202, 3. It is only of terrestrial
ix 9. fire that Zeno can {Stob. Eel. i.
'
Sm. Nat. Qu. vi. 16, 2 356) say, it moves in a straight
(totum hoc ccelum, quod igneus line. Cleanthes even attri-
aether, mundi summa pars buted to the stars the spherical
claudit), and p. 198, 3, where shape, which on the strength
the same thing is called irvp by of this passage he attributes to
Stobseus, aether by Cicero. it. See Plut. Plac. ii. 14, 2
See p. 146, 4. The same thing Stob. i. 516 ; Aoh. Tat. Isag.
is meant by Zeno, where he 133, B.
says (jSoJ. Eel. i. 538, 554, and * They denied it, according
Cleanthes says the same in do. to Orig. c. do.
Cels. iv. 56.
N. D. ii. 15, 40. Ach. Tat. Isag. Acad. i. 11, 39, says Zeno dis- :

133, o) that the stars are made pensed with a quinta natura,
of fire ; not, however, of vvp being satisfied with four ele-
irexvov, but of irvp TfxviKbv. ments statuebat enim ignem
:

which appears in plants as esse ipsam naturam, quae quaeque


(piais, in animals as ^vx'h- See gignerit, et mentem atque
p. 201, 5. sensus.
;

202 THE STOICS.

Chap, whereas within those limits it moved in the form of


VIII.
a circle.
c. The Taking this view of the elements, the Stoics did
universe.
not deviate to any v^ry great extent, in their ideas
of the World, from Aristotle and the views which
were generally entertained. In the centre of the
Universe reposes the globe of the earth;' around
it is water, above the water is air. These three
strata form the kernel of the world, which is in a
state of repose,^ and around these the Ether revolves
in a circle, together with the stars which are set
therein. At the top, in one stratum, are all the
fixed stars; under the stratum containing the fixed
stars are the planets, in seven different strata
Saturn, Jupiter, Mars, Mercury, Venus, then the
Sun, and in the lowest stratum, bordering on the

region of air, is the Moon.^ Thus the world con-

' The spherical shape


of the earth is the natural framework,
earth a matter of course, and
is and, as it were, the skeleton of
is mentioned by Aoh. Tat. Isag. the world. Around it water
126, c Plut. Plao. iii. 10, 1
; has been poured, out of which
9, 3. Cleom. Met. p. 40, gives the more exalted spots project
an elaborate proof of it, for the as islands. For what is called
most part taken from Posi- continent is also an island:
donius. atrh Se roO Sdaros rhv ^epa
^ HeracUt. AUeg. Hom.
c. 36, ^J^<(>eoi KoSiircp i^wriua^ivTa
and Diog. 145, also affirm that ir<l>aipiKas Kai irepiKcx"<r9'u, ix Sk
the earth is in the centre, vm- roirou rhy al94pa dpaidTarai' tc
moved. The reason for this KaielKiKpiv4<riaTor. It moves in
fact is stated by Stob. i. 408, to circular form round the world,
be its weight. Further proofs Then follows what is given in
in Cleomcd. Met. p. 47. the text as to the stars, next
' Stob. Bel. i. 446 toS 5^ i to which comes the stratum of
. . Kiirfiov rh fikv elvai irepi-
. air, then that of water, and
<j>ip6iJievop irep\ rh /i4aov, rh 8' lastly, in the centre, the earth,
vwofievov, -KepLtpepifiivov nkv rhv Conf. Achil. Tat, Isag. 126, B,
su9f pa, tmopiivov Si riiv ftfi/ Ka\ Tck see p. 200, 3. The language of
i-ir' aiiTrjs iypa /col rhv otpo. The Cleomed. Met. c. 3, p. 6, is
:

THE UNIVERSE. 203

sists, as with Aristotle, of a globe containing many Chap.


vm.
strata, one joining the other,' That it cannot be
unlimited, as Democritus and Epicurus maintain,
follows from the very nature of body.' The space
within the world is fully occupied by the material
of the world, without a vacant space being anywhere
left.' Outside the world, however, is an empty place,
or else bow the Stoics asked would there be a
place into which the world could be resolved at the
general conflagration ? * Moreover, this empty place
must be unlimited ; for how can there be a limit, or
any kind of boundary, to that which is immaterial
and non-existent ? ^ But although the world is in

somewhat divergent. He places Tat. Isag. 152, A, who probably


the sun amongst the planets, has the Stoics in view, the axis
between Mars and Venns. That of the world consists of a cur-
Archidemus also ref usedto allow rent of air passing through the
the earth a place in the centre centre. On the division of the
has been already stated, p. 147, heaven into five parallel circles,
2. The language of Ach. Tat. and that of the earth into five
Isag. c. 7, 131, B, is ambiguous zones, conf. Diog. 155 ; Straio,
As the circumference originates ii. 2, 3, p. 95.
from the centre, so according ' Stob. i. 392 ; Simpl. Phys.

to the Stoics the outer circle jii. 6 ; Diog. 143 and 150.

originates from the earth ; when s


Mog. 140 ; Stob. i. 382 ;
compared with the quotations Phit. Plac. i. 18, 4 ; Sext. Math,
on p. 161, 2 162, 1. ; vii. 214 ; Theedoret, Cur.Gr. Afi.
' 356 ; Plut. Plac. ii.
Stob. i. iv. 14, p. 58 ; Sippolyt. Befut.
2, 1 Siog. 140; Cleomed.
; i.6, 3; Haer. i. Sen. Nat. Qu. ii. 7,
21.
Met. pp. 39 and 46 ; Meradlit. observes that motion is possible
Alleg. Horn. c. 46. Ihid. on the by means of avTiTrffAatturii,
perfection of this form and its without supposing the existence
adaptation for motion. Com- of empty space. A number of
paring Achil. Tat. Isag. 130, c, arguments against the exist-
Phct. Plac. ii. 2, 1 {Galen. ence of empty space may be
Hist. Phil. c. 11), with the pas- found in Cleomed. Met. p. 4.
sages on p. 201, note 4, it ap- * See p. 168, 1 ; Cleamed.
pears probable that Cleanthes Met. 2 and 5.
believed in a spherical form of ' Chi7sippus,injS*J.i. 392:
the earth. According to. Ach. The Empty and the Non-Mate-
;;

204 THE STOICS.

Chap. empty space, it does not move, for the half of its
vin.
component elements being heavy, and the other half
light, as a whole it is neither heavy nor light.'
(1) SttM-S. The stars are spherical masses,^ consisting of fire ;

but the fire is not in all cases equally pure,' and is

sustained, as Heraclitus taught, by evaporations from


rial is unlimited. Sirirep yhp Diog. 145 Plut. Plac. ii.
2 ;

rh /XTibev oviev iffri ir4pas, oSto> 14,1;22, 3;27,1; Stoh.i.blG;


KaX rod /jLTtSevhs, oJ6y 4itti rh 540; 554; Ach. Tat. 133, D.
Kev6v. The Empty could only Compare the reference to
be bounded by being filled. To Cleanthes on p. 201, 4, with
the same efiEect, Cleomed. p. 6. which, however, the statement
On the unlimited beyond the in Stob. i. 554, that he con-
world, see Diog. 140 and 143 sidered the moon iriAoeiS^s
Stoh. i. 260 and 382 Plut. Sto. ; (ball-like the MSS. have
Eep. 44, 1, p. 1054 C. Not. 30, ; miKoeiSri) does not agree.
2, p. 1073 Plac. i.
; 18, 4 ii. 9, ;
' According to Cic. N. D.
2 Theodoret, 1. o. and p. 196, 2.
; ii. 15, 40, IHog. 144, Stob. Eel.
That Posidonius denied the in- i. 314; 519; 538; 554; 565,
finity of the Empty has been Phit. Fao. Lun. 5, 1 ; 21, 13,
already stated, p. 168, 1. Chry- p. 921, 935, Plac. ii. 25, 3;
sjppus, in aflttrming, that the 30, 3, Galen, Hist. Phil. 15,
world occupies the centre of Philo, De Somn. 587, B, AeMl.
space, was therefore contra- Tat. Isag. 124, D 133, c, and
;

dicting himself, as Plut. Def. above p. 200, 3 ; 162, 2, the


Or. 28, p. 425, Sto. Kep. 44, 2, stars generally consist of fire,
observe. or, more accurately, of irvp
' Achil. Tat. Isag. 126, A; rexv'Khv, or Ether. The purest
132, A, see p. 200, 1; Stoh. fire is in the sun. The moon is
i. 408. According to Stoh. a compound of dull fire and air,
i. 442, Plut. C. Not. 30, 2 and or, as it is said, is more earth-
10, p. 1073, Plac. ii. 1, 6 ; i. 5, like, since (as Plin. Hist. Nat.
1, Diog. 143, Seaat. Math. ix. ii. 9, 46, without doubt after

332, Ach. Tat. 129, D, the Stoics Stoic teaching, observes) owing
had various names for the to its proximity to the earth, it
world, according as the Empty takes up earthy particles in
was included or excluded in vapour. Perhaps it was owing
the conception. Including the to this fact that it was said to
Empty, it is called ri trav receive its light from the sun
without it, iXov (ri iKov, rtb (Diog. 145) whicli, according to
8ao, frequently occurs with the Posidonius in Plut. Fac. Lun.
Stoics). The Tray, it was said, 16, 12, p. 929, Cleomed. Met.
is neither material nor imma- p. 106, not only illuminates its
terial, since it consists of both. surface, but penetrates some
Plmt. C. Not. 1. c. depth. Cleomed. 100, believes
::
; ;;
:;

THE UNIVERSE. 205

the earth and from water.' With this process of Chap.


sustentation the motion of the stars is brought into
vm.
connection, their orbit extending over the space in
which they obtain their nutriment.^ Not only the
sun, but the moon also, was believed to be larger
than the earth.' Plato and Aristotle had already held

that, besides the light of the stars without anything "very


sun, it has also a fight of its peculiar in Stob. i. 448 ; 538
own. Pint. PI. ii. 15, 2 16, 1 ; I>wg.
;

'
Biog. 145; Stob. i. 532; 144; Cleomed. Meteor, i. 3.
538 ; 554 ; Floril. 17, 43 Pint. ; Eclipses are also discussed by
De Is. 41, p. 367 ; Sto. Eep. 39, Biog. 145 Stob. i. 538 560 ;
; ;

1 ;
Qu. Conv. viii. 8, 2, 4 Plac. ; Pint. Fac. Lun. 19, 12, p. 932 ;

ii. 17, 2; 20, 3; 23, 5 Galen, ; Plac. ii. 29, 6; Cleom.ed.pTp.WG


Hist. Phil. 14; Porphyr. Antr. and 115, nor is there anything
Nymph, c. 11 Cic. N. D. iii. ; remarkable. Quite in the or-
14, 37 ii. 15, 40
; 46, 118 Sen. ; ; dinary way are some observa-
Nat. Qu. vi. 16, 2 Heraclit. ; tions of Posidonius and Chry-
Alleg. Horn. c. 36, p. 74 and56, sippus given in Stob. i. 518;
p. 117; most of whom affirm b 165, c.
JtoAiZ. 3'a#. Isag. 132, ;

that the sun is sustained by


vapours from the sea, the moon

The information quoted from
Posidonius by Cleomed. Meteor,
by those of fresh water, and 51 ; Prod, in Tim. 277, B
the other stars by vapours from Straio, ii. 5, 14, p. 119 re-
the earth. The stars are also specting observations of Cano-
said to owe their origin to such bus have no bearing on our
vapours. Chrysippus, in Plut. present enquiry.
Sto. Kep. 41, 3, adds to the ' Stob. i. 554 (Plut. PI. ii.

passage quoted p. 161, 2 ; oi 3' 26, 1). This statement, how-


aarepes 4k toD
6a\d.a-inis fieri ever, appears only to be true of
Tl\lov avdTTTovTai. Plut. Ibid. 2 the sun, to which, indeed, it is
efiypvxov TjyeiTai rhv n^\iov, iripivov confined by Biog. 144. That
iina KOI yeyfvriiiei'ov 4k tjjj i.va- the sun is much larger than
Sv/uiffeas fls irvp ;uTa/3oAoi<(rrjs. the earth, Posidonius proved;
Id. C. Not. 46, 2, p. 1084 not only because its light ex-
yeyoyevat Se Koi rbv t^\iov ifi^uxof tends over the whole heaven,
\4yovffi ToO ir/pov fifraPdWovTos but alsobeoause of the spherical
tls irvp voep6ii. form of the earth's shadow in
^ Stob. i. 532 ; Cic. 1. c. eclipses of the moon. Biog.
Macrob. quoting
Sat. i. 23, 1. c. ;Macrob. Somn. i. 20
CleanthesandMacrobius Plut. ; Keracl. AUeg. Horn. c. 46
Plac. ii. 23, 5. Diogenes of Cleomed. Met. ii. 2. According
Apollonia had already expressed to Cleomed. p. 79, he allowed to
similar views. Further par- it an orbit 10,000 times as
ticulars as to the courses of the large as the circumference of
;

!S06 THE STOICS.

Ohap. that the stars are living rational divine beings ; and
VIII.
the same view was entertained by the Stoics, not
only because of the wonderful regularity of their
motion and orbits, but also from the very nature of
the material of which they consist.' The earth, like-
wise,, is filled by an animating soul ; or else how
could it supply plants with animation, and afiford

nutriment to the stars ? ^ Upon the oneness of the


soul, which permeates all its parts, depends, in the
opinion of the Stoics, the oneness of the universe.
(2) Me- Most thoroughly, however, did the and, Stoics
teorology.
in particular, Posidonius ^
devote themselves to in-

the earth, with a diameter of 54 ; Acad. ii. 37, 110: Porphyr.


four million stadia. The Stoic, 1. c.Ackill. Tat. Isag. o. 13,
;

in Cic. N. D. ii. 40, 103, only p. 134, A, Hence, in several of


calls the moon half that size ;
these passages, the sun is called
and Cleomed. p. 97, probably after Cleanthes and Chrysippus
following Posidonius, calls it a voiphv &vafi^a (or e^aju/tci) ck
considerably smaller than the daKda-frris.
earth. The other stars, ac- ' Sen. Nat. Qu. vi. 16, dis-

cording to Cleomed. p. 96, are cusses the point at length. See


some of them as large as, and also the quotations' on p. 144, 1,
others larger than the sun. from Oic. N. D. ii. 9, and on
Posidonius, according to PUn. p. 161, 1, from Diog. 147.
His. N. ii. 23, 85, estimated the Mog. vii.138, 152 and
moon's distance from the earth mentions a of his,
treatise
at two millions, and the sun's called fiereupoKayiKTj or juCTew-
distance from the moon at 500 po\oyiii^ ffToixeioKTis ; also, yii.
million stadia. He estimated 136, a treatise nepl nendpav. in
the earth's circumference at several books. Alexander, in
240,000, according to Cleomed. iSimpl. Phys. 64, 6, speaks of an
at 180,000 according to Htrabo, ^^yTjffis iJ.rewpo\oytKa>u, which,
li. 2, 2, p. 95. judging by the title, may be a
' Conf. Stoh. i. 66; 441; commentary on Aristotle's me-
618 ; 532 538 ; 554; Floril. 17,
; teorology. Geminus had made
43 Put. Sto. Kep. 39, 1 41,
; ; an extract from this book, a long,
2 ; c; Not. 46, 2 Plao. ii. 20,
; portion of which on the rela-
3 Diog. 146
; Pluedr. Nat. De.
; tion of astronomy and natural
{Philodem. irepl cutrEySedu) Col. science is there given. Whether
3 ; Oio. N. D. i. 14, 36 and 60 ;
these various titles really belong
ii. 15, 39 and 42 16, 43
; 21, ; to these diflerent treatisas is not
;;; ;

TEE UNIVERSE. 207

-Vestigating those problems, which may be summed Chap.


VIII.
up under the name of meteorology. This portion,
however, of their enquiries is of little value as illus-
trating their philosophical tenets. It may there-
fore suffice to mention in a note the objects which
it included, and the sources whence information may
be obtained.' The same treatment may apply to

clear. Posidonius is probably donius (further particulars in


the author of most of the later Schol. in Arat. v. 1091) con-
statements about the Stoic sidered them passing pheno-
meteorology. He appears also mena. Even Seneca declared
to be the chief authority for for the opinion that they are
Seneca's Naturales Qusestiones, stars. On the phenomena of
in which he is frequently named light and called iruyavl^i,
fire,
(i. 5, 10 13 ii. 26, i 64, 1
; ; ; SoKol, etc., see Arrian in Stab. i.
iv. 3, 2 vi. 21, 2
; 24, 6 vii. ; ; 584; Sen. Nat. Qu. i. 1, 14 15, ;

20, 2 ;4), particularly in his 4. On a4\tts, consult Biog. 153 ;


meteorological treatises. Sen. i. 15 ; on halo (Samj), Sen.
' On the Milky Way, which i. 2 ; Alem. Aphr. Meteorol.
Posidonius, agreeing with Aris- 116 ; on the rainbow, Siog.
totle, looked upon as a collec- 152 ; Sen. i. 3-8 ; on virg/B and
tion of fiery vapours, see Stoi. pa/rlielia, Sen. i. 9-13 ; Schol.
i. 676; Plvt. Plac. iii. 1, 10; in Arat. v. 880 (Posidonius)
Macrob. Somn. Scip. i. 15. On on storms, lightning, thunder,
the comets, which are explained summer lightning, cyclones,
in a similar way, Stob. i. 580 and siroccos, Stob. i. 596 ; 598
(Plac. 8. Whether the
iii. 2, (Plac. iii. 3, 4) Arrian, Ibid. ;

Diogenes mentioned here who 602 ; Sen. ii. 12-31 ; 51-58 (c.
looked upon comets as real 54, the view of Posidonius) ; ii,
stars is Diogenes the Stoic, or 1, 3 ; Diog. 163 ; on rain, sleet,
Diogenes of ApoUonia, is not hail, snow, Diog. 153 Sen. iv. ;

clear. The former is more 3-12 ;on earthquakes, Diog.


probable, Boethus having been 154 Plac. iii. 15, 2 Sen. vi.
; ;

just before mentioned) Arrian, ; 4-31 (particularly c. 16 21, 2) ;

in Stob. i. 584 JHoff. vii. 152


; also Strabo, ii. 3, 6, p. 102 on ;

and, particularly, Sen. Nat. Qu. winds, Plac. iii. 7, 2; Sen. v.


vii. We learn from the latter 1-17 Strabo, i. 2, 21, p. 29
;

that Zeno held (vii. 19-21 30, ; iii. 2, 5, p. 144 on waterspouts^


;

2), with Anaxagoras and De- Sen. iii. 1-26 the Nile floods,
;

mocritus, that comets are Ibid. iv. 1 ; Strabo, xvii. 1, 5, p.


formed by several stars uniting 790; Cleomed. Meteor, p. 32;
whereas the majority of the on tides, Strabo, i. 3, 12, p. 55 ;
Stoics and, amongst their iii. 3, 3, p. 153 ; 5, 8, p. 73
; on
number, Pansetius and Posi- seasons, p. Ill, 'J,.
;

208 TEE STOICS.

Chap, the few maxims laid down by the Stoics on the sub-
1_ ject of inorganic nature which have come down to
us.' Nor need we mention here the somewhat co*
pious writings of Posidonius,^ on the subjects of
geography, history, and mathematics.
(3) Plants Little attention was devoted by the Stoics to the

mil!""*' '^o'^ld of plants and animals. About this fact there


can be no doubt, since we neither hear of any trea-
tises by the Stoics on this subject, nor do they ap-
pear to have advanced any peculiar views. The most
prominent point is, that they divided all things in
nature into four classes the class of inorganic beings,

the class of plants, that of animals, and that of ra-


tional beings. In beings belonging to the first class

a simple quality {s^is) constitutes the bond of union


in those of the second class, a forming power {j^vats);
in those of the third class, a sgul ; and in those of the
fourth class, a rational soul.' By means of this divi-

' Thus colours are explained ixev efei SioiKehai rck Si ipisft, ri
as being irpuToi ff;t7jjLtaTiff/xol t^s Se &\6y{f ^vxV> "^^ ^* '^"^ XAyojr
8Xi)s (Stob. i. 364 ; Plac. i. 15, ix<>^<n> ""' Sidvoiav. Themist.
5) ; and sounds are spoken of De An. M. Awel. vi. 14
72, b ;

as undulations in the air by Philo, Qu. De. S. Immut. 298,


Plmt. Plac. iv. 19, 5 ; Siog. 158. D De Mundo, 1154, E Leg.
; ;

^ Conf Bake,
. Posidonii Alleg. 1091, D Ihoorrupt. M, ;

Rhod. Eeliquise, pp. 87-184 ; 947, A Platin. Enn. iv. 7, 8, p.


;

Muller, Fragm. Hist. Grasc. iii. 463, c, Bas. 861, Cr. (Otherwise
245. Clc. N. D. ii. 12, 33. See p.
' Sext. Math. ix. 81 : rSiy 146, 1). Eespecting the dif-
fivu/ievaiv (on fnaais see p. 103, ference of (piais and ifux^l, ^iJiris
1) traiid-raiv fi^v imh \jii\tis
Tck is said to consist of a moister,
?ffa>s avvix^'ra.i, tA Se Imi ipiffiui, colder, and denser irxeD/ia than
T^ Si uirb ^vxvs nal ejeus uiv ifiux'S; but, on this point, see
&s MBot Kal iiiXo, <j>i<rfas Si, Phit. Sto. Rep. 41, 1 ; Com.
KaBdrep ret (()i>Tck, ^vxvs Si ri Not. 46, 2 Galen, Hipp, et Plat.
;

C$a. Pint. Virt. Mor. o. 12, p. v. 3. Vol. v. 521. Qu. Animi


451 Kae6\ov Se tuv ivTav airol
: Mores, c. 4. Vol. iv. 783. In
TE </)a(ri Kol SriJ\.6v iariv Sti tA IHog. 139, ejis and vovs as the
,

THE UNIVERSE. 209

sion, the various branches of a science of nature


were Chap.
VIII.
mapped on a gradually-increasing deve-
out, based
lopment of the powers of life. But no serious at-
tempt was made by the Stoics to work out this
thought. With the single exception of man, we .

know exceedingly little of their views on organic


beings.'

highest and lowest links in the of sleep, death, and age in Pint.
series, are contrasted. IHd. Plac. V. 23, 4 ; 30, 5 ; the as-
156, there is a definition of sertion that animals are not
<\iiffis -nvp rexvLK^v dScp ^aSi^ov only deficient in reason (on
eis yeveaiv; and (148) another this point see PMt. Solert. An.
= e|ts i^ auTTis Kivovfihi) Kara 2, 9 ; 6, 1; H, 2, pp. 960, 963,
ffirep/jLariKobs \6yovs ci,iroT6\ov<rtl 967), but also (according to
TE (cal avvixfivaa ri ^| aurijj iv Chrysippus in Oaleti, Hippoc.
&ptfffji^yois ;^p(ifOs Koi Totavra et Plat. iii. 3 ; v. 1, 6. Vol. v.
Spacra acp' olav StireKplOT). It 309, 429, 431, 476) in emotions
hardly need be repeated that (or as Galen also says in Sviihs
the force is one and the same, and iTriBu/ila), even in man the
which at one time appears as emotions being connected with
fij, at another as <jii<ris. Conf. the rational soul. Posidonius,
Dioff. 138 Themist. 1. c. Sext.
; ; however, denied this statement
Math. ix. 84. ( Galen, p. 476), and Chrysippus
' The
belief that blood cir- believed that animals had a
culates in the veins, spiritus in Tiyeiiovmiv. QChaloid in Tim.
the arteries {Sen. Nat. Qu. ii. p. 148, b.) He even discovered
15, 1), which was shared by in the scent of dogs traces of
the Peripatetics, deserves to be an unconscious inference. Sext.
mentioned here, Sen. Nat. Qu. PjTrh. i. 69. See also p. 225,
ii. 15, 1 also the explanations
; 2.
''

210 TSE STOICS.

CHAPTER IX.

THE SirDT OF NATURE. MAN.

Chap. The stoic teaching becomes peculiarly interesting,


IX.
when it treats of Man and the line it here follows
;

A. The was decided by the tone of the whole system. On


soul.
(1) Ma- the one hand, the Stoic materialism could not fail
terialistic
to show itself most unmistakeably in the depart-
natti/re of
the soul. ment of anthropology ;on the other hand, the con-
viction that all actions must be referred to active
powers, and all the several active powers to one ori-
ginal power, could not be held without leading to a
belief in the oneness and in the regulating power of
the soul. Not only does it follow, as a corollary
from the materialistic view of the world, that the
soul must be in its nature corporeal, but the Stoics
took pains to uphold this view by special arguments.
Whatever, they said, influences the body, and is by
it influenced in turn, whatever is united with the
body and again separated from it, must be corporeal.
How, then, can the soul be other than corporeal ?

Cleanthes, in Nemes. Nat. a&na criifmrt


o-u/iircJirxei Se V
Horn. p. 33, and Tert. De An. c. ^x^ TV irdiiaTi voaowri (col reix-

5 : o65>' aadifiaTov avfiiiiax^^ voiiivif Kol th aSifui rfi ^xS


tr<i)uaTt oirSe daivjUc^T^ ffw/xa a\\^ oXffXwofiiviis yovv ipvBphy yfycTOi
;

THE SOUL: ITS NATURE. 211

Whatever has extension in three dimensions is cor- Chap.


IX.
poreal and this is the case with the soul, since it
;

extends in three directions over the whole body.'


Moreover, thought and motion are due to animal
life.^ Animal life is nurtured and kept in health by
the breath of life.' Experience also proves that mental
qualities are propagatedby natural generation, and
that they must be consequently connected with a
corporeal substratum.* As, therefore, the mind is
nothing but fiery breath, so the human soul is de-
scribed by the Stoics sometimes as fire, sometimes as
breath, at other times, more accurately, as warm
breath, diffused throughout the body, and forming a
bond of union for the body,^ in the very same way

Kal <l>o$ovii4v7}s wxp^v ffu^ia &pa


' yiv6^9a, Kari rh trw/xa, aWa. koX
7} Tpuxh- Chrysippus in Nemes. Karh. T^y ^^vxhv, rois irdBeffi, rots

p. 34 ; b &iyaT6s iffri xwptcjttbs ^fleci, Tois Sta94ire(n ' ffwfiaros Se


^vy^TJs avh (Ti^fiaTos * ovS^v Se rh SfAOiov Kal aj/ifioiov, ov^l Se
atrii/xaTOV Airi a^fiUTOS x'^'P^C^Tat

aadfiaTov ffufia fipa ri i//ux^* The

ovSe y&p itpdiTTerai (Tii^fiaTos atr^- same in Tertullian, 1. c.


fiarov 7} 5e ij/ux^ Kai ^(piirTerai ' Chrysippus in Galen, Hipp.

Kal xwpi ^6To( Tov ffdfiuTOs (Tw/xa ' et Plat. iii. 1. Vol. v. 287 ri :

Spa ri i^ux^. The same is said


by Tertullian. cuvex^s -navrX rtf frdfiaTL SirjKOv.
' Nemes. Nat. Horn. c. 2, p. Zeno. Maorob. Somn.i. 14 Zenon :

30. [dixit animam] coneretum eor-


^ Diog. 157; ae. N. D. ii. pori spiritum . . Boethos (pro-.

14, 36. bahly the Stoic, not the Peripa-


' Zeno, in Tertull. 1. c, and tetic of the first century, is
very nearly the same in Chalcid. meant) ex aere et igne [se. con-
in Tim. p. 306 Meurs. Quo : stare]. Diog. in Oalen,ii. 8, p.
digresso animal emoritur con- ; 282 rh klvovv tov di'dpunov rhs
:

sito autem spiritu digresso Kara irpoaipeffiv Kivfiffeis ij/yxttt^

animal emoritur : ergo consitus ris ^ffriv avaBv}jiia(ni. Cie. Nat.


spiritus corpus est, consitus D. iii. 14, 36 ; Tusc. i. 9, 19
autem spiritus anima est ergo : 18, 42 ; Zeno considers the soul
corpus est anima. Chrysippus to be fire ; Pansetius believes
in Chalcid. 1. c. that burning air. Diog. L.
it is
Cleanthes, in Nemes. 1. o. vii. 156, on the authority o
32 ov \i.6yov 'dfioioi rots yofevtri
: Zeno, Antipater, Posidouius,
2
^

212 TEE STOICS.

Chap. that the soul of the world is diffused throughout


IX.
the world, and forms a bond of union for the world.'
This warm breath was believed to be connected with
the blood ; and hence the soul was said to be fed by-

vapours from the blood, just as the stars are fed by


vapours from the earth.
The same hypothesis was also used to explain the
orig;in of the soul. One part of the soul was believed
to be transmitted to the young in the seed.^ From

says that it is irwCfia ffifi^vrov, 'Clm/sippus. See previous


TTceu/ia ^v9epfiov. Eel. i. Stob. note. This diffusion is further
796 (^Plut. Plac. iv. 3, 3). Cor- explained Ijy Iamb, in Stob. Eel.
nut. N. D. p. 8 ko! yap oi fiii4-
: i. 870 and 874, Themist. De
Tepat }pvxctl irvp eitrt. Ar. Didy- Anim. f. 68, a, Plotin. iv. 7, 8,
mus, in Hus. Pr. Ev. xv. 20, 1 : p. 463, c, as being xpaa-is, i.e. an
Zeno calls the soul ata-Bvffiv t) intermingling of elements. That
avaBvfitairiv (should be oiVflijTi- the soul forms the bond of
K^v vivaBvuiturtVf conf, 2 and union for the body, and not
Ps. Pint. Vit. Horn. c. 127 : tV vice versS, was a point vindi-
^vxhy 01 STwi'Kol Spi^ourat vj/eO^ua cated by the Stoics against the
ffufiipvh Kol ayaOviilatriv aiffBri- Epicureans. Posid. in AcMl.
TiK^v avaTTTOfievTiv airh tS>v 4v Tat. Isag. o. 13, p. 133, E ; Sext.
(TiifmTt Longin. in Eus.
iypav). Math. ix. 72.
Ibid. 21,1 and 3. Alex. De An. Galen. Hippocr. et Plat. ii.
'^

127, b 01 inrh ttjs ctoSs Trv^vfia


:
8, p. 282, on the authority of
auT^V XeyofTes eTvai ffuyKeifj.ev6v Zeno, Cleanthes, Chrysippus,
TTws eK T iruphs KoX a.4pos. Since, and Diogenes ; Longin. in Eas.
however, every irvcC/na is not a Pr. Bv. XV. 21, 3 M. Aurel. v. ;

soul, a soul is stated to be 33 vi. 16 ; Ps. PUt. Vit. Horn.


;

TrreE/jo iriis exo" {Plotin. Enn. 127.


iv. 7, 4, p. 458, B) and the dis- ;
^ Zeno described the seed as
tinctive quality of the soul- TT^ey^a juefl' vypov ^uxvs fJ-^pos Kol
element is its greater warmth aTr6criTa(r^a . . . fiiyi^a tuv tJjs
and rarity. See Plvt. Sto. Eep. ^vxvs lifpSiv (Arius Didymus, in
41, 2, p. 1052 Chrysippus con-
: jEus. Pr. Ev. XV. 20, 1), or as
siders the ^vxh to be apai6Tepoii ffifiixiyfut ttal K^pofffia rihv t^s
irpev/jia r^s (piKTeaii Kol XeirTop^pi- ifiux^s Swdfieav (Pint. Coh. Ir.
(TTspov. Similarly, Galen,, Qn. 15). Similarly Chrysip. in
An. Mores, c. 4. Vol. iv. 783 : Dioff. ,159, Conf. I'ertullian, De
The Stoics say that both (piiris An. c. 27. According to Sphserxis,
and iuxh is irueviM, but that the in Diog. 159, the seed is formed
neuiw. is thick and cold in by separation from all parts of
(pvffis, dry and warm in ^vx'^- the body, and can consequently
TRB SOUL: ITS PARTS. 213

the part so transmitted there arises, bv development Chap.


"

within the womb, first the soul of a plant ; and this

becomes the soul of a living creature after birth by


the action of the outer air.' This view led to the
further hypothesis that the seat of the soul must be
in the breast, not in the brain ; since not only breath
and warm blood, but also the voice, the immediate
expression of thought, comes from the breast.^
Nor is this further hypothesis out of harmony (2) Divi-

with the notions otherwise entertained by them as to ^""/"^^''^

produce all, as Democritus had brain the seat of the soul, in


already said. Pansetius (in Cio. proof of which they appealed
Tuso. i. 31, 79) proves, from to the story of the birth of
the mental similarity between Pallas. Sea^. Math. ix. 119;
parents and children, that the Diog. in Plusdr. Fragm. De
soul comes into existence by Nat. De. col. 6. Conf. Knsche,
generation. For the mother's Forschungen, i. 488, and Chry-
share in producing the soul, see sip. in QaUn, 1. c. iii. 8, p. 349.
Ar. Did, I. 0. See above p. It appears, however, from Galen,
127, 5. 1. c.i. 6, ii. 2 and 5, iii. 1, pp.

' Pint. Sto. Eep. 41, 1 and


8, 185, 214, 241, 287, TeHull. De
p. 1052 ;C. Not. 46, 2, p. 1084. An. c. 15, that the most distin-
De Primo Frig. 2, 5, p. 946 oi ; guished Stoics Zeno, Chrys-
'S.Tia'iKoX KoX Tb TTVet/jLta \iyovffiv ippus, Diogenes, a,nd ApoUo-
iv rois ffd}^a,tTi Twc ^fii^wv Ty
dorus decided in favour of the
Trepuj/tJ^et tTTOixovtrdai KaX ixerafidK- heart. The chief proof is, that
\ojf iK <pia'ea>s '^eveffdai ^vxh^. the voice does not come from
Similarly, Plotin. Enn. iv. 7, 8, the hollow of the skull, but
p. 463, c ; Conf. Bippolyt. Ee- from the breast. Chrysippus
fut. Hser. c. 21, p. 40 Tertull. ; was aware of the weakness of
De An. c. 25. Plutarch (Plac. this proof, but still did not
V. 16, 2 ; 17, 1 ; 24, 1) draws shrink from using it. Galen,
attention to the inconsistency 1. c. p. 254, 261. At the same
of saying that the animal soul, time, he also appealed to the
which is warmer and rarer than fact (ii. 7, 268 iii. 1, 290, c. 5,
;

the vegetable soul, has been 321, c. 7, 335, 343 iv. 1, 362)
;

developed thereout by cooling that, by universal assent, sup-


and condensation. ported by numerous passages
2 On this point, the Stoics from the poets, the motions of
were not altogether agreed. the will and the feelings pro-
Some (not all, as Plut. PI. Phil, ceed from the heart.
iv. 21, 5, asserts) made the
214 THE STOICS.

Chap, the nature of man. Plato and Aristotle had already


IX.
fixed on the heart as the central organ of the lower
powers, having assigned the brain to reason, with
the view of distinguishing the rational from the
mere animal soul.' When, therefore, the Stoics as-
similated man's rational activity to the activity of
the senses, deducing both from one and the same
source, it was natural that they would depart from
Aristotle's view. Accordingly, the various parts of
the soul were supposed to discharge themselves from
their centre in the heart into the several organs, in
the form of atmospheric-currents. Seven such parts
were enumerated, besides the dominant part or
reason, which was also called '^ysfioviKov, Biavo-
TjriKov, Xoyia-TiKov, or XoyLcr/Mos. These seven parts
power of reproduction,
consist of the five senses, the
and the power of speech;^ and, following out their
view of the close relation of speech and thought,'
' Aristotle had assigned no Dioff.110 and 157 ; Porphyr.
particulai organ of the body to and lamblich. in i^ob. 1. 836,
reason. 874, and 878 ; Chaleid. in Tim;
* Plut. Plac. iv. 4, 2. Ibid. 307 ; Nicomachns, in lamll.
c. 21 : The Stoics consider the Theol. Arith. p. 50. But there
TiyeiioviKhv to be the highest part 'was no universal agreement
of the soul it begets the (par-
; among the Stoics on this sub-
Tojiai, ffvyKaToBeiriis, ala0iiirfis, ject. According to Tertull. De
and 6p/ial, and is by them called An. 14, Zeno only admitted
Xoyurji6s; from it the seven three divisions of the soul,
divisions of the soul reach to whilst some among the later
the body, like the arms of a Stoics enumerated as many as
cuttle-fish, and are therefore ten ; Pansetius only held six,
collectively defined as TrveS/io and Posidonius went still fur-
SiareTj'oj' airh rov riy^ixoyiKov ther away from the view cur-
(fiexpis 6(p6a\fiay, Htuv, /hvk- rent among the
Stoics. The re-
rfipuiv, y\d>Tr-ns, itri^aveias, irapv- marks of Stob. 1. 828, probably
trrdTuv, Kpdpvyjos yXdiTTris Ka.1 refer to the Peripatetic Aristo.
Tuv olxeiaiv bpyavav). Galen, ' See p. 73, 2.
1. 0. iii. 1, 287. See p. 215, 2 ;
THE SOUL, 215

great importance was attached to the power of Chap.


IX.
speech.^ At the same time, the Stoics upheld the
oneness of the substance of the soul with greater
vigour than either Plato or Aristotle had done.
Eeason, or to ^ysfioviKov, is with them the primary
power, of which all other powers are only parts, or
derivative powers.'* Even feeling and desire are
derived from it, in direct contradiction to the teach-
ing of Plato and Aristotle;' and this power was

' Conf Clecmth. Hynm. 4


. : et operffi . . . non enim mem-
yap y^yos
e/c <rov icrfihf irjs fiiftTjfia bra smit snbstantiee animalis,
Kax^vres sed ingenia (capacities). Iambi,
fiovvoi, 3(ro ^dei re koL epvei i/t^t* in Stob. i. 874 The powers of :

^irl yaiay. the soul bear, according to the


- See p. 214, 2 and Chrys. Stoics, the same relation to the
in Galen, 1. c. iii. 1, p. 287. soul that qualities have to the
Conf. p. 211, 5 rairris oZv [t^s
: substance and their difference
;

i^ux^s] Tuv fiepwv eKiiffTtp Siare- is partly owing to the diffusion


ray^4iov \<i3v~\ ixoplcj), rb StTJKOp of the nveip.a.ra, of which they
ouTTJs els r^f rpa^eiav otpn]plav consist, in different parts of
^itiVTiv eivoUj rb 5k els 6^9d\fiohs the body, partly to the union of
ifiv, K.T.\. Kol T-b els Spxeis, several qualities in one subject-
eTep6p Tiv' ^X"*' ToiovTov \6yoyj matter, the latter being neces-
tnrepfiaTiKbv, els t Se trvfjL^diveL sary, for %yenovmbv to include
irdvra Toyra, 4f ttJ KapSl^ elvai, ^avTaffia^ (ruyKarddeffiSf opy.^,
fiepos %v avTiis Tb TiyefiovntSv, and \6yos.

Plmt. Plac. iv. 4, 2 tov iiye- : Flut. Virt. Mort. c. 3, p.
lioyiKov dcp' ov lavra irivTa eirne- 441, speaking of Zeno, Aristo,
raxrai \_ = TaTOi\ 5iq; tuv omeitav and Chrysippus vojii^ovinv oux :

opyavwv irpocrtpepvs rais tov voKi- eivai rb vaBriTiKbv koX &\Qyov Sia-
ToSos irheKTivais. Conf. Sext. (l>op^ TlVl Koi IpVffet y^VXVS TOV
Math. Lx. 102. Alex. Aphr. KoytKov SiaKeKpifievoVf kWa t6
(De An. 146) therefore denies avTb TTJs ^vxvs fiepoSj t 5^ Ka^
the Stoical assertion, that the A.ou<rt Stdvotav Koi TiyeiioviKbv,
xfivxtKii Simiits is only one, and Zi6\ov Tpeird/J-evoy Koi fieTa^dWov
tliat every activity of the ev T6 Tots Trddeffi Kol tclIs Korb.
soul is only the action of the e^ip fl Btddeaiv /A6Toj8o\a7s KaKiav
wijs exov 7iyefj.oyiK6v. Conversely Te yiveo'Oai Kol apeT^p Kal fiTi^ep
TertulUan, De An. 14, speaking ^X^^^ &^oyop ip eavT$, Plac.
quite after the manner of a Phil. iv. 21, 1. Galen, 1. c. iv.
Stoic, says: Hujusmodi autem 1, 364
p. Chrysippus some-
:

non tam partes animae habe- times speaks as if he admitted


buntnr, quam vires et efficacise a distinct Sipaitis ^iri9u/i7)TiKi) or
:

216. THE STOICS.

Chap. declared to be the seat of personal identity, a point


IX.
on -which former philosophers had refrained from
expressing any opinion,'
B. The in- The individual soul bears the same relation to
dividual
soul and the soul of the universe that a part does to the
the soul of 'vrhole The human soul is not only a part, as are all
t?ie uni-
verse. other living powers, of the universal power of life,

but, because it possesses reason, it has a special rela-


tionship to the Divine Being * a relationship which
BviioeiS'fis ; at other times, as if spiritus sedet ... in unoquo-
he denied latter is
it. The que virorum bonorum, quis Deus
clearly his meaning. Ibid. v. incertum est, habitat Deus. Id.
6, 476 6 Se XphffvK-Kos ohQ^ erepov
; Bp. 66, 12 Ratio autem nihil
:

sJuBU vofxi^ei 7h vaBjiTiKhv ttjs ^v- aliud est quam in corpus hu-
XVs Tov hoyKTTiKov Kai Tuv aK6yc0v manum pars divini spiritus
Cvuv ^tpaipeirat Tct irdBTf, See p. mersa. Consequently, reason,
209, 1. Iamb, in StoK Eel. i. thought, and virtue are of the
890; IHoff. vii. 159. Orig. c. same nature in the human soul
Gels. V. 47 robs a-vh ttJS ffroas
: as in the soul of the universe,
apvovfievovs rh rpifjiepes Trjs ^uxv^. as Iambi, in Stol. Eel. i. 886,
Posidonius (in Galen, 1. c. 6, states as a Stoic view. From
476) endeavours to prove that this relationship to God, Posi-
Cleanthes held a different view, donius deduces in a well-known
by a passage in which he con- simile (see p. 84, 1) the soul's
trasts Sujuij with A6yos but capacity for studying nature,
this is confounding a rhetorical and Cicero (De Leg. i. 8, 24)
flourish with a philosophic the universality of a belief in
view. God. All souls, as being parts
Chrys. (in Galen, ii. 2, of the divine mind, may be col-
215) ovTuis Se Kai rh ^yij Ksyoix^y
: lectively regarded as one soul
Kara toSto (the primary power or reason. Marc. Aurel. ix. 8 :

in the breast) SemvivTes ouroiis is ft^v Tck &KQya, ^Qa fiia i^x^
ec T(p airatpaiveffSat t^v htivoiav SppnTai" ci'j Si Tck Ao7iKt fila
clvai, \oyiKii ^x^ p.fp,epuTTai. xii. 30
' Cleanthes, v. <^m TjKiov, Kttv SteipTjTat toIxois,
4, p. 215, 1. %v
Mpictet. Diss. i. 14, 6 oi ^ux'^ : Upeffty, &Wois fivplots fiia oiiffia
'

ffvva<peis Tq? Be^ fire aiiTov fi6pia Koiv^, Khe StelpyriTai iblas irOLois
oZa-ca Kal a-iroa-irdfffiaTtt. Id. ii. (rd/jxairi fivplots- fila ^todl, ictti'

8, 11. M. Aurel. ii. 4, v. 27, ^iffetxi SiiiprfTat fivplais Kal iSlats


calls the soul puipos ijr6pf>oia, irepiypa^ats. This oneness, how-
hir6aTrairiia flcou; and, xii, 26, ever, must, as the comparison
even calls the human xoOs Bi6s. shows, be understood in the
Sen. Ep. 41, 2 : Sacer intra nos sense of the Stoic realism the :
THE SOUL OF THE UNIVERSE. 217

becomes closer in proportion as we allow greater play Chap.


'

to the divine element in ourselves, i. e. to reason.'


On this very account, however, the soul cannot escape
the law of the Divine Being, in the shape of gene-
ral necessity, or destiny. It is a mere delusion to
suppose that the soul possesses a freedom indepen-
dent of the world's course. The human will, like
everything else in the world, isbound into the in-
dissoluble chain of natural causes, and that irrespec-
tively of our knowing by what causes the will is
decided or not. Its freedom consists only in that,
instead of being ruled from without, it obeys the call
of its own nature, external circumstances concurring.^
To this power of self-determination, however, the
greatest value is attached. Not only are our actions due
to it to such an extent that only because of it can they
be considered ours,' but even our judgments are, as

the Stoics thought, dependent on it. The soul itself


inclining towards truth or error, our convictions are
quite as much in our power as our actions : both
are alike the necessary result of our will. And just
as the individual soul does not possess activity inde-
pendently of the universal soul, no more can the
individual soul escape the law of destiny. It, too,

at the end of the world's course, will be resolved


into the primary substance, into the Divine Being,

universal soul, in the sense of bonus, magnus, a Deus in cor-


etherial substance, is the ele- pore humane hospitans.
* Further particulars,
ment of which individual souls p. 174,
consist. See also Ma/rc. Awrel. 180, 189.
viii. 54. ' See p. 179.
'
In this sense. Sen. Ep. 31, < See p. 88, 1.
11, calls the animus rectus,
;

THE STOICS.

Chap. The only point alxiut which the Stoics were unde-
IX.
cided was, whether all souls would last until that
time as separate souls, which was the view of Clean-
thes, or only the souls of the wise, as Chrysippus
held.'

Diog. 156
' Plwt. N. P.
; to the ether, and there, accord-
Suav. Viv. 31, 2, p. 1107 Plac. ; ing to M. Aurelius, united to
iv. 7. 2 Ar. Didymus, in Eus.
; the ainp^riKhs \6yos ruv Z\tav,
Prsep. Bv. xv. 20, 3 Sen. Con- ; it lives, according to the com-
sol, ad Marc. o. 26, 7 Ep. 102, mon view, until the end of the
;

22 117, 6 Cio. Tusc. i. 31, 77.


; ; world. The ether is also al-
Seneca (ad Polyb. 9, 2 Bp. 65, lotted to the blessed, for their
;

24 71, 16 36, 9, and in Ter-


; ; residence, by Oio. Tuse. i. 18,
tnll. De An. o. 42 Kesurr. 42 Laotant. Inst. vii. 20; Phct.
; ;

Cam. c. 1) and M. Aure- N. P. Suav. Vivi. 31, 2, p. 1107.


lius (iii. 3 vii. 32 viii. 25, 58)
; ; The souls, as Cicero remarks,
are only speaking kot' li,v9fuTrov, penetrating the thick lower air,
in seeming to doubt a future mount to heaven, xmtil they
life after death, in order to dis- reach an atmosphere (the juncti
pel the fear of death in every ex anima tenui et ardore solis
case. It is, however, a mistake temperate ignes) congenial with
of Tiedeinann (Sto. Phil. ii. 155) their own nature. Here they
to suppose that they, in many naturally stop, and are fed by
passages {Sen. Bp. 71, 102, M. the same elements as the stars.
Aw. ii. 17 v. 4, 13), supposed According to Chrysippus (in
;

the immediate dissolution of Eustath. on II. xxiii. 65), they


the soul after death. It is, on there assume the spherical
the contrary, clear, from M. shape of the stars. According
Awel. iv. 14, 21, that the soul to Tertull. De An. 54, conf.
lives some time after death, Liican. Phars. ix. 5, their place
and is not resolved into the is imder the moon. Zeno, in
world-soul till the general con- speaking of the islands of the
flagration. But even this is blest (Zact. Inst. vii. 7, 20),
a variation from the ordinary probably only desired to enlist
view of the Stoics. According popular opinion in his own
to Seneca (Consol. ad Marcum) favour. The souls of the foolish
the souls of the good, as in the and bad also last some time
doctrine of purgatory, undergo after death only, as being
;

a purification, before they axe weaker, they do not last until


admitted to the ranks of the the end of the world {Ar. Did.
blessed and here this purifica- Thendm-et. Cur. Gr. Affec. v. 23,
;

tion is no doubt required on p. 73) and meantime, as it is ;

physical grounds. When the distinctly asserted by Sen. Ep.


soul is purified, both in sub- 117, 6, Tertullian, and Lactan-
stance and morals, it rises up tius, they are punished in the
FREEDOM AND IMMORTALITY. 219

The effects of the Stoic principles appear unmis- chap.


takeably in the above statements. They, however, ^'
pervade the whole body of the Stoical views on c. Free-

man.' From one


point of view, the theory of ne- tmmor-
cessity, and the denial of everlasting life after death, *^%-

seem quite unintelligible in a system the moral tone


of which is so high yet the connection of these
;

theories with the Stoic ethics is very intimate.


These theories commended themselves to the Stoics,
as they have done in later times to Spinoza and
Schleiermacher, because they corresponded with their
fundamental view of morality, according to which
the individual can only be regarded as the instru-
ment of reason in general, as a dependent portion
of the collective universe. Moreover, since the
Stoics admitted a future existence
of limited, but
yet indefinite, length the same practical results
followed from their belief as from the current belief
in immortality. The statements of Seneca,^ that
this life is a prelude to a better ; that the body is

a lodging-house, from which the soul will return to


its own home ; his joy in looking forward to the day
which will rend the bonds of the body asunder,

nether world. Tertullian in mam hominis magno pondere


placing a portion of the souls extriti permanere non posse et
of the foolish in the region of statim spargi, quia non f uerit
the earth, and there allowing illi exitus liber was not re-

them to be instructed by the quired by their principles, as


wise, is probably referring to Seneca already observed. It
the puriticatiou mentioned by belongs, in fact, only to indivi-
S'eneca. For the supposed trans- dual members of that School,
migration of souls see p. 166, 2. ^ Conf. Sam; Seneca nnd
The peculiar notion men-
' Paulus in Hilgenfeld's Zeit-
tioned by Seneca (Ep. 57, 7) as schrift fiir wissensch. Theol. i.

belonging to the Stoics ani- 2, 221.


:

220 THE STOICS.

Chap. which he, in common with the early Christians, calls


IX.
the birthday of eternal life
;
' his description of the
peace of the eternity ther6 awaiting us, of the free-
dom and bliss of the heavenly life, of the light of
knowledge which will there be shed on all the secrets
of natxu:e ; ^ his language on the future recognition
and happy society of souls made perfect ; ^ his see-
ing in death a great day of judgment, when sentence

Ep. 102, 22 Cum venerit


' : Alius tuus terminos intra quos
dies qui mixtum hoc divini
ille, servitur excepit ilium magna
:

humanique seoernat, corpus et aeterna pax. No fear or care,


hie, ubi iuveni, relinquam, ipse no desire, envy, or compassion
me Dis reddam per has . . . disturbs him. IHd. 26, 5.
mortalis vite moras illi meliori Consol. ad Polyb. 9, 3, 8 : Nunc
vitEe longiorique proluditur. As animus fratris mei velut ex
a child in its mother's womb, diutino oarcere emissus, tandem
sic per hoc spatium, quod ab sui juris et arbitrii, gestit et
infantia patet in senectutem, rerum naturae spectaculo fruitur
in alium maturescimus partum. . . fruitur nunc aperto et
.

All we possess, and the body libero ccelo et nunc illic


. . .

itself, is only the baggage, libere vagatux omniaque rerum


which we neither brought into naturae bona cum summa vo-
the world, nor can carry away luntate perspicit. Ep. 79, 12 :
with us. Dies iste, quem tan- Tunc animus noster habebit,
quam extremum reformidas, quod gratuletur sibi, cum emis-
aeterni natalis est. Ep. 120, sus tenebris . .
his totum .

14 The body is breve hos-


: diem admiserit, et ccelo red-
pitium, which a noble soul does ditus sue fuerit. Ep. 102, 28 :

not fear to lose. Scit enim, quo Aliquando naturae tibi arcana
exiturus sit, qui, unde venerit, retegentur, discutietur ista
meminit. Conf. Ep. 65, 16. caligo et lux undique clara
^ Consol. ad Marc. 24, 3 percutiet, which Seneca then
Imago dumtaxat fllii tui periit further expands.
. .ipse quidem seternus me-
. ' In Consol. ad Marc. 25, I,

liorisque nunc status est, de- Seneca describes how, the time
spoliatus oneribus alienis et of purification ended, the de-
sibi relictus. The body is only ceased one inter felices currit
a vessel, enveloping the soul in animas (the addition excepit :

darkness nititur iUo, unde


: ilium ccetus sacer Hanse rightly
dimissus est ibi ilium seterna ; treats as a gloss) and how his
requies mauet. Tbid. 26, 7 Nos : grandfather shows him the hall
quoque f elices animae et seternfe of heaven. Ibid. 26, 3.
sortitse. Ibid. 19, 6 : Excessit
:

FREEDOM AND IMMORTALITY. 221

will be pronounced on every one ;


' his making Chap.
IX.
the thought of a future life the great stimulus to
moral conduct here ;
^ even the way in which he
consoles himself for the destruction of the soul by
the thought that it will live again in another form
hereafter ' all contain nothing at variance with
the Stoic teaching, however near they may approach
to Platonic or even Christian modes of thought.*

' Bp. 26, 4: Velut adpro- are employed for fresh bodies.
pinquet experimentum et ille Accordingly, the passage just
latiirus sententiam de omnibus quoted, and also Ep. 71, 13,
annis meis dies quo, re-
. . . must refer to the physical side
motis strophis ac fuois, de me of death, or else to the return
judicaturus sum. Compare the of personality after the con-
hora decretoria, Ep. 102, 24. flagration of the world.
2 Bp. 102, 29: Hsec oogi- Besides
the definitions of
tatio (that of heaven and a oiiffB^ais in Diog. 52, and the
future life) nihil sordidum remark that impressions are
animo subsidere sinit, nihil made on the organs of sense,
humile, nihilcrudele. Deos but that the seat of feeling is
rerum omnium esse testes ait in the riyeiioviKhy (Phit. Plac. iv.
illis nos adprobari, illis in 23, 1), the following statements
futurum parari jubet et seterni- may be mentioned In the pro-:

tatem menti proponere. cess of seeing, the SpanKiv


= Ep. 36, 10 Mors : in- . . . TTvevfitt, coming into the eyes
termittit vitam, non eripit from the TiysfioviKbv, gives a
veniet iterum qui nos in lucem spherical form to the air before
reponat dies, quem multi re- the eye, by virtue of its tov^kt)
cusarent, nisi oblitos reduoeret. Klrqais (on t6vos, see p. 128, 2),
Sed postea diligentius dooebo and, by means of the sphere of
omnia, quEe videntur perire, air, comes in contact with
mutari. Mqm animo debet things ; and since by this pro-
rediturus exire. The souls can- cess rays of light emanate from
not return, according to the the eye, darkness must be
Stoic teaching, until after the visible. Diog. 158 Alex. ApTi.
;

general conflagration and that ; De Auim. 149 Pint. Plac. iv.


;

is on the supposition that the 15. The process of hearing is


same persons will be found in due to the spherical undula-
the ful ure world as in the pre- tions of the air, which com-
sent. See p. 166, 2. As long municate their motion to the
as the latter lasts, the better ear. Mog. 158 Phit. Plac. iv.
;

souls continue to exist, and 19, 5. On the voice, called also


only the particles of the body (jiavaev, see Plut. Plac. iv. 20, 2
;
222 THE STOICS.

Chap. Seneca merely expanded the teaching of his School


L_ in one particular direction, in which it harmonises
most closely with Platonism ; and, of all the Stoics,
Seneca was the most distinctly Platonic.
Excepting the two points which have been dis-
cussed at an earlier time,' and one other point re-
lating to the origin of ideas and emotions, which will
be considered subsequently, little is on record re-
lating to the psychological views of the Stoics.

21, 4 ; Diog. 55, and above fi^vov, Iambi, (in Stoh. Eel. i.

p. 214, 2 ; 74, 5. Disease is 922), who, however, does not


caused by changes in the iri/e5/io, mention the Stoics by name. In
Diog. 158 ; sleep ixXvofiivou toG the case of man, the ex-
a!<r6r)TiKoS rdyuu irepl ri iiyfiiovi- tinguishing of the power of
Khy, Diog. 158 ; Tertull. De An. life is only a liberation of
43 ; and in a similar way, death rational souls.
iK\voiifvov 70V t6pov Kttl irupie- '
Page 77.
;

ETHIC OF TRE STOICS. 223

CHAPTEE X.

ETHICS. THE GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF THE STOIC


ETHICS. ABSTRACT THEOET OF MORALITY.

Whateter attention the Stoics paid to the study of Chap.


"

nature and to logic, the real kernel of their system


lies, as has heen already observed, in their Ethics
even natural science, that ' most divine part of philo-
sophy,' being only pursued as an intellectual prepa-
ration for Ethics. In the domain of Ethics the true
spirit of the Stoic system may therefore be expected
to appear, and it may be anticipated that this sub-
ject will be treated by them with special care. Nor
is this expectation a vain one ; for here the springs

of information ilowing freely give ample data re-


specting the Stoic doctrine of morality. Never-
theless, "respecting the formal grouping of these data
only vague and contradictory statements are forth-
coming. Moreover, the Stoics appear to have been
so unequal in their treatment, and so little afraid of
repetitions, that it is hardly possible to obtain a
complete survey of their whole system by following
any one of the traditional divisions.'

^
The chief passage in Diog. Kbv fiepos Trjs ^ihoao^ias Siaipov-
vii. 84, is as follows : ri> Se ijBi- aiv its tc rhv ite/jI ipftTis xal eij
224 THE STOICS.

Chap. Proceeding to group the materials in such a way


X.
as to give the clearest insight into the peculiarities

Thv Trepl ayoBiav Kal KaKSiv tStcov third of Epictetus (which, ac-
Kal rhy irepl iraduv Kal wepl itper^s cording to what follows, rather
KaX tcepl t4\ovs Trepi re t^? irpd^ryis refers to the critical confirma-
a^ias Kal ray Trpd^euu Kai irepi tuv tion of moral principles not
KadriKSpTCoy trpoTponSiv re Kal airo- specially mentioned by Dio-
Tpoiruv. Kal oi^7(a S' viro^laipovffiv genes), but rather with his first
01 irepl Xp^ffLiriroif Kai ^ hpx^^fllJ^ov division treating of 6pe|Eij and
Kal Z^j/wi^a Thv Tapffia Kal 'AiroA- 4KK\i(reis. Stobseus again differs
\6Stopov Kal Aioyeyriv Kal 'Aj^^- from either. In his survey of
varpov Kal TlotreiS^vioy 6 fi^y ' the Stoic ethics (Bel. ii. c. 5),
yhp KiTTieiis Z^ij'coj' Kal 6 K\eiv6ris he first, p. 90, treats of what is
&s ttv apxaiSrepoi a(pe\ea'Tpov good, evil, and indifferent, of
ireplTuv irpayfiiriDv 5ieKa$ov. what is desirable and de-
There may be doubts as to the testable, of the end-in-chief,
punctuation, and, consequently, and of happiness, in this sec-
as to the sense, of the first sen- tion discussing at length the doc-
tence; but the fonn of ex- trine of virtue. He then goes on,
pression seems to imply that p. 158, to consider the KaBrixov,
the five first portions contain the impulses, p. 166, and the
main divisions, and the six emotions (irii97), as being one
following subdivisions. The kind of impulse), appending
ethics of Chrysippus and his thereto, p. 186, a discussion on
followers would therefore be friendship ; and, concluding,
divided into the following main p. 192 to 242, with a long trea-
divisions irepl dpfiys, irepl ^yaSuv
: tise on ivepytifiara (KOTopfliil-
Kal KaKtav,
Trepl iraQStv but it ] the
juara, a/jLapriinaTa, ouSerepa),
would be hard to assign to these greater portion of which is de-
divisions their respective sub- voted to describing the wise
divisions. The statement of man and the fool. Turning to
Mpictetns, Diss. iii. 3, agrees in Sen. Ep. 95, 65, it is stated, on
part with this division. He dis- the authority of Posidonius, that
tinguishes in his introduction not only praeceptio, but also
to virtue three t6ttoi b Trepl ras : suasio, consolatio,and exhorta-
6p4^eLs Kal Tcfcs iKK\i{rets, called tio, and, moreover, causaru^i
also 6 irepl TO TrdOn d Trepl t&s ; inquisitio (which, however, can
dpju^s Kal aijyopfiks Kal aTrXws 6 hardly have been called etymo-
vepl Tb Kafl-^Koy; and, lastly, i logia by Posidonius, as Hanse
trepl T^v aya^a-jraTTjiriav Kal ayei- reads but setiologia) and etho-
Kal6Trira Kal bKws & Trepl rhs avy- logia, description of moral
The first of these
KaTaSe'ireis. states, are necessary. In Ep.
divisions would correspond to 89, 14, the parts of moral
the third of Diogenes, the science are more accurately
second to his first; but the given as three the first deter-
;

division Trtpl ayaSwv Kai KaKtJov mining the value of things, the
does not harmonise with the second treating de aotionibus,
THE HIGHEST GOOD. 225

fl,nd connection of the Stoic principles, the first dis- Citap.

tinction to be made will be one between morality in '


'

general and particular points in morality. In con-


sidering morality in general, those statements which
give the abstract theory of morals will be distin-
guished from those which modify it with a view to
meet practical wants. The former again may be
grouped round three points : the enquiry into the
highest good, that into the nature of virtue, and
that relating to the wise man.
The enquiry into the destiny and end of man a. The
'"^'"''*
turns, with the Stoics, as it did with all. moral phi-
losophers since the time of Socrates, about the funda- (i)Nufure
mental conception of the good, and the ingredients %]',"st
necessary to make up the highest good or happi- O""'!-

ness.' Happiness, they consider, can only be sought


in rational activity or virtue. Speaking more ex-

the third de impetu, Trcpl ipuris. problems proposed by Cic. Off.


Two of these parts coincide ii. 5, the three sections
18, or
indeed with those of Diogenes, enumerated by Mpict. Enchir.
but this is not the case with o. 51 (76), in which Petersen
the third, which is only one of (Phil. Chrys. Fund. p. 260) re-
the subdivisions in Diogenes cognises Seneca's three main
(irepl TiSi' irpaffoiy) ; and even divisions of Ethics. In the
Seneca's first part more nearly midst of such contending au-
agrees with one of these (Trspl thorities it seems impossible to
rris trpdTTis alias). Unfortu- establish the main division of
nately, Seneca does not mention the Stoic Ethics. One thing
his authorities ; and, accord- alone is clear, that they were
ingly, we are not sure whether themselves not agreed on t'lie
his division is a genuine Stoical subject. Petersen's attempt,
division. A similar division 1. c. p. 258, appears to' me a
will be subsequently met with failure.
in the eclectic Academician ' (SioS. Ed. ii. l.'SS: t4\us Se
Eudorus (living under Au- !/>a(rii/ ehai t6 euSaifiovsTy, 06
gustns). None of the divisions ej/eKo Trwra vpdrTerai, avjb Sk
quoted agree with the three xpiiTTeTui fiiv, oiSevbs Si 'ivsKa.

Q
;

226 THE STOICS.

Chap. plicitly,' the primary impulse of every being is


X.
towards self-preservation and self-gratification.* It
follows that every being pursues those things which
are most suited to its nature,' and that such things

' Diog, vii. 85 ; die. Fin. iii. Benai Kal t& oiKeia irpotrieTai.

5 ; Sell. N. A. xii. 5, 7. That Similarly, Cie. 1. c. Anti-


5, 16.
the two latter writers follow sthenes had already reduced
one and the same authority the conception of the good to
appears partly from their literal that of olKeioy, without the
agreement with each other, and fuller explanation. Here the
partly from their adopting a Academic theory of life accord-
uniform method in refuting ing to nature, which had been
the Epicurean statement, that enunciated by Polemo, Zeno's
the desire for pleasure is the teacher, is combined therewith.
primary impulse. That autho- Some difficulty was nevertheless
rity is probably the treatise of caused by the question whether
Chrysip] us ire^l -riKovs, since it all living creatures possess a
is distinctly referred to by consciousness (^ffuveiSrifftSy sen-
Diogenes. Plwt. Sto. Eep. 12, 4, sus) of their own nature
quotes from it: Sis oiKewiufBa without such a consciousness,
irpos ainabs eiiBiis ysvo^evoi Kal to natural self-love seemed to
f^epTj Koi Tct ^icyova eaurwv. The the Stoics impossible. They
difference mentioned by Alex. thought, however, that this
Aj>hr. De An. 154 that at one question (according to Sen. Bp.
time self-love, at another the 121, 5, conf. (Mc. 1. c.) could
preservation of one's own na- be answered in the affirmative
ture, is the impulse is unim- without hesitation, appealing
portant. for evidence to the instinctive
' Diog. vii. 85 thv Se irpirqv
: activities by which children
Spfi'fjv tpatri rh Cv^^ tff-xeiv 4ir\ ro and animals govern their bodily
motions, guard themselves from
[outm] Tjjs (pia-fas air' apxvs, KuBd dangers, and pursue what is to
<pfl(riv *5 XpytTiTTTToy iv r^ Trpilorta their interest, without denying
TTepl TiXwv, Trparov oiKetov elpai that the ideas which children
\4yuv trdvTi ^(itf> t^v aitrov (xii- and animals have of themselves
UTa.(nv al t%v -raiiTTis avvel^Tjirtv. are very indistinct, that they
oijTc y&p aWiiTpmfTat cIkos ^v dnly know their own consti-
aliTov [Cobet incorrectly out!i] tution, but not true con-
its
rb fejjoj', oUre noiriffat tty [1. ttoltj- ception (constitutionis finitio
(raffcw sc. T^v tftvo'Lv'] avrh fifir' Sen. p. 11). Coustitutio, or
a\Korpiu(rat fiiir' ouk [must evi- ffiio-Tainj, was defined by the
dently be struck out] olKemarm. Stoics, Sen. p. 10, as principale
airoAitirerai rotpvv Af-yFiv (TUffTT?- animi quodam modo se habens
curb oiKiiuis npus iaurS *
<X0Lfx4vi)v erga corpus.
oBtui yap t( tc ^\dnTOVTa Biu- ' Cic. Fin. iii. 5, 17 ; 6, 20.
;;

THE HIGHEST GOOD. 2i7

only have for it a value (a^ia). Hence the highest Chap.


good the end-in-chief,' or happiness can only be
X.

found in what is conformable to nature.^ Nothing,


however, can be conformable to nature for any indi-
vidual thing, unless it be in harmony with the course
of law of the universe,^ or with the universal reason of
the world ; nor, in the case of a conscious and rea-
sonable being, unless it proceeds from a recognition
of this general law in short, from rational intelli-

gence.* In every enquiry into what is conformable

' The terms are here treated opQhs \6yos Sict irilyTuv ipx^fJi-^yo^
as synonymous, without regard 6 avrhs &v t( Ait . . . elvai S'

to the hair splitting with which ainh rovro tV toO 6uSa(;uocos


the Stoics distinguished (^Stoi. aper^v Kal eiSpoiav fiiovy 'irav
Eel. ii. 136) three meanings of ndfTa TTpfiTTTlTai KttTCt T^V ffVfjLtpU-

TeAos, between Te\os and (TKi^Tros. ytav Tov Trap' eKtiffTip ^aip-ovov irphs.
* Stoh. 134 and 138
ii. T^p TOV rwv SAwz* SlOlKTJToO j6oi5-

Diog. vii. 88 94 Plut. C. Not.


; ; \Tl(Tiy.

27, 9 ae. Fin. iii. 7, 26 10,


; ;
' Stob. ii. 160 (conf. 168) :

33 Sen. V. Beat. 3, 3 conf.


; ;
SiTTas QeaipeiffBat riiv re if roh
Ep. 118, 8 Sext. Pyrrh. iii. 171
; XoyiKOLS ytyyofievTiv &pfi^y Kol 7^v
Math. xi. 30. In Stob. ii. 78 4v ro7s a\6yois C^ois. Diog. 86 :

and 96, formal definitions are Plants are moved by nature-


given of aya3\)V, tcXos, and without impulse, animals by
eliSaiiiovitt. The latter is gene- means of impulse. In the case
rally paraphrased by eipoia ptov, of animals, therefore, t6 Kara
as Zeno had defined it. Various T'hv (piiTiv is the same as rh Korei
f ormulse for the conception of t5)j/ ipii^y. In rational creatures,

a life according to nature are reason controls impulse ; and


given by Cleanthea, Antipater, accordance with nature means,
Archedemus, Diogenes, Panse- accordance with reason. In
tius, Posidonius,and others in Oalen, Hippoc. et Plat, v.' 2
Clem. Alex. Strom, ii. 416; p. 460, Chrysippus says rifms :

Stob. 134 and Diot/., all appa-


;
oiKeiovffBai trphs fidvoy rh Ka\6j/..

rently taken from the same M. Awel. vii. 11 : t^j Ao-yi/cif f^'ij)

source. T\auT^ Trpa|ts Kar^ ^vffiv iirrl Kal


' Bioff. vii. 88 : Sii57rp reAos Kara xiyov. Hence the definition
yiferai rh h,KO\oi&(os ri] ipvffei of a virtuous life, or a life ac-
Qjv 'oTrep iffr) Kard re t^v ainav
cording to nature (^v kwt' ifi- :

Kol Kuril. T^v T&v '6\wVf ovSev neipiav rSav (^iSffet (rv^^aiv6vruv
^t/epyovj/xas wp inrayopeiieiv ettoBev (Chrysippus, in ySioJ. 134 ; Diog.
d vSfXos 6 KOLvhs iicnrep itrrlv 6 87 ; Cl&m. 1. o. ; also Diogenes,
2
:::

228 THE STOICS.

CHAP. to nature, all turns upon agreement with the essen-


X.
tial constitution of the being, and this essential con-

stitution consists, in the case of man, simply in


reason.' One and, the same thing, therefore, is al-
ways meant, whether, with Zeno, life according to
nature is spoken of as being in harmony with one-
self, or whether, following Cleanthes, it is simply
said to be the agreement of life with nature, and
whether, in the latter case, (j>vcns is taken to mean
the world at large, or is limited to human nature in
particular.^ In every case the meaning is, that the

Antipater, Archedemns, Posi- sippug and his followers aug-


donius) ; and that of the good mented the formula by several
rh Ti\etoi' KctTct <piiTlv KoyiKQv &s additions. 87 attributes
Sioif.
XoyiKov (^Diog. 94). the words to Zeno,
rp' ipiaei
' Sen. Ep. 121, 14: Omne adding, however, 89, that Chry-
animal primum constitutioni sippns understood by (piiTis, rfiy
suae conciliari hominis autem
: re Koiviji' Ka\ Idioos t^v avdpaTrivr]Vf
constitutionem rationalem esse whereas Cleanthes understood
et ideo conciliari hominem sibi TT^J/ KoivTiy pAvtlV OVKfTt 6 Kal T7)V
non tanquam animali sed tan- iirl These differences
liepous.
quam rationali. Ea enim parte are, however, not important.
sibi carus est homo, qua homo The simple expression d/ioXo-
est. Id. Ep. 92, 1 The body is : yovfievws Cyv means, without
subservient to thesonl, and the doubt, aK6xovBov iv piif, the Cpir
irrational part of the soul to the Koff GvaK6yovKai(ri/x(pu)yoi'(^Stob.
rational part. Hence it follows ii. 132 and 158), the SfioXoyia

In hoc uno positam esse beatam TTavrhs tov filou QDioff. vii. 89),
vitam, ut in nobis ratio perf ecta the vita sibi concors, the Con-
sit. Similarly, Ep. 76, 8. M. cordia animi (Sen. Ep. 89, 15 ;

Awrel. vi. 44 crv/jLipepet 5e eKatrrtp


: V. Be. 8, 6), the unum hominem
rh Kara. 77)v IoutoD KaTa<TKfv}}V agere, which, according to Sen.
Hal (pviriv
7] Se 4iJL^ (piKTts \oyiK^ Ep. 120, 22, is only found in a
KolTroXtTMfi. Conf. viii. 7andl2.
wise man in a word, the even
2 According to 132, Stcb. ii. tenour of life and consistency.
Dioff. vii. 89, the ancient Stoics Nevertheless, this consistency
were not altogether agreed as to is only possible when indi-
the terms in which they would vidual actions accord with the
express their theory. Zeno, for requirements of the character
instance, is said by Stobseus of the agent. Accordingly,
to have defined t4\os = Sfio\oyov- Stob. ii. 158, places iKoKaidus rii
nevaisCf)i> Cleanthes first added
; eouToji/ ipvcru by the side of
the words rp ^uo-ei, and Chry- aK6XovBov iv pitp. Cleanthes
;
;

THE HIGHEST GOOD. '22'i^

life of the individual approximates to or falls short Chap.


X.
of the goal of happiness, exactly in proportion as it
approaches to or departs from the universal law of
the world and the particular rational nature of man.
In a word, a rational life, an agreement with the
general course of the world, constitutes virtue. The
principle of the Stoic morality might therefore be
briefly expressed in the sentence Only virtue is :

good, and happiness consists exclusively in virtue.'


Iff^owever, following Socrates, "the 'goodTTs defined
as being what is useful,^ then the sentence would

therefore, in adding to the ex- num, secundum naturam is spe-


pression ^juoAoyoujueVwy the cially considered. To prove
words rf </)i<rei, which, however, their position, the Stoics make
according to Diog. 87, Zeno had use of the chain-argument, of
done before him, was only which they are generally fond.
going back to the next con- Thus Ghrysippus (in Plut. Sto.
dition of dfioKvyov^^vus Cw- ^V'e Kep. 13, 11) ri ayaBhv atperSy
:

can, however, hardly believe Tb 8* alperhv apetrrdy rh 5* kp^ffThv

with Diogenes that Cleanthes i-Tratyerdv t^ 5' 4TraiveThv Ka\6tf.


understood by <pviris only nature (The same in Cio. Fin. iii. 8, 27,
in general, but not human and iv. 18, 50, where I would
nature. He may have alluded suggest the reading validius
in express terms to kolv^ <^iais instead of vitiosius.) Again :

or KOivhs v6fios only, with the rb ayaQhv x^T^^ "^^ ^e ^^prhv '

praise of which his well-known (refiv6v rh 5e ffep.vhv Ka\6v. (The


hymn ends, but it cannot have same somewhat expanded in
been his intention to exclude Cic. Tusc. v. 15, 43.) Stoh. ii.
human nature, which is only a 126 : kyaBhv
Ttav alperhv elvai,
particular form of nature in apetTrhv yap Kai SoKifiafrrhv Kai
general. Ghrysippus therefore itratverhy virdp^^tv Trav Se KaKhy '

only expanded, but did not ipeuKThi'. Another sorites of the

contradict, the teaching of his same kind in Sen. Ep. 85, 2.


master. ' Stab. ii. 78 94; Biog. vii.
;

'
Mog. 30
vii. 94 101 ; ;
;
94 and 98; Sext. Pyrrh. iii. 169 ;

Stob. ii. 200 138 Sext, Pyrrh.


; ; Math. xi. 22, 25, and 30. Ac-
iii. 169; Math. xi. 184; do. cording to Cie. Fin. iii. 10, 33,
Tusc. ii. 25, 61 Fin. iv. 16, 45
;
Diogenes reconciled this defi-
Acad. i. 10 Farad. 1
; Sen. ; nition with the definition of the
Benef. vii. 2, 1 Ep. 71, 4 ; good and the perfect quoted on
74, 1 ; 76, 11 ; 85, 17 ; 120, 3 ; p. 227, 4, by observing that the
118, 10,where the relation of useful is a motus aut status
the conceptions honestum bo- natura absoluti.
;

330 THE STOICS.

Chap, run thus : Only Virtue is useful ; advantage cannot


'

be distinguished from duty, whilst to a bad man no-


thing is useful,' since, in the case of a rational being,
good and evil does not depend on what happens to
him, but simply on his own conduct.^ A view of
life is here presented to us in which happiness coin-
cides with virtue, the good and the useful with duty
and reason. There is neither any good independently
of virtue, nor is there in virtue and for virtue any
evil.

(2) T/ie The Stoics accordingly refused to admit the ordi-


""'
eM nary distinction, sanctioned by popular opinion and
the majority of philosophers, between various kinds
and degrees of good ; nor would they allow bodily
advantages and external circumstances to be in-
cluded among good things, together with mental
and moral qualities. A certain distinction between
goods they did not indeed deny, and various kinds
of goods are mentioned by them in their formal
division of goods.* But these distinctions amount,

'
Sext. 1. c. Stob. ii. 188 : with the good in it-
iitp4\eLa,
/ijjSeVo aauAoK firiT oKpeAeTirSai self, just as the virtuous man is
H-llTs ait>e\i7i/. thai yhp ih w^e- connected with virtue, which
Aeii/ iirxe'v opfrV, Kol rh
/car' is a part of himself. See Sea)-
ii<j>e\e7crBai KiveTaBm kot' Bper^v. tws 1. 0. and above p. 104, 2),
Ibid. ii. 202 ; Phit. Sto. Rep. or, what is the same thing,
12; Com. Not. 20,1; Cio. OS. iperii fi rh fierfxof apeTTJs. {Sext.
ii. 3, 10 ; iii. 3, 11 ; 7, 34. Math. xi. 184.) A distinction
* M. Awel. ix. 16. is made between three kinds of
' See Diog. 94 Stob. ii. 96; good t6 inp' oZ % a<t>' oS eimv
:

124; 130; 136; Se(et. Pyrrh. -rh naif 4 aufiPaivei


ii</)eA6T(reai,
iii. 169 Math. xi. 22 Oic. Fin.
; ; w^eAewreai, rh ot6v re a<^Ki!v.
iii. 16, 55 Sen. Ep. 66, 5.
; Under the first head comes vir-
Good is here defined to be tue, under the second virtuous
either a^iKeia or ovx ertpov i><j>t- actions, under the third, be-
Ae/os (inseparably connected sides the two others, virtuous
);

THE HIGHEST GOOD. L>ai

in the end, to no more than this, that whilst some Chap.


X.
goods are good and useful in themselves, others are
only subsidiary to them. The existence of several
equally primary goods appears to the Stoics to be at
variance with the conception of the good. That only
is a good, according to their view, which has an un-
conditional value. That which has a value only in
comparison with something else, or as leading to
something else, does not deserve to be called a good.
The difference between what is good and what is

not good is not only a difference of degree, but also


one of kind ; and what is not a good per se can never

subjects men, Gods, and de- selves) ; fourthly and fifthly,


mons. A second division of IMiKra (as ^ineicvia and eiryqpia),
goods {Diog., Sext. iii. 1 81, Stob.) and ajTAft or &fitKTa (such as
is into goods of the soul, ex- science), and the etc! irafdvTa,
ternal goods, the possession of (virtues), and ovk i,il Trap6vTa
virtuous friends and a virtuous {otov xopcfc) TfeptirdTTiffts'). The
country, and such as are neither corresponding divisions of evil
(t6 avrhv Iout^ eTcai otrovSatot/ are given by Diogenes and Sto-
hol evSaliwva, virtue and happi- baaus. The latter (ii. 126 and
ness considered as the relation 136) enumerates, in addition,
of the individual to himself, as the ayada. h KLvfja-ei (jcapo, &c.
his own possessions). Goods and iv a-x^im (etfraKTOS ^irux^a,
of the soul are then divided &c.), the latter being partially
into SiaBeaiis (virtues), ejeis (or if |i the a7afla KaO' aura (vir-
;

iiTLTri^evfiaTa, as instances of tues) and Trphs tI ttws exovTa


which Stub. ii. 100, 128, quotes (honour, benevolence, friend-
fiaj/Tttc^ and (pi\oye(M}fji.erpla, tfec, ship) the goods which are
;

these are not so unchangeable necessary for happiness (vir-


as peculiarities of character, tues), and those which are
and are therefore only H^is, p. not necessary (^x^pK 6iriT7)5eu-

103, 1), and those which are /iHTo). Seneca's list is far more
neither fis nor BuiSfirfis ac- limited, although it professes
tions themselves. A
third divi- to be more general. He men-
sion of goods {Diog., C'w. 1. c, tions,prima bona, tanquam
Stob. 80, 100, Hi) distinguishes gaudium, pax, salas patrise
TiKtKa or Bi' avrh. atpera (moral secunda, in materia infelici ex-
actions), irontTiKa (friends and pressa, tanquam tormentorum
the services they render), re^iica patientia ; tertia, tanquam mo-
and ttoi^jtikA (virtues them- destus incessus.
THE STOICS.

Chap. be a good under any circumstances.' The same re-


X.
marks apply to evil. That which is not in itself
an evil can never become so from its relation to
something else. Hence only that which is absolutely
good, or virtue, can be considered a good and only ;

that which is absolutely bad, or a vice,^ can be con-


sidered an evil. All other things, however great
their influence may be on our state, belong to a class
of things neither good nor evil, but indifferent, or
dSid(popa.^ Neither health, nor riches, nor honour,
not even life itself, is a good ; and just as little are
the opposite states poverty, sickness, disgrace, and
death evils.* Both are in themselves indifferent.

'
Cic. Fin. iii. 10, 33: Ego Se KoX rsAeuTOtiiii rpiirov ^afflv
assentior Diogeui, qui bonum aStatf>opov rh fi'tire trphs evSaifiayiaif
definiet id quod esset natura fJ\TS nphs KaKodaifjL iviav truAAo^-
absolutum [ouTOTeAes] . . . hoc fiavoiMfvov. To this category be-
autem ipsum bonum non acces- long external goods, health,
sione neque crescendo aut cum &c. ^ yap
ioTiv eZ koI kukus
ceteris comparando sed propria XPVf^^ai, TovT\iiv itii aSiti^opoV'
vi et senlimus et appellamus Sta TTOPT^JS S* aperi] juej/ KaKUS,
bonum. Ut enim mel, etsi dul- KaKi(jc Se Kaicm, vyisi^ 5h Kai Tois
cissimum est, suo tamen pro- iTfpt (Tc^fiaTL TTore fiiv ev iroT6 5e
prio genere saporis, non com- KaKus IcTTi xpvi'^ai. Similarly,
paratione ciim aliis, dulce esse Pyrrh. iii. 177, and Uioi/. 102,
sentitur, sic bonum hoc de quo who defines ovBerepa as '6<ra /a^t*
agimus est illud quidem plurimi affteKei fJiiire ^KditTei, Stob. ii.
Eestimandum, sed ea sestimatio li2: aSid(/)o/)oi' = Tb /i^re ayadhp
genere valet non magnitudine, fi'fjTe KoKby, Koi tJ* /a^tc aiperhv
&c. /i^Tf <pvieT6v. Pint. Sto. Rep.
' Sen. Benef. vii. 2, 1 Nee : 31, 1 ^ yap ia-nv e5 XP^"'"'^'"
:

malum esse ullum nisi turpe, Kai KOKws tovt6 <l>aai /ii^t' ayadbj'
nee bonum nisi honestum. slvai fii\Ti KaK6v.
J lev. Apk. De Fat. c. 28, p. 88: ^ Zeno (in Sen. Ep. 82,
9)
1} tJ.tt aperi] Tt Kai ^ KaKta jj-dfai proves this of death by a pro-
Kar' aitTohs 1} /j-kv ayaOhi/ tJ 5e cess of reasoning, the accuracy
kukSv. 229 233, 1.
(See p. ; of which he appears to have
Sext. Math. xi. 6] after , mistrusted Nullum malum
:

giving two irrelevant defini- gloriosum est mors autem :

tions of aBiiiipopov: Karb. Tpirov gloriosa est (there is a glorious


;; :
;

THE HIGHEST GOOD. 233

a material whicli may either be employed for good' Chap.


X.
or else for evil.^
The Academicians and
Peripatetics were most
vigorously hy the Stoics for including
attacked
among goods external things which are dependent
on chance. For how can that be a good under any
circumstances, which bears no relation to man's
moral nature, and is even frequently obtained at the
cost of morality ? ^ If virtue renders a man happy,

death) ergo mors non est ma-


: he endures pains, quantum ad
lum. In general, two considera- ipsas virtutes, plurimum inter
tions are prominent in the ilia, in quibus virtus utra^^ue
Stoic treatment of this subject ostenditur . . virtutem ma- .

that what is according to nature teria non mutat. Ep. 71, 21


cannot be an evil, and that Bona ista aut mala non eflScit
life taken by itself is not a good. materia, sed virtus. Ep. 85,
Other arguments, however, for 39 Tu ilium [sapientem] premi
:

diminishing the fear of death putas malis 1 Utitur. Id. Ep.


are not despised. See Sen. Ep. 44; 120, 8; Plwt. G. Not. i, 1
30, 4 ; 77, 11, 82, 8 ; Cons, ad Sto. Bep. 18, 5 31, 1 Chrys- ; ;

Marc. 19, 3 ; M. Aurel ix. 3 ippus, in Ps. Plitt. Be Nobil. 12,


viii. 58.And other passages 2 Bioff. 102 Stoi. ii. 90 ; Sext.
; ;

quoted in JBaumhauer's Vet. Pyrrh. iii. 181; Alex. Aphr.


Philosoph. Doctr. De Morte To- Top. 43 and 107.
luntaria, p. 211. ^ Sext. Math. xi. 61. See
Chrysippus (in Plut. Sto. above, p. 232, 3. Pioff. 103:
Rep. 15, 4) : All virtue is done The good can only do good,
away with, fey fi T^v^ionijufi t^c and never do harm ; ou /xaAAo;'
i-yieiav i Tt ruv &Wiiii/, h jU^ Ka\6i/
ItTTiv, aryadhy airoKlTrufiei'. Id. Koi 7j {tyieia
oiiK lip'' aya66v
(in Plut. C. Not. 5, 2) Iv t^ : oijre n\ovros ofid' vyieia. Again :

Kar^ apsriju ^toOv y.6vov etrri Ti ^ ecTTiv e5 Kal aaKais XP^^^***,


iv^a.ifi6vtcs, TWf &Wiiiv oifdett SfToip tout' ovk effTzy aya96v TtXointp
trphs 7],'ias oiiS" els tovto trvpepyo{/p- 5e Ktii iiyieia ^ffriv eS Kai Kaaus
Tuv. Similarly, Sto. Eep. 17, Xprjireui, K.T.K. In Sen. Ep. 87,
2. Sen. Vit. Be. 4, 3 The only : 11, instead of the proposition,
good is honestas, the only evil that nothing is a good except
turpitudo, cetera vilis turba virtue, the following arguments
rerum, neo detrahens quicquam are given as traditional among
beatte vitse nee adjiciens. Id. the Stoics (interrogationes nos-
Bp. 66, 14 There is no differ-
: trorum), apparently taken from
ence between the wise man's Posidonius (see p. 31, 35, 38) :
joy and the firmness with which (1) Quod bonum est, bonos
;:: :

234 THE STOICS.

Chap. it must render him perfectly happy in himself, since


X.
no one can be happy who is not happy altogether.
If, on the other hand, anything which is not in

man's power were allowed an influence on his hap-


piness, it would detract from the absolute worth of
virtue, and man would never be able to attain to
that imperturbable serenity of mind without which
no happiness is conceivable.'

facit : f ortuita bonum non fa- proved by the argument, quoted


ciuut ergo non sunt bona.
: in Sen. Bp. 85, 30 Quod ma- :

(Similarly in M. Aii/rel. ii. 11, lum est nocet quod nocet de-:

iv. 8 Whatever does no moral


: teriorem facit. Dolor et pau-
harm, does no harm to human pertas deteriorem non faciunt
life.) (2) Quod contemptis- ergo mala non sunt. The Stoic
simo ouique contingere ao tur- proposition is also established
pissimo potest, bonum non est from a theological point of view.
opes autem et lenoni et lenistse Nature, says M. Aurel. ii. 11,
contingunt ergo, &c. (So, too.
: ix. 1, could never have allowed
Marc. Awrelitis, v. 10.) (3) that good and evil should
Bonum ex malo non fit divitije : equally fall to the lot of the
fiunt, fiunt autem ex avaritia good and the bad consequently, ;

ergo, &c. (Conf. Alex. Aphr. what both enjoy equally life
Top. 107 T^ SiA KaKOv "ytrfV^-
: and death, honour and dis-
fievov ovK eariy a'ya,Q6v' ivKovros honour, pleasure and trouble,
S^ Koi Sta iropvo^offKla^ Kanov riches and poverty can neither
(4) Quod
uvTos jiviTai, K.T.K.y be good nor evil. On the value
dum consequi volumus in mult a of fame, see id. iv. 19.
mala incidimus, id bonum non This view is compared
'

est dum divitias autem conse-


: with the Academician in Clc.'
qui volumus, in multa mala in- Tusc. V. 13, 39 18, 51 &.
; ;

cidimus, &c. (5) QuEe neque Ep. 85, 18; 71, 18; 92, 14. In
magnitudinem animo dant nee the last passage, the notion that
fiduciam neo securitatem, con- happiness can be increased by
tra autem insolentiam,tumorem, external goods, and is conse-
arrogantiam oreant, mala sunt quently capable of degrees, is
a fortuitis autem (previously, refuted by arguments such as
not only riches but health had 4, 24 Quid potest desiderare
:

been included in this class) in is, cui omnia honesta contin-


hsec impellimur ergo non sunt : gunt? et quid stultius tur-
. . .

bona. That riches are not a piusve, quam bonum rationalis


good is proved by Diogenes (in animi ex irrationalibus nectere 1
die. Fin. iii. 15, 49) that po- ; , . . non intenditur virtus, ergo
verty and pain are no evils is ne beata quidem vita, quse ex
: .

THE BIGIIEST GOOD. 235

Least of all, however, according to the Stoic view. Chap. '

can pleasure be considered a good, or be regarded, as ___1^^


by Epicurus, as the ultimate and highest obiect in (^) ^^"'r

life. He who places pleasure on the throne makes a the good.

slave of virtue;' he who considers pleasure a good


ignores the real conception of the good and the pecu-
liar value of virtue;^ he appeals to feelings, rather
than to actions ;
^ he reqiures reasonable creatures to

virtute est. Conf. Bp. 72, 7: the highest good, justice (the
Cui aliquid aocedere potest, id Peripatetic view) might per-
imperfeotum est. haps still be safe, since, in
Cleanthesexpandsthis no-
' comparison with pleasure, it
tion, in rhetorical language, in may be regarded as the higher
do. Fin. ii. 21, Conf. Sen. 69. good. Still, this was only a
Benef iv. 2, 2 . [Virtus] non : preliminary and tentative con-
est virtus si sequi potest. cession, which Chrysippus sub-
Primse partes ejus sunt duoere : sequently proved could not be
debet, imperare, summo loco admitted, inasmuch as it was
stare tu illam jubes signum
: out of harmony with the true
petere. Id. Vit. Be. 11, 2; conception of the good, and
13,5; 14, 1. changed the difference in kind
^ Compare on this subject, (on which see p. 232, 1) be-
the words of Chrysippus on tween virtue and other things
p. 233, 1, quoted by Plwt. Sto. into a simple difference in
Eep. 15, and, for their ex- degree. Plutarch (Sto. Eep. 15,
planation, Sen. Benef. iv. 2, 4 : 6),with more reason, blames
Non indignor, quod post volup- Chrysippus for asserting against
tatem ponitur virtus, sed quod Aristotle that, if pleasure be
omnino cum voluptate con- regarded as the highest good,
feratur contemptrix ejus et justice becomes impossible, but
hostis et longissime ab ilia not other virtues for how
;

resiliens. Id. Vit. Be. 15, 1 could n, Stoic, of all philo-


Pais honesti non potest esse sophers, make such a distinc-
nisi honestum, nee sumraum tion between virtues 1 Evi-
bonum habebit sinceritatem dently the zeal of controversy
suam, si aliquid in se viderit has here carried away the
dissimile meliori. According philosopher beyond the point
to Pint. 15, 3 ; IB, 3, Com. Not. at which his own principles
25, 2, this statement of Chry- would bear him out.
' M. Awel. vi. 15 i niv
sippus is at variance with :

another statement of his, in iptX6^Q^os cLWorpiav iv4pyeta


which he says If pleasure be : iSioy cLyaBhtf {nroha/ipdyei *
& S^
declared to be a good, but not tpiKii^Qvos l^iav TTcitTiv ' & Si vovp
;

236 THE STOICS.

Chap, pursue what is unreasonable, and souls nearly allied


'
to Grod to go after the enjoyments of the lower ani-
mals.' Pleasure must never be the object of our
pursuit, not even in the sense that true pleasure is
invariably involved in virtue. That it no doubt is.^

It is true that there is always a peculiar satisfaction,


and a quiet cheerfulness and peace of mind, iu moral
conduct, just as in immoral conduct there is a lack
of inward peace and in this sense it may be said;

that the wise man alone knows what true and lasting
pleasure is.' But even the pleasure afforded by
moral excellence ought never to be an object, but
only a natural consequence, of virtuous conduct;
otherwise the independent value of virtue is im-
paired.''

eXwt' ISiav 'Kpa^iv. Coni. ix. 16 :


* mog. 94 : Virtue is a
oitK iv neitret, d\V ivepyeicf, rhTov good ; ^TTLyevtrfitiaTa Sh Ti\v re
KoyiKov TToXiTiKoD ^i^ov Karciz/ Kai X^P^v KoL t\iv evippoffi)Vi]V KaX ra
a'YaB6i/. irapawKiicia. Sen. Benef. iv. 2,
' iScn. Ep. 92, 6-10 ; Vit. 3 : It is a question utrum virtus
Beat, 5, 4 9, 4 ; ; Posidonius, in summi boni causa sit, an ipsa
Sen. Ep. 92, 10. summum bonum. Seneca, of
^Taking the expression in course, says the latter. Conf.
its strictmeaning, it is hardly- De Vit. Be. 4, 5 The wise man :

allowed by the Stoics, when takes pleasure in peace of mind


they speak accurately. Under- and cheerfulness, non ut bonis,
standing by iiSovii an emotion, sed ut ex bono suo ortis. Tbid.
i.e. something contrary to na- 9, 1 : Non, si voluptatem prses-
ture and blameworthy, they tatura virtus est, ideo propter
assert that the wise man feels banc petitur . . voluptas non
delight (xP") gaudium), but est merces nee causa virtutis,
not pleasure (fiSavii, Isetitia, vo- sed accessio, nee quia delectat
luptas). See Sen. Ep. 59, 2 placet, sed si placet et delectat.
IHogf. 116 ; Alex. Aplir. Top. 96 ;
The highest good consists only
the last-named giving defi- in mental perfection and health,
nitions of x*P" 7i^ov)i, Tepij/is, in ipso judicio et habitu op-
timse mentis, in the sanitas et
Sen. Ep. 23, 2; 27, 3; libertas animi, which desires,
59, 2 ; 14 ; 72, 8 ; Vit. Be. 3, 4 nothing but virtue ; ipsa pre-
4, 4 ; De Ira, ii, 6, 2. tium sui. Ibid. 15, 2 : Ne,
THE SIGSEST GOOD. 237

^or may pleasure be placed side by side with Chap.


X.
virtue, as a part of the highest good, or be declared
to be inseparable from virtue. Pleasure and virtue
are different in essence and kind. Pleasure may be
immoral, and moral conduct may go hand in hand
with difiEculties and pains. Pleasure is found among
the worst of men, virtue only amongst the good;
virtue is dignified, untiring, imperturbable ;
pleasure
is grovelling, effeminate, fleeting. Those who look
upon pleasure as a good are the slaves of pleasure ;

those in whom virtue reigns supreme control plea-


sure,and hold it in check.' In no sense, therefore,
ought any weight to be allowed to pleasure in a
question of morals : pleasure is not an end in view,
but only the result of an action ;
"^
not a good, but
something absolutely indifferent. The only point on
which the Stoics are not unanimous is, whether every
pleasure is contrary to nature,' as the stem Cleanthes

gaudium quidem, quod ex vir- may be placed the inference in


tute oritur, quamvis bonum sit, Clem. Strom, iv. 483, C, which
absoluti tamen boni pars est, bears great similarity to the
non magis quam Isetitia et third argument, quoted on
tranquillitas . . sunt enim p. 233, 2 If thirst be painful,
:

ista bona, sed consequentia and it be pleasant to quench


summum bonum, non consum- thirst, thirst must be the cause
mantia. Here, too, belongs ofthis pleasure: 070605 SeiroiTjTi-
the statement in Stoh. ii. 184, xbii rb Kaxiv om Uv yivoiro, /t.T.\.

188 (conf. 31. Aurel. vii. 74) : ^ Siog. 85 84 Kiyovai


:

TTffvTa Thvbvrivovv atp^KovvTO, tivSj irphs ijSov^y yiyvfodai Tijf


Xffniv wfpiKiiav airo\afji$tiviu irop* irpc^TTiv &pfii]v rms ^^Jois, iltevSos
avrh toSto, for the reasons anotfjaivovtrii^. iniyevvrffia ydp
stated, p. 230, 1. (paa-iv, ei &pa ^trrh, riSoviiy ehai,
Sen. Vit. Be. c. 7 and
' Stok avTri naff tt,M]v v ^i<ris
10-12 M. Aurel. viii. 10.
; eVifriT^o-offa -rh ii;ap)i6QjVTa tfj
Among the Stoic arguments avarian aTrohdpri.
against identifying pleasure " Taking pleasure in its
and pain with good and evil, widest sense. In its more re-
' ;:
:

238 TKE STOICS.

Chap. asserted, in the spirit of Cynicism, or whether there


X.
is such a thing as a natural and desirable pleasure.'
Virtue, on the other hand, needs no extraneous ad-
ditions, but contains in itself all the conditions of
happiness.^ The reward of virtuous conduct, like
the punishment of wickedness, consists only in the
character of those actions, one being according to
nature, the other contrary to nature.^ And so un-
conditional is this self-sufficiency of virtue,* that the

strioted sense, they reject iiSovii, per se expetendam nee metu


understanding thereby a par- nos ad. illam cogi neo mercede
ticular emotion. See p. 236, 2. condnci. Non esse justum cui
' Sext. Math. xi. 73: rhv quicquam in hac virtute placet
ijSov^v & juev 'Eirifoupos ayaShv praster ipsam. Id. Bp. 87, 24
eJi/al tpTicriy 6 Se eiir&jv * fiaveiijv
' Maximum scelerum supplicium
fd.aK\ov ^ fiaSeiiiv '(Antislhenes) in ipsis est. Benef. iv. 12:
KaK6v ol 5e cLTch T^s (rroas aSid- Quid reddatbeneficium ? die tu
(popov Kal ov Trporyy/ieyoi/. aA\ct mihi, quid reddat justitia. Sec. ;

KA.ecy0r]s fiey fi-tfTe Karct ipimv siquicquam prseter ipsas, ipsas


ahr^v fJvai fiiire a^iav ^x^*^ non expetis. M. Awel. ix. 42 :

auT7]v 4v T(f ^iify KaBiiirep Se rh Ti yhp Tr\eoy fleXets 5 iroiTjiros &y-


KiWvvrprv KttTtt tp{itTiv fi^ elvat Bpcoiroy ; ovk apK^ toiJtqj, St* kqtc^
d 5e 'Apx57]/ios koto tpifflv fiev (pitriy T^v ffiiy Tt effpo^as, aAAcl
eJyat asiy juocxo^T? Tpf^'^^i
Tcis roirov /wrShy fTjTeis ; When man
ovxl Se Kal a^iav ^X^*"* IlavaiTios does good, ireiroiTjKe vphs tt Kare-
Se Ttca fiev Kara tpvtrty inrapx^ty (TKeOafTTai Kal exf* Tb auTou. Id.
riyoi 6e irapa (pvuiv, vii. 73 ; viii. 2. See pp. 230, 1
'Accordingly, it is also de- 236, 4.
fined to be rex^'J^wSoi/ioWas irot-t)- *
Sioff. vii. 127 airdpicn :

Tiicfi. Alex. Aphr. De An. 156, b". elyair^y aper^y vphs eiiSat^ovlav.
' IHog. 89 t^i' t' AperV
: ac. Parad. 2 Sen. Bp. 74, 1;

tiaQifyiv ilvai dfioKoyovfievriv Kal Qui omne bonum honesto cir-


ayrV 5i* ain^y elyai oiper^c, ou cumscripsit, intra se felix est.
Sid Ttya <p6Poy ^ iKtriSa ^ ri ray This airipKeia is even asserted
e^ajdey eV ouTp t' eZl/af t^v euSal- of individual virtues, by virtue
fjioylay, St' oiJtn; [-tjs] ij'tJxp ['?^] of the connection between
veiTotT)fji,eyri [-Tjs] irpbs i^oAoyiai' them all. Of (ppdyncris, for in-
TTcw'Tis ToO ^I'ou, ASfe?i. De Clem. i. stance, in Sen. Ep. 85, 2, it is
1, 1 ; Quamvis enim recte facto- said Qui prudens est, et lem-
:

rum verus f ruct us sit f ecisse, nee perans est. Quitemperans, est
uUum virtutum pretium dignum et constans. Qiji constans est,
illis extra ipsas sit. Id. Ep. imperturbatus est. Qui im-
81, 19. ^p. 94, 19 : iEquilatem perturbatus est, sine tristitia

THE HIGHEST GOOD. 239

happiness which it affords is not increased by length Chap.


"

of time.' Eational self-control being here recog-


nised as the only good, man makes himself thereby
independent of all external circumstances, abso-
lutely free, and inwardly satisfied.^

The happiness of the virtuous man and this is (4) Nega-

a very distinctive feature of Stoicism thus


is far ^ac!ter"of
more negative than positive. It consists more in Itai'piness.

independence and peace of mind than in the enjoy-


ment which moral conduct brings with it. In men-
tal disquietude says Cicero, speaking as a Stoic
consists misery ; in composure, happiness. How can he
be deficient in happiness, he enquires, whom courage
preserves from care and fear, and self-control guards
from passionate pleasure and desire ? ^ How can he
fail happy who is in no way depen-
to be absolutely
dent on fortune, but simply and solely on himself ? *
To be free from disquietude, says Seneca, is the
est.Qui sine tristitia est, beatus ' Plui. Sto. Eep. 26; C.
est. Ergo prudens est beatus, Not. where Chrysippus is
8, 4,
et prudentia ad vitam beatam charged with at one time deny-
satis est. Similarly in respect ing that happiness is aug-
of bravery (_ibid. 24). This mented by length of time, and
ainipKeia of virtue was natu- at another declaring momen-
rally a chief point of attack for tary wisdom and happiness to
an opponent. It is assailed by be worthless. C'io. Fin. iii. 14,

Alex. Apia: De An. 156, on the 45 Sen. Ep. 74, 27 ; 93, 6 ;


;

ground that neither the things Benef v. 1 7, 6 ; IM. Am-el. xii.


.

which the Stoics declare to be 35. The Stoics are, on this


natural and desirable (vpoi\y- point, at variance with Aris-
/ueyo), nor, on the other hand, totle.
the na*ural conditions of vir- ' This view is frequently

tuous action, can be without expressed by the Stoics of the


effect on happiness, and that it Roman period, Seneca, Epic-
will not do to speak of the tetus, and M. Aurelius. Proofs
latter as only negative con- will be found subsequently,
ditions (fiv oxjk &vfv). See Phd. " Tusc. v. 15, 43 14, 42. ;

C. Not. 4, and 11, 1. Parad. 2.


240 ritE STOICS.

Chap, peculiar privilege of the wise ; ' the advantage which


'

is gained from philosophy is, that of living without


fear, and rising superior to the troubles of life.^ Far
more emphatically, however, than by any isolated
expressions is this negative view of moral aims sup-
ported by the whole character of the Stoic ethics,
the one doctrine of the apathy of the wise man
sufficiently proving that freedom from disturbances,
an imconditional assurance, and self-dependence, are
the points on which these philosophers lay especial
value.
(5) The The Grood, in as far as it is based on the general

amid as
arrangement of the world, to which the individual is
law. subordinate, appears to man in the character of Law.
This law being, however, the law of his own nature,
the Good becomes the natural object of man's desire,
and suits his natural impulse. The former view,
which was never unfamiliar to moral philosophy, was
cultivated by the Stoics with peculiar and zeal ; ^

thisview of morality forms one of the points on


which Stoicism subsequently came into contact, partly
with Roman jurisprudence, partly with the ethics of
the Jews and Christians. Moreover, as the Stoics
considered that the Eeason which governs the world

' De Const. 13, 5; 75, 18: testatem : infestimabile bonnm


Expectant nos, si ex hao ali- est, suum fieri,
quando fece in illnd evadimus ^ 12 Ep. 29,
Quid ero-o :

sublime et excelsum, tran- . .philoaophia prastabit ?


.

quillitas animi et expulsis Scilicet ut malis tibi placere,


erroribus absoluta libertas. quam populo, .utsinemetu . .

Quseris, quae sit ista ? Non IJeorum hominumque vivas, ut


homines timere, non Deos. Nee aut vincas mala aut finias.
turpia veils nee nimia. In se ' See Xrische,
Forschungeii,
ipsum habere maximam po- 368 and 476,
THE HIGHEST GOOD. 241

is the general Law of all beings,' so they recognised Chap.


X.
in the moral demands of reason the positive and
negative aspects of the Law of God.* Human law
comes into existence when m^an becomes aware of
the divine law, and recognises its claims on him.^
Civil and moral law are, therefore, commands abso-
lutely imperative on every rational being.'' No man
can feel himself to be a rational being without at
the same time feeling himself pledged to be moral.'

> See p. 148, 2, human creation sed geternum


^ v6ii.os, to the
according quiddam, quod universummun-
Stoic definition (<Sfoo. Eel. ii. dum regeret imperandi pro-
190, 204 Floril. 44, 12, and in
; hibendique sapientia, the mens
the fragment of Chiysippus omnia ratione aut cogentis aut
quoted by Marcian in Digest, vetantis Dei, the ratio recta
i. 3, 2, and the Soholiast of summi Jovis (conf. Fin. iv. 5,
Hermogenes in Spengel, %vvay. 11, in the fragment in Lact.
Tfxv. 177,jEm6'Ae, Forsch. 475) Inst. vi. 8). It is, accordingly
= \6yos op6})s irpoffraKTiKhs fJ-ev as Chrysippus 1. c. says in the
tSiv TTonqTsoiVj atciiyopevTiKh^ 5e Twy words of Pindar. {Plato, Georg.
u noi7]Teojv. It is therefore a-rroi'- 484, B), irdvTwv &atTt\ehs Beluv re
Sa?<ii> Ti or aaruov, something of Ka\ d.v9pQyirlpoJv irpayfidTwv.
moral value, imposing duties ' ao. Leg. i. 6, 18; ii. 4,8;
on man. The ultimate source 5,11.
of this \6yos must be looked < Or as Stob. ii. 184, ex-
for in the \6yos Koivhs, the presses it, SiKuiov is ipiaei Kal ixt)
divine or world reason. The 64(rei.

general law is, according to ' This is proved by de.


Dioff. vii. 88, who here (ac- Legg. i. 12, 33, in a chain-
cording to the passage quoted argument clearly borrowed
from de. N. D. i. 15, 40 on p. from the Stoics Quibus ratio :

148, 2, is apparently following a natura data est, iisdem etiam


Chrysippus) = i opBhs Kdyas Sia recta ratio data est. Ergo et
lex, quEe est recta ratio in
i.ct.It is the ratio summa jubendo et vetando. Si lex,
insita in natura, quae jubet ea jus quoque. At omnibus ratio.
quse faciehdasunt, prohibetque Jus igitur datum est omnibus.
contraria (Cic. Legg. i. 6, 18, Upon this conception of law is
conf. the quotation from Oio. based the Stoic definition of
N. D. i. 14, 36, respecting Zeus KaT6p6afm as eu;'((/ir)/iit, 'that of
on p. 150). According to Che. a,)j,i,pTi\fia as hi6iii]iia.

"^-e.'Tg. ii. 4, 8 and 10, it is no

K
;

242 THE STOICS.

Chap. Obedience, therefore, to this law is imposed upon


X.
man, not only by external authority, but by virtue of
his own nature. The good is for him an object of

pursuit the natural object of man's will on the ;

other hand, evil is that against which his will re-


.

volts.' The former arouses his desire {opfi.-q), the lat-


ter his aversion {dcfiopfj,!]) :
^ and thus the demands of

' The good alone, or virtue, impulses of reasonable beings


is aipeTSf ; evil is i^evxriv. See and beings devoid of reason.
p. 229, 1 238, 3, and Stoh.
; It is only in the case of reason-
Esl. ii. 202. tttpeThv is, how- able beings that it can be said
ever. Ibid. 126, 132, h a'lpeffiv that impulse is called forth by
iSxoyov KLvel, or, more accu- the idea of a thing as some-
rately, Th bpiirfs auToreKovs Kivri- thing which has to be done
nK6v and alperiv is accordingly {^avrarria. &p/jL7]TtK^ tov KaBiiK6v'
;

distinguished from \7iTrT6i' Tos) that every impulse con-


;

alperhv being vrhat is morally tains an affirmative judgment


good, \rijrTiti being everything in itself (^avyKardSeiris), to
which has value, including ex- which has been superadded a
ternal goods. The Stoics make KLvy\iiK6v ;
(TvyKaTAdiffis apply-
a further distinction (according ing to particular propositions
to Stob. ii. 140 and 194) with (those in which truth and
unnecessary subtlety between falsehood consist. See p. 110, 3
oipETic and atpiTiov, and simi- 83, .2), whereas ipii.ii applies to
larly between bp^KThv and bpeK- xarriyopiifiara (i. e. activities
reov^ vTTQfjLeverhv and uTrojuei/ercov, expressed by verbs. See p. 95,
using the first form to express 1 and 2), since every impulse
the good in itself (for instance, and every desire aims at the
the latter to express
<pp6pT)(ris), possession of a. good. 'Opfiii
the possession of the good (for \oyiicii is defined to be <popa,
instance, tppovftv). Siai^oias iiri n Totv iv r^ TrpdrreiVj
* ipn't] is defined by Stob. ii. and is also called 6piiii irpoKxi/cJ;
160, as ipopk^vyris iirlTt ; atpapfiii, (only a rational being being
which is contrasted therewith capable of irp5|is). If the (jyopi
in Ejnct. Enchirid. 2, 2 Diss. iii. Siavotas refers to something
2, 2, 22, 36, as (according to the future, the dp/iii becomes an
most probable correction of the ipf^'s, for which the text twice
text) tpopk Btavoias Si.tr6 Tivos. See reads Spovtris. Among the va-
p. 243, 3. A further distinction rieties of 6piiii irpoKTi/cJ), Stob.
(connecting herewith what may enumerates irpdBeiris, iiri$o\ii,
be otherwise gathered from the irapaffKevijy ^7XffpiJ0'iS, aipiffis,
statements of Stobseus respect- 'irp6de(ris, j3oiJA7;(tis, fleXijfff?, the
ing the Stoic doctrine of im- definitions of which he gives,
pulses) is made between the passing then lo tlie doctrine of
:

EMOTIONS AND VIRTUE. 24.'{

morality, besides arising from the natural impulse Chap.


X.
of a reasonable being, are, at the same time, also
an object towards which his desires are naturally
directed.'
However simple this state of things may be to B. Emo-
a purely rational being, it must be remembered that X'^,*^"'*
man is not purely rational.* He has, therefore, ir- (i) I'lie
, TT emotions.

rational as well as rational impulses, ' He is not (^a) neir .

nature.

emotions, these being also a 368 Klihn) rh Aoyixbv (foy


:

kind of ipfih. It appears, there- aKo\ovdT]TiKhy (f>6iTei ^orl ry \6ytp


fore, that activities of feeling Kai Kark rhy \6yoy as hy Tiyefidya
and will are included in the jrpoKTtKdy troWdKis fi4vTot koI
'

conception of ipfiM, as will be &\?iMS </>6peTat ini riva Kai Sltt^


subsequently seen more fully in Tiyaiy (for so we must punctuate,
the doctrine of emotions, the the reference being to ip/iii
conception of which likewise and aipopii.il, according to the
includes both. definition, p. 242, 2) iwreiflSs t^
' Stoi. ii. 116, similarly Xiytp Q)8o6fi^yov iirl irXeioy, k.t.A.
108 ; irdi/ras yap icvdpt^novs From this, it appears that
atpopii&s ex^tv ^k ipiirews nphs Chrysippus' definition of 6piiii
apeTTjy KaX olovel rh [1. rhv^ ruv (in. Pint. Sto. Rep. 11, 6 = Toi;
Tjfiiafjipeudajv X^you ^X^^^ kut^ rhy hvOptjo-rrov Kiyos TrpoffraKTiKhs
K\dv6riv, 80ei/ dreAets fihv Svras avT^ Tov voie'iv') must not be
eJyat <pa{/\ovs, Te\eta6fVTas Se understood (as in BaMviliauer's
airovSaiovs. Diog. 89, see p. 238, Vet. Philos. Doct, De morte
3 The
; soul rests on the voluntaria, p. 74) to imply
harmony of life with itself that man has only rational,
(virtue) extraneous influences
; and no irrational impulses.
corrupt it, eirei ^ tpiuis aipop/jLcts Chrysippus, in the passage
SlBaffiy aSiaa'Tp6(f}ovs. Sen. Bp. quoted, must either be referring
108, 8 Facile est auditorem
: to that impulse which is pecu-
concitare ad cupiditatem recti liar to man, and is according
omnibus enim natura funda- to his nature ; or else Kiyos
menta dedit semenque vir- must be taken in its more ex-
tutis. tended meaning of notion oi
" The one point, according idea, for all impulses are based
to do. N. D. ii.12, 34, whicti on judgments, see p. 242, 2 ;

distinguishes man from God and it is clear, from Cio. Fin.


is, that God is absolutely iii. 7, 23 ('as our limbs are
rational and by nature good given to us for a definite pur-
and wise. pose, so ipnTi is given for some
^ Chrysippus (in Galen. De definite object, and not for
Hippccr. et Plat. iv. 2, vol. v. every kind of use '), that ipn))
;

244 THE STOICS.

Ghap. originally virtuous, but he becomes virtuous by


X.
overcoming bis emotions. Emotion or passion ' is

a movement of mind contrary to reason and nature,


an impulse transgressing the right mean.^ The
Peripatetic notion, that certain emotions are in ac-
cordance with nature, was stoutly denied by the
Stoics.* The seat of the emotionsand, indeed, of
all impulses and every activity of the soul* ^is in
man's reason, the '^ys/xxiviKov.^ Emotion is that state
of the ^ys/MOviKov in which it is hurried into what
is contrary to nature by excess of impulse Like
virtue, it is due to a change taking place simulta-

is itself rational, but


not in If itwas in one of the lost
first becomes rational by the books (^Heeren suggests in the
direction given to it by man. treatise irepl Traflaii/ opyr\5 Diog.
' The term emotion is used V. 28), was that book genuine 1

to express irdBos, although the ' Acad. i. 10, 39


Cic. : Cum-
terms of modem psychology que eas perturbationes [iraflr)]

are more or less inadequate to antiqui naturales esse dicerent


Express the ancient ideas, as et rationis expertes aliaque in
Cic. Fin. iii. 10, 35, already parte animi cupiditatem, alia
observed. rationem coUocarent, ne his
2 ZHocf. vii. 110 : eo-ri 5e avrh quidem assentiebatur [Zeno].
Nam et perturbationes volun-
Hoi irapa ^vffiv ypvxv^ kIi/tjctis ^ 1 arias esse putabat, opinion-
Spfii) irAeovafouira. The same isque judicio suscipi,et omnium
definitions are found in iStob, ii. perturbationum arbitrabatur
36, with this difiEerence,
166, esse matrem immoderatam
that aireidris r^ aipovvTt \6ycp quandam intemperantiam. Fin.
stands in place of &,\oyos, as in iii. 10, 35 Nee vero perturba-
:

Maro. Awel. ii. 6. Cic. Tuso. tiones animorum vi aliqua . . .

iii. 11, 2i iv. 6, 11


; 21, 47; naturali moventux. Tusc. iv.
Chrysippus in Oale.n. De Hipp, 28, 60 Ipsas perturbationes
:

et Plat. iv. 2, 4 v. 2, 4, vol. v.


; per se esse vitiosas nee habere
368, 385, 432, 458 Kuhn., and quidquam aut naturale aut ne-
Id. in Pint. Tirt. Mor. 10, cessarium.
Sen. Ep. 75, 12. * See
Schl. p. 450 ; p. 215, 8 242, 2. ;

A similar definition is attri- = Chrysippus, in Galen, iii.

buted to Aristotle by Stob. ii. 7, p. 835 ; V. 1 and 6, p. 476


36, but it is no longer to be and above, p. 215, 8.
-found in his extant writings.
:'

EMOTIONS AND VIRTUE. 2i5

heously, nob to the effect of a separate extraneous rJHAP:


X.
force.' Imagination, therefore, alone calls it into
being, as it does impulse in general.^ All emotions
arise from a fault in judgment, from a false notion
of good and and may therefore be called in so
evil,

many words, judgments or opinions * avarice, for ;


instance, is a wrong opinion as to the value of money,''
fear is a wrong opinion as regards future, trouble as
regards present ills.' Still, as appears from the gene-
ral view of the Stoics respecting impulses,^ this
language does not imply that emotion is only a theo-
retical condition. On the contrary, the efifects of a
faulty imagination the feelings and motions of will,
to which it gives rise are expressly included in its

Pint. Virt. Mor. 3, p. 441


' Key. e?j/.], trapaKafi^ilveiTBai [add
(the part of this passage
first S^] TT^v d6^ay iiyrl ttjs aaOeyovs
has been already quoted, p. 215, iiroKTiifieiis. Conf. Cie. Tusc,
3, the continuation being) iv. 7, 14 : Sed omnes pertur-
\eye(r6cu 5e [rh Tyye/xoviKhv^ bationes judicio censent fieri et
&\oyov, Zrav T^ ir\^ov6.^ovrt ttis opinioue . .. opinationem
iffxupv yeyofji^i/Cj} Kal Kparit-
dpfjLTis autem volunt esse imbecillam
ffavri Trp6s ri rav kT^nuiV irapa assensionem. Id. iii. 11, 24 :
rhi/alpovyra \6yoy iKtpeptiTai Est ergo causa omnis in opi-
Kol yhp rh irafloj, k.t.K. See nioue, Dec vero segritudinis
below, note 3. solum sed etiam reliquarum
2 See p. 242, 2. omnium perturbationum 1 Fin.
' IMog. vii. Ill Soice! 5' : iii. 10, 35 Perturbationes
:

avToTs Tcl irdBri KpCffeis clcoi, KoBd autem nulla naturse vi commo-
tprjiri XpiJfftiTTros iv r^ irepl TraOSiv. ventur ; omniaque ea sunt
Put. Virt. Mor. p. 441
o. 3, opiniones ac judicia levitatis.
rb TrdBos eivai \6yov vovuphv KaX Acad. i. 10. See p. 244, 3.
i,K6\aaTov ix ipai\ris (col 8ir)/nap- Diog. 1. u.
TTjfievTjs Kplffeus (T(l>ohp6T'r]ra Ka\ > die. Tusc. iii. 11, 25 iv. ;

bdiixrivirpoaKa^&vra. Stob. ii. 7, 14. Posidon. (in Galen, iv.


168 : M
TrivTuv St tuv t9\s 7, p. 416)
apprehension
: Chrysippus defined
^vxrts Traday cttI 5(J|as outo \eyou- (_&<rii) as S6^a
aw ilvai [instead of which read trp6ff<t)aTos KaKov irapovfflas,
vdvray , - . iradwy S($|as cartas ' See p. 242, 1.
240 THE STOICS.

Chap. conception ;
' nor is it credible, as Galenus states,*
X.
that this was only done by Zeno, and not by Chry-
sippus.^ The Stoics, therefore, notwithstanding their

Cic. Tusc. iv. 7, 15: Sed vp6ir(paTm being Kii^TiKiv ava-


quse judicia quasque opiniones TO'KTis (iK6'yov ^ i/Ktipffeas.

perturbationum esse dixi, non ''


De Hipp, et Plat. v. 1,
in eis pertnrbationes solum p. 429 : XpiiffiTTTTOS fikv oZv iv r^
positas esse diount, verum ilia irpdtrtp irepX ira6av aTrobeiKvvvai
etiam, quse eflElciiintiir pertur- TTftpafai, Kpiffets rivas eivat rov
bationibus, ut segritudo quasi XoyiffTiKov TO Tr&Byj, Z'fjvuiv 5' ov
morsuui quendam doloris ef- ras Kpiffeis aiiTas, csWa tAs ivtyt-
metus recessum quen-
ficiat: yvofi4vas avrais avtTToXhs Kal
dam animi et fagam: Islitia XiJfrcts, itrdptreis re Kal t4$ nrtiffeis
profusam hilaritatem libido ; T7IS ^vxvs iv6fit^ev etyai to irddTj.

effirenatamappetentiam. Galen. Conf. iv. 2, p. 367, and 3,


Hipp, et Plat. iv. 3, p. 377: p. 377.
(T.-ilvuvt KoX iro^Aoiy &\Kois ruif ' Dwg. Ill (see above, p.
^Tw'iKav) ot oit Tcts Kplffeis auTcts 245, 3, and the definition quoted
dA\o koX [should
T^s yfnixii^, on p. 245, 5) confirms the view
perhaps be struck out], rhs iirl that, in the passage referred to
rairats aK6yovs (TvffTo\iis Kal by Galenus, Chrysippus ex-
rairciyiiafis Kol Sfffeii [both for plained the emotions to be
Sefjets, and for \^$is in the Kpitreis. Elsewhere Galenus
passage about to. be quoted asserts (iv. 2, p. 367) that he
from Plutarch, Thurat, Etudes called Ki-iTTj a fielatris iirl (pev-
sur Aristote, p. 249, suggests KT^ SoKovvTt ; TjSov^j an eirapffis
S4(rfis S^|cis is more probable,
i<p' alperi^ SoKovvri vndpx^tv ; and
confirmed too by Cicero's mor- charges him (iv. 6, p. 403),
sus doloris] iirdpireis t6 Kal quoting passages in support of
the charge, with deducing
rfis ^"X^^ irdBii. Plut. Yirt. emotions from arovia and aade-
Mor. 10, p. 449 t4s i-nniaeis : veia xlivxvs. That Chrysippus
T&v traduv Kal rhs (Tf^oSpoTTjras uG agreed with Zeno in his defi-
ylvioBai kotA
<j>aa't Kplaiv, iv tV nition of emotion, has already
?] rh
a^prrjrtKhv, ciAAct t&s been stated (p. 244, 2). No
A^Jfis [8^{ij] Kal ras trvaroXas doubt, too, with an eye to Chry-
Kul rh ^TTOX T(j) a,\6ytii S^xonevas. sippus, Stobseus also (ii. 166)
The same results are involved defines emotion as inoia
in the definitions of emotion (violent mental motion), the
already given, p. 244, 2. In words used being iraaai/ irTolav
reference to this pathological trdBos fivai Kal irdkiv irdQos irrolav ;
action of representations, one and, in Galenus (iv. 5, p. 392),
kind of emotions was defined Chrysippus says : oiKeias 5e
(Stob. ii. 170 ; Cic. Tusc. iv. 7, t4? Twy 7ra6w^ y4vei iLirobldorat
14) as 56^a irp6cr<t>aTos,oi opinio Kol Tnaia Kara rh iv(T$o$r}iJ.fVOV
7]

recens boni (ormali)pra3sentis, TovTO Kal <t>ip6iJievov (K^. Chrys-


EMOTIONS AND VIMTUE. 247

theory of necessity, did not originally assent to the


Socratic dictum, that no one does wrong voluntarily,'

although younger members of the School may have


used an excuse for human faults,^ fearing lest,
it as
in allowing the freedom of emotions, they should
give up their moral inadmissibility and the possi-
bility of overcoming them.' Nay more, as all that

ippus even repeatedly insists tion. This is clear from the


on the difference between fact that the modes in which

emotion and error error being the pathological character of
due to deficient knowledge, emotions displays itself are ap-
emotion to opposition to the pealed to as evidence. See
claims of reason, to a dis- his words in Galen, iv. 6,
turbance of the natural relation p. 409, T^ [1. T(i] re yhp flu/nji
of the impulses (jTiv (\}vfftK^v ipepefftiat wai e|0'T7jWi Koi oi/

rap ipfiSav ffvfjLfieTpiav unepfialj/eiv). vap^ etiyTOis ovS' 4v eavTOiS elfat


He shows that both Zeno's de- Kal irdvff '6<Ta roiavra <pavepws
finitions come to this ( Galen. /j-apTvpei T(p Kpltreis ehal ri irdBTj
iv. 2, p. 368 and iv. 4, p. 385 ;
Khf TTJ \oyiKrj Swdfiei rijs ^uxv^
Stob. ii. 170), and elsewhere rk oiirois
trvyia'TaffSai Kadtiirep Kal
explains (Plat. Yir. Hor. 10, ^XO'Ta. On
the other hand,
p. 450) how emotion takes Zeno never denied the influence
away consideration, and im- of imagination on emotion, as
pels to irrational conduct. The is perfectly clear from the ex-
quotations on p. 246, 1 from pression of Galenus, quoted
Cicero and Stobseus are an pp. 246, 2 246, 1. ;

explanation of positions of Stob. Eel. ii. 190 (Floril.


'

Chrysippus, of which Chrysip- 46, 50) The wise man, accord-


;

pus is himself the source. And ing to the Stoic teaching, exer-
were he not directly the source, cises no indulgence for indul- ;

Galenus (iv. 4, p. 390) observes gence would suppose rhv itnap-


that the view of Chrysippus on TijKiJTa p.)] Trap' ainhv TifiaprtiKlvai
the emotions was generally held wdyTwy ap.apTav6vTQ)v irapa t^p
in the Stoic School after his ISlav KaKiatf.
time. In designating the emo- ^ Ejnctei. Diss. i. 18, ]-7;
tions Kpitreis, Chrysippus can- 28, 1-10 ; ii. 26 ; M. Av/rel. ii.
not therefore have intended 1 ; 14
iv. 3 ; viii.
xii. 12. ; xi. 18 ;

thereby to exclude the emo- This motive can be best


*

tions of impulpe and feeling. gathered from the passages in


All that he meant was, that Cicero already quoted, p. 244,
emotions, as they arise in the 8, and from Sen. De Ira, ii. 2,
individual soul (we should say 1 Anger can do nothing by it-
:

as conditions of consciousness), self, but only animo adpro-


axe called forth by imagina- bante . . . nam si invitis nobis
'2i8 THE STOICS.

Chap. proceeds from our will and impulse is by them de-


X.
clared to be voluntary,' so too emotions are also in
our power ; and, as in the case of every other convic-
tion,^ so in the case of convictions out of which emo-
tions arise, it is for us to say whether we will yield or
withhold assent.' would they allow
Just as little

that only instruction is needed in order to overcome


emotions for all emotions arise, as they say, from
;

lack of self-control,^ and differ from errors in that they


assert themselves and oppose our better intelligence.*
How irregular and irrational impulses arise in reason
was a point which the Stoics never made any serious
attempt to explain.

nascitur, nunquam rationi suo- from Chrysippus, of whom simi-


cumbet. Omnes enim motus lar remarks were quoted, p. 246,
qui non voluntate nostra fiunt 3 Trav yap irdOos &tciffTiK6v eariv,
:

invicti et inevitabiles sunt, Koi voWiiKis 6pwi/Tas robs iv


(J)?

&c. Tois trddeoty SvTas Sti (TvfjiipepeL


' Seep. 179, 3, 4. T^y tTtpoSa6T7i-
T(i5 ov TTOieiy, uirb
2 See p. 88, 1. ros ^Ktpipofkivtws . . cLvdyeffOat
Cic. Acad. i. 10, 39
Per- : vphs rh TTotf'tv avrh irdvres . . .

turbationes voluntarias esse. S' oi iv TOLS trdOeffiv litres airo-


Tusc. iv. 7, 14 Emotions pro-
: aTp^<povrai Thv \6yov, ou iropa-
ceed from judgment itaque ; irKriffiws Se rots e^ipraTTtfievots iv
eas definiunt pressius, ut intel- &TUOVV, &^\* i5ia^6vT(os. ot fihv
ligatur non modo quam vitiosse, yhp ijnaTTifievoi . . . SiSaxflevTcs
sed etiam quam in nostra sunt . . . iuptffravrai Tris Kpitreas ' ol
potestate, upon which follow S* iv ToiS Trd0e<Ttv ^cres, Kti.v fid-

the definitions quoted, p. 246, Boifft Ktiv fieTaSiSax&&(yiVf bn ou


1. Sci XimeTaSai fl 0o$f7ff6ai ^ SAks
Oic. Tusc. iv. 9, 22 : Om- iv To7s trdOeatv eTvai rijs }]/vxVSy
nium autem afllectionum fon- dfitosovK aipiiTTavTai Toinav aXV
tem esse diount intemperan- &yovTai inrh tUv iraBuv e*s ri vwh
tiam quas est a tota
(&/tptTcio) Toinuv Kpareio'dat rvpavviBos. A
mente et a recta ratione de- different view is taken by
f eotio sic aversa a prffiscriptione JBpiatet. Diss. i. 28, 8, who o
rationis ut nuUo modo adpeti- proposoi Medea remarks : il,i)Trd-
tiones anima nee regi nee con- TrjTOi- iiit,ov owrp ivapyus, 3ti
tineri queant. i^r]TrdrnTo.i, Kol ou iroi^trei.
' Sttib. Bel. ii. 170, probably
EMOTIONS AND VIRTUE. 24{)

Emotions being called forth by imagination, their Chap.


peculiar character depends on the kind of imagina-
tion which produces them. Now, all our impulses (?) T-'urie-

are directed to what is good and evil, and consist emotion.


either in pursuing what appears to us to be a good,
or in avoiding what appears to us to be an evil.' This
good and this evil is sometimes a present, and some-
times a future object. Hence there result four chief
classes of faulty imagination, and, corresponding with
them, four classes of emotions. From an irrational
opinion as to what is good there arises pleasure,
when it refers to things present ; desire, when it re-
fers to things future. A faulty opinion of present
evils produces care ; of future evils, fear.'^ Zeno had
already distinguished these four principal varieties
of emotions.^ The same division was adopted by his
pupil Aristo,* and afterwards became quite general.
Yet the vagueness, already mentioned, appears in the
Stoic system in the definition of individual emo-
tions. By some, particularly by Chrysippus, the es-
sence of these emotions is placed in the imagination
which causes them ; by others, in the state of mind
which the imagination produces.^ The four principal

See p. 2i2,
' 2. The same In Clem. Strom, ii. 407, A,
*

idea is expressed in applying the words being vpbs iKov ri


the terms alperhv and (f>evKThv nrptixopBov, tiSqvtjv, Autttiv, (p6-
to good and evil (Stob. ii. 126 $ov, iTnOvfilav, iroWij? Set t^s
and 142 see p. 229, 1, and
j
io-Kija-eajs xal fiixts.
232, 3). The
definition of Kimi) or
^ Stoh. ii. 166 Cic. Tusc.
;
Sffjj(Cicero EBgritudo) as S((|a
iii. 11 ; iv. 7, 14 ; 15, 43 Fin. ; irpdff^aros kukov irapovtrias is ex-
iii. 10, 35. plioitly referred to Chrysippus
' According to Dioff. 110, (more at length in Cio. Tusc.
this distinction was fovind in iv. 7, 14 : Opinio recens mali
the treatise irepl iradav. praasentis, in quo demitti oon-
:

250 THE STOICS.

Chap. classes of emotions were again subdivided into nume-


X.
rous subordinate classes, in the enumeration of which
the Stoic philosophers appear to have been more
guided by the use of language than by psychology.'
In treating the subject of emotions in general,
far less importance was attached by the Stoics to
psychological accuracy than to considerations of
moral worth. That the result could not be very satis-

trahique animo rectrnn esse latter definitions appear to be-


videatur), as also the definition long to Zeno. They were pro-
of <pl\apyvpia= bir6\T)'^i^ rav to bably appropriated by Chrys-
apyipiov Ka\bv ^Ipai. See p. 254, ippus,and the additions made
4, 5. In like manner jhe'St), axo- which are found in StobEeus.
Kaaia, and the other passions, ' Further particulars may
were, according to Siog. 110, be gathered from Diog. vii.
defined. To Chrysippus also Ill Stoi. ii. 174.
; Both in-
belong the definitions quoted clude under KiTrri sub-divisions
Tusc. iv. 7, 14 iii'. 11, 25 of
; as 'i\ios, <j>06vos, ^Aos, f7)^o-
TjSoo^ (Ifetitia, voluptas ges- &X0OS, avla, o^ivrj.
Tuiria, Dio-
tiens) = opinio recens boni prse- genes adds ifSxAriC's and iriy-
sentis, in quo ellerri rectum Xuff's ; Stobsus TTeVfios, &x<>^,
videatur of fear = opinio im-
;
fiirr). Both include under <p6pos,
pendentis mali quod intolera- Seijita, ijKvoS) ai(rx^vTj, 6K7r\7?|is,
bile esse videatur, agreeing 86pvl3os, i.yu)i>ia; Stobaeus adds
Vfiththe irpoaSoKia xaKovot Siog. Seos and SeKridaifjLovia. Under
112 ;of desire (cupiditas, libido, ilSovii, Diogenes includes ic-ft-

dwiBvn(a) = opinio venturi boni, XTjffts, iirixaLpsKaKiai, repT^is^ Sid-


quod sit ex usu jam prsesens Xi'C'S ; Stobaeus, i-TrixaipucaKiai,
esse atque adesse. It is, how- &(rjuVia^ol, yorjTetai Kal ra d^oia.
ever, more common to hear Under iiriSv^ia. Diogenes places
Atot) (Biog. Ill ; Stob. 172 CTrdviSj fitffos, tpLXoveiida, opy^,
do. Tusc. iii. 11) described as ipms. /ivfLs, 8uiJ,6s ; Stobseus,
tri/ffToA^ y^/ux^s a.ireid))S ^6y^, opy)} KoX rh i57j avTrts {Qviibs,
more briefly crvToX)\ &Koyos, X^XoSy M^ws, KdroSy irtKpia.
fear as ^kkKktls a.Trei9^s Kdytp^ K.T.K.), epwres cr(podpo\, trSOoi,
ijSou^ even according to Alex. *{fj.pot, ^piKti^ovioUy (()L\0'ir\ovTiai,
Aphir. top. 96, as SAoyoj hrapais (pi\oSo^iai.Definitions for all
c'^' alpsTcfi two
SoKovvTi iniipxeiv, these terms which, without
different translations of which doubt, belong to Chrysippus
are given by Cio. 1. c. and Kin. may be found in the writers
ii. 4, 13, iiriOvfAla as ^pe^ts d.-irei- named. Greek lexicographers
or
e5)s \6ja!, immoderata appe- may obtain many useful hints
titio opinati magni boni. The from Stoic definitions.
:

EMOTIONS AND VIRTUE. 261

factory, follows from what has been already stated.' UHAP.


Emotions are impulses, overstepping natural limits,
X
upsetting the proper balance of the soul's powers,
contradicting reason in a word, they are failures,
disturbances of mental health, and, if indulged in,
become chronic diseases of the soul.'^ Hence a Stoic

' Plwt. Yir. Mor. 10, p. 4i9 ^auoviTi Tct jU^ atperet ircpiSpa
irav ^iv yctp Trddos afxafyria kot^ alpcTh flvai (Stob. translations
ainovs ^(XTiv KaX ttSs 6 Kinro^ixevos of the definition in Cicero and
^ tpo^O'v^evos ^ itriQvixiav CLfjLap- Seneca). The opposite of such
rdvei. The Stoics are therefore a 56^11, or a confiision arising
anxious to make a marked dis- from false fear, is an opinio ve-
tinction in the expressions for hemens iuhserens atque insita
emotions and the permitted de re non fugienda tanquam
mental affections, between
fugienda such as hatred of
pleasure and joy, see p. 236, 2, womankind, hatred of mankind,
fear and precaution (eiAa/Seio), &o. If the fault is caused by
desire and will (Soi!\i)irif, Diog. some weakness which prevents
116; cupere et velle, Sen. Ep. our acting up to our better
116, 1), alffxii'V and alSiis (^Plut. knowledge, the diseased states
Vit. Pud. c. 2, p. 529). of the soul are called o^^wo-t^-
' On this favourite proposi- /iaTa,negrotationes {Diog. ; Stob.;
tion of the Stoics, consult Dio0. Cic. Tus. iv. 13, 29) but this
;

115 ; Stob. ii. 182 Oic. Tuso.


; distinction is, of course, very
iv. 10 whose remarkable
; uncertain. , The same fault is
agreement with Stobeeus seems at one time classed among
to point to a common source of v6iroi, at another among oi^^m-
information directly or in- a-Tiinara; and Cicero (11,24;
directly drawn upon by both ; 13, 29) repeatedly observes
iii. 10, 23 Galen. Hipp, et
; that the two can only be dis-
Plat. V. 2 ; Sen. Ep. 75, 11. Ac- tinguished in thought. More-
cording to these passages, the over, just as there are certain
Stoics distinguish between sim- predispositions (ete/wrranrfai)
ple emotions and diseases of for bodily diseases, so within
the soul. Emotions, in the the sphere of mind there are
language of Seneca, are motus evKaracl>opittt els irddos. Diog.y
animi improbabiles soluti et Stob., Cic. 12. The distinctioij
eoncitati. If they are fre- between vitia and morbi (6'ie.
quently repeated and neglected, 13) naturally coincides with
then inveterata vitia et dura, the distinction between emo-
or diseases, ensue. Disease of tions and diseases. The former
the soul is therefore defiiied as are caused by conduct at vari-
5(i|a iwiBv/iias i^^vnKv7a eis e^ik ance with principles, by incon-
sta^ntia et repugnautia, like-i
;
:

252 THE STOICS.

Chap. demands their entire suppression: true virtue can


X.
only exist where this process has succeeded. As
being contrary to nature and symptoms of disease,
the wise man must be wholly free from them.' When
we have once learnt to value things according to
and to discover everywhere nature's
their real worth,
unchanging law, nothing will induce us to yield to
emotion.^ Hence the teaching of Plato and Aris-
totle, requiring emotions to be regulated, but not up-
rooted, was attacked in the most vigorous manner
by these philosophers. A moderate evil, they say,
always remains an evil. What is faulty and op-
posed to reason, ought never to be tolerated, not even
in the smallest degree.* On the other hand, when
wise vitiositas in a, habitus in Olc. Acad. i. 10, 38: Cum-
'

tota vita ineonstans the latter


; que perturbationem animi illi
consist in corruptio opinionum. [superiores] ex homine non
It is not consistent with this tollerent . . . sed eam contra-
view to call KaKiat, Siadeffeis herent in angustumque dedu-
and kJitoi, as well as a^j>a>arl]- cerent : hie omnibus his quasi
fiara and evKaTa(f)opiat, e'lety (^Stob. morbis voluit carere sapientem.
ii. 100, on the difference be- lUd. ii. 43, 135. "We shall find
tween e|is and SidSfins. see 102, subsequently that the mental
1) ; and, accordingly, Heine affections, which cause emo-
suggests (De Font. Tuscul. Dis. tions, are allowed to be un-
Weimar, 1863, p. 18) that, on avoidable.
this point, Cicero may have 2 do. Tusc. iv. 17, 37.

given inaccurate information. ' Cic. Tusc. iii. 10, 22 Omne :

The unwise who are near wis- enim malum, tiam mediocre,
dom are free from disease of magnum est. Nos autem id
the soul, but not from emo- agimus, ut id in sapiente nul-
tions (_&n., Cic). The points lum sit omnino. Ibid. iv. 17,
of comparison between diseases 39 Modum tu adhibes vitio ?
:

of the body and those of the An vitium nullum est non


soul were investigated byChrys- parere rationi ? Ibid. 18, 42 :

ippus with excessive care. Po- Nihil interest, utrum moderatas


sidonius contradicted him, ho w- perturbationes approbent, an
ever, in part ( Oalen, 1. c, Cic. moderatam injustitiam, &c.
10, 23 12, 27) ; but their differ-
; Qui enim vitiis modum apponit,
ences are not of interest bo us. is partem susoipit vitiorum.
;

EMOTIONS AND VIRTXIE. 253

an emotion is regulated by and subordinated to rea- Chap.


"

son, it ceases to be an emotion, the term emotion


only applying to violent impulses, which are opposed
to reason.^ The statement of the Peripatetics, that
certain emotions are not only admissible, but are
useful and necessary, appears of course to the Stoics
altogether wrong.^ To them, only what is morally
good appears to be useful : emotions are, under all

circumstances, faults ; and were an emotion to be


useful, virtue would be advanced by means of what
is wrong.^ The right relation, therefore, towards
emotions indeed, the only one morally tenable is

an attitude of absolute hostility. The wise man


must be emotionless.'' Pain he may feel, but, not
regarding it as an evil, he will suffer no affliction,

and know no fear.^ He may be slandered and ill-


treated, but he cannot be injured or degraded. Being

Sen. Bp. 85, 5, says that mo- a virtute mahim, ut unquam


deration of emotions is equiva- ratio ad vitia confugiat.
lent to modice insaniendum, ' 117 </>a(rl Si koL
JDiog. vii. :

modlce segrotandum. Ep. 116, airaSij Tin (T6(fiov, 5io rb


sTfai
1 : Ego non video, quomodo hviiaTwrov (faultless) dvai.
salubris esse aut utilis possit From the apathy of the wise
uUa mediocritas morbi. man, absence of feeling and
' Sen. De Ira, i. 9, 2 par- ;
severity, which are faults, must
ticularly with reference to be distinguished,
anger, conf. Ep. 85, 10. ' Chrysippus (in Stoi.
^ Full details are given by Floril. vii. 21) : ihyflv pev rhv
Cic. Tusc. iv. 19-26 ; Off. i. 25, a-6(pov nil Pacravi^effBai S4- ij.ii -yip
88 Sen. De Ira, i. 5, 21 ; ii.
;
ivSiSSmi rp ij/uxs. Sen. De
Prov.
12 ; particularly with regard to 6, 6 ; Bp. 85, 29 ; Cic. Tusc. ii.
the use of anger. 12, 29 ;25, 61 ; iii. 11, 25.
s
In the same spirit Sen. i. Phd. Sto. Eep. 20, 12
9, 1 10, 2, meets the assertion
; Musonius (in Stoi. Floril. 19,
that valour cannot dispense 16) ; Sen. De
Const. 2 3 ; 5 ; 7 ; ;

with anger by saying: Nun- 12. The second titleofthistrea-


quam virtus vitio adjuvanda tise is nee injuriam nee con-
:

est se contents absit hoc


. . . tumeliam accipere sapientem.
254 THE STOICS.

Chap, untouched by honour and dishonour, he has no vanity,


'

To anger ' he never yields, not needing this irrational


impulse, not even for valour and the championship
of right. also feels no pity,** and exercises
But he
no indulgence.* For how can he pity others for
what he would not himself consider an evil ? How
can he yield to a diseased excitement for the sake
of others, which he would not tolerate for his own
sake ? If justice calls for punishment, feelings will
not betray him into forgiveness. We shall subse-
quently have an opportunity for learning the further
application of these principles.
(2) Idea Virtue is thus negatively defined as the being

(a^Posi- exempt from emotions, as apathy ;* but there is also


tive and a positive side supplementing this barely negative
negative . r . , . ,-,

aspects. View. Looking at the matter ot virtuous action, this

may be said to consist in subordination to the gene-


ral law of nature, looking at its manner, in rational
self-control.' Virtue is exclusively a matter of rea-
son ^ in short, it is nothing else, but rightly-ordered
reason.' To speak more explicitly, virtue contains

'
See 253, 2 and 3 and do. 6, p. 24) : rliv t' opcT?)i/ Siofleiny
Tuso. iii. 9, 19. eTvai iiioKoyouiiivriv.
2 Cie. Tusc: iii. 9, 20 ; Sen. ' do. Acad. i. 10, 38 Cum- :

De Clem. ii. 5 ; Diog. vii. 123. que superiores (Aristotle and


' Stoh: Eel. ii. 190 ; Floril. others) non omnem virtutem
46, 60 Sen. 1. c. 5, 2 ; 7 ; Diog.
; in rations esse dicerent, sed
1. c; Gell.'S. A.-Kiv. i, i. quasdam virtutes natura aut
* Ps. Pint. v. Horn. 134 ot : more perfectas hie [Zeuo] :

lih oiv StioVko! Trji/ iperiiv rlSef- omnes in ratione ponebat.


TcLi iv T7 wiraBdi}. ' do. Tuso. iv. 15, 34 Ipsa :

See p. 193. Alex. Aphr.


' virtus brevissime recta ratio
De An. 156, b. Virtue consists dici potest. Conf. Sen. Ep.
in iK\oy)i T&v /carol ipiaiv. Diog. 113, 2 Virtus autem nihil
:

vii. 89 (conf. Plut. Aud. Po. c. aliud est quam animus quodam-
EMOTIONS AND VIRTUE. 256

in itself two elements one practical, the other spe- Chap.


dilative. At the root, and as a condition of all

rational conduct, lies, according to the Stoics, right


knowledge ; and on this point they are at one with
the well-known Socratic doctrine, and with the teach-
ing of the Cynics and Megarians. Natural virtue,
or virtue acquired only by exercise, they reject alto-
gether, defining virtue, after the manner of Socrates,
as knowledge, vice as ignorance,' and insisting on the
necessity of learning virtue.'* Even the avowed enemy
of all speculative enquiry, Aristo of Chios, was on
this point at one with the rest of the School. All
virtues were by him referred to wisdom,' and, conse-
quently, he denied the claims of most to be virtues
at all."

But, however closely the Stoics cling to the idea


that all virtue is based on knowledge, and is in itself -

nothing else but knowledge, they are not content


with knowledge, or with placing knowledge above

modo se habens, and the re- tues into eVirrTifio>/i/al Ka\ fleaprj-
marks, p. 128, 1 129, 3. ; .tikoI {crva-raaw ex"""''" ''"wf
' The proof of this will be and kee^frifToi for
ecajprjiCioTwy) ;

found subsequently in the Stoic by the latter must be under-


"deiinitions of various virtues stood not the virtuous actions
and vices. Compare prelimin- themselves, but only the states
arily 254,6 and Biog. vii. 93 : resulting from them health of
elrai 8' ayvoias Ttis KaKi'as, S ai soul, strength of will, and the
operal iirurrrjuai.. Stob. Ecl. ii. like. On the health of the
108 ravras lifv ovv ras ^rjfleio-ns
:
soul, in its relation to virtue,
aperis Ts\4as ehtu \eyov<Ti irepl see Cic. Tusc. iv. 1 3, 30.
Tij/jSioc/caitrweo-TTjicwaieKflewpi)- ' Diog. vii. 91 (following
It is not opposed to these
/iiircoj'. Cleanthes, Chrysippus and
statements for Stob. ii. 92 and others) ; Ps. Pint. V. Horn.
110, to distinguish othervirtues 144.
besides those which are re'x'''" ' See p. 260, 3.
and ittia-rriii.ai ; nor for Hecato Pint. Sto. Bep. 7 ; Diog.
in {Diog. vii. 90) to divide vir- vii. 161 ; Galrni, vii. 2, p. 595.
256 TSM STOICS.

Chap, practical activity, as Plato and Aristotle had done.


-
As we have seen already that, with them, knowledge
was only a means towards rational conduct,' so it is
expressly mentioned, as a deviation from the teach-
ing of the School, that Herillus of Carthage, Zeno's
pupil, declared knowledge to he the end of Ufe,
and the only unconditional good.^ Virtue may, it is

true, be called knowledge, but it is, at the same time,


essentially healthand strength of mind, a right state
of the soul agreeing with its proper nature ' and it ;

is required of man that he should never desist from

labouring and contributing towards the common


good.'' Thus, according to Stoic principles, virtue
is such a combination of theory and practice, in
which action is invariably based on intellectual
knowledge, but, at the same time, knowledge finds

'See p. 56. good in our conduct from


'See p. 58, 2. Diog. vli. drovia and la-xis ; what is bad,
165, Conf. 37 "Hpi\A.os Si b
: from i.TOiiia koX lta-8tveia -rrjs \liu-
KapxvSivios t^Kos elire tV ^ti- X^s i
and (ibid. vii. ], p. 590)
aT-fiix-ni', Kirep icrrl fpv oel irdvTa he referred the differences of
ava(l>epovra irphs -rh /it' inar-l}- individual virtues to changes
f-ris Cv" tol f'h T?) a.ivoi(f Siafie- in quality within the soul. Bj
$\r]ij.emr. iiuat 5e tV ^iruTTiiiinv Aristo, p. 220, 1, virtue is de-
(jmvTainav irpoaSi^fi i/ie-
'i^iy ii' fined as health by Stub. ii.
;

rdirraTov iirh Xiyov. On the 104, as SicESsiris i/zox^i ain^aivos


definition, seep. 82, 1. aurp; by Siog. 89, aa SMeais
' Cleanthes (in Plut. Sto. 6ii.o\oyovfii.4vn.
Rep. 7) When rSros, on which
: ' Sen. De Otio, i. (28) 4 :

see p. 128, 2, is found in the Stoioi nostri dicunt : usque ad


soul in a proper degree, l<rxiis ultimum vifee finem in actu
KoXeiToi Kal Kpiros r) 8' iVxir erimus, non desinemus com-
oD'tt) t!> Kp6,Tos Srav fjiiv iir\
Kal muni bono operam dare, &c.
Toir ivufavidiv ^/ifisyeTioif iy- Nos sumus, apud quos usque eo
yevriTai iyxpdTfid 4<rTi, k.t.\. In nihil ante mortem otiosum est,
the same way, Chrysippus (ac- ut, si res patitur, non sit ipsa
cording to Galen, Hipp, et Plat, mors otiosa.
iv. 6, p. 403) deduced what is

EMOTIONS AND VIRTUE. 257

its object in moral conduct it is, in shqxt, power of Chap.


'

will based on rational understanding.^ Nor yet must


this definition be taken to imply that moral know-
ledge precedes will, and is only subsequently re-
ferred to will, nor conversely that the will only uses
knowledge as a subsidiary instrument. In the eyes
of a Stoic, knowledge and will are not only insepa-
rable, but they are one and the same thing. Virtue
cannot be conceived without knowledge, nor know-
ledge without virtue.^ The one, quite as much as
the other, is a right quality of the so.ul, or, speak-
ing more correctly, is the rightly-endowed soul,
reason, when it is as it ought to be.' Hence virtue
may be described, with equal propriety, either as
knowledge or as strength of mind ; and it is irre-
levant to inquire which of these two elements is

anterior in point of time.


But how are we to reconcile with this view the (j) The
"''*"''
o of a plurality
Stoic teaching r J
of virtues and their
severalli/.
mutual relations ? As the common root from which
they spring, Zeno, following Aristotle, regarded un-
derstanding, Cleanthes, strength of mind, Aristo, at
one time health, at another the knowledge of good
and evil.* Later teachers, after the time of Chry-
'
This will appear from the amhs iperiiv iiroiei kcH iyifiav
definitions of virtue about to ayiiiiiofe, k.t.X. Jd. on Zeno,
follow. see p. 260, 3, and Cleanthes, p.
' See pp. 59, 1 56, 2.
; 236, According to Galenus,
3.
' See
p. 254, 7. Sea. Bp. Aristo defined the one virtue
65, 6, after describing a great to be the knowledge of good
ar.d noble soul, adds Talis : and evil (Hlpp_. et Plat. v. 5, p.
animus virtus est. 168) : KdWiovoli/'Apla-Twi' i XTos,

* Pint. Vir. Mor. 2 : 'Aplaruv oi/re iroWiis ehcu rot Apsris rfjs

Be 6 Xios Tp /jLif ovai(f liiav koX r/fi/xi)' aTroiprii/diJ.eiios, AAAA /itai',

S
: ;

358 THE STOICS.

Chap. sippus, thought that it consisted in knowledge or


X.
wisdom, understanding by wisdom absolute know-
ledge, the knowing all things, human and divine.'
From this common root, a multiplicity of virtues
was supposed to proceed, which, after Plato's example,
are grouped under four principal virtues^ intelli-

iiv ivuTTimnv iyaSav te koI kukSiv ing particular virtues as spring-


thai i/jijo-iy. vii. 2, p. 595. ing from the essence of virtue,
vofxitxas yovv 6 'Apicrrtav, fiiav with the addition of a differen-
elvai TTJs ypvxvs Siva/jLiv, y \oyi^6- tial quality, he needed separate
fieda, /cat r^v ap^r^v ttJs ^vxv^ terms to express generic and
^6eT0 ^iav, iitLiTT'fifiTiv hyaSSov Kal specific virtue. In Zeno's de-
Koxav. The statement that finition too, as later writers
Aristo made health of soul would have it (^Plwt. Vir. Mat.
consist in a right view of good 2), to <^p6vi\ais was given the
and evil agrees with the lan- meaning of eTrio-T^/w;.
guage of Plutarch. Perhaps 2 Aperal irpwTiu. Diog. 92 ;

Zeno had already defined Stoi. ii. 104. In stating that


as StTLffTijfnn a7a0ei)j/ KaX
(pp6yi}(^ts Posidonius counted four
KaKUV, Cleanthes, Chrysippus, and An-
' Conf. p. 255, 1. Cic. De tipater more than four virtues,
Off. i. 153 Princepsque om-
43, : Diogenes can only mean that
nium virtutum est ilia sapien- the latter enumerated the
tia, quam <ro(j)tai' Grseci vocant subdivisions, whereas Posi-
prudentiam enim, quam Grseci donius confined himself to the
(ppSvjiffiv diount, aliam quandam four main heads of the four
intelligimus quse est rerum
: cardinal virtues. Besides this
expetendarum f ugiendarumque division of virtues, another,
scientia. Ilia autem soientia, threefold, division is also met
quam principem dixi, rerum with, see p. 56, 2 ; 57, 1, that
est divinarum atque human- into logical, physical, and
arum A similar de-
scientia. ethical virtues. In other words,
finition of wisdom, amplified the whole of philosophy and
by the words, nosse divina et likewise its parts are brought
humana et horum 'oausas, is under the notion of virtue
found Ibid. ii. 2, 5. Sen. Ep. but it is not stated how this
85. 5 PlMt. Plac. Prooem. 2 ;
; threefold division is to har-
Straho, i. 1, 1. It may proba- monise with the previous four-
bly be referred to Chrysippus ; fold one. A twofold division,
and it was no doubt Chrysip- made by Panetiusandreferre4
pus who settled the distinction to by Seneca (Ep. 94, 45)
between ao^ia and (pp6miins, in that into theroretical and prac-
the Stoic school, although tical virtues is an approxima-
Aristo had preceded him in tion to the ethics of the Peri.-
distinguishing them. Explain- patetics.
EMOTIONS AND VIRTUE. 259

.genee, bravery, justice, self-comtrol.' Intelligence Chap.


X.
consists in knowing what is good and bad, and what
is neither the one nor the other, the indifl'erent ^
;

bravery, in knowing what to choose, what not to


avoid, and what neither to choose nor to avoid ; or,

substituting the corresponding personal attitude for


knowledge, bravery is fearless obedience to the law
of reason, both in boldness and endurance-'' Self-
control consists inknowing what to choose, and what
to eschew, and what neither to choose nor eschew * ;

justice, in knowing how to give to everyone what is


his due.* In a corresponding manner, the principal

'
The scheme was in vogue sine timore. The last-named
"before Zeno's time. See Plut. characteristic appears still more
Sto. Eep. 7, 1, and the quota- strongly in the definition at-
tions, p. 260, 3. tributed to the Stoics by Cic.
Off. i. 19, 62 Virtus propug-
:

KoL oitSerepuv, or kKatnwv Stv nans pro aequitate.


oh iroifiTeov koL oiiSe-
troLTiriov KoX * itTitrj'tju.Tj CilpeTwy Koi (ftevK-
Tipant. Stobseus adds,
Stob. 102. Ttov KaX ovSerdpotv. Stob. 102,
that the definition needs to be The definition of in <fip6vriiris

completed by the words, occur- Cicero the same, word for


is
ring in the definition of every word. See p. 258, 1 that of ;

virtue, (p^ffei TroMriKoO fyow. valour in Diogenes is not very


But this is superfiuous, for only different. Since all duties
in the case of such a being can refer to irotTjrea and ob troiTjrea,
the terms good and evil apply. the definitions of the remain-
Diog. 92; iSeart. Math. xi. 170 ing virtues must necessarily
and 246; Cio. I.e. agree with those of ippovriiTis.
' itriffTiifjiTj Setviav f ol o& Seivwy * iniffT-fifiTi aTTovefiriTLK^ ttjs
Kai ovSerepaiv (^Stob. 104) ; i-Trur- in Stob. Id. p. 104,
dji'as iKiiirTijj,

TflfiTJ ^v aipereoi/ Kol uv v\a$lj- further enumerates the points


TeovKcii ov^erepuv {Dioff.) ;
iiriff- of difference between the four
Sc xp^ ea^jiiiv ^ fiii Ba^peiv
Ti]IJ.i\ virtues Intelligence refers to
:

{Galen. Hipp, et Plat. vii. 2, KaS4]KovTa, self-control to im-


.597). Cic. Tusc. iv. 24, 63, pulses, valour to {nroinoval, jus-
conf. V. 14, 41: (Chrysippus) tice to aTrove/iiiirfis. See also
fortitudo est, inquit, scientia the distinctive peculiarities of
perferendarum rerum, vel affec- the four virtues in Stob. 112.
tio animi in patiendo ac per- Below, p. 263.
ierendo, summie legi parens
s 2
'

260 THE STOICS.

Chap. faults are traced back to the conception of igno-


X.
rance.' Probably all these definitions beldng to

Chrysippus.^ Other definitions are attributed to his


predecessors,' some more, others less, agreeing with
him in respect of their conception of virtue. Within
these limits, a great number of individual virtues
were distinguished, their differences and precise
shades of meaning being worked out with all the
pedantry which characterised Chrysippus/ The de-
' Diog. 93 ; Stol. 104. The Stoi/ fikv oiv alpeiffBal re i4ri
TTfuTai icaKlai are a^poffvvi}, Sei-
: T&7a0a Kol <l>e{ryeiv rh. /co/ccb, tV
A(o, i.Ko\airia, aSmia. The de- hri(TTi\p.l\v TT^vde /coXei actxppoffi-
finition of cuppoavni is &ymia VT)!/ ' Urav Si irpaTTew fiey rayoBit,
ayaOwv koI KaKwv Kol oi/Berdptev. lii] TrpaTTeiv Sh Tcfc Ko/ccb, tppdjnjffiv
See p. 255,- 1. avipeiav Se (irav to fihv flo^^p, tA
' This follows from the fact 5e (pe^yy' Sto// 5e rh Kar* &^lav
that the conception of iTruTriiiiri CKaartp vefirj, SiKaioiT^VTjv evl 5e
is the basis in all. See p. 258, \(J7q/, yiv(^ffKov(Ta /le// fi ^vxh
1. Xcupls Tov TrpdTTeiv rayaOii t6 /col
' Of Zeno, Phit. Vir. Mor. 2, /CO/C& <ro(pta t' itrrl /col iirurTriiiii,
p. 441, says: dpi^d^ievos r^v Trphs Se rits Trpd^els h<\>lKvov^fvri
l^p6v7\(TlV iv fJLGV CLTTOVe^TireOtS Si- TOJ /cotJ -rhv ploy ofd/UOTO ir\eiai
KawcrivTjv iy S* alpiTeois (rco(ppo- \a^pdvi Tci irpoaprifieva. We
cr6vi]f iv 5' iirofievr4oLs ^vSptav. know, from Pint. Sto. Eep. 7,
The like in regard to justice in 4, see p. 256, 3, that, according
Sto. Eep. 7, 2. On the other to Cleanthes, strength of mind,
hand valour is here termed %ray p.iv eVl toTs iirt(pav(riv ^jti-
<t>p6v7i(Tis in iiiepyriTeoi!. He also fievereots 4yy4p7iTaif iyKpdTeii
says, p. 440, that, according to iffTiv lirav S* iv tois virofifve-
Aristo, ri apsTij jroiriTEo /liv im- reois, avSpeia' trepl rhs a^ias Sh,
(TKOiroVffa KoL fX^ VOltlTSa K4K\7}Tai SiKcuotr{ivT] ' irepl tAs alp4(reis /col
<pp6i'ri(ns' ^TTiBvfiiav Se KOfTfjt,o\iffa 4KK\i(reLS, (TaKppoaiinr]. With him,
KaX t6 fjLejpaoj/ Kai rh eitKaipov too, if Plutarch's account is ac-
4v ridotfcus dpiCovffa^ atatppoffiirff
curate, iyKpdreia, or persever-
Koivavi\im<ri 5e /col <rvfi.$oKalois ance, takes theplace of <l>p6yri(rts,
6p.t?i.ov(Ta To7s trphs erepot's, 5i- do. Tusc. iv. 24, 53,*quotes no
Kcuuirivr). Farther particulars less than three definitions of
as to Aristo may be found in bravery given by Sph^rus. See
Galen. Hipp, et Plat. vii. 2, p. p. 259, 3.
69.5 Since the soul has only
: ' Phct. Vir. Mor. 2, p. 441,
one power, the power of thought, charges him with creating a
it can only have one virtue, (Tfirivos aperaii/ ov irvvTjBfs ou5e
the eVitTT^^Tj ayaduj/ /col KaKuv. yviipifiov, and forming a x'p'e>'-
;

EMOTIONS AND VIRTUE, 261

finitions of a portion or them have been preserved Chap.


by Diogenes and Stobseus.' In a similar way, too, _^!_^___
the Stoics carried their classification of errors into
the minutest details.^
The importance attaching to this division of (c) Mutual
virtues, the ultimate basis on which it rests, and the "tj^^^j^al
relation which they bear, both to one another and to mrtues.

the common essence of virtue, are topics upon which


Zeno never entered. Plutarch, at least, blames him^
for treating virtues as many, and yet inseparable,
and at the same time for finding in all only certain
manifestations of the understanding. Aristo at-
tempted to settle this point more precisely. Accord-
ing to his view, virtue is in itself only one ; in
speaking of many virtues, we only refer to the va-
riety of objects with which that one virtue has to
t6t71!, iiTe\6TTis. fi.ja\6Tris, Ka\6- ' Stob. 106, includes under
T7JS, eVi5e|t(JT7?9, euoTrai/TT7(rio, eu- <pp6vTlffts, eiifiovKia, evXoyurria,
Tpaire\ia, after the anology of d7x(>'oio, voui/exfut, eu/XTixaWa
irpa6Tris, avSpffa, &0. In Stoi. under aanpfoaiirn, euToJia, Koff-
ii. 118, among the Stoic virtues, (uSttis, aiSriiiO<rivn, iyicpdreta ;

is found an ipanxT} as lirtirT^/*?; under ai/Speia, Kaprepia^ 6a^^a\i6-


viwv flTJpos (v(puai>, &e., and a tjjv, iieyaKo<f>vxia, ^v^vxia, ipiAo-
{rvfiiroTiKi] as ^niar^iMT] rod wwy vovla ; under StKaiorriit/f], eutre-
86* e^iyeirSat tA trvfivSaia Kai tov 0eia (on which jyiog. 119),
Treifs Set ffvfi-n-lveti'. An ipuTlKh xP^^'^^'^'^^t evKoivuvnfyia, eiiffw-
and o-u/iitotik}) aperii are also aWa^la. Diog. 126, is slightly
mentioned by Philadem. De different. Stobseus gives the
Mus. col. 15. According to definitions of all these virtues,
4it/tft. 162, b (Vol. Here, i.), Per- and Diogenes of some. By
BiEus, in his avfiiroTucot Sid\oyoi, Stobseus, they are generally
had discussed a-viiiroTiKii at' described as ima-TTJiuu by Dio- ;

length and since, according


;
genes, as e|eii or Siafleireit.
to the Stoics (&. Ep. 123, 15: Otherwise, the definitions are
Stob. 1. c), none but the wise the same. A definition of ei-
know how to live aright and toi'o is given by Cic. OS. i. 40,
how to drink aright, these arts 142.
belong to a complete treatment ^ Diog. 93 ; Stob. 104.
of wisdom. " Sto. Eep. 7.
;

^63 THE STOICS.

(Jhap. do.' The difference of one virtue from another is

__1^__ not one of inward quality, but depends on the ex-


ternal conditions under wliich they are manifested
it only expresses a definite relation to something
else, or, as Herbart would say, an a,ccidental aspect.^
The same view would seem to be indicated by the
manner in which Cleanthes determines the relations
of the principal virtues to one another.^ It was,
however, opposed by Chrysippus. The assumption
of many virtues he believed rested upon an inward
;
difference ''
each definite virtue, as also each defi-
nite fault, becoming what it does by a peculiar
change in character of the soul itself ;
* in short, for
a particular virtue to come into being, it is not
enough that the constituent element of all virtue

should be directed towards a particular object, but

' Pint. Vir. Mot. 2 : 'Apia-Twv fi^vv, as of MeyaptKol, aA.Ai Kai


Be 6 Xios Ty ^\v ohtria [liav Kal [1. koto] t& irp6s ri nuts ex^tv
aifrhs apsri^v eiroiet Kal tyUtav (soil. koWois 6j/6fiafft icoXou-
av6fia^e ' T<f Se Ttpis rt Sia^dpovs fievriv').

Kal ir\slovas, ois e? Tis i64\ot tt^i' *


See p. 260, 3.
SpaiTiv 7]/x(ov KevKwv fi^j/ avriKafi- Their distinguishing fea-
*

Pai/Q/j.4i/Tjv \evKo6eav KaKuv, /ie~ tures fall under the category


Kaviav 5e fnXavdiatf ^ Tt roiovTov of iroihv, to tise Stoic terms, not
erepoy^ Kal ykp ri oper^, k.t,\. under that of Trp6s ri vus exov.
See p. 260, 3. KoBdTrep rh /la- as Aristo maintained.
Xalpiov tv ix4v 4(rTty, &WoTe 5g * G'alenus 1. c. continues: 6

icWo Sioipet' KaL -rh irvp ivepyet 'Toivvv Xpvannros Seifcyuctv, OVK 4v
Trepl CAoy 5ta<p6povs /xt^ (pitret rp 'jrp6s ri ff^fVei yey6^ipov t&
Xp^/J'.^vov. TrA^flos Tuv apeTunt T koL KaKiui/,
^ Galen. Hipp, et Plat. vii. dXA' 4v tojs olxelais oviriais wttoA-
1, p. 590 : vofii^ei ycLp d avT}p haTT0fi4vais KOTci riy ttoiiJttjtos.
iKs7yos, fdav o^Krav t)}v aperijy Plut. Sto; Kep. 7, 3 XpiKTnriros,
:

ovdfiaffi TrXsloffiv ovofld^eaBat Karh 'ApiffTuyi fiky SyKaXuv, 3ti /iias '

riiv ax^aiv.
TTp6s Ti Conf. note operas (rxeVeis fAsye tAs SaAoj
5 and Diog. vii. 161 iperds r' : ehai. Id. Vir. Mor. 2 Xpijcriw-
:

oSt ttoAAAs elffTJyev, ws & Z-f]vwv, iros Si Karh rh iroihv aptT^y iSia
oifTC fiiav TToAAoij dvdfxatn /coAou- iroiirriTi (rvyiffToaBai yofii^anr. -'
:.

EMOTIONS AND VIRTUE. 263

to the common element must be superadded a fur- Chap.


X.
ther characteristic element, or differentia; the several
virtues being related to one another, as the various
species of one genus.
All virtues have, however, one and the same end,
which they compass in different ways, and all presup-
pose the same moral tone and conviction,' which is
Only to be found where it is to be found perfect, and
ceases to exist the moment it is deprived of one of its

component They are, indeed, distinct from one


parts.''

another, each one having its own end, towards which it


is primarily directed; but, at the same time, they again
coalesce,inasmuch as none can pursue its own end with-
out pursuing that of the others at the same time.^ Ac-

' Stob. ii. 110 : iriaas Sc rir virtus sit ; nihil demi, ut virtus
ApcTefcs, <^<Tat. iTTiarrifxaX elffi Kol nomen relinquatur. Conf Sen .

Tex""' (compare on this addi- Ep. 66, 9. See p. 267.


tions p. 255, 1) Kotyd re fleojp^- ' Stob. 112 (conf. Diog. 126)
ftara ex^iv KoX t\os, is itp-qrat Siafpepeiv S* a\\'fi\tov to?? K^ipa-
(p. 108 the same is more fully \aiois. ippovfiffews 'vap etyat /ce-

given by Panetius, p. 112), ri (pdKaia rh fiev Oiupilv Kal TrpdrTeiv


auri, 5(8 KaX axotpiffrovs iivaf & 'Konjreov irptnjyovfifvcos, Kara e
rhv yhp fiiav exoi'Ta Trdffas ^X^^^j rbc SevTepoi' \6you rh deotpetit Kal
Kol rhv KaTct fjilatf Trpdrroyra /carcb & Set anovE^etf. Xdpiv tou aSia-
irdcras Trpdmi". IHog. 125 rir : iTTdrus irpdrretv tl TroLTireov r'/jy

S' apfT^s KiyoviTLv avTOKoKovOeie S^ O'cc<ppoffvv)]^ IfSio*' Kftpd\at6y-


oXA'^Aois zeal Thv fiiay syovra iuTt rh '7rap4xE<T0ai ras dpfias y-
jrdffas ^x^tv elvai yap aiiriav Tci (TTaSets Kaldewpuv auras irporjyov-
9eaipi)/j.aTa Koii/ct, as Chrysippus, fievctts, KaT^ Se rhy Se^irepov \6yov
Apollodorus, and Hecato assert. TO uirh ras &\\as aperas^ eVe/ca
Thv yap impeTOV BsapriTiKdv t' Tou aSiawTCAiTuis 4v rals 6pfj.a7s ava-
ehai Kal irpaKTiKhv -rav Tronyriaiv. <rTpe<j)e<rdat. Similarly of bra-
T<J Se iroirjTe'a KOi aipcria iSTl very, which has for its basis
Kol vTropLevriTea Kttl i.T!OVip.T\Tia, Tray 5 Sc? vTropLfveiv and of jus-;

knowledge and action including tice, which has rb KaT a(lav


all the four principal instincts. Uda-Ttp. Plwt. Alex. Virt. 11;
2 Cw. Parad. 3, 1 Una vir- : The Stoics teach that /ii'o ijiiv
tus est, consentiens cum ratione aperi] vpwTayiavKTTil irpd^ews
et perpetua constantia. Nihil sKdcTTiSt irapaKaKe7 Se ray &k\as
huic addi potest, quo magis Kal avvrelyei trpbs rb tc'Aos,

THE STOICS.

Chap. cordingly, no part of virtue can be separated from


X.
its other parts. Where one virtue exists, the rest are
also to be found, and where there is one fault, there all

is faulty. Even each single virtuous action contains


all other virtues, the moral tone of which it comes
including in itself all the rest.' What makes virtue
virtue, and vice vice, is simply and solely the inten-
tion.^ The will, although it may lack the means of
execution, is worth quite as much as the deed ;
^ a
wicked desire is quite as criminal as the gratification
of that desire.^ Hence only that action can be called
virtuous which is not only good in itself, but which
proceeds from willing the good ; and although, in the
' Stob. 116 : <ptw\ 8 J xaX Trdvra Titiishominum metienda stmt.
Thf fficpop Kara wdfras roLS
TToieTi/ Sen. Benef vi. 11, 3 : Voluntas
.

aperds iratrav yap irpa^iv TeKeiav


' est, quEe apud nos ponit offi-
avTov flvat. Plut. Sto. Eep. 27, cium, which Cleanthes then
1, conf. Aleie. Virt. 1. o. : -rhs proceeds to illustrate by a par-
apercis^ffi [Xpu(ri7nros] auraKo- able of two slaves, one of whom
\ov6etv aW'fi\ais, oil ^6vov t^ t^v diligently seeks for the man
fiiav Ix^*''^'* TTtiffas exeiv, kwhi. Kai whom he is sent to find but
Ty rhv KOTct liiav inovv ipepyovvra without success, whilst the
Karii irdfras ivspyeiv oi"? &v$pa other taking it easy accidently
t\>tiff\ TcAeiOi/ elcat rhv flij Tcdffas comes across him. Ibid. i. 5,
^Xovra Ths apsras, oijre irpa|ic 2 A benefaction is only ipsa
:

TeKelav, iJtis ov KaroL trdffas trpdr- tribuentis voluntas. 6, 1 Non :

TToi T&s dpETaj. If Ghrysippus quid fiat aut quid detur refert,
allowed, as Plutarch states, that sed qua mente.
the brave man does not always ' Compare also the paradoxi-
act bravely, nor the bad man
always like a coward, it was a
cal statement Qui libenter
beneficium accepit, reddidit

confession to which he was which Sen. 1. o. ii. 31, 1, justi-
driven by experience, contrary fies by saying Cum omnia ad :

to Stoic principles. animum referamus, fecit quis-


do. Acad. 1. 10, 38 Neo : que quantum voluit.
virtutis usum modo [Zeno dice- * Cleanthes, in Stoh. Floril.-
bat] Tit superiores (whom the 6, 19:
Stoic evidently wrongs), sed StTTts hrtBvfiuv eti/exer' cucrxpov
ipsum habitum per se esse prae- trpdyp.i3.ros
clarum. Id. Parad. 3, 1 Nee : ovTos Koi'fjoet tout' iav Kaiphv
enim peccata rerum eventu sed \dPv.
: :

EMOTIONS AND VIRTUE. 265-

firstinstance, the difference between the discharge Chap.


X.
and the neglect of duty {KaTopOwjjia and dfidpTTjfj^'i)
depends on the real agreement or disagreement of
our actions with the moral law,' yet that alone can
be said to be a true and perfect discharge of duty
which arises from a morally perfect character.^
' Onthe notions of Kardp- KaSriKov navras iirexoy Tabs &pid'
BtafjLa and afidprrifia, see Pint. liiois. do. Fin. iii. 18, 69.:
Sto. Rep. 11, 1 rb icaTopBuifnA: Quoniam enim videmus esse
tpaffi f6fj.ou TTpofTTdyfjia Jtfai, rh 5* quiddam, quod recte factum
afj.dpT7]fjLa vdjxov anaydpevfia. To appellemus, id autem est per-
a Bad man, law only gives pro- feotum offioium erit autem ;

hibitions, and not commands etiam inchoatum ut, si juste ;

ov yap Svvarat KojTopBovv. Chrys- depositum reddere in rec:e


ippus, Ibid. 15, 10: mv Kardp- factis in officiis (Kae^Ko>To)
sit,
Sufj.a Kal eufj6fx7ii.ia koL SiKato- ponatur depositum reddere.
irpdyriixd iari. StoJ). ii. 192 : %n Ofi. i. 3, 8 Et medium quod-
:

S^ T(UV ivefjyrip.dToty ^airl ra p.^v dam officium dicitur et perfec-


flvai Karopdt&fiaTa, t& 5' afiapr-fi- tum ; the former is called kot-
pLaja, 7d S' ouSerepa (examples dpOoifiaf the latter KodTJKov. A
of the latter are speaking, giv- virtuous action can only be
ing, &c.) . irdvTa Se Tci xarop-
. . done by one who has a virtuous
Btofiara SiKatoTrpayiifiaTa eJuat fcal intention, i.e. by a wise man.
e.vvoiifjia.Ta Kal evTOJCTiipLaTa, k.t.K. do. Fin. iv. 6, 15 If we under- :

Tct.Se apiapT-flfKXTa ix Ttov avrtxei- stand by 'a. life according to


pievcitv aSiK-tificLTa Kal Ofop.^pta'ra nature, what is rational, rectum
Kttl aroKjiipLaTa. est, quod KaTSpBioiia dioebas,
^ view that the
It is to this Qontingitque sapienti soli. Off.
distinction between itaTdpiaijm iii. 3, 14 Illud autem officium,
:

and KaBriKov refers from the one quod rectum iidem [Stoici] ap-
side. A KoSfinov (the concep- pellant, perfectum atque abso-
tions of which will be subse- lutum est, et, ut iidem dicunt,
quently more fully discussed) omnes numeros habet, nee prse-
is, in general, any discharge of ter sapientem, cadere in quen-
duty, or rational action KarSp- ; quam potest. Off. iii. 4, 16
ewiM only refers to a perfect When the Decii and Scipios are
discharge of duty, or to a vir- called brave, Fabricius and
tuous course of conduct. Couf. Aristides just, Gato and Laelius
Stob. 158 rav
S^ Ka8riK6vT<ov tiJ
: wise, the wisdom and virtue of
/iiv ehoi T4\eia, & Sii Kol
(paffi the wise man are not attributed
KaTop0t&p.aTa\eye(rdat. Karop&di' to them in the strict sense of
pjara 5' elyai to kot' ctperV ^'epT^- the term sed ex mediorum
:

fjiara . . . ih Si xaffnitov reXeiai- officiorum frequentia similitu-


flev Kar6p9wiJ,a yiveffSai. Simi- dinem quandam gerebaut spe-
larly, 18i A Km6p9aim is a: oiemque sapientum.
:
'

THE STOICS.

Chap. Such a character, the Stoics held, must either


X.
exist altogether, or not at all ; for virtue is an indivi-
W Viity sible whole, which we cannot possess in part, but must
either have or not have.^ He who has a right in-
tention, and a right appreciation of good and evil,

is virtuous ; he who has not these requisites is lack-


ing in virtue ; there is no third alternative. Virtue
admits neither of increase nor diminution,' and there'
is no mean between virtue and vice.^ This being

See p. 263, 2. tween kpf-ri] and Texvi) the



In Sim.pl. Categ. 61, one being preceded by an a|i(i-
(Schol. in Arist. 70, b, 28), the Koyos TrportoTT^, the other by a
Stoics say: rij /*ei/ e'l^is en-i- simple ^iriT7)5ei(!T7;j {Simpl.
T^ivstrOai Siiva<Tdai Kai avietrScu- Categ. 62, 3 ; Schol. 71, a, 38).
T(Js 5e SiaQecrets dveirtTdrous eli/ai There is also a definition of
Koi dvirovs. Thus straightness TEX"") attributed by Olympio-
is, for instance, a Sui6e(ns, and dorus, in Gorg. 53 (Jahrb. fiir.
no mere e^is. ovjaxxl Se /cal ras Philol. See Supplementb. xiv,
aperas Siadeaeis elvai, oif Karci rh 239), to Zeno, Cleanthes, and
ISiuna, aWa kcltcl rh ave-
IJi.6viiJ.ov Chrysippus ; to Zeno in Sext.
TrWaTov Kai aveiriSsKTOv rou fia\- Pyrrh. iii. 241 ; Math. vii. 109
\ov' Tas Se rexvas^ ijrot SuffKivf]- and 373 ; more fully in Zuoian,
Tovs otia'as ^ fji.^ (add ouk} elvai Paras, c. 4, Conf. Cic. Acad. ii.
SiofleVcij, Conf. p. 103, 1. Jbid. 7,22.
72, S (Schol. 76, a, 12): rav ' Diog. vii. 127 apetrKet Se :

^TuCKOiV, o'inves SiiK6fievQi x<wpis auTois foiSiV fiiffov eTvai opeTTJs


Tots Aperiis airb twv fl^ffuv rex^^^ KaX KaKias- rHv UepnrarnTtKav
TavTas oi/Te iirtTeiveadat \4yovirLV /liTo^ii opeTrjs Kai uaKfac eivai
atire avleirdaij tcis 5e /leffas T;^j/os \py6vTQtv T^v trpoKOTriiv us ycip '

Kai fnWauiv Kai &vfftv S^x^^jGat 5etv, tpacriVj fi 6pdov elvai ^v\ov ^
ipaaiv. Simpl. (73, a. Schol. 76, (TTpe^Khv, oStws ^ SlKaiov fj &StKOv
a, 24) replies: This would be oiJTe Sk StKaiSrepov oUre dStKtii-
true, if virtue consisted only repov, Kai iirl ruv &\Kav dixoius.
in theoretical conviction such : Similarly, Sen. Bp. 71, 18
a conviction must be either Quod summum bonum est supra
true or false, and does not ad- segradum non habet hoc . . .

mit of more or less truth (for nee remitti neo intendi posse,
the same line of argument, noimagis, quam regulam, qua
see p. 267, 1); but it is rectum probari solet, iiectes.
otherwise where it is a matter Quicquid ex ilia mutaveris in-
.

for exercise. It may be re- juria est recti. Stob. ii. 116:
marked, in passing, that a fur- dpeTTJs Si KOI KaKittS oviev elvai
ther distinction was made be- jeTa{lJ,
;: ;:

EMOTIONS AND VIMTUE. 267

the case, and the value of an action depending wholly Chap.


'

on the intention, it follows, necessarily, that virtue


admits of no degrees. If the intention must be
eithergood or bad, the same must be true of actions
and if a good intention or virtue has in it nothing
bad, and a bad intention has in it nothing good, the
same is true of actions. A good action is uncondi-
tionally praiseworthy ; a bad one, unconditionally
blameworthy, the former being only found where
virtue exists pure and entire ; the latter, only where
there is no virtue at all. All good actions are, on
the one hand, according to the well-known paradox,
equally good ; all bad actions, on the other, of equal
moral worth. The standard of moral judgment is
an absolute one and when conduct does not alto-
;

gether conform to this standard, it falls short of it


altogether.'

' The much-disoussed para- away. Similarly, Stobasus


dox ( Cic. Parad. 3 27
; Fin. iv. The Stoics declare all errors to
IHog. 101 and 120 Stub. 218 ; ;
be Ua, although not o^oio- t5i/
Plut. Sto. Eep. 13, 1; Sext. 7cip rii ij/eCSos ^Trdrijj ij/eCSos iru<;8e'-

Math. vii. 422 Sefi. Ep. 66, 5)


; p-i]Kiv(a statement quoted as
is this Sti iaa tA a/uopr-^^iioTO
: Stoical by Alex, in Metaph. p.
Kct! T(i KwropeiimTa. It was, ac- 258, 3 Bon. 667, a, 19 Brand)
cording to Biog., supported, on every o/iaprio is the result of a
the one hand, by the proposi- Suiij/euffis. It is, however, im-
tion, irSj' ar/aSbv eV ixfov ehai possible for KaTopSii/mTa not to
aipiThv icai /nijre &iie(riv fi'fiTe iiri- be equal to one another, if vices
TOirii/ Six^aScuon the other
;
are equal iiiiiiTa -ydp can reAeio,
;

hand, by the remark, to which SiiSirep oik' ihXe'meiv oiff mep4-


Sext. and SUmpl. in Categ., x^"* SiifaiT' ^.v iMJiiKwv. Cicero
Schol. in Arist. 76, a, 30, refer and Seneca devoted particular
If truth and falsehood admit of attention to this enquiry. The
no difference of degree, the investigations of Cicero in the
same must be true of the errors Paradoxa result in bringing him
of our conduct. man is not A to the passage quoted p. 263, 2,
at the mark, no matter whether from which it follows that no-
he is one. or a hundred stadia thing can be recto rectius, nor
THE STOICS.

Chap. From what has been said, it follows that there


X.
cau be but one thorough moral distinction for all
mankind, the distinction between the virtuous and
the vicious ; and that within each of these classes

there can be no diflference in degree. He who pos-


sesses virtue possesses it whole and entire ; he who
lacks it lacks it altogether ; and whether he is near
or far from possessing it is a matter of no moment.
He who is only a hand-breadth below the surface of

bono melins. The equality of accesset ergo ne virtuti quidem,


:

faults corollary from the


is a, cui si quid adjici potest, defuit
equality of virtues ; it also . . ergo virtutes inter se pares
.

follows from the consideration sunt et opera virtutis et omnes


that whatever is forbidden at homines, quibus illae contigere
all is equally forbidden. De . .unaindudturhumanis vir-
.

Pin. It is said, all faults are


; tutibus regula. Una enim est
equal, quia nee honesto quid- ratio recta simplexque. Nihil
quam honeslius nee turpi tur- est divino divinius, ccelesti coe-
pius. Saneoa (Ep. 66, 5) raises lestius. Mortalia minuuntur
the question, How, notwith- . . . crescunt, &c. ;divinorum
standing the difference between una natura est. Ratio autem
goods (see p. 230, 3 end), can all nihil aliud est, quam in corpus
be equal in value 1 and at once humanum pars divini spiritus
replies Is virtue or, what is
: mersa . .nullum porro inter
.

the same thing, a rightly- divlna discrimen est ergo nee :

moulded soul the only pri- inter bona. Ibid. 32 Omnes :

mary good ? Virtue, indeed, virtutes rationes sunt rationes :

admits of various forms, ac- sunt rectse si rectse sunt, et


:

cording to the activities im- pares sunt. Qualis ratio est,


posed on it, but can neither be tales et actiones sunt ergo :

increased nor diminished De- ; omnes pares sunt: ceterum


crescere enim summum bonum magna habebunt discrimina
non potest, nee virtuti ire retro variante materia, etc. On the
licet. It cannot increase, same ground, Seneca, Ep. 71,
quando incrementum maximo defended the equality of all
non est nihil invenies rectius
: goods and of all good actions,
recto, non magis quam verius in particular p. 18, where to the
vero, quam temperato tempera- quotation given, p. 266, 3, the
tius. All virtue consists in words are added 8i reotior ;

modo, in certa mensura. Quid ipsa [virtus] non potest fieri,


aooedere perfecto potest ? Ni- ne qu,^ ab ilia quidem fiunt,
hil, aut perfeotumnon erat, cui alia aliis rectiora sunt.
:

THE WISE MAN, 2C9

the water will be drowned just as surely as one who Chap.


X.
is five hundred fathoms deep ; he who is blind sees
equally little whether he will recover his sight to-
morrow or never.' The whole of mankind are thus
divided by the Stoics into two classes those who are
wise and those who are foolish ^ and these two classes ;

are treated by them as mutually exclusive, each one


being complete in itself. Among the wise no folly,

among the foolish no wisdom of any kind, is possible.^


The wise man is absolutely free from faults and mis-
takes all that he does is right in him all virtues
: ;

centre ; he has a right opinion on every subject, and


never a wrong one, nor, indeed, ever what is merely

> Plut. C. Not. 10, i:va\, Tel recte facere. Quod nobis
tpaalv
aW^ &fftrep & tttjxvp non licet dicere, qui crescere
tLTrexdiV ^v BaXdrTTj ttjs inKftapfias bonorum finem non putamus.
oitSev 7)7X01/ irpiyerat tov Kara- Then follow the same com-
5e5uK(jTOS opyvias irepraKOciaSf parisons as in Plutarch. Sen.
oiirots ovSe 01 irs\ti^ovTS aperf Ep. 66, 10 As all virtues are
:

T&y fioKp&v SvTiey firrdv elaiv 4v equal, so are omnes homines


KUKia Kal KaOaircp oi TV<p\ol
quibus ills contigere. Ep. 79,
Tv<p\oi eict Kttv oKiyov Varepov 8 What is perfect admits of
:

dyajSAeireii/ fieWwffiV^ ovtus ol no increase ; quicunque f ue-


irpoKdiTTOVTes fixP*^ **" "^^^ aperijp rint sapientes pares erunt et
ava\d$oi(riv ap6T)Toi koX noxSrtpoX sequales.
ZiaiiivoMLV. Diog. 127 (see p. 2 Stoh. ii. 198: ApcVKei yhp

266, 3). Stoi. ii. 236 irivrav : T^ re 7.^v(i>pt KoX roh air* aiirov
re 7WV afiOprrifJuiTap Iffaiv ovTtov ^w'lKols ^i\o(t6^ois, 5i5o yivT] tup-
Kal Ttav KaTopdotfidroiP Koi Tois avdpciTrotP eJval, rh /jl^p tup fftrov-

&<l>pova5 iirlffris vdvras &ippopas Sa{wp t5 Se rup (jiai/Koip Kal rh

cipai T^p aurV "! ''"'VP ^X""'''" fiep TUP (Tnovdalaip dta iraprhs rov
SidBio-ip. Cic. Fin. iii. 14, 48 : ^iov XP')'^^*^ rais kp^TOLS rh 5^
Consentaneum est his quffi ruv (l>a{iKwp Tats KaKlats.

dicta sunt, ratione illorum, qui ' Plui. Aud. Poet. 7, p. 25


ilium bonomm finem quod ap- jttTJTC Ti {pavKop aperij irpoaelpat
pellamus extremum quod ulti- jtf^re KaKta x,pvo''rhp a^uwaiPj aWa
mum crescere putent posse, iraVTOisfiep 4p irao'ip afxap^uKbp

iisdem placere, esse alium alio eXpairhp ifiaf-ri, irepl irdpra 5' ad
etiam sapientiorem, itemque KUTOpGovp rhp acTTUop.
alium magis alio vel peccare
; ;;;

270 ,
THE STOICS.

Chap, an opinion. The bad man, on the contrary, can do


'

nothing aright : he has every kind of vice ; he has


no right knowledge, and is altogether rude, violent,
cruel, and ungrateful.^
The upon the perfec-
Stoics delight in insisting
tion of the wise man, and contrasting with it the
absolute faultiness of the foolish man, in a series of
paradoxical assertions.^ The wise man only is free,
because he only uses his will to control himself; ' he
only is beautiful, because only virtue is beautiful and
attractive;^ he only is rich and happy {svtvxtj^),
because goods of the soul are the most valuable, true
riches consisting in being independent of wants.*
Nay, more, he is absolutely rich, since he who has a
right view of everything has everything in his in-
tellectual treasury," and he who makes the right use
of everything bears to everything the relation of
owner.' The wise only know how to obey, and they
also only know how to govern they only are there- ;

;
fore kings, generals, pilots ' they only are orators,
' Stod. Eel. ii. 116; 120; ' Cic. Parad. 6
; Acad. 1. c.
196 198 220 232 JHoff. vii.
; ; ; ; Cleanthes, in Stob. Floril. 94,
117; 125; CSc. Acad. i. 10, 38 28; Sext. 1. o. Alex. Aphr. ;

ii. 20,66; Phit. Sto. Eep. 11, Top. 79.


1 Sen. Benef iv. 26
; Sext. . ;
Sen. Benef. vii. 3,
2 ; 6, 3
Math. vii. 434. 8, 1.
' Compare the collection of ' Cic. Acad. 1. c. ; Siog. vii.
expressions respecting the wise 125.
and unwise in aam/K5Mr, Vet. ' 1. o. Diog. vii. 122;
Oic. ;

Phil. Doct. De Mort. Volunt. Stoh. 206; Pint. Arat. 23.


ii.

p. 169. On all the points discussed,


' Diog. 121 ; 32 ; Cic. Acad. Plvt. C. Not. 3, 2 De Adul. ;

ii.44, 136. Parad. 5: 8ti ii.6vos 16, p. 58 Tran. An. 12, p. 472
;

b (Tuiphs 4\ev8epos Kol irSj &(pp<ov Ps. Pltit. De Nobil. 17, 2 ; Cif.
SovKos. Fin. iii. 22, 75 Sor. Ep. i. 1
;

Phit. C. Not. 28, 1 ; Cic.


* 106 ; Sat. i. 3, 124,.
Acad. 1. c. Sext. Math. xi. 170.
;
;; :
;

THE WISE MAN. 271

poets, and prophets ;


' and since their view of the Chap.
X.
Gods and their worship of the Gods is the true one
only, only amongst them can true piety be found
they are the only priests and friends of heaven ; all

foolishmen, on the contrary, being impious, profane,


and enemies of the Gods.^ Only the wise man is
capable of feeling gratitude, love, and friendship,'
he only is capable of receiving a benefit, nothing
being of use or advantage to the foolish man.''
To sum up, the wise man is absolutely perfect, ab-
solutely free from passion and want, absolutely
happy as the Stoics conclusively assert, he in no
;

way falls short of the happiness of Zeus, since time,


the only point in which he dififers from Zeus, does
not augment happiness at all.' On the other hand,
the foolish man is altogether foolish, unhappy, and
perverse ; or, in the expressive language of the Stoics,

'
Pint. Tran. An. 12 Cig. ; a Deo difiert. THd. 6, 4
Divii ii. 63, 129 Stab. ii. 122 ; ;
Jupiter says to the virtuous :

conf Ps. Plut. Vit. Horn. 1 43.


. Hoc est, quo Deum antecedatis
' ii. 122 and 216
Stob. ille extra patientiam malorum

IHoff. 119; Sen. Provid. i. 5. est, tos supra patientiam. Ep.


Philodemws, iripl 6eiav Siayaylis 73, 11 De' Const. 8, 2
; Cic. ;

(Vol. Heroul. vi. 29), quotes a N. D. ii. 61, 153 Mjpictet. Diss. ;

Stoic saying that the wise are i. 12, 26 Man. 15 ; Horat. ;

the friends of heaven, and Bp. i. 1, 106.


heaven of the wise. ' Seep. 239, 1 Sen. Ep. 53, ;

' Sen. Ep. 81, 11; Stoh. ii, Jl; Kon multo te Di ante-
118. cedent diutius erunt. At
. . .

Sen. Benef. v. 12, 3 ; Pint,


* mehercule magni artificis est
Sto. Eep. 12, 1 G. Not. 20, 1 ;
clausisse totum in exiguo.
and above, p. 230, 1. Tantum sapienti sua, quantum
* Stob. ii. 196 Pint. Stoic. ; Deo omnis setas patet. 73, 13 :

Abs. Poet. Die. 1, 4. Jupiter quo antecedit virura


Chrysippus, in Plut. Sto. bonum-? Diutius bonus est:
Eep. 13, 2 Com. Not. 33, 2 ; ;
sapiens nihilo se minoris sestir
Stoh. ii. 198. Seneca, Prov. i. mat, quod virtutes ejus spatio
5 : Bonus ipse tempore tantum breviore clauduutur.
;

272 THE STOICS.

Chap, every foolish man is a madman, he being a madman


"

who has no knowledge of himself, nor of what most


closely affects him.^
2) Vhi- This assertion was all the more sweeping, since
*^ Stoics recognised neither virtue nor wisdom
pritvity^'
outside their own system or one closely related to it,

holding at the same time a most unfavourable opi-


nion of the moral condition of their fellow-men.
That their opinion should be unfavourable was inevi-
table from their point of view. A system which
sets up its own moral ideal against the current no-
tions so sharply as that of the Stoics can only be the
offspring of a thorough disapproval of existing cir-
cumstances, and must, on the other hand, contribute
thereto. According to the Stoic standard, by far
the majority, indeed, almost the whole of mankind,
belong to the class of the foolish ; were all foolish
people equally and altogether bad, mankind must
have seemed to them to be a sea of corruption and
vice, from which, at best, but a few swimmers emerge
at spots widely apart.* Man passes his life such
had already been the complaint of Cleanthes ' in
wickedness. Only here and there does one, in the

^ TTas &<j>pwv fiaivejai. do, ffS^ovs yyov4vat. Similarly


Parad. 4 ; Tusc. iii. 5, 10 ; Diog. Plut. Sto. Rep. 31, 5.
vii. 124 ; Stob. Eel. ii. 124 Seayt. Math. ix. 90 in the

Horat. Sat. ii. 3, 43. argument quoted, p. 146, 1 ;

^ The
Peripatetic Dioge- Man cannot be the most perfect
nianus raises the objection (in being, oiav evBeas, Sti 5io /caic/or _

!us. PriEp. Ev. vi. 8, 10) ; iropiieTai rhv irivra xpi^""", ' Se
TTws odv oithsva <^s &vQpwTrov, %s fi^ ye, rhv irKiiaTOV /cal yhp cX
*

ovxl ixcdvetdai (Toi SoKct /far' Xffov Trore irepty^voiro &pT^s, oi|/e Kal
'OpeffTTj Kal ^
A\KfJ.aiuij/t, ttK-^v tov Trphs rats rod fiiou dv^fxais irepi-
rr6<j>0u ^ eVa 8e ff Svo fidi/ovs ip^s yli/srat.
;

THE WISE MAN. 273

evening of life, after many wanderings, attain to Chaj>.

virtue. And that this was the common opinion among IJ


the successors of Cleanthes, is witnessed by their
constant complaints of the depravity of the foolish,
and of the rare occurrence of a wise man.'
No one probably has expressed this opinion more
frequently or more strongly than Seneca. We are
wicked, he says ; we have been wicked ; we shall be
wicked. Our ancestors complained of the decline of
morals we complain of their decline and posterity
; ;

will utter the very same complaint. The limits


within which morality oscillates are not far apart
the modes in which vice shows itself change, but its

power remains the same.'' All men are wicked ; and


he who has as yet done nothing wicked is at least in
a condition to do it. All are thankless, avaricious,
cowardly, impious ; all are mad.' We have all done
wrong one in a less, the other in a greater degree ;

and we shall all do wrong to the end of the chapter.''


One drives the other into folly, and the foolish are
too numerous to allow the individual to improve.^

' This point will be again Sis laiSfv Sio^fpeiv &\\ov liWov,

considered in the next chapter. nalveaBai Sc bjiolas irdj/ras, Phi-


Compare at present S?a*. Math, lodem. De Mus. (Vol. Here, i.),
ix. 133, who
says eio-lc Spa : col. 11, 18 The Stoic cannot
:

(ro(/>of ouK ijpeaKe tois airb


8irp take his stand upon the opinion
Tris iroaSy fiexp^ '''o^ ^^^ ayevperov of the majority (consensus gen-
SvTos kut' avTobs rod aofov. tium), since he has declared it
-Alex. ApTwod. De Fat. 28, p. to be profane and impious.
^ Benef. i. 10, 1-3.
90 tSi/ %\ avSpdirav ot irXeiffToi
:

' De Ira,
Kaicol, fiaWov Se ciyaflbs /ih iTs ?) iii. 26, 4 Benef. ;

Seirepos inr' airav yeyovhai V. 17, 3.


fivBeierai, &<rirep ri irapiiSo^ov * De Clemen, i. 6, 3 ; De
^^ov Ka\ TTopoi (piffiv, airavidiTfpov Ira, ii.28, 1 ; iii. 27, 3.
ToS *oij/iKos . . ol Si irdvTes
.
' Ep. 41, 9 ; Vit. Be. i. i.
KOKai Koi iiriffris ciWliKots toioStoi,
T
'

274 THE STOICS.

Chap. He who would be angry with the vices of men, in-


X,
stead of pitying their faults, would never stop. So
great is the amount of iniquity !

No doubt the age in which Seneca lived afiforded


arnple occasion for such effusions, but his predeces-
sors must have found similar occasions in their own
days. Indeed, all the principles of the Stoic School,
when made it impossible to
consistently developed,
consider the great majority of men as anything else
but a mass of fools and sinners. From this sweep-
ing verdict, even the most distinguished names were
not excluded. If asked for examples of wisdom,
they would point to Socrates, Diogenes, Antisthenes,^
and, in later times, to Cato ;
^ but not only would
they deny philosophic virtue, as Plato had done be-
fore them, to the greatest statesmen and heroes of
early times, but they would deny to them all and
every kind of virtue.* Even the admission that ge-
neral faults belong to some in a lower degree than to

' See the pathetic descrip- as flEioi.

tion, De Ira, ii. 8-10, amongst


' See the immoderate Ian-

other passages the following :. guage of praise of his admirer


Ferariun iste couventus est Sen. De Const. 7, 1
:, The wise :

. . .certatnr ingenti quidem man is no unreal ideal, although,


nequitise certamine major like everything else that is
:

quotidie peccandi cupiditas, great, he is seldom met with ;


minor vereoundia est, &c. ceterum hie ipse M. Cato vereor
Diog. vii. 91 TeKfiiipiov Si
''
: ne supra nostrum exemplar sit.
ToO {ynapKT^v elvai t^v aper^v Hid. 2, I Catonem autem cer- :

(/>7)(ric Iloo-eiSiii'ios iv rif irpiiTif


(S tins exemplar sapientis viri
ToC ijBiKou \6yif rb yeveffBai iv nobis Deos immortales dedisse
irpoKOTrrj Tois irepl SuKpaTiji', Alo- quam Ulixen et Heroulem
yeirnv KaX 'AvTurBevTiv. The limi- prioribus sseoulis.
tation likewise containedherein * Pluta/rch, Prof, in Virt.
2,
will be presently discussed, p. 76 Cic. Off. iii. 4, 16, p.
;

Epictet. Man. 15, mentions 265, 2,


Heraolitus as well as Diogenes
THE WISE MSN. 275

others can hardly be reconciled with their principle .Chap.


X.
of the equality of all who are not wise.^
The two moral states being thus at opposite poles, (3) Con-
version.
a gradual transition from one to the other is, of course,
out of the question. There may be a progress from
folly and wickedness in the direction of wisdom,^ but
the actual passage from one to the other must be
momentary and instantaneous.^ Those who are still

progressing belong, without exception, to the class of


the foolish ;
* and one who has lately become wise
is in the first moment unconscious of his new state.*

Sen. Benef iv. 27, 2 Ita-


' . : Abs. Poet. Die. 2. The Stoics
que errant illi, qui interrogant are here ridiculed because, ac-
Stoieos quid ergo 1
: Achilles cording to their view, a man
timidus est ? quid ergo 1 Aris- may go bed ugly, poor,
to
tides, cui justitia nomen dedit, and rise the
vicious, miserable,
injustus est ? &o. Non hoc next morning wise, virtuous,
dicimus, sic omnia vitia esse in rich, happy, and a king. In
omnibus, quomodo in qui- Prof, in Virt. 1, p. 75, a saying
busdam singula eminent sed : of Zeno's is given, that it is
malum ac stultum nuUo vitio possible to tell by a dream
vacare .omnia in omnibus
. . whether we are advancing in
vitia sunt, sed non omnia in virtue.
singulis extant (i. e., all points See
p. 266, 3 ; Plut. Prof,
are not equally prominent in in Yirt. 1; Com. Not. 10, 2;
each one). It hardly requires see p. 269, 1 ; Sen. Ep. 75, 8.
to be noticed how nearly this = PImt. C. Not. 9, 1: t?j
view coincides with that of hpcTTis Kol rTis evSaifioplas irapa-^
Augustine on the virtues of yiyofievTis iroWdKis ou5' ai(r$ii-
the heathen, how close a re- veffdat Thy KTTiffdfieyov oiovrai
semblance the Stoic doctrine of Sia\\7jd4yai 8' avrhy Sri fiiKp^
folly bears to the Christian TTp6(r6va6Ku&TaTosS>yKala.xpoy4<r-
doctrine of the unregenerate, Taros vvv dfjLov <pp6yifios Kal
and how the contrast between jiaKapios yiyovev. So Sto. Eep.
wisdom and folly corresponds 19, 3. In explanation of these
to that between the faithful words. Sitter, iii. 657, aptly
and unbelievers. refers to Stub. ii. 234 (_ylyye<r9ai
2 Plut. C. N. 10, 1 ; Prof, 8e Kal Sta\e\ri66Ta TtySi ffo^hy
in Virt. 12, p. 82; Sen. Bp. vofj.i^ov(ri KarSt robs irptirovs
75,8. Xpiyovs), and Philo, De Agric.
Plut. C. Not. 9 ; Stoic. p. 325 : Those yet inexperienced
I a
'

76 THE STOICS.

Chap. The transition takes place so rapidly, and his former


'

few points of contact with the one on


state aifords so
which he has newly entered, that the mind does not
keep pace with the change, and only becomes con-
scious of it by subsequent experience.
In this picture of the wise man, the moral ideal-

ism of the Stoic system attained its zenith. A vir-


tuous will appears here so completely sundered from
all outward conditions of life, so wholly free from all

the trammels of natural existence, and the indivi-


dual has become so completely the organ of universal
law, that it may be asked. What right has such a
being to call himself a person ? How can such a
being be imagined as a man livingamong fellow-
men ? Nor was this question unknown to the Stoics
themselves. Unless they were willing to allow that
their theory was practically impossible, and their
ideal scientifically untenable, how could they escape
the necessity of showing that it might be reconciled
with the wants of human life and the conditions of
reality ? Let the attempt be once made, however,
and withal they would be forced to look for some
means of adapting it to those very feelings and opi-

in wisdom iropo tois cj>iAo(riJ<j>iii; likewise investigates the same


Keyovrai cofpot
StoA.6\7j0(JTs iivai point, but ranges those who
robs yap &xi^ (rocpias &Kpas eA.?7\a- have not yet attained the con-
KiSras Kol Twi/ Spmv auTTJs Spri soiousness of perfection among
jrpuTov a^afiiiiovs aii-lixavop ciSe- advancers, but not among the
vaij ^aalf r^v ^avTwv rsKslaifTiv. wise. PrantVs conjecture
/i^ 7a:p KctT^ -rhv avrby xP^''"" (Gtesch. d. Logik, i. 490, 210),
&[j^u (TvvlffTaffOai riiv re irphs rh that the (To^is Sta\i\ri0(iis is
irepas Hfi^iv Kal rijv t^s i,(pl^e(i)s connected with the fallacy
KaTiiXTii\iiv, &A\' (Ivai puBipiov known as hia\av96,viev, appears
i,yvi>iav, K.T.K. Sen. Bp. 75, 9, to be questionable.
THE WISE MAN. 277

nions towards which their animosity had formerly Chap.


been so great. Nor could the attempt be long de- _JLi__
layed. Daily a greater value was attached to the
practical working of their system, and to its agree-
ment with general opinion. If, therefore, the origi-
nal direction of Stoic morality aimed at the absolute
and unconditional submission of the individual to
the law of the universe, still, in developing that
theory, the rights of the individual asserted them-
selves unmistakeably. From this confluence of op-
posite currents arose a deviation from the rigid type
of the Stoic system, some varieties of which, in the
direction of the ordinary view of life, deserve now
further consideration.
278 THE STOICS.

CHAPTER XL
THE STOIC THEORY OF MORALS AS MODIFIED BY
PRACTICAL NEEDS.

Chap. The Stoic theory of Ethics is entirely rooted in the


'

proposition, that only virtue is a good and only vice


A. Things an evil. This proposition, however, frequently brought
fei'red and the Stoics into collision with current views ; nor was
eselmwed.
^ without its difficulties for their own system. In
the first place, virtue is made to depend for its ex-

istence upon certain conditions, and to lead to cer-


tain results, from which it is inseparable. TheSe
results, we have already seen,' were included by the
Stoics in the list of goods. Moreover, virtue is

said to be the only good, because only what is accord-


ing to nature is a good, and rational conduct is for
man the only thing according to nature. But can
this be so absolutely and unconditionally stated?
According to the Stoic teaching the instinct of self-

preservation being the primary impulse, does not


this instinct manifestly include the preservation and
advancement of outward life ? The Stoics, there-
fore, could not help including physical goods and
activities among things according to nature for in-

' See p. 230, 3,


:

THINGS TO BB PREFEBRED OR ESCHEWED. 279

stance, health, a right eDJoyment of the senses, and Chap.


XI.
such like.' Practically, too, the same adnaission was
forced upon them by the cotsideration' that, if there
is no difference in value between things in them-
selves, rational choice and, indeed, all acting on
motives is impossible. At the same time, they re-
ject the notion that what is first according to nature
must therefore be perfect or good, just as in theory
they allow that the source of knowledge, but not
truth itself, is .derived from the senses. When man
has once recognised the universal law of action, he
will, according to their view, think little of what is

sensuous and individual, only considering it an in-


strument in the service of virtue and reason.^

1 ao. Fin. iii. 5, 17. Gell. a.vd\oyop. Conf. Ibid. p. 60,


N. A. xii. 5, 7 : The primary where the enumeration of the
objects of natural self-love are TrpaJraKara <^vfftv is also in the
the irpaiTa Kara (pvatv and self- ; Stoic sense, and above, p. 225.
love consists mainly in this ^ Cic. Fin. iii. 15, 50 Dein-:

Ut omnibus corporis sui com- ceps explicatur differentia re-


modis gauderet [unusquisque], rum quam si non ullam esse
:

ab incommx)dis omnibus abhor- dioeremus, oonfunderetur om-


reret. Sfob. Bel. ii. 142 Some : nis vita, ut ab Aristone nee ;

things are according to nature, uUum sapientis munus aut opus


others contrary to nature, inveniretur, cum inter res eas,
others neither one nor the quae ad vitam degendam per-
other. Health, strength, and tinerent, nihil omnino interes-
such like, are among things set neque nllum delectum
according to nature. Ibid. p. adhiberi oporteret. The same
148: T&v Se KaTCKpiiTiv aiuupSpuv argument was used by the Stoa
uVTtuv TO. fief i<TTi irpSiTix faTa against the theoretical aitanpopla
(piffiv .t4 hi Kara /j6Tox^>'. Trpura of the Sceptics (see above, p. 37,
IJ.fv i(TTi KOTO! ipiaiv xivvffiS tl 1), with which the practical
iTxeVis KXTCl Tois a-TTeptiariKoiis i).Sia(bopla of Aristo, differing
Kiyovs yivop.evr\, olov vyieia Ka\ only in name from the imapa^la
\fy&> Se t^I" /rariJxijif'ii'
ulffBriffts, of the Sceptics, is most closely
Kal Icrxi". ""Ttt |iTOxV 5e .^ .
. connected, Aristo declining to
olov X'ip apria leal aS>im iyia'i/ov Scepticism. See p. 61, 1.
' do. Fin. iii. 6, 21 Prima
Kal iwVWo-ei! fiil jreiTTjpaiyue'i'oi. :

dfiotcijs Be Kal twv irapa <ftvtrtt/ Kar^ est enim oonciliatio [oiKei'ucris]
:

THE STOICS.

Chap. would be difficult to say how this can be


Still, it
XI.
possible. The contemporary opponents of the Stoics
already took exception to the way in which the
first demands of nature were excluded from the aims

of a life ' according to nature ; and we, too, cannot


suppress a feeling of perplexity at being told that all
duties aim what is primarily according
at attaining
to what is according to nature
nature, but that
must not be looked upon as the aim of our actions ^ ;

since not that which is simply according to nature,


but the rational choice and combination of what is
according to nature constitutes the good.' Even if

the Stoics pretend to dispose of this difficulty, they


could not, at least, fail to see that whatever contri-

hominis ad ea quae sunt seeun- reote dici possib, omnia officia


dum naturam, sinrnl autem eo ref erri, ut adipisoamur prin-
cepit intelligentiam vel no- oipia naturse nee tamen ut:

tionem potius, quam appellant hoc sit bonorum ultimum, prop-


Ivvotav illi, viditque rerum terea quod uon inest in primis
agendarum ordlnem et ut ita nature conciliationibus honesta
dicam conoordiam, multo earn actio. Consequens enim est et
pluris sestimavit quam omnia post oritur.
ilia quEe primum dilexerat = Plut. C. Not. 26, 2:
617^^
atque ita cognltione et ratione auT^ fj.ev [to] irpura Kara tftiatv
ooUegit ut statueret in eo col- ayaBii fiii ia-nv, 71
6' eihSyiffTOS
looatum summum illud hominis iKKoy^ Kol A^i^is avTUV KaX rh
per se laudandum et expeten- iravTo. TO. trap* eavrhv Ttoieiv '4k-
dum bonum . . . cum igitur in atrroi/ '4vena tov Tuyxo-veiv tSiv
eo sit id bonum, quo referenda irpciTUV KdT^ <pi(riv, K.T.A. ellTfp
sint omnia . . . quamquam yap o'iut'Tai, fi^ ffroxaCofievovs
post oritur, tamen id solum vi fi'fjS^ 4^ifiEvovs rod Tv^uv ^KeTcov
sua et dignitate expetendum rh leKos ^X^^^i a\K^ o5 Set iKHva
est, eorum autem quEe sunt ai'a(f:eptT6at, r^v roirttiy eK\oy^v,
prima naturae propter se nihil Kat fiij TavTa. t\os fiiv ykp tS
expetendum, &c. Similarly 4K\4y^(FBai ttol Kan^dvetv 4Ke7va
GeU. 1. 0. <f>povliJiojs iKelva S' aura koI rh
'

' Plut. Com. Not. 4; do. rvyx^vetv avjuv ov TfAos, a\\*


Pin. iv. 17; t. 24, 72; 29, &<nrip ii\ri ris imdKsiTai rhv 4k-
89. \ektik})!' i^iav Ixovira. Cic. See
2 Cic. Fin. iii. 6, 22; TJt p. 279, 3,
;

THINGS TO BE PREFERRED- OR ESCHEWED. 281

butes to bodily well-being must have a certain posi- Chap.


'

tive value,and must be desirable in all cases in


which no higher good suffers in consequence ; and,
conversely, that whatever is opposed to bodily well-
being, when higher duties are not involved, must
have a negative value (aTra^t'a), and, consequently,
deserve to be avoided.' Such objects and actions
they would not, however, allow to be included in the
class of goods which are absolutely valuable ;
"^
and
it was therefore a blending of the Stoic with the
Peripatetic teaching when Herillus, the fellow-stu-
dent of Cleanthes, enumerated bodily and outward
goods as secondary and subsidiary aims besides virtue.^
Nor yet were the Stoics minded to follow the con- (2) Classes

temporary philosopher, Aristo of Chios (who in this fnHif!!'''^

point, too, endeavoured to place their School on the ferenU


platform of the Cynic philosophy), in denying any
difference in value between things morally indif-
ferent'' and in making the highest aim in life

'
C?c. 20 ; Pfaf. 1. c.
1. o. 6, however, says that he taught ra
Stoi. ii. 142
Diog. vii. 105.
;
/ueTofu operiis ko! xaxias aSid^opa
2 See p. 232. Stob. ii. 132 : ehcu ; and Cic. Off. i. 2, 6, men-
Sia^epeiv Si K4yov(riv aipcric Koi tions him, together with Pyrrho
?K7ITTThv . . . Kal Ka06Kou rh aya- and Aristo, as an upholder of
ehv ToC a^iav ex<""''i". o5m</)opfo. It would appear
' Biog. 165 Herillus
vii. : from these passages that Heril-
taught SLiKp4peiv TeKos Koi inore- lus was not far removed from
\lSa- (On this expression com- true Stoicism. According to
pare Stob. ii. 60) Trjs ixiv ^Apwal Cic. Fin.ii. 13, 43 (conf. Offic),
Touj liii ffoifiovs ffTOX^C^i^Sai, rov he had no followers after the
5e fidmv riv <ia<p6v. Hence Cic. time of Chrysippus.
* Cic.Legg. i. 21, 55 Si, ut
Fin. iv. 15, 40, raises the objec- :

tion, Facit enim ille duo se- Chius Aristo dixit, solum bonum
juncta ultima bonorum, becau.se esse diceret quod honestum
he neither despises external esset malumque quod turpe,
things, nor connects them with cete^-as res omnes plane pares
the ultimate aim. Siug. 1. c, ac ne minimum quidem utrum
;: :

82 THE STOICS.

Chap, consist in indifference to all external things.' Their


virtue bearing, in comparison with the Cynic virtue,
the more positive character of an energetic will, they
required even for the outward circumstances and
conditions of this activity some definite relation
which should regulate the choosing or rejecting
in short, the practical decision. Accordingly, they
divided things indifferent into three classes. To the
first class belong all those things which, from a moral
or absolute point of view, are neither good nor evil,
but yet which have a certain value; no matter
whether this value belongs to them properly, because
they are in harmony with human nature, or whether
it belongs to them improperly, because they are
means for advancing moral and natural life, or
whether it belongs to them on both grounds. The
second class includes everything which, either by it-

self or in its relation to higher aims, is opposed to


nature and harmful ; the third, things which, even

adessent an abessent interesse. ixifii t]vtivovv 4v avTo2s lrapa^Aa-


Ibid. 13, 38. Fin. iv. 17, 47 yhv aTro^ciTroi/Ta a\X' Mtrns iiri
Ut Aristonis esset explosa sen- ir({i'Ta)</ exoi'Ta. Cic. Acad. 1. c.

tentia dicentis, nihil differre Huio summum bonum est in


aliud ab alio nee esse res iillas his rebus (the morally adia-
prseter virtutes et vitia intra phora) neutram
in partem
quas quidquam omnino inter- moveri quae aSia<popia ab ipso
:

esset." Ibid. ii. 13, 43 iii. 3, ; dicitur. Chrysippus, in Pint.


11 ; 15, 50 iv. 16, 43 ; 25, 68
; C. Not. 27, 2 Indifference to
:

V. 25, 73Acad. ii. 42, 130


; that which is neither good nor
Offio. Fragm. Hortens. (in Norm, bad presupposes the idea of the
Pr^fract.) Diog. vii. 160 Sext.
; ; good, and yet, according to
Math. xi. 64. Cic. usually Aristo, the good only consists
places Aristo together with in that state of indiilerence.
Pyrrho. StoT). i. 920; Clem.. Strom, ii.
Diog. 1. 0.
' re'Xos ^(pnffev
: 416, c. See Cic. Fin. iv. 25,
eTrai Tb a!>ia(p6pais ex"'''''" Cp" 68, for Chrysippus' attack on
vphs ra uerajfi aper^j leai xaicltts this 48iO(^o/) a.
THINGS TO BE PREFERRED OR ESCHEWED. 283

in this conditional sense, have neither positive nor Chap.


negative value. The first class bears the name of
XL
things preferential {jrporijiiEVov), or things desirable ;

the second is the class of things to be eschewed


{dTro-TrpoTjyfisvov) ; the third is the class of things
intermediate.' The latter is called, in the strict
sense, indifferent oBi,d(f>opov.^ It includes not only
what is really indifferent, but whatever has such a
slight negative or positive value that it neither enkin-
dles desire nor aversion. Hence the terms -n-porjyfjJvov
and diroTrporjyfiivov are defined to mean respectively
that which has an appreciable positive or negative
value.^ Under things preferential, the Stoics in-
clude partly mental qualities and conditions, such as

* Diogi. vii. 105 : rwy aSia- tion from aya66y: irporiyfievov S'
tp6pwv TO, iJL^v \eyou(rt i:pOT\yiieifa eJval \4yovtriv, & aSiA^opov %v e/c-
ra Se airoirpoTiyfi^va. TtpoTiyfieva \ey6fjie$a Karct itpoTiyoifieyov Kdyov
fiev rh. ^xovTa a^iav ctirotrpoTiy- , . ovSev 5f r&v ayadutf eJycu
.

fiiva 8e tA airai^iav exovTO. By vpor^yfievov, Sih. t5 t^p lieyiffTtiv


a|(o, the three meanings of ii^iav ainh. ^x^*^* '^^ ^e TvpoTjy-
which axe discussed, they un- fieyoVf rij" Seirepavx^pO'V KoX ai^iav
derstand here /xeffriv rivi. tivafuv exor, tTvyeyyi^eiif iruts rp twv
fl xp^^^y cv^^aKKofLivTiv mphs Thv ayaOui/ tpiffei oiiSh yap iy av^.y
'

Karh. (pviriv ^iov. 107 twv nporiy- : ThyvpoTjyovfievov elvaiThv ^aaiXea,


fievQiv ra /j.v Si* avrh TrporjKTal, aAAa rhv fier' ai/Thv Terayfievov.
Tcfc Se Si^ ertpa, ra Se St' aina Kol Stoi. ii. 142
' aSitii(>opo S' :

Si' mpa ... Si' airh jiiv iri ejpat \fyovffi toi fiera^b t&v a7a-
Kara tpvcriv iarl. Si' eVepa 5e 8ti 6up Ral Toiv KoKwv^ Sixus rb aSid-
ircpmoiei XP^^^^ "'^ oKiyas. ^opov yoE^adai tpdfieiroi, Kaff" epa
i/iolais Se ?x*' ""' inrOTrpoTiyiJ.4vov fjiei/ Tpiirov ri) ^i]Te dya&bv flilTf

Karci rhif ivavriov \6yov. Essen- KaKitv KoX rb /^^re aUierbv ;U^Te
tially the same account, only (f>evKT6v Kaff erepov Se rh ffljTe
'

somewhat fuller, in Stoi. Eel. dpfiTJS fJi'fire dtpitpfjirjs kivi)tik6v


t&
ii. 142. Conf. Cic. Acad. i. 10, KaQdira^ dSidtpopa. Similarly
36; Fin. iii. 15, 50; if. 26, 72; IHoff. vii. 104. Sext. M. vi. 60,
Seiet. Pyrrh. iii. 191 ; Math. xi. distinguishes a third meaning.
60 Alex. Aphr. De An. 157.
;
It is, however, only a subdivi-
Zeno (in Stojb. 156; Cic. Fin. sion of the second.
iii. 16, 52) explains the concep- Stoi. 144, 156
' ii. ; Smef. P.
tion wporiynefov, and its distinc- iii. 191 ; M. xi. 62.
; ;

284 THE STOICS.

Chap, talents and skill, even progress towards virtue, in as


"

far as it is not yet virtue ;


partly bodily advantage
beauty, strength, health, life itself ;
partly external
goods riches, honour, noble birth, relations, &c.
Under things to be eschewed, they understand the
opposite things and conditions ; under things indif-
ferent, whatever has no appreciable influence on our
choice, such as the question whether the number of
hairs on the head is even or uneven ; whether I pick
up a piece of waste paper from the floor, or leave it

whether one piece of money or another is used in


(3) Hoi- payment of a debt.' Yet they made a rigid difference

modified
between the purely relative value of things preferen-
aiid ah- tial, and the absolute value of things morally good.
tlwory. Only the latter were really allowed to be called good,
because they only, under all circumstances, are useful
and necessary. Of things morally indifferent, on
the other hand, the best may, under certain circum-
stances, be bad, and the worst sickness, poverty,

and the like may, under certain circumstances, be
useful.^ Just as little would they allow that the
independence of the wise man suSered by the recog-
nition outside himself of :a class of things preferential.
For the wise man, said Chrysippus,^ uses such things

' Diog. vii. 106 Stol.


; ii. 142 ;
Academician Carneades, al-
Cio. Fin. 15, 51
iii. ; Sea^. 1. o. lowed it. Sen. Ep. 102, 3, even
Pint. Sto. Eep. 30. The Stoics quotes it as a Stoic maxim that
were not altogether' agreed as posthumous fame is a good,
to whether fame after death But probably bonum is here in-
belonged to things to be de- accurately used for Trporiyiiiiiov.
sired. According to Oic. Fin. do. Fin. iii. 10, 34
' 16, ;

iii. Chrysippus and Dio-


17, 57, 52; Sext. M. xi. 62. See p.
genes denied it whereas the ; 232 and 283, 2.
younger Stoics, pressed by the ' Sen. Ep. 9, 14 Sapientem :
THINGS TO BE PREFEBRED OR ESCHEWED. 285

without requiring them. Nevertheless, the admis- Chap.


"
sion of classes of things to be preferred and to be
declined obviously undermines their doctrine of the
good. Between what is good and what is evil, a
third group is introduced, of doubtful character ; and
since we have seen the term dBid(j>opov was only in its
more extended meaning applied to this group, it be-
came impossible for them to refuse to apply the term
good to things desirable,'- or to exclude uncondition-
ally from the highest good many of the things
which they were in the habit of pronouncing indif-
ferent.^ Nor was this concession merely the yielding
of a term, as will appear when particular instances
are considered. Not only may Seneca ' be heard, in
Aristotelian manner, defending external possessions
as aids to virtue not only Hecato, and even Dio-
genes, uttering ambiguous sentences as to permitted

nulla re egere [Scio-flai], et ta- 103, says that Posidonius in-


men multis illi rebus opus esse eluded bodily and external ad-
[xp^i""]- vantages among the dyoBd. In
' Plut. Sto. Kep. 30, i Si : h Sen. Bp. 87, 35, he, howe-s^er,
T^ irpiircf irepl dyaSiiv rpdirov expressly proves that they are
Tifct ffvyx^P^'^ '^**' SiSwci Tols not goods. ,

PovKoiievois TB irponyiiha Ka\elv ^ Sen,. Bp. 95, 5 Antipater


:

dyoflii Kai Kaici ramvrla TaiTus quoque inter magnos sectse hu-
Tots Aejecriv ecrri, et -ns /3oii\ETai, jus auctores aliquid se tribuere
KoTck Tcts irapaWajas
TomuTaj dioit externis (namely for the
(with reference to the great- perfection of the highest good),
ness of the difference between sed exiguum admodum. Seneca
irp(yi\yii.hov and dwoir poiiyiiivov) here declaims, in the spirit of
rh tieii ayaShv av-rSiv \iyetv rh Se strict Stoicism, against such a
KoK&v . .. iv liiv ToTs. ffTifMtvo- horesy, but he himself says (De
lievois ob SiariirTovTos avTov TaS' Vit. Be. 22, 5) : Apud me divi-
SXAo aroxa.Coii.evov t^s kkto tos aliquem locum habeut, only
tise
hvoiwjrias avvTiSelas. Seep. 284, not summum et postremum.
1 ; Ole. Fin. iv. 25, 68,and the But what philosopher would
previous remarks on the divi- have said they had this 1
sion of goods, p. 230, 3. Diog, ^ De Vit. Bea. 21.
;
286 THE STOICS.

Chap.
XI.
and forbidden gains ^
not only Pansetius giving ex-
pression t" much that falls short of Stoic severity ^

but even Chrysippus avows that in his opinion it is

silly not to desire health, wealth, and freedom from


pain,^ and that a statesman may treat honour and
wealth as real goods *
adding that the whole Stoic
;

School agrees with him in thinking it no disparage-


ment for a wise man to follow a profession which lay
under a stigma in the common opinion of Grreece.*
He did not even hesitate to assert that it is better
to live irrationally than not to live at all.* It is

' Cic. Off. iii. 12, 51 ; 13, .55 condemned in the Alexandrian
23, 91; 15, 63; 23, 89. Dio- period, as they had been before,
genes of Seleucia says that it but still they were in bad re-
is permitted to circulate base pute, and the second was par-
money, knowingly to conceal ticularly so. Still more at
defects in a purchase from the variance with Greek customs
purchaser, and such like. He- was the course advocated by
cato of Bhodes, a pupil of Panae- Chrysippus (in Plut. Sto. Rep,
tius, thinks that not only will 30) KaX Kv^tfTTrjaeiv rpls Trl tou-
:

a wise man look after his pro- Tif) Aaj8(ii'Ta TaKayroj/. Chrys-
perty by means lawful and ippus himself (In Biog.) enu-
right, but he believes that in a merates the objections to the
famine he will prefer to let his modes of life just named, and,
slaves starve, to maintaining in general, to all trading for
them at too great a sacrifice. money, but his objections can-
According to Cio. OfE. ii.
^ not have appeared to him con-
14, 51, he would allow an at- clusive.
torney to ignore truth, provided ' Pint. Sto. Rep. 18, 1 and
his assertions were at least 3. Com. Not. 12, 4: AuiriTE\
probable. ^ipv &(t)pova fiaWov % p.^ ^tovv kUv
= Phtt. Sto. Rep. 30, 2. flTiSeinyre t^eWr} (ppovijcreu' or, aS
;

lUd. 5.
* it is expressed, 11, 8 : Heracli-
According to Plut. Sto.
' tus and Pherecydes would have
Rep. 20, 3 and 7 and 10 30, 3, ; done well to renounce their
Biog. the
vii. 188, Stoh. ii. 224, wisdom, if they could thereby
Stoics, following Chrysippus, have got rid of their sickness.
admit three ways of earning A prudent man would rather be
an honest livelihood by teach- a fool in human shape than a
ing, by courting the rich, by wise man in the shape of a
serving states and princes. The beast.
first and the last were no longer
PERFECT AND INTERMEDIATE DUTIES. 287

impossible to conceal the fact that, in attempting to Chap.


adapt their system to general opinion and to the ' '

conditions of practical life, the Stoics were driven


into admissions strongly at variance with their pre-
vious theories., It may hence be gathered with cer-
tainty that, in laying down those theories, they had
overstrained a point.
By means of this doctrine of things to be pre- b. Perfect
<^ '"-
ferred and things
to be eschewed,' a further addition mediate
was made to the conception of duty. Under duty, duties.

or what is proper,' we have already seen, the Stoics


understand rational action in general, which becomes
good conduct, or KaTopdw/xa, by being done with a
right intention.^ The conception of duty, therefore,
contains in itself the conception of virtuous conduct,
and is used primarily to express what is good or
rational. Now, however, duty appears to have a
twofold meaning, in consequence of the twofold cha-
racters of things desirable and things good. If the
good were the only permitted object of desire, there
would, of course, be but one duty that of realising
the good and the various actions which contribute
;

to this result would only be distinguished by their


being employed on a different material, but not in
respect of their moral value. But if, besides what
is absolutely good, there are things relatively good,
things not to be desired absolutely, but only in cases
in which they may be pursued without detriment to
the absolute good or virtue if, moreover, besides

' KaflrJKoj', an expression introduced by Zeno, according to


Diog. 108. ' See p, 265,

288 THE STOICS.

Chap. vice, as the absolute evil, there are also relative evils,
XI.
which we have reason to avoid in the same cases
the extent of our duties is increased likewise ; a
number of conditional duties are placed by the side
of duties vinconditional, differing from the latter in
that they aim at pursuing things to be preferred,
and avoiding things to be eschewed. From this
platform, all that accords with nature is regarded as
proper, or a duty in the more extended sense of the
term ; and the conception of propriety is extended
to include plants and animals.' Proper and dutiful
actions are then divided into those which are always
such and those which are only such under peculiar
circumstances the former being called perfect, the
latter intermediate duties;^ and it is stated, as a

*
Diog. 107 : na^TiKov (pairiv dpsT^V Qv OVK del Si rh ipurav
elvai h 'npax^iv eijKoydv tli^ f^X^* ' rh diroKpii/eirdat Kai irepiiroTetf Kai
aTToKoytirflhv otoif tJ) aK6Kovdov 4y TO S^om. Cic. Fin. iii. 17, 58 :
'''V i'^V (tlie same in Cicero), Est autem officium quod ita
StTC^ Kol ^Tri TCt (pVTO. KoX Ql^O. SlO- factum est, ut ejus f acti proba-
reipet' &paff6at yap K&irl tovtuv bilis ratio reddi possit. Ex
Ka6i]K0VTa. Stob. 158: ipiferat quo intelligitur, officium me-
5^ t)> KaOrJKov rh iiKdKovQov 4v dium quoddam esse, quod neque
^w^, % irpax^^v ^ijKoyov hnroKoyiav in bonis ponatur neque in con-
ex^i* irapa t6 KaQviKovZk ^vavrioi^. trariis quoniam enim vide-
. . .

toOto Siare/j'ei KoX iXs Tot &\oya mus, &c. (see p. 265, 2) . . .

Tav fywj', eyepyei ydp K&Ke'iva n quoniamque non dubium est,


aKoKoiOws rij eauTwi/ (^t^trel eiri '
quin in us quEe media dicimus
5e raf KoytKav ^ywj' oSras diroSi- sit alind sumendum aliud re-
Sorai, rh aKdKovdov iv ^lai. KaBij- jiciendum, quidquid ita fit aut
Kov is, in general, what is ac- dicitur communi officio con-
cording to nature, with which tinetur. Also Off. i. 3, 8. Acad,
aK6\ovBov coincides. (See p. i. 10, 37. Corresponding to
228, 2.) See Diog. 108 Mpyvina : irpoTiyiiepoy and diroTrporiy^fvov
5* avrh [ri) KO.BriKOtf'^ elyai raty Zeno placed officium and contra
Karh, (pvffLV KaTatTKcvais olKe7oy. officium, as media quaedam be-
' X>iog. vii. 109 rHv KaSriKSv-
; tween recte factum and peoca-
Tav Tck fiEi/ kii KaM\Ka th. tk ovk tum. Stob. ii. 158 ray Si :

aet' Kai del /iiy KttBiiKei rh kot' KaBriKivTav tA niy ehai ipairi
PERFECT AND INTERMEBIATE DUTIES. 289

pectiliarity of the latter, that, owing to circum- Chap.


XI
stances, a course of conduct may become a duty
which would not have been a duty without those
peculiar circumstances.' In the wider sense of the
term, every actionis proper or according with duty

which consists in the choice of a thing to be pre-


ferred (Trporjy/jLevov) and in avoiding a thing to be
eschewed. On the other hand, a perfect duty is only
fulfilled by virtuous action. A virtuous life and a
wish to do good constitutes the only perfect duty.^

Te\eta, & S)^ Kal KaTopBt^^ara ffufiirepi<f>epea'9ai fpl\ois ' iraph rh


\4yeff6ai . . . ohx e?vot Se Karop- KttSiJKOv Si Stra fij) atpe! ?,6yos,
Qtij^iara ra fx^ oSras ^x'^^'^^t ^ ^^ e.g. neglect of parents ; olhe BJ
ovSh TcAeia, tcaO'fiKOVTa irpocrayo- KaSiiKovTa oUre napa rh KadrjKov,
pevovtrtv, dM.a fi4iTa, olov rh 7a- Stra oSQ' alpel T^yos trpdrreiy oUt^
fjLeiv, rb trpetrfieietv, rh StoAeye- airayopeiieit o^ov Kdptpos ayeXetrOatj
itBcUj t& ToiSrois H/iota. K.T.\. Combining with this the
'
Stob. 160. Dioff. 1. 0. : tA passage previously quoted, it
jttey elj/ai KaG'fiHovra &vev irepi- appears that KaBfiKov includes
trTd(rtos, Tcfc 8e irepiiTTaTtKd. Kal not only actions which aim at a
&yiv piv jrepiffrdo'eeiis ToSe, vyeias moral good, but those which
iirifie\e7tT6ai Kal aiffOTiTTipiav Kal aim at a simple irpofiyp.^vov and, ;

T& bfioia' KOTct iraplfTTatTiv Sh rh in view of the latter, koStikov is


inipovv eavrhv Kal r^v KTTJtrtv diafi- included among things inter-
^iTTTety. dydKoyov Sk Kal Twf mediate, or aSid(popa in its more
irapd t6 KadrlKoy. This distinc- extended meaning. (Mc. see ;

tion, of course, only applies to p. 288, 2. iStob. 158, says that


lieffov KafliJKOK. The uncondi- those Ka9i]K0VTa which are at
tional duty of virtuous life can- the same time KaTopBdimra, are
not be abrogated by any cir- oi/Se r4\eia, ctXA^ fieffa . . . irapa-
cumstances. fierpeiffOat Sh rh lieaov KaBrtKov
' Compare, on this point, dSta<l}6poLS Tiffl Ka\ovpLvois Ss
besides the quotations on p. irap^ (piatv Kal Karct ^itriv, Toi-
265, 2, Dioff. 108 tmi/ y&p Kofl' : auT7]V S* evipviap Trpo(Ttftepop.evoiSt
l>pph)v fvepyovfievatv r^ p.^v HaBii- Sffr' et fi^ KapL^dvoiiiiv ahrh ^
Kovra elvat, tA Se KaSri- naph rh Stw&ovixiBa d-KepitrirdffTUs (if,
Kov, T& 5' oSre KaSiiKOVTa aire without particular occasion, or
vapa Th KoSriKov. Ka^Kovra as Diog. 109 observes, &vev wept-
piv oiv iivai iaa 6 \6yos alpei
grddea! see previous note
(demands ; see p. 244, 2, we despise or reject them) pAi
the alpSiv \6yos) iraieiv. ws ^x** '''^ eiSaiptovetv.
yove^s Tijii^y, Sids\(povs, Trarpt5a,
290 THE STOICS.

Chap. Some confusion is introduced into this teaching


XI.
by the fact that in setting up the standard for dis-
tinguishing perfect from imperfect duties, the Stoics
sometimes look at the real, sometimes at the per-
sonal value, of actions, without keeping these two
aspects distinct. They therefore use the terms per-
fect and imperfect sometimes to express the difference
between conditional and unconditional duties ; at
other times, to express that between morality and
law.' Far worse than the formal defect is the group-
ing in this division under the conception of duty
things of the most varied moral character. If once
things which have only a conditional value are ad-
mitted into the circle of duties, what is there to pre-
vent their being defended in the practical application
of the Stoic teaching, on grounds altogether repug-
nant to the legitimate consequences of the Stoic
principles ?

C. Eirw- In accordance with these admissions, the Stoic


tiom.
(1) Per- system sought in another respect to meet facts and
mitted practical wants by abating somewhat from the aus-
affections.
terity of its demands. Consistently carried out,
those demands require the unconditional extirpation
of the whole sensuous nature, such as was originally
expressed by the demand for apathy. But just as
the stricter Stoic theory of the good was modified
by the admission of Trporjj/jLeva, so this demand was
modified in two ways the first elements at least of
;

the forbidden emotions were allowed under other


names; and whilst emotions were still forbidden,
' In the latter sense Ka6riKoi> and KarSpduim have been already
discussed, p. 264.
: '

EMOTIONS. 291

certain mental affections were permitted, and even Chap.


XI.
declared to be desirable. Taking the first point, it
was allowed by the Stoics that the wise man feels
pain, and that at certain things he does not remain
wholly calm.' They appealed to this admission to
show that their system was not identical with that
of the Cynics.'' For men to be entirely free from all
such mental affections cannot be required, but only
that he refuse assent to them, and do not suffer
them to obtain the mastery.' In illustration of the
other point, they propounded their doctrine of
svwaOeiai, or rational dispositions, which, as distinct
from emotions, are to be found in the wise man,
and in the wise man only. Of these rational dis-
positions, they distinguish three chief varieties, be-
sides several subordinate varieties.'* Although this

' Sen. De Ira, i. 16, 7: When Conf. Sen. De Ira, ii. 2-4,
'

the wise man sees anything re- particularly the quotation in


volting, non . . tangetur ani-
. 6feU, from Epiotetus Even :

mus ejus eritque solito com- the wise man is apt, at terrible
motior ? Fateor, seutiet levem occurrences, paulisper moveri
quendam tenuemque motum. et contrahi et pallescere, non
Nam, ut dixit Zeno, in sapientis opinione alicujus mali peroepta,
quoque animo etiamcum vulnus sed quibusdam motibus rapidis
sanatum eat, cicatrix manet. et inconsultis, offioium mentis
Id. ii. Ep. 57, 3 De Const,
2 ; ; atque rationis prsevertentibus.
10, 4 Stob. Floril. 7, 21 Plut.
; ; But what distinguishes him
C. Not. 25, 5 ; Bpictet. in Gell. from the foolish man is that
N. A. xix. 1, 17. Conf. p. 253, only the foolish man and not
5, 6. the wise man assents ((riry/ta-
* Sen. Brevit. Vit. c. 14,2: TOTfAerai, irpo(reiriSo|(ifi)tosuch
Hominis naturam cum Stoicis impressions (if>ai'TO(roi).

vincere cum Cyniois excedere. IHoff. vii. 115 : ehai St koX


*

Similarly Ep. 9, 3 Hoc inter : evTraHeias ^curl rpeis, X"'?^", evKd-


nos et illos (Stilpo and the /8eio>', ^oiKi)(!iv koI t^v jiiv
Cynics in general) interest x"-?^" ^"avrlav (pcurlv ehat rp
noster sapiens vincit quidem iidav^ oi<rav fSXoyov i-napaui
tV
inoommodum omne, sed sentit 8e ebXafinav rif (pd^if oiaav ej-
illorum ne sentit quidem. Xoyov iicKKtaiv
tj 5i iTrtdvinlif

TT 2
:

292 THE STOICS.

Chap, admission was intended to vindicate the absence


XI "

of emotions in the wise man, since the permitted


feelings are not emotions, still it made the boundary-
line between emotions and feelings so uncertain that
in practice the sharply-defined contrast between' the
wise and the foolish threatened wellnigh to disap-
pear altogether,
(2) 3lodi- This danger appears more imminent when we
JicaUon of
apathy. observe the perplexity
,
m which the Stoics were placed
.

when asked to point out the wise man in experience.


For not only do opponents asseverate that, accord-
ing to their own confession, no one, or as good as no
one, can be found in actual history who altogether
deserves that high title,' but even their own admis-
sions agree therewith.^ They dare to describe even
Socrates, Diogenes, and Antisthenes as not completely
virtuous, but only as travellers towards virtue.^ It was
of little avail to point to Hercules or Ulysses,* or,

ivavriav tpairiv elj/at r^v ^oiKTjtrtv Sen. Tranq. An. 7, 4


^
Ubi :

oSffau eSKoyov Sp{iv. Sub- enim istum invenies, quern tot


divisionsof ;8oii\7)(risare : eScoia, seculis quEerimus ? (the wise
6u/icia, aa-iraiTiihs, iiyiiirritTis; of man.) Ep. 42, 1: Sois quern.
fi\d$eia : oiSij, ayveid ; of X"?"^ nunc virum bonum dicam ?
Tfpifiis, elxjipoiTivri, Euflu/ifa. The Hujus secundae notse. Nam ille
same three firndBeuu are men- alter fortasse tanquam phoenix
tioned by Cio. Tuso. iv. 6, 12, semel anno quingeutesimo nas-
with the remark that they only citur, see p. 273, 1, just as
belong to the wise. See Stob. everything great is rare. But
92, and Sen. Ep. 59, 14 72, 4 ; compare p. 274, 3.
and 8, respecting the wise man's ' Cio. Fin. iv. 20, 56, and
cheerfulness. p. 274, 2.
' Besides the quotations, * Hos enim
(says Sen. De
p. 271, see PhU. Sto. Eep. 31, Const. of the two named)
2, 1,
5 : Kol ^V oW afn'bv 6 Xpvffnnros Stoici nostri sapientes pronun-
anocpaivet ffirov^atov, oirerivhruv tiaverunt, invictos laboribus,
ouToB yvapliiav ti KaOrrytf-ii""'. etc. Further particulars in
Cie. Acad,47, 145
ii. ;
Quintil. Seraelit. AUeg. Horn, c. 33
Inst. xii. 1, 18. and 70.
EMOTIONS. 293

with Posidonius,' to the mythical golden age, in Chap.


which the wise are said to have ruled. The pictures
of those heroes would have to be changed altogether,
to bring them into harmony with the wise men of the
Stoics ; and Posidonius might be easily disposed of
on Stoic principles, by the rejoinder that virtue and
wisdom are things of free exercise, and, since free
exercise was wanting in the case of the first men,
their condition can only have been a state of imcon-
scious ignorance, and not one of perfection.^ If, in re-
ality, there are no wise men, the division of men into
wise and foolish falls at once to the ground all man-
:

kind belong to the fools ; the conception of the wise


man is an unreal fancy. It becomes all the more
difficult to maintain the assertion that all fools are

equally foolish, and all the wise are equally wise. If,

instead of producing real wisdom, philosophy can


only produce a progress in that direction, still it

will hardly take such a modest estimate of its own


success as to allow that there is no real distinction
between a zealous student and a bigoted despiser of
its doctrines.

It was therefore natural that the Stoics, notwith- (3) The

^ their
standinsf own maxims, found themselves com- *^''*'' "/
progress.
pelled to recognise differences among the bad and
'
Sen. Ep. 90, 5. To these ^ Sen. 1. c. 44 Non dat :

wise men of the old world natura virtutem, ars est bonum
Posidonius traced back all fieri . ignorantia rernm in-
. .

kinds of useful discoveries, nooentes erant . . virtus non


.

Posidonius is probably meant contingit animo nisi instituto


by the younger Stoics {Sesnt.
' ' et edocto et ad summum ad-
Math, ix. 28), who say that sidua exeroitatione perduoto.
they introduced belief in the Ad hoc quidem, sed sine hoc
Gods. nascimus, ka.
294 THE STOICS.

Chap. differences among the good. In reference to their


XI.
system these dififerences were, indeed, made to de-
pend in the case of the bad upon the greater or
less difficulty of healing the moral defects, or, in the
case of the good, upon qualities morally indifferent.'
It was also natural that they should so nearly iden-
tify the state of irpoKoirr) or progress towards wis-
dom, the only really existing state with wisdom that
it could hardly be distinguished therefrom. If there
is a stage of progress at which a man is free from
all emotions, discharges all his duties, knows all that
is necessary, and is even secure against the danger of
relapse,^ such a stage cannot be distinguished from
wisdom, either by its want of experience or by the

> Stoi. Eel. ii. 236 : iirav 5J Tcov airavra TrdvTtus cnro5iSw<n rii
imwv Twv afjLapTTjfjAruy eTvai rivas KoQ-fiKOVTCt KaX ou^hv wapa\eitrt *

4v ainois Statpof/hs, KU.96(rov tA fiev rhv Se roirov ^lov ovk elyal iru
avTuv anh ffKktjpas Kol SvaiiiTou ipTjirlv evBaifiova aAV 4irtyiyvf(r0aL
5la94(Tews yiyveraij tA 5' oft. (See auTfj] T^v irav at /jieirai
evSatfjLQviav
p. 251, 2, for the difference irpd^ets aSrai wpoaXdQufTt t& &
between emotion and disease of jSalov Kai KTlnhv Kai iiiav irrj^lv

the soul.) KoX Twv fTTTiiv^aiay ye Chrysippus was


Tii/a \dpii)(riv.
&\\ovs &\\aiy TpoTpetrriKaTepovs probably the author of the divi-
ylyyeffdai Kai irta'TtKuTepous en 5e sion of progressers into three
Kal a7xi'Oi"''^^pot^s, Kaii
t& /x^ffo classes, which is discussed by
T^ ^^trepi^afx^avdiiiva ruv itnTa- Sen. Ep. 75, 8. Of those who
virtuous
(Tifjiv (rvfi^atvovo'ciiv, i. e., have reached the highest stage
men are not all equally secure. it is said, omnes jam affectus
These differences of degree do et vitia posuerunt, quas erant
not, however, apply to wisdom compleotenda didicerunt, sed
(nor on the other hand to folly), illis adhuc inexperta fiducia
which admits of no increase, est. Bonum suum nondum in
hut only to such properties as usu habent. Jam tameu in ilia
are included in the whole moral quae f ugerunt recidere non pos-
state, but are not themselves sunt, jam ibi sunt unde non est
of moral nature. See Cic. Fin. retro lapsus, sed hoc illis de se
iv. 20, 56, and p. 275, 1. nondum liquet et . . scire se .

" Stob. Serm. 7, 21 : 6 5' iv' nesciunt.


iKpttVf (pTlffl [XpiifrnrTTOs] TrpoK6Tr-
;

EMOTIONS. 295

absence of a clear knowledge of oneself. For has it Chap.


XI.
not been frequently asserted that happiness is not
increased by length of time, and that the wise man
is at first not conscious of his? how- wisdom ' If,

ever, the highest stage of approximation to wisdom


is supposed still to fall short of wisdom, because it

is not sure of its continuance, and though free from


mental diseases, it is not free from emotions,'^ how,
it may be asked, do these passing emotions differ
from the mental affections which are found in the
wise man ? Is there any real distinction between
them ? If the progressing candidate has attained
to freedom from diseased mental states, is the clanger
of a relapse very great ? Besides, the Stoics were by
no means agreed that the really wise man is free from
all danger, Cleanthes holding with the Cynics that
virtue can never be lost ; Chrysippus admitting that,
in certain cases, it is defectible.' After all this

See pp. 239, 1 ; 271, 7.


^ Chrysippus, it belongs to those
Sen. Bp. 75,-10
2 Quidam : points in which the original
hoc proflcientium genus de quo relation of Stoicism to Cyni-
locutus sum ita complectuntur, cism was weakened by him.
ut illos dicant jam effugisse Sen. Bp. 72, 6, speaking in the
morbos animi, afifectus nondum tone of Cleanthes, says that
(on this distinction, see p. 251, elsewhere he considered a can-
2), et adhuc in lubrico stare, didate of the first class secure
quia nemo sit extra periculum against relapses. On the con-
malitiEB nisi qui totam earn ex- trary, Simpl. Categ. 102, it, ^
cussit. The same view is up- (Schol. in Arist. 86, a, 48
held by Sen. Bp. 72, 6. b, 30), says first that the Stoics
' Diog. vii. 127 ; t^jk aper^v declared virtue to be indefec-
XpiiTLirros jxiv otto/SAijt))!', K\- tible, but subsequently limits
ivSifs 5e a</oir(J;8\i)T0i'

6 jjiiv, aito- this assertion by saying that,
PK-qriiv, Sii ;iif'fli)!' Koi lieXayxo- ^v Kaipots (the reading K&pois is
Xiav 6 86, avm6p\-riTov, Sia better) Koi iie\ayxo?^lats, virtue,
Pf&alous Karahii'pfis. The latter together with the whole rational
view was that of the Cynics, life (\oyiKii eJu), is lost, and
Although departed from by succeeded, not indeed by vice,
296 THE STOICS.

Chap, admission is only one among many traits which prove


"

that the Stoics were obliged to abate from the ori-


ginal severity of their demands.

but by a ejij /ttco-rj. A similar out some modifying clauses,


question Whether the wise
is, Aphr. De An. 156, b, also
Aleas.
man can become mad ? which combats the view that the wise
is answered in the negative by man will act virtuously when
Biog. vii. 118, though not with- in a frenzy.
APPLIED MORAL SCIENCE. 297

CHAPTEE XII.

APPLIED MOBAL SCIENCE.

All that has hitherto been stated had regard to the Chap.
general principles only of the Stoics touching the ^'^^

end and the conditions of moral action. Whether


the mere exposition of principles be enough, or
whether the practical application of these principles
to the special relations of life does not also form part
of moral science was a question as to which the Stoic
School was not originally unanimous, Aristo, on this
as on other points a Cynic, was of opinion that this
whole branch of moral science was useless and un-
necessary ; the philosopher must confine himself ex-
clusively to things which have a practical value, the
fundamental points of morality.' Within the Stoic
School, however, this view did not gain much

' Further particulars have 8, as itapaivf7iK6s. He who is


been already given, p. 61. himself insufficiently educated
Seneca (Ep. 95, 1) calls the will do well (ririiv hiywv axoietv
subject of applied ethics, which uTrofleriKui' Trapci tS>v ireTronififvaiv

Aristo rejected, parsnetice, or ^pyov eiSepat riva fiev $\aPepli.


pars prfficeptiva. Sextus speaks Tiua Si a<pe\iim wSpd^rois. {mo-

ot two TiJTroi a irapaivfTiKhs and BsriKbs tiSttos is therefore iden-
a uitoSeriKSs. Both terras, how- tical with the suasio of Posi-
ever, appear to denote the same donius (in Sen. Ep. 95, 65),
thing ; for iroeeriKhs is defined See p. 223, note 1.

by Muson. in Stub. Floril. 117,


298 THE STOICS.

Chap, support. Even Cleanthes, otherwise agreeing with


XII.
Aristo, would not deny the value of an application of
theory to details, provided the connection of these
details with general principles be not lost sight of.*
Nor can there be any doubt that, after the time of
Chrysippus, details engrossed much of the attention
of the Stoic philosophers. Posidonius enumerates, as
belonging to the province of moral philosophy, pre-
cept, exhortation, and advice.^ His teacher, Panse-
tius, had discussed the hortatory side of morality' in
three books on duties, imitated by Cicero's well-
known treatise.^ The division of ethics attributed
to Diogenes,' and by him referred to Chrysippus,
leaves a place for such discussions ;
^ and, not to men-
tion Aristo's opposition thereto, which supposes the
existence of applied moral science, the example of
his fellow-student Perseeus, whose precepts for a
banquet ' have been already referred to, proves how
Sen. Ep. 9i, i Cleanthes
' : vote his attention to officia,
utilem quidem judicat et banc quorum prsecepta traduntur.
partem, sed imbecillam nisi ab Cicero then goes fully into
universe fluit, nisi decreta ipsa particulars. He treats of
philosophiie et capita cognovit, amusement and
occupation
2 See p. 223, 1. (i. 29, 103) of the peculiar
;

' See (Mo. Off. i. 2,


7 ; 3, 9 ;
duties of the young and the
iii. 2, 7. Cicero himself said old, of officials, citizens, fo-
that he chiefly followed Pause- reigners (i. 34) of outward
;

tins (ifepl Tuv KaBi\K6vTuv), not appearance, gait, conversation


as a mere translator, but cor- (i. 36) ; of the means of win-
rectione quadam adhibita. See ning others (ii. 6, 21). Panse-
p. 300, 2. . tius must have given a similar
'dc. OS., i. 3, 7 Omnis de
: treatment to the subject,
officio duplex est qusestio: unum * See p. 223, 1.

genus est, quod pertinet ad ' Particularly in the por-

finem bonorum alteram, quod


: tions treating irspl tUv KaBti-
positum est in prseceptis, quibns k6vtii>v and vepl Trporpowav re Kal
in omnes partes usus vitse con- imoTpimuv.
formari possit. He would de- ' See p. 272, 2.
;

APPLIED MORAL SCIENCE. 299

early practical ethics had obtained a footing within Chap.


XII.
the Stoic School. Moreover, the elaborate theory of
virtue propounded by ChrysippuS and his followers ^

can hardly have failed to include many of the prin-


cipal occurrences in life. Thus a number of parti-
cular precepts are known to us, which are partly
quoted by other writers as belonging to the Stoics,
and are partly to be found in the pages of Seneca,
Epictetus, and Marcus Aurelius, and in Cicero's trea-
tise on duties. Indeed, the Stoics were the first who
went at all deeply into the subject of casuistry.^ At
a later epoch, when more general questions had been
settled by Chrysippus, the preference for particular
enquiries on the domain of applied moral science
appears to have increased among the Stoics.^ Pro-
bably, however, none but the later members of
the School advanced the unscientific assertion*
that we ought to confine ourselves to precepts for

' See p. 260, 4, and 261, 1. Cicero, but by others. An-


^ According to do. Off. i. tipater of Tyre, a cotemporary
2 7, Ad Att. xvi. 11, Pansetius,
;
of Cicero, had added dis-
in the third chief division of cussions on the care of health
his treatise on duties, intended and wealth ( do. Off. ii. 24, 86)
to discuss cases of collision be- and Hecato, in his treatise on
tween apparent interest and duties, had added further
duty, but his intentions were casuistical investigations (^Cic.
never carried out. It appears, iii. 23, 89). Brutus, too, who,
however, from Off. i. 45, 159 ;
like his teacher Antiochus, was
iii. 12, 50 13, 55
; 23, 89, that
;
devoted to a moderate Stoicism,
these cases were frequently and of whom Sen. Ep. 95, 45,
discussed, not only by the reports that he had laid down
pupils of Panaetius, Posidonius, rules for the relations of
and Hecato, but by Diogenes parents, children, and brothers
of Seleucia and Antipater of in his treatise ircpl toS ko9^-
Tarsus. koptos, may have followed
' treatise of Pansetius
The Pan^tius.
appears to have been used as a * Sen. Ep. 94, 1 ; 95, 1.
chief authority, not only by

00 THE STOICS.

Chap, particular cases, since only these have any practical


value.
In this extension of the moral theory, besides
the longing for scientific completeness, the endea-
vour may also be observed to subordinate all sides
of human activity to moral considerations. In the
virtuous man, as the Stoics held, everything becomes
virtue ;' and hence everything is included in moral
philosophy. Thereby, without doubt, the Stoic School
contributed in no small degree towards settling and
defining moral ideas, not only for its immediate con-
temporaries, but also for all subsequent times. Never-
theless, the more the teaching of the School entered
into the details of every-day life, the more impossible

it became to prevent practical considerations from


overriding the natural severity of Stoic principles,
or to keep the strictness of scientific procedure from
yielding to the less accurate bias of experience.
The order and division which the Stoics adopted
for discussing details in the hortatory part of moral
science are not known to us ; nor, indeed, is it known
whether that order was uniform in all cases.' It

' Stob. ii. 128 in e{i (not


: interest. The third part, which
only iv irxeVci, see p. 230) S^ ov Pansetius proposed to him.self
IJ,6vas tAs iperiis iwi. Kol
fli/oi the collision between duty and
Tcts SWos T&s ^y Toj (Tirou-
TExi'ttf
interest was never fully oar-
Satij) avSpi, liWoiiaBelaas vnh ttjs ried out. Cicero adds disous-
ipET^j KoX yevoufvas oni6TairT<i- sions on two questions, which
T0U9, olovel 7ctp apsT^s yiyvi- of two conflicting duties and
a8ai. which of two conflicting in-
The treatise of Pansetius
" terests must be preferred (i. 3,
we learn from Cio. OfE. i. 3, 9 ;
10, c. 43 ii. 25).
; Otherwise
iii. 2, 7 7, 33 ; discussed its he appears in his two first
subject first from the platform books to follow the order of
of duty, and then from that of Panastius.
TUB INDiriBUAL. SOI

will be most convenient for the purpose of our pre^ Chap.


'

sent description to distinguish, in the first place,


those points which refer to the moral activity of the
individual as such, and afterwards to go on to those
which relate to social life. Subsequently, the teach-
ing of the Stoics on the relation of man to the course
of the world and to necessity will engage our atten-
tion.
It was consistent with the whole tone of the a. The in-
Stoic system to devote, in ethics, more attention to <^*^*'^-

the conduct and duties of the individual than had poHance


been done by previous philosophy. Not that pre-
""^^g'|f.
vious philosophers had altogether ignored this side, dividual.

Indeed, Aristotle, in his investigations into indivi-


dual virtue, had been led to enquire carefully into
individual morality. Still, with Aristotle, the in-
fluence of classic antiquity on the border-land of
which he stands was sufiBciently strong to throw the
individua;l into the background as compared with
the community, and to subordinate ethics to politics.
In the post-Aristotelian philosophy, this relation was
exactly reversed. "With the decline of public life in
Greece, intellectual interest in the state declined

also ; and, in equal degree, the personality of the in-


dividual and circumstances of private life came into
prominence. This feature may be already noticed
in some of the older Schools, for instance, in the
Academy and Peripatetic School. The Peripatetic,
in particular, had already, in the time of its first ad-
herents, travelled far on the road which the founder
had struck out. Among the Stoics, the same
302 THE STOICS.

Chap, feature was required by the whole spirit of their


xn.
system. If happiness depends upon man's internal
state only, nothing external having power to affect
it, the science which professes to lead man to hap-

piness must primarily busy itself with man's moral


activity. It can only consider human society in as
far as action for society forms part of the moral duty
of the individual. Hence, in the Stoic philosophy,
researches into the duties of the individual occupy
a large space, there being a corresponding subordi-
nation of politics. These duties form the subject of
by far the greater part of the applied moral science
of the Stoics ; and how minutely they entered in that
study into possible details has been already set forth.'
At the same time, the scientific harvest resulting
from these researches is by no means in proportion
to their extent.
Confining our attention to form some idea of the
treatise of Paneetius on duties to the two first books of
Cicero's work, De Officiis, after a few introductory re-
marks, we find morality as such (honestum) described,
according to the scheme of the four cardinal virtues
(i. 5-42). In discussing the first of these, intelligence,
love of research recommended, and useless subtlety
is

is deprecated. Justice and injustice are next discussed,

'
See pp. 260, 298. Amongst Stoics, iv tois irspl KaBjiKivrav,
other things, as we learn from an enquiry whether it is proper
the fragment in Athen. xiii. to take the largest portion
565, a, Chrysippus discussed before one's father at table,
at length the question of and whether it is proper to
shaving ; and Aleoj. Aphr. cross the legs in the school of a
Top. 26, quotes, in illustration philosopher,
of the useless enquiries of the
THE INDIVIDUAL. 303

in all their various forms, due regard feeing had to the Chap
XIT.
cases of ordinary occurrence in life. Liberality, kind-
ness, and benevolence are treated as subdivisions of
justice ;and this leads to a consideration of human
society in all its various forms (c. 16-18, 60). Next,
turning to bravery (18, 61), the philosopher draws
attention to the fact that bravery is inseparably con-
nected with justice. He then describes it partly as it
appears in the forms of magnanimity and endurance,
regardless of external circumstances, partly in the
form of energetic courage ; and, in so doing, he dis-
cusses various questions which suggest themselves,
such as the nature of true and false courage, mili-
tary and civil courage, and the exclusion of anger
from valour. Lastly, the object of the fourth chief
virtue (c. 27) is described, in general terms, as what
is proper (decorum, irpkirov), and the corresponding
state as propriety, both in controlling the impulses
of the senses, in jest and play, and in the whole per-
sonal bearing. The demands are discussed
peculiar
made by individual nature, by time of
life, by civil

position. Even outward proprieties of speech and


conversation, of domestic arrangement, tact in be-
haviour,' honourable and dishonourable modes of
life do not escape attention.^
In the second book of his work, Cicero considers
the relation of interest to duty and having proved, ;

f\na{,ia, evKaipia, talis ordo ^ i. 43. We omit Cicero's


actionum ut in vita omnia sint treatise, this section not being
apta inter se et convenientia. found in Panjetius.
i. 40, 142 144. ;
304 THE STOICS.

Chap, at length,' that most that is advantageous and disad-


XII.
vantageous is brought on us by other men, he turns
to the means by which we may gain the support of
others, and by which affection, trust, and admiration
may be secured. He reviews various kinds of ser-
vices for individuals and the state, and embraces, at
the same time, the opportunity of giving vent to his
grudge against despotism and republican court of the
people. The principles on which this review is con-
ducted are such that objection can rarely be taken
to them from the platform of modem morality. Yet
unmistakeably the Stoic bias is present in the con-
ception and support of the rules of life, and parti-
cularly in the definitions of various virtues, few of
the moral judgments, however, are other than might
have been expressed from the platform of the Pla-
tonic and Aristotelian ethics.'' The same remark
holds good of some other points on record, by means
of which the Stoics gave a further expansion to their
picture of the wise man.^ Eevolting as their tenets
at times appear, there is yet little in their applica-
tion that deviated from the moral ideas generally
current.

' Panaetius still more dif- frank (axlpSnXos), and with no


fusively, 5, 16. inclination to pretence. He
^ Such, for instance, as the stands aloof from the affairs of
prohibition against being angry lest he should
life (^airpdy/xav),
with enemies (i. 25, 88), which do anything contrary to duty,
recalls at once the difference of See p. 323, 1. Stob. ii. 240,
the Stoics and Peripatetics on says : The wise man is gentle
the admissibility of emotions. (irpSo!),quiet (riirixios), and
See p. 252. considerate (Kiaiuos), never ex-
'Diog. 117, says The aii^os
: citing angry feelings against
or (TwouSoTos is free from vanity others, never deferring what
(Sti/^os), is earnest laiarnpbs), he has to do.
'

THE INDIVIDUAL. 305

More peculiar, and at the same time more start- Chap.


^^^'
ling, is another feature about the Stoics. Let not
too much be made of the fact that they, under certain (2) Oyni-

circumstances, permitted a lie.' Were not Socrates "^^"^


and Plato, at least, of the same opinion ? And, to () f^"**-

be frank, we must admit that, although in this re- stoics mth

spect moral theories are strict enough, yet practice '^^'"<''*-

is commonly far too lax now. Very repulsive, how-


ever, are many assertions attributed to the Stoics,
respecting the attitude of the wise man to the
so-called intermediate things. Was not this very in-
dependence of externals, this indifference to every-
thing but the moral state, which found expression
in the doctrine of things indifferent and of the wise

' Chrysippus, in Plut. Sto. mentioned by Xen, Mem. iv. 2,


Rep. 47, 1 ^Ka-^ovuiv ol (rotpol
: 17, and Plato, Eep. ii. 382, c.
i/zcuSeTs (pavraffias ifnroiovvreSj ttp 389, B iv. 459, C, in which the
;

at tpavratriai iroiucriy avTore\us interests of another or of the


Tcts avyKaraOeffets ' ttoWAki^ yhp community require deception)
ol ffo<poi ;//iJSt j(^p5}vrai wpbs rovs Kol Kar' &\\as oiKovOfdas tov
(j>ai\ous KaX tpavTaffiav irapLffTaaL ptov iro^Xds. In accordance with
KiQav^iv, ov fj.i]v airiay rrfs avyKa- this passage, too, the statement
radetreais- IttcI KatTTis vnoKii^ews of Procl. in Aloib. (Op. ed.
alrla rris il^euSoOs tffrat Kol ttis
Cous. iii. 64) that the Stoics
awdrtis. Stob. ii. 230 :/i^ t^siieaeai differ from their predecessors
rhv ff6ipov aXA.' ^v iratnvh.\7iBGvetv in that they reject all lies
oh yhp ^v T^ K^yeiv tl i^/evSos t6 must be explained oute yap :

e^a-naT^lf ifjri iiKaiuti Kar avTobs

5iai|/EU(rTQ)s -rh tj/eiSos \iyeiy /col o^TE ^id^effBat oUre ^.TToffrepuy,


^ttI oiraTT) TiSy r\ria-lov. t^ /ieV- dA.X' E/C(iTT7j Twv irpd^euy toiitqiv

Tot i//ei55z TTOTe trvyxp'hff^^^^^ cLirh pLOX^T)pas irpAeifftv e^etos Ka\

[1. o-Eo-eai] voiii(ovini> avThf Kara &diK6s ia-Tip. The point here in
dispute is simply verbal the
voKKohs TpSTTOvs Sj/Ei) (TvyKara- ;

AeVeiuj Kal yap Kara irrparriylav Stoics were, in realitj', at one


wphs ruv &yTl7rdKwv, Kal Kara Ti]if with Plato, in not calling per-
TovtTV/j.<t)epovrosTrpo6pa(rtv (yrhich, mitted falsehood untruth or
however, may not be translated deceit only for the reasons
as muer
iii. 662 does for the ' quoted by ^hrysippus and Sto-
sake of advantage'; it rather bseus.

refers to such cases as those


;

30G THE STOICS.

Chap, man's apathy, at the root of that onesidedness of life


XII.
and principle which is so prominent in the Cynic
School, the parent School of the Stoics ? Granting
that in the Stoic School this onesidedness was toned
down and supplemented by other elements, still the
tendency thereto was too deeply rooted from its ori-
gin, and too closely bound up with its fundamental
view of life, to be ever properly eradicated. It did
not require, indeed, a Cynic life from its members
nay, more, it even avowed that, except in rare cases,
such a life ought not to be followed ;' still the Cynic's
life was its ideal ; and when it asserted that it was not
necessary for a wise man to be a Cynic, it implied
that, if once a Cynic, he would always be a Cynic.^
Stoicism took for its patterns ' Antisthenes and Dio-
genes quite as much as Socrates ; even those who
held with Seneca,'' that a philosopher ought to ac-
commodate himself to prevailing customs, and, from
regard to others, do what he would not himself ap-
prove, did not therefore cease to bestow their highest
admiration on Diogenes's independence of wants, with
'
do. Fin. iii. 20, 68 Cy- : nhi' o-o^bi' Svt' ttv ipiaaSai toC
nicorum autem xationem atque KwurftoS.
vitam alii cadere in sapientem See p. 274, 2. According
'

dicuut, si quis ejusmodi forte to the epigrams of Timon, in


casus inciderit, utid faciendum Diog. vii. 16, At/ten. iv. 158, a,
sit, alii nnllo modo. The latter Sext. Math. xi. 172, Zeno's
must, however, have been in a School must have presented a
minority. very Cynical appearance. Pro-
' Diog. 121 Kwie'iv t airhD
: bably, the description is par-
[rjy aoif>6v~\ ehai yap rhv Kvvi-

tially true of the earlier history
aiibv ffivToiwv iTf li.piTiiii dShv, Sis of that School ; still I would
'AirowdSoipos [on whom, see p. attach no great value to it as
51, 1] ev rfi ^9iKp. Stab. 238 : illustrating the system.
Kvvteiy Te rhv <ro^hv Keyovfftv, * Ep. 5, 1 103, 5; Fr. 19, ;

X<rov Tip iirififpfiv tQ KwuTfuif, oh in Lactant. Inst. iii. 16.


THE INDIVIDUAL. 30',

all its eccentricities.' More consistent thinkers even Chap.


XII '_
approximated to Cynicism in their moral precepts,'
and in later times a School of younger Cynics actually
grew out of the Stoic School.
Bearing, as the Stoics did, so close a relationship (j) in-

to the Cynics, it cannot astonish us to find amongst *^*i^j"f


them many instances of the most revolting traits in

Cynicism the contempt for cultured habits, the vio-


lation of right feelings fully justifying the righteous
indignation of their opponents. Chrysippus regarded
many things as perfectly harmless in which the reli-
gious feeling of Grreece saw pollution,' in defence
of his opinion pleading the example of animals^ to
show that they were according tO' nature. The
care for deceased relatives he not only proposed!
to limit to the simplest mode of burial, but would
have it altogether put in the background and he ;

even made the horrible suggestion, which he described


in full, of using for purposes of nourishment the-
flesh of amputated limbs and the corpses of even the

nearest relatives.'' Great offence, too, was given by

'
See, on this point, Tranq. tarch objects, he would not
An. 8, 4 Benef v. 4, 3 6, 1
; . ; ;
allow these considerations.
* Besides i)i^. vii. 188, and
Ep. 90, 14. Sen. Ep. 29, 1,
does not, however, agree with Sext. Pyrrh. iii. 207, see Chry-
the Stoic custom of sowing ex- sippus's own words, in Sext.
hortations broadcast. Pyrrh. iii. 247 (Math. xi. 193).
^ As may be seen in Muso- The majority of the Stoics
nius and Bpictetus. appear to have limited canni-
'
Plut. Sto. Kep. 22 (the balism to cases of extreme
question being as to the pollu- necessity. See JHog. 121. Chry-
tion of the temples by the sippns had probably been
contact with the dead or lying- speaking, in the context, of the
in women or unclean foods) ;
difierent modes of treating the
in other cases indeed, as Plu- dead among various nations
X 2
;

J HE STOICS.

tbe Stoics, and, in particular, by Chrysippus, by their


'^^'
treatment of the relations of the sexes to each other
nor can it be denied that some of their utterances on
this subject sound exceedingly insidious. The Cynic
assertion, that anything which is in itself allowed
may be mentioned plainly and without a periphrasis,
is also attributed to the Stoics.' By his proposals for
the dress of women, Zeno offended against propriety
and modesty,^ and both he and Chrysippus advocated
community of wives for their state of wise men.' It
is, moreover, asserted that the Stoics raised no ob-
jection to the prevalent profligacy and the trade in
unchastity,* nor to the still worse vice of unnatural
crime.* Even marriage among the nearest relatives
was found quite according to nature by the leaders
of the School ; * and the atrocious shamelessness of
Diogenes found supporters in Chrysippus,^ perhaps,
too, in Zeno.*
<c) Cyni- It would, however, be doing the Stoics a great

tJieoretical
to take these statements for more than
ii^jiistice

conse- mere theoretical conclusions drawn from the prin-


quenoe of
SStoic prin-
{Cio. Tuso. i. 46, 108), in- *Pyxrh. iii. 201.
Seaif.
ciples.
tending to prove that no uni- = Pyrrh. iii. 200 ; 245
Secet. ;

formity of practice prevailed. Math. xi. 190 ; Clement. Homil.


Oic. Off. 1. 35, '128, with
'
V. 18.
the limitation Cynioi aut gi
:
Sext.Pyrrh. i. 160; iii.
qui fuerunt Stoici p^ne Cy- 205 ; 246 Math. xi. 191 Pint.
; ;

nioi. Sto. Rep. 22 Cle^nent. Horn.


;

2 mog. vii. 33 : koI itrSTiTi. Se V. 18.


'
Plut. \. c. 21, 1.
Kal yvvaiKas KoX fiTjdey fiopiov airo- Sextus, however (Pyrrh.
'

KfKpiipBai. The latter act is iii.206), attributes to him, as


only conditional, and allowed the representative of the School,
in certain cases, such as for what properly only belongs to
purposes of gymnastics. Chrysippus t6 t alaxpovpy^'iv
:

' Mog. 33 131. . , . i Zifvuv otiK i,Tro3oKtiid((i.


;
THE INDIVIBUAL. 309

ciples to which they were pledged. The moral cha- Chap.


'

racter of Zeno, Cleanthes, and Chrysippus ia quite "

above suspicion. It seems, therefore, strange that


they should have felt themselves compelled to admit
in theory what strikes the natural feeling with horror.
It cannot, however, be unconditionally accepted that
the statements laid to their charge imply as they used
them all that historians find in them. Far from it ; of
some of their statements it may not only be said that
they do not justify conduct recognised to be immoral,
but that they are directed against actions customarily
allowed, the argument being, that between such
actions and actions admittedly immoral there is no
real difference. This remark applies, in particular, to
Zeno's language on unnatural vice.' It was not,
therefore, in opposition to the older Stoics, or in de-
nial of their maxim, that love is permitted to a wise
man,^ that the younger Stoics condemned most ex-
plicitly any and every form of unchastity, and, in
particular, the worst form of all, unnatural vice^'

His words (_Sext. Math. xi.


' very Cynic-like, but the mean-
190; Pyrrh. iii. 245 Plut. Qu. ; ing is not what Sextus supposes.
Con. iii. 6, 1, 6) are as follows : Zeno's object is. not to justify
Siaffnpi(tiv Se furiSev liaWov ^ijSe unnatural vice, but to show
flirirov jroiSittA t) /lii TroiSiiti fvuSi that those who allow any form
6ii\ftt fl &p(Tva oil yhp &Wa irai- of unchastity cannot forbid this
SiKois ? ft-h TtaiS'toTs ouSe flr(\eiaiy form, and that the wish and
ij &pjie<nii, iXKk Tcl amk irpe'irei re the attempt are morally on a
(fa! jTfie'iroi'Tti eCTi and: Sio/tefi^-
; par with the deed.
epdS^ecov; oiiK ^yaiye' ^ See the following note.
pucas rbv
airhv 5ia- ' Musonius, in Stoi. Serm. 6,
vdTfpov oiv i-KeBi/iiiffas!

fjiripia-ai ; leal pd\a. iAAa iwedi- 61 (conf. Cio. Fin. iii. 20, 68) :

fLTiaas Trapcurx^'f <">' ai'Tii' fi Ne amores quidem sanctos


i(pop-!l$ris ice\evaai; fi^M'. aW alienos a sapiente esse volunt.
ineKevfras ; ical ftd\o. fir' oix According to Diog. vii. 129,
vnnp4TT)<r4 <roi ; oii yip. The Stob. U. 238, love is only direc-
form of expression is certainly ted'to beauty of soul. By Diog.,
310 THE STOICS.

Chap. In the same way, the language permitting marriage


XII.
between those nearest of kin, when examined, is

very much milder than it seems.' And Zeno's pro-


position for a community of wives may be fairly laid
to the charge of Plato, and excused by all the chari-
table excuses f which Plato is allowed the benefit.^
Still, taking the most unprejudiced view of the
Stoic propositions, enough remains to raise an ex-
treme dislike to them, imless they could, without
difficulty, be deduced from the fundamental prin-

ciples of their system. A moral theory which makes


such a sharp distinction between what is without and
what is within, which r^ards the latter alone as
essential, the former as altogether indififerent, which
Stoi., Alex. Aphr. Top. 75, and ' Oonf. Orig. c. Gels. iv.
.Cic.Tuso. iv. 34, 72, it is de- 45 The
: Stoics made good
and
fined to be ^7ri;8o\5) ^A.ovoAo.s evil depend alone on the in-
Sia Kiiwos ifjLipaiv6fivop and, ; tention, and declared external
according to Pint. C. Not. 28, actions, independent of inten-
f/iipaffts xdWovs is an incentive tions, to be indifferent: ehov
to love but these statements
; odv fv T& irepX aZiatp6puv T6Tr(^
are guarded by adding that the 8ti T(f liiif \6yi)i (the action
bad and irrational are ugly, taken by itself) Bvyarpiat iniyvv-
and the wise are beautiful. It ffSai aSi6.^op6v iffTiv^ ci KaX ^^
was probably in imitation of XP^ v Tois KaB(TTci(raLS iroAtreiots
Plat. Sym. 203, E, that the rh ToiovTovtroi^'tv. Kalinrodeffsws
Stoics nevertheless stated robs X'^P'-v ' . Trapi\-fi<paiTi rhf ffot^hv
epour64vras aiaxpcov -navetTdat Ka- /xerit T^y Ovyarphs fi&vrns KaroXe-
KwvyGvo^ivuv. Love is excited XeijUjUevoi'TracTis rovTuv avdpdnruv
by a sensation of tv^vla jrpbs yfi/Qvs Sie<p6aofi4voUf KaX ^TjTOVfnv
aperiiv, its object being to de- CI KaBTjK6vT0}S & Tvarrip iTvve\ci-
velope this capacity into real (feral rp Bvyarpl birep rov ti^
virtue. Until this end has been cLTroKetrBat rh . . , irav tui/ ay-
attained, the loved one is still BpdyirQiv y4vos.
foolish, and therefore ugly. ^ How strictly he respected
When it has been attained, the chastity and modesty in women
striving, in which Eros con- is proved by the fragment, pre-
sists, has reached its object, and served by Clem. Pasdag. iii. 253,
the love of the teacher to his c, respecting the dress and
pupil goes over into friendship conduct of maidens.
between equals.
SOCIAL RELATIONS: THEIR ORIGIN. 311

attaches no value to aDything except virtuous in- Ohap.


'

tention, and places the highest value in being inde-


dependent of everything such a moral theory must
of necessity prove wanting, whenever the business of
morality consists in using the senses as instruments
for expressing the mind, and in raising natural im-
pulses to the sphere of free will. If its prominent
feature is to allow less to the senses than naturally
belongs to them, there is a danger that, in particular
cases, in which intentions are not so obvious, the
moral importance of actions will often be ignored,
and those actions treated as indifferent.
The same observation will have to be made with B. Social

regard to other positions which the Stoics laid down


in reference to social relations. Not that it was
their intention to detach man from his natural re-
lation to other men. On the contrary, they held (i) Origin,

that the further man carries the work of moral im-


^J^"**
^
provement in himself, the stronger he will feel drawn () Uriffin
to society. By the introduction of the idea of society, ^lai^
opposite tendencies arise in their ethics
one towards
individual independence, the other in the direction
of a well-ordered social life. The former tendency
is the earlier one, and continues throughout to pre-
dominate ; still, the latter was not surreptitiously in-
troduced nay, more, it was the logical result of the
Stoic principles, and to the eye of an Epicurean
must have seemed a distinctive feature of Stoicism.

In attributing absolute value only to rational thought


and will, Stoicism had declared man to be indepec-
dent of everything external, and, consequently, of
;

i'-i
THE STOICS.

Chap, his fellow-men. But since this value only attaches


XII
^ .

to rational thought and intention, the freedom of


the individual at once involves the recognition of
the community, and brings with it the requirement
that everyone must subordinate his own ends to the
ends and needs of the community. Eational conduct
and thought can only then exist when the conduct
pf the individual is in harmony with general law
and same for all rational beings. All
this is the
rational beingsmust therefore aim at the same end,
and recognise themselves subject to the same law.
All must feel themselves portions of one connected
whole. Man must not live for himself, but for society.
^_^ The connection between the individual and society
f was clearly set forth by the Stoics. The desire for
1 society, i.bey-held", is immediately involved in Teason.
\ By the aid of reason, man feels himself a part of a
\ whole, and, consequently, bound to subordinate his
own interests to the interests of the whole.' Like
having always an attraction for like, this remark
holds true of everything endowed with reason, since
the rational soul is in all cases identical. From the
consciousness of this unity, the desire for society at
once arises in individuals endowed with reason.^ They
'
Cic. Fin. iii. 19, 64: Mun- Sen. Ep. 95, 52: The whole
dum autem censent regi nnmine world is a unit membra sumus
;

Deorum eumque esse quasi , corporis magni. Natuia nos cog-


communem urbem et oivitatem natosedidit. Hence mutual love,
hominum et Deorum et unum- ; love of society, justice, and fair-
quemque nostrum ejus mundi ness. Ep.48, 2: Alterivivasopor-
esse partem, ex quo illud con- Hseo socie-
tet, si vis tibi vivere.
sequi, ut communem utilitatem tas . nos homines hominibus
. .

nostrse anteponamus. miscet et judicat aliquod esse


2 M. Awrel, ix. 9 xii. 30. ; commune jus generis hxunami.
;

SOCIAL RELATIONS: THEIR ORIGIN. 313

are all in the service of reason ; there is, therefore, Chap.


XII.
for all, but one right course and one law,' and they
all contribute to the general welfare in obeying this
law. The wise man, as a Stoic expresses it, is never
a private man.^
At other times, social relations were explained by
the theory of final causes.^ Whilst everything else

exists only for the sake of what is endowed with rea-


son, individual beings endowed with reason exist
for the sake of each other. Their social connection is

therefore a direct natural command.'' Towards animals


w& Jiever stand in a j)osition to exercise justice, nor
yet towards ourselves.' Justice can only be exercised
towards other men and towards Grod.^ On the
' Cw. Legg. Quibus
12, 33 : i. 22
7, ; Sen. Clement, i. 3, 2
enim ratio a natura data est, Benef. vii. 1, 7 ; M. Av/rel. v.
iisdem etiam recta ratio data 16, 30 ; vii.55 ; viii.59 ; ix. 1 ;

est ergo et lex, qii est recta


: xi. 18 ; Diog. vii. 129 ; Sext.
ratio in jubendo et vetando Math. ix. 131.
(see p. 241, lex, jus * Hence, according to Cic.
2) : si
quoque. At omnibus ratio, jfus Fin. 21, 69, not only axj>e\'/i-
iii.

igitur datum est omnibus. Ibid. fiara and PKafifiara (moral good
7, 23 Est igitur
: prima . . . and evil), but ebxpri(rriiiJ,aTa and
homini cum Deo rationis so- (other advan-
Svffxp'ncriiii.aTa
cietas. Inter quos autem ratio, tages and disadvantages) are
intereosdem etiam recta ratio common to all men.
communis est. Quse cum sit ' According to Pint. Sto.
lex, lege quoque consociati Rep. 16, Chrysippus denied that
homines cum Diis putandi a man could wrong himself. If,
smnus. Inter quos porro est in other passages, he seems to
communio legis, inter eos oom- assert the contrary, this appa-
munio juris est. Quibus autem rent inconsistency is probably
hsec sunt inter eos communio, due to the double meaning of
et civitatis ejusdem habendi aSiKEiK, which sometimes means
sunt. Ps.-P?M. T._^ Horn. 119: 'to wrong,' at others, simply
The Stoics teach i/o fiiv elvat 'to harm.' Strictly speaking,
Thy K6(TfiOV, avfjiTToMTeiiiffOai Se iy a relation involving justice can
auTij) 0eobs Kci avSpilmovs, Sixaia- only exist towards another.
uvyi)s fierdxovras tpiiff^i. See on p. 315, 2.
CHc.
2 Oic. Tus. iv. 23, 51. Towards the Gods, man

Oia. Fin. iii. 20, 67 ; Off. stands, according to the above


SU THE STOICS.

Chap, combination of individuals and their mutual sup-


XII
^
port rests all their power over nature. A single man
by himself would be tha most_helpless ot cTeap
"" " ~
~Turei7'"'~~
The consciousness of this connection between ail
rational beings finds ample expression in Marcus
Aurelius, the last of the Stoics. The possession of
reason is, with him, at once love of society (vi. 14;
72). Rational beings can only be treated on a
social footing {koivojvikojs) (vi. 23), and can only feel

happy themselves when working for the community


(viii. 7); for all rational beings are related to one
another (iii. 4), all form one social unit {-TroXiToicov

^-^(fva-TTjfia), of which each individual is an integral


\ part (awfnrX'qpmriKos) (ix. 23) ; one body, of which
j
every indivdual is an organic member (fiiXos) (ii. 1 ;

vii. 13). Hence the social instinct is a primary


instinct in man (vii. 55), escery:_manifestatioa-of
wWeh-"raratrrbtrtesr'^her---det]y--r,Jjjiiix^
5QQd_a_ihfi- whole (ix. 23). Our fellow-men
ought to be loved from the heart. They ought to
be benefited, not for the sake of outward decency,
but because the benefactor is penetrated with the
joy of benevolence, and thereby benefits himself."
Whatever hinders union with others has a tendency

passages, in a relation in- only consider yourself a part,


volving justice. There is, there- and not a member, of human
fore {Sext. ix. 131), a justice society, oiira knh xapSlas (j>i\eU
towards the Gods, of which roij avBpdmovs oUttoi at xara-

piety (see p. 261, 1 ) is only a Xny^mh&s ev<^paivei rh eiifpyfreiv

part. ?Ti ws vp4noy ai/rh jj/iKhv iroteTs

* Sen, Benef . iv, 18. oItttu is avrbv eS ttolui/.


* 3f. Av/rel. vii. 13 : If you
SOCIAL MELATIONS: JUSTICE. 315

to separate the members from the body, from which Chap.


'

all derive their life (viii. 34) and he who estranges


;

himself from one of his fellow-men voluntarily severs


himself from the stock of mankind (xi. 8).\We shall
pr^ently see ^at the language used by thdNphilo-
sophiB. emperor iKguite in harmony with the S^oic
principle
In relation to our fellow-men, two fundamental (2)Jmtice
points are insisted on by the Stoics the duty of merey.
justice and the duty of mercy. Cicero, without
doubt following Pansetius,' describes these two vir-
tues as the bonds which keep human society toge-
ther,^ and, consequently, gives to each an elaborate
treatment.' Inv^xpanding the^e^ duties, the Stoics
were led by the fundajnental principles of their sys-
tem tQ most -distracting eo^seqiiences. On the one
hand, they required from their wise men that strict
justice which knows no pity and can make no allow-
ances ;* and hence their ethical system had about it

an air of austerity, and an appearance of severity


and cruelty. On the other hand, their principle of
the natural connection of all mankind imposed on
them the practice of the most extended and unre-
served charity, of beneficence, gentleness, meekness,
of an unlimited benevolence, and a readiness to for-
*
See p. 298, 3. tutis splendor est maximus, ex
' Off. i. 7, tribus
20 : De qua viri boni nominantur, et
autem leliquis [virtutibus, the huic conjuncta beneficentia,
thiee others besides under- quam eandem vel benignila-
standing] latissime patet ea tem vel liberalitatem appellari
ratio, qua societas hominum licet.
inter ipsos et vitse quasi com- * Oflf. i. 7-13 ; il. 14-17.
munitascontinetur,oujuspartes * See p. 254, 2, 3.
duse sunt justitia, in qua vir-
:
THE STOICS.

Chap, give in all cases in -whicli forgiveness is possible.


XII.
This last aspect of the Stoic teaching appears prin-
cipally in the later Stoics in Seneca, Epictetus,
Marcus AureHus, and Musonius ;' and, it is quite pos-
sible that they may hav^ given more jjrominence to
it than their predecessors. But the fact is there,
that this aspect Is due, not only to the peculiar cha-
racter of these individuals, but is based on the spirit

and tone of the whole system.^


The qijestion then na,turally ariseSj'tp.w these two
opposites may be reconciled how stern jiistice may
be harmonised with forgiveness and mercy. Seneca,
who investigated the question fully, replies : Not
severity, but only cruelty, is opposed to mercy ; for
no one virtue is opposed to another : a wise man will
always help another in distress, but without sharing
his emotion, without feeling misery or compassion ;

he will not indulge, but he will spare, advise, and


improve ; he will not remit punishments in cases in
which he knows them to be deserved, but, from a
sense of justice, he will take human weakness into
c'bnsideration in allotting punishments, and make
every-^ossible allowance for circumstances.* Every
difficully.is not, indeed,removed by these statements ;

still, those which remain apply more to the Stoic


demand for apathy than to the reconciliation of

' We shall subsequently i. 3, 3) Nullam ex omnibus


:

have occasion to prove this in virtutibus magis homini con-


detail. It may here suffice to venire, cum sit nulla huma-
ref er to the treatises of Seneca, nior.
De Beneficiis, De dementia, ' Conf. Pansetius, in Cie.
and De Ira. On the value of Off. i. 26, 88.
mercy, he remarks (De Clem. ' De Clem. ii. 5-8.
SOCIAL RELATIONS: FRIENDSHIP. 317

the two virtues which regulate our relations to our Chap.


"

fellow-men.'
The society for which all rational beings are in- wFriend-
tended will naturally be found to exist principally
among those who have become alive to their rational 1

nature and destiny in other words, among the wise.


All who are wise and virtuous are friends, because
they agree in their views of life, and because they
all love one another's virtue.^ Thus every ac-
tion of a wise man contributes to the well-being
of every other wise
man or, as the Stoics pointedly
express it, if .a wise man only makes a rational move-
ment with his finger, he does a service to all wise
men throughout the world.* On the other hand,
only a wise man knows how to love properly ; true
friendship only exists between wise men.* Only the
wise man possesses the art of making friends,' since

^
' Among the points cha- nobis diligetur. See Off. i. 17,
raoteristic of Stoicism, the cea- 55. Conf. p. 309, 3.
sure deserves notice which Sen. ' Plut. C. Not. 22, 2. The
(Ep. 7, 3 95, 33 Tranq. An.
; ; same thought ia expressed in
2, 13) passes on gladiatorial the statement (ibid. 33, 2) that
shows and the Roman thirst the wise man is as useful to
for war. (Bp. 95, 30.) The atti- deity (the universe) as deity is
tude of the Stoics to slavery and to him.
the demand for love of enemies Sen. Benef vii.
12, 2 ; Bp.
.

will be considered hereafter. 81, 11 123, 15


; 9, 5; Stob. ii.
;

2 Stob. ii. 184 T<jy t iii6.


: 118 see p. 271, 3. Diog. 124.
;

miav iTrKTriiixriv ihai kowwv According to Diog. 32, Zeno,


tryaSav, Sih /cal Tois ffTrouSafouj like Socrates, was blamed for
irkcras 6fjLoyottt aW-fiKois Sia rh asserting that only the good
trvfiL<pa:ve'iv iv rots Kari, rhv jSiox. (o-jrouSaiot) among themselves
Oic. N. D. i. 44, 121 : Censent are feUow-citizens, friends, and
autem [Stoici] sapientes sa- relations; whilst all the bad
pientibus etiam ignotis esse are enemies and strangers,
' He
amicos, nihil est enim virtute is, as Sen. Ep. 9, 5,

amabilius. Quam qui adeptus puts it, faciendarum amicitia-


erit, ubicumque erit gentium, a rum artifex.
.

318 THE STOICS.

Chap, love is only won by love.' If, however, true friend-


XII.
ship is a union between the good and the wise, its

value is thereby at once established ; and hence it is

distinctly enumerated among goods by the Stoics.^

On this point, difficulties reappear. How can this


need of society be reconciled with the wise man's
freedom from wants ? If the wise man is self-suffi-

cient,how can another help him ? How can he stand


in need of such help ? The answers given by Seneca
are not satisfactory. To the first question, he replies,
that none but a wise man can give the right induce-
ment to a wise man to call into exercise his powers.'
He meets the second by saying, that a wise man suf-
fices himself for happiness, but not for life.^ Every-
where the wise man finds inducements to virtuous
action ; if friendship is not a condition of happi-
ness, it is not a good at all. Nor are his further
observations more satisfactory. The wise man, he
says,'' does not wish to be without friends, but still

' Si vis amari, ama, says Kark -rhv fiiov, xp"!'^^'""' w"
Hecato, in Sen. Bp. 9, 6. tois <pt\ois iis eourois (^JDiog.
2 We have already enooun- 12i). Similar definitions are
tered friendship in the Stoic given by Stoi. of varieties of
list of goods. See p. 230, 3. friendship : 7(pi/n<iT7)s, o-uWjfleio,

186, says, more accurately,


;SicJ. k.t.K. On
the absolute com-
that friendship, for the sake of munity of goods among friends,
the commonwealth, is not a see Sen. Bp. 47, 2 3, 2 ; Benef ;

good, Sia rb ixffiir kittiiiTTiiK6TWv vii. 4, 1 ; 12, 1.


i.yaSiiv flvai on the other hand,
; Ep. 109, 3 and 11.
'

friendship, in the sense of Ep. 9, 13 Se coutentus


' :

friendly relations to others, est sapiens ad beate vivendum,


belongs to external goods in ; non ad vivendum. Ad hoc
the sense of a friendly dis- enim multis illi rebus opus
position merely, it belongs to est, ad illud tantum auimo
intellectual goods. On the sano et ereoto et despiciente
value of friendship, Sen. 99, 3. fortunam.
Friendship is defined as /toivaiWa ' Ep. 9, 5.

Piov (^Stob. 130) Kowuipla -ruv


;
SOCIAL RELATIONS: FRIENDSHIP. 319

he can be without friends. But the question is not Chap.


^^^'
whether he com be, but whether he can be without
loss of happiness. If the question so put is answered
in the negative, it follows that the wise man is not
altogether self-sufficing ; if in the affirmative and
a wise man, as Seneca affirms, will bear the loss of
a friend with calmness, because he comforts himself
with the thought that he can have another at any
moment then friendship is not worth much. More-
over, if a wise man can help another by communi-
cating to him information and method, since no wise
man is omniscient,' we ask, Is not a wise man, if not
in possession of all knowledge, at least in possession
of all knowledge contributing to virtue and happi-
ness ? If it be added, that what one learns from
another he learns by his own powers, and is conse-
quently himself helping himself, does not this addi-
tion still overlook the fact that the teacher's activity
is the condition of the learner's ? True and beautiful
as is the language of Seneca : Friendship has its value
in itself alone ; every wise man must wish to find
those like himself ; the good have a natural love for
the good ; the wise man needs a friend, not to have
a nurse in sickness and an assistant in trouble, but
to have someone whom he can tend and assist, and
for whom he can live and die^ nevertheless, this
language does not meet the critical objection, that
one who requires the help of another, be it only to
have an object for his moral activity, cannot be wholly
dependent on himself. If friendship, according to a

Sen. Ep. 109, 5. ^ Ep. 109, 13 ; 9, 8 10, 12 ; 18.


;
::

THE STOICS.

Chap. previously-quoted distinction,' belongs to external


goods, it makes man, in a certain sense, dependent
on externals. If its essence is placed in an inward
disposition of friendliness, such a disposition depends
on the existence of those for whom it can be felt.

Besides, it involves the necessity of being recipro-


cated, and of finding expression in outward conduct,
to such an extent that it is quite subversive of the
absolute independence of the individual.
Nor yet is the friendship of the wise the only form

of society which appeared to the Stoics necessary


and essential. If man is intended ^ to associate with
his fellow-men in a society regulated by justice and
law, how can he withdraw from the most common
institution the state ? If virtue does not consist
in idle contemplation, but in action, how dare he
lose the opportunity of promoting good and repres-
^
sing evil by taking part in political life ? ^ If laws

'See p. 318, 2. wp^tp Trepl ^iofv Kal yctp KaKiav


^Stoh. ii. 208 rhv yip v6nov
: itpe^etv KaX 4ir^ aperijv itpopp.ijffstt'.
eXvoLi, KaBdirep iXirofnv, airov^aTov, Sen. De Ot. 3, 2 : Epicurus ait
dfioiws Sf Kat T^y ir6\tv. iKavws non accedet ad rempublicam
Sfr Koi KKeiivdTis vep\ rh irvov5a7ov sapiens, nisi si quid intervenerit.
eTyai t^v n6\iy \6yov TtptitT7i(re Zenon ait : accedet ad rempub-
rovTov (wrongly
irdKis /Aei' i licam, nisi si quid impedierit.
struck out by Meineke) fffriv Cie. Fin. iii. 20, 68 Since man :

oiKTiT'fipiov KaTOffKevofffjia els tt exists for the sake of other


Karatl>G{iyovTas ?ffTt SfKtjv 5oui/at men, consentaueum
est huic
Kal XajSeTc, ovk offreTov Br] irdKis natures, ut sapiens velit gerere
iffrlv; Floril. 44, 12. See pp. et administrare rempublicam
223 241, 3.
; atque, ut e natura yivat, uxorem
Plut. Sto. Kep. 2, 3 Chry-
" : adjungere et velle ex ealiberos
sippus recommends political procreare. Stob. ii. 184 t6 re :

life, placing fitos (rxo^airrtKhs on 5lKat6i/ tpatTi tpiffci tlvai Kal fi^
the same footing with $los Betrei. kv6fifvov 5^ toiJtois {map^
r]SoviK65. JKog. vii. 121 ttoKi- : X^iv Kal rb voMreiefrBai rhy troiphy
TiviffQai (\>atriv rhv aotphy tiv fiij tl . .Kol rh vofiodeTeiv T Kal trai-
.

KutKij}^ Sts <p7i(ri XpifftTTiros iv Beieiv iivOptitnovs, k.t,\.


SOCIAL RELATIONS: THE FAMILY. 321

further the well-being and security of the ' citizensi Chap.


XIL
if they advance virtue and happiness, how can the\
wise man fail to regard them as beautiful and praise-
'

worthy ? ' For the same reason, matrimony will


command his respect. He will neither deny himself
a union so natural and intimate, nor will he deprive
the state of relays of men nor society of- the sight of
well-ordered family life.^ Hence, in their writings and
precepts, the Stoics paid great attention to the state
and to domestic life.^ In marriage they required
chastity, and moderation. Love was to be a matter
of reason, not of emotion not a yielding to personal /

attractions, nor a seeking sensual gratification.' As"^

' Cic. Legg. ii. 5, 11. founding a family ; love for


' Diog. Ibid.koI ya/iiia'eiv,
: wife and children is the deepest
is 6 Ziivav t^Tjaly ^v iroAire^a, KOL love.
iroiSoiroi^ireo-flai. IMd. 120 The :
= Pint. Sto. Eep. 2. 1 i-rd :

Stoics consider love towards Tolvvv TvoWh. jucv, &3S 4v \6yois,


children, parents, and kindred avT^ Z-fivcai/i, 7ro\\ct Se KA.(i*'0ei,
to be according to nature. irAeitTTa 5e Xpvffitnrtft yeypafJLfiei/a
Chrysippus (in Eie^'on. Ad. Tvy)(6.vei TTfpl iroAiTcfas Koi rov
Jovin. i. 191) The wise man : ^/);^EO'0aiKaX &pxety Kal StKa^fLv
will marry, lest he offend Zeus Kai ptfropeieiv. Conf. the titles
ra/i^\ios and TeveflXios. Anti- in Diog. vii. 4 ; 166 175 178. ; ;

pater (whether the well-known Diogenes's list contains no poli-


pupil of Diogenes of Seleucia, tical writings of Chrysippus.
or the younger Stoic Antipater It is, however, known to be
of Tyre mentioned by Cio. Off. incomplete ; for Diog. vii. 34 ;

ii. not stated) in Stob.


24, 86, is 131, quotes Chrysippus's trea-
Ploril. 67, 25 Wife and child
: tise irepl iro\iT6ias, a treatise
are necessary to give com- also quoted' by Flut. Sto. Eep.
pleteness to civil and domestic 21 (1, 3, 5). According to Cio.
life a citizen owes children to
;
Legg. iii. 6, 14, Diogenes and
his country, and family love is Pansetius were the only Stoics
the purest. Musonius (^Ibid. before his time who had en-
67, 20, Conf. 75, 15) A philo- : tered into particulars respecting
sopher ought to be a pattern in legislation, though others might
married life, as in every other have written much on politics.
natural relation, and discharge " Conf. the fragment of &.
his duties as a citizen by De Matrimonio, in Hieron. Ad.
322 THE STOICS.

Chap. to their views on the constitution of a state, we


XII.
know that they prefer a miKed
' coiistitution, com-
pounded of the three simple forms, without objecting
to other forms of government. The wise man, ac-
cording to Chrysippus, will not despise the calling
of a prince, if his interest so require, and, if he can-
not govern himself, will reside at the court and in
. camp of princes, particularly of good princes.''
the
\,_ The ideal of the Stoics, however, was not realised
in any one of the existing forms of government-hut.
inJhaJL4iolity-jaf.JJifi.j8dse-*hit5h-'EeinT-4eaM4b^ -mj-
dfluhtedly when a .C^c,^.-.^afe wi*A-^as-fully-eet
forttr "by 6'hrjgiyjpu.M^^ a state without marriage, or
family, or temples, or courts, or public schools, or
coins ' a state excluding no other states, because all

differences of nationality have been merged in a


common brotherhood of all men.' Such an ideal may
show that, for the Stoic philosophers, there could be
no hearty sympathy with the state or the family, their
al state being, in truth, no longer a state. Indeed,

Jovin. i. 191, Fr. 81 Haase, ' JDiog. vii. 131.


which, like the Essenes, re- Pint. Sto. Rep. 20, 3-5 ;
quires absolute abstinence from r ; 30, 3 ; C. Not. 7, 6.
pregnant women. A few un- ' Diog. vii. 4.
important fragments are also * Diog. vii. 131.
preserved by Chrysippus's trea- * Diog. 33 Kouds
: re yhp
tise on the education of child- IwiuKas SoyfiaTl^fiv ifuiias iv rrj
ren. See Qwmtil. Inst. i. 11, Tlo\iTfiif Ko! Karh, Tois SiaKocrlovs
17 1, 4 and 16 3, 14 10, 32
; ; ; ;
trrixovs, M^fl' lepi niire SiKaariipia.
Saguet, De Chrys. (Annal. /i^Tf yvfivdiria iy rats Tri\itriv
Lovan. iv. p. 335). He is re- oiKoSoneurBai . . . v6iu(Tna S" oSt'
proached by Posidonius ( Galen. oA\o7fls 'iviKfv oU<r6ai Stti/ nara-
Hipp, et Plat. v. 1, p. 465) for (TKevd^fiv oir' inroSiinias. Ibid
neglecting the first germs of 131.
education, particularly those PImt. Alex. Virt. i. 6, p. 329.
previous to birth.
SOCIAL RELATIONS: PUBLIC LIFE. 328

the whole tone of Stoicism, and still more, the cir- Chap.
YTT
cumstances of the times to which it owed its rise

and growth, were against such a sympathy. If Plato


could find no scoj)^ for a philosopher in the political
institutions of his tinje, how could a Stoic, seeking
as he did for happiness more exclusively in seclusion
"ii^om the world, contrasting, too, the wise man more
sharply with the multitude of fools, and living for
the mositvpart under political circumstances far less
favourable than Plato had enjoyed? To him the
private life of a philosopher must have seemed be-
yond compare more attractive than a public career.
An intelligent man, taking advice from Chrysippus,'
avoids business ; he withdraws to peaceful retire-
ment ; and, though he may consider it his duty not
to-^tand aloof from public life, still he can only ac-
tively take a part in it in states which present an
appreciable progress towards perfection.^ But where
could such states be found Did not Chrysippus state ?

it as his conviction that a statesman must either

displease the Gods or displease the people?^ -Aiid|,

did not later Stoics accordingly advise philosophers


not to intermeddle at all in civil matters ? ^ Labour

' Plut. Sto. Kep. 20, 1 : oXnm iiupaivoiaais Tivh. irpo/coTrJjc itphs
yap $yuye rhv <fip6vtfwv Kal atrpd- rtis Te\eias irnAiTcias.
yfjiOvaehmKal6\iyo'irpdyfiovaKal ' Stob. Floril. 45, 29: In
tA aiirov irpdrreLVf dfiolws rris re answer to the question, why he
aliTowpayia! Kol S\iy(nrpayiw(rivris withdrew from public life, he
affTcluv tvruv t^ yap htni ipai-
. . . replied ; Sitirt el fiiv iryj/Tjpa TroAt-

vtTatbKarhr^v7]ffvxlav ^ios h.iiiv- TeiJejat [ fferot], to*s 60is aTro-


i<iv6v TE Kol aa(^a\h ^X""! "''A. peVei, ei Sc xflTToi, tois TroKWais.
' Stob. Bel. ii. 186 ttoKirei- : Sen. Ep. 29, 11 Quis enim
* :

effQat thv troiphv Kal fiAXttTTa iv placere potest populo, cui placet
rals TOiairaif iroAiTei'ais tois virtus ? mails artibus popularis
T 2
:

324 THE STOICS.

Chap. for the commonwealth is only^then a duty when there


XII.
is ne obstacle to such labour ;"T)utj as a matter of
"fact, there is always some obstacle, an^ifi particular,
the condition of all existing states.^ A philosopher
who teaches and improves his fellow-men benefits
the state quite as mijch as a warrior, an adminis-
trator, or a civil functionary.^

(*) Prac- Following out this idea,' Epictetus dissuadgsirom


tical oAier-
sion to matrimony and the begetting of children. Allowing
political that the family relation may be admitted in a commu-
life.
nity of wise men, he is of opinion that it is other-
wise under existing circumstances ; for how can a
true philosophetjBiigage in connections and actions
which withdraw him from the service of God ? The
last expression alrejidy implies that unfavourable
times were not the only cause deterring this Stoic
from caring for family of ,the state, but that the
occupation in itself seemed to him a subordinate and
limited one ; this is even stat^ in plain terms by

favor quseritur. Similem te autem interest, quomodo sa-


illi facias oportet
: conci-
. . . piens ad otium veniat, utrum
liari nisi turpi ratione amor quia respublica illi deest, an
turpium non potest. quia ipse reipublicse, si omnibus
' Sen. De Ot. defutura respublica est. (So
3, 3, p. 320, 8
It needs a special cause for de- we ought to punctuate.) Sem-
voting oneself to private life. per autem deerit fastidiose
Causa autem ilia late patet si : quEerentibus. Interrogo ad
respuhlica corruptior est quam quam rempublicam sapiens sit
ut adjuvari possit, si occupata accessurus. Ad Atheniensium,
est mails ... si parum habebit etc. 1 Si percensere singulas
[sc. sapiens] auctoritatis aut voluero, nullam inveniam, quse
virium nee ilium admissura erat sapientem aut quam sapiens
respublica, si valetudo ilium pati possit. Similarly Atheno-
impediet. Ibid. 8, 1 Negant
. ; dorus, in Sen. Tranq. An. 3, 2.
ad quamlibet
nostri sapientem 2 Athenodor. 1. c. 3, 3.

rempublioam accessurum quid :


''
Diss. iii. 22, 67.
;

SOCIAL MELATIONS: PUBLIC LIFE. 325

Seneca and Epictetus : He who feels himself a citizefl Chap.


XII.
of the wprld finds in an individual state a sphere far
too limited he prefers devoting himself to the uni-
verse ; ' man is no douht intended to be active, but
the highest' activity is intellectual research.'* On the
subject of civil society, opinions were likely to vary,
according to th\ peculiarities and circumstances of
individuals. The p&ilosopher on the throne was more
likely than the freedvjnan Epictetus to feel himself

a citizen of Eome as \^>ell as a citizen of the world,^


and to lower the demaOi^s made on a philosophic
statesman.* At the same time, the line taken by the
Stoic philosophy cannot be ignored. A philosophy
' Sen. De Otio, 4, 1 Duas : does busy himself, not consult-
respTiblicas animo compleota- ing the citizens of one city
mur, alteram maguam et vere alone for the purpose of obtain-
publicam, qua Di atque homines ing information about the re-
quanon ad liunc
continentux, in venues of a state, and such like,
angulmn respicimus aut ad il- but the citizens of the world,
ium, sed terminos civitatis nos- that vrith them he may con-
trse cum sole metimux alteram
: verse of happiness and unhap-
cui nos adscripsit condicio nas- piness, of freedom and slavery.
cendi. Does it not seem like TrihLKaiTT}V voKireiav iroKlT^vffa-
reading Augustin's De Civitate fievov afBptiTrov, a{i fjLOi irvyddvri, ei
Dei 1 Some serve the great, 7ro\tTei5ffTai'; wSov fiou Koi, el

others the small state; some 6/)|ef ttolAlv ipa ffof f^tope, Ttoiav
serve both. Majori reipublioae apx^iv fi.el(ova ^s fipx^i
et in otio deservire possumus, Sen. De Otio, 5, 1 ; 7 ;. 6, i.

immo vero nescio an in otio ' Marcus Awelim, vi. 44 :

melius. Bp. 68, 2: Cum sa- n6Kis KoX irarpls &s [.lev ^Avravitp
pientirempublicamipsodignam fiot 7] 'Ifcifj.7j, i)S Se ajAdptti-iTCi} d
dedimus, id est mundum, non k6itiios. to. rats TrdKetriv oZv to6-
est extra rempublicam etiamsi rais di(pe\i^a, fi6va iffrl iioi hjaBd.
recesserit : immo fortasse re- ii. 5 : TTtitrfis Spas tpp^vrtQe an-
licto uno angulo in majora ^apS)s 5)S 'PwfjLoios Kal &ppTiv.
atque ampliora transit, &C: Ibid. ix. 29 ipuria-oy 4^v Bi-
* :

iii. 22> 83
:E^et. Diss. Do you
: b&Tat Kal /jtii irepi^Aejrou et Tty
iaskwhether a wise man will elfffcTOi fjLTiSk r^v XiKdrwvos 7ro\U

busy himself with the state 1 reiav IXirife, aAAa apKou ti rh


What state could be greater flpaxuraTOv itpiaun.
than the one about, which he-
326 -.
THE STOICS.

Chap, which attaches moral value to the cultivation of in-


" xir
tentions only, considering at the same time all exter-
nal circumstances as indifferent, can hardly produce
a taste or a skill for overcoming those outward in-
terests and circumstances with which a politician is
I

chiefly concerned. A system which regards the mass


of men which denies to them every healthy
as fools,
endeavour and all true knowledge^ can hardly bring
itself unreseryedly to work for a state, the coiirse
and institutioils of which depend upoii,the majority
of its members, and are planned with a view to their
needs, prejudices, and customs. Undoubtedly, there
were able statesmen among the Stoics of the Koman
period ; but Eome, and not Stoicism, was the Cause
of their statesmanship. Taken alone. Stoicism cotild
form excellent men, but hardly excellent statesmen.
And, looking to facts, not one of the old masters of
the School ever had or desired any public office.

Hence, when their opponents urged that retirement


was a violation of their principles,' Seneca could with
meet the charge by replying, that the true
justice
meaning of their principles ought to be gathered
from their actual conduct.^
(c) cm The positive substitute wherewith the Stoics
zensMp
thought to replace the ordinary relations of civil
of the
world. society was by a citizenship of the world. No pre-
ceding system had been able to overcome the diffi-

culty of nationalities. Even Plato and Aristotle


shared the prejudice of the Greeks against foreigners.

,
' Plut. Sto. Rep. 2, 1.
* De Otio, 6, 5 ; Tranq. An. 1, 10.
' .

SOCIAL MELATIONS: COSMOPOLITANISM. \ 327

The Cynics alone appear as the precursors of the! Chap.


xn.
Stoa, attaching slight value to the citizenship of any-
particular state, in comparison with citizenship of
\
the world.' Still, with the Cynics, this idea had not '\

attained to the historical importance which after- \

wards belonged to it ; nor was it used so much with \


a positive meaning, to express the essential oneness
of all mankind, as, in a negative sense, to imply the ,

philosopher's independence of country and home.


From the Stoic philosophy it first received a definite
meaning, and became generally called into service.
The causes of this change may be sought, not only in
the historical surroundings amongst which Stoicism
grew up, but also in the person of its founder. Far
easier was it for philosophy to overcome national dis-
likes, after the genial Macedonian conqueror had
united the vigorous nationalities comprised within
his monarchy, not only under a central government, '

but also in a common culture.^ Hence the Stoic ;

citizenship of the world may be appealed to, to prove {

the assertion, that philosophic Schools only reflect j

the existing facts of history. On the other hand, |

taking into account the bias given to a philosopher's I

teaching by his personal circumstances, Zeno, being 1

only half a Greek, would be more ready to underesti- f

mate the distinction of Greek and barbarian than /

any one of his predecessors.


However mucEtliese two causes and, in parti-
' See Socrates and Sooratic indicated by Plutarch's group-
Schools, p. 324. ing the Stoics and Alexander
^ This connection is already together.
:,

28 THE STOICS.

Chap,
XTT
cular, the first must have contrihuted to brine
L_ about the Stoic ideal of a citizenship of the world,
nevertheless the connection of this idea with the
whole of their system is most obvious. If human
society, as we have seen, has for its basis the identity
of reason in individuals, what ground have we for

limiting this society to a single nation, or feeling our-


selves more nearly related to some men than to others?
All men, apart from what they have made themselves
by their own exertions, are equally near, since all
'

equally participate in reason. All are members of


one body ; for one and the same nature has fashioned,
them all from the same elements for the same des-
tiny.' .Or, as-^piotetafr-expressfisitin religiQius_lan-
guage^ all- ifteB are -brethren, since' all have in the
ame -iifigre God^fer-iheir. father. Man, therefore,
who and whatever else he may be, is the object of
our solicitude, simply as being a man.^ No hoaLlUty
and ill lre atmnt-hcmld-'qTiengh--trur-beBevolenee.'* No-

Sen. Ep. 95, 52 ; M. Aurel. 3 : Nemo non, cui alia desint,


See 2 313.
p. 312, ; hominis Bomine apud me gra-
2 Diss. i. 13, 3. Seep. 381, 2. tiosns est. De Ira, i. 6.
' Sen. Bp. 96, 52, continues * Sen. De Otio, i. 4 see p. :

after the quotation in p. 312, 2 256, 4 Stoici nostri dicimt . .


: .

Ex illius. [naturse] constitutione non desinemus communi bono


miserius est nocere quam Isedi. operamdare, adjuvare singulos.
Ex illius imperio paratas sint opem f erre etiam inimicis. We
juvantis manus. Die versus et shall subsequently meet with
in peotore et in ore sit homo : similar explanations from Mu-
sum, nihil humani a me alienum sonius, Epictetus, and Marcus
puto. V, Be. 24, 3 Hominibus : Aurelius. In particular, Sene-
prodesse natura me jubet, et oa's treatise, De Ira, deserves
servi liberine sint hi, ingenui to be mentioned here, and es-
an libertini, justae libertatis an pecially i. 5, 2 Quid : homine
inter amioos datae quid ref ert ? aliornm amantius ? quid ira in-
Ubicumque homo est, ibi bene- festius t Homo in adjutorium
ficii locus est. De Clem. i. 1 mutuum genitus est, ira in exi-
. ;
:

SOCIAL RELATIONS: COSMOPOLITANISM. 329

oae.ia.aQ low.feut that he has claims on the. love .and Chap.


XII.
jtrstice'^f his fellow-men.' Even the -slave is a man
"^serving our ^jsteeffl^ and able to claim from us
hjffTtghtsA
^
Nor yet did the Stoics go so far in their recogni-
tion of the universal rights of mankind as to disap-
prove of slavery. Attaching in general little value
to external circumstances,' they cared the less to run
tium. Hie congregari vult, ilia nes admittit, omnes invitat, in-
discedere. Hie prodesse, ilia genuas, libertines, servos, reges,
noeere. Hie etiam ignotis sue- exules. Non eligit domum neo
currere, ilia etiam carissimos censum, nude homine contenta
perdere. IHd. ii. 32, 1 It is : est. Slavery, he continues,
not so praiseworthy to return does not affect the whole man.
injury for injury, as benefit for Only the body belongs to his
benefit. Illic vinoi turpe est, lord his heart belongs to him-
;

hie vincere. lohumanum ver- self, c. 20. The duties of the


bum est ultio et talio.
. . . slave have limits, and over
Magni animi est injuxias des- against them stand certain de-
pioere. Couf. Cic. Off. i. 25, finite rights (c. 21. Conf. De
88 Violent anger towards ene-
: Clement, i. 18, 2). He enu-
mies must be blamed nihil : merates many instances of self-
enim laudabilius, nihil magno sacrifice and magnanimity in
et prseelaro viro dignius placa- slaves, and concludes by say-
bilitate atque dementia. Even ing Eadem omnibus principia
:

when necessary,
severity is eademque origo, nemo altero
punishment ought not to be ad- nobilior, nisi cui rectius ingen-
ministered in auger, since such ium unus omnium parens
. . .

an emotion cannot be allowed mundns est neminem des- . . .

at all. See p. 254, 1. pexeris sive libertini ante


. . .

> Sen. Ep. 95, 52. See p. vos habentur sive servi sive ex-
328, 3. do. Off. i. 1.3, 41. terarum homines: erigite'au-
''
Cic. Even towards
1. e. : dacter animos, et quicquid in
slaves, justice must be observed. medio sordidi est transilite
Here, too, belongs the question, expectat vos in summo magna
discussed at full by Sen. Benef nobilitas, &c. So Ep. 31, 11
iii. 18-28, Whether a slave can V. Be. 24, 3. See p. 328, 3.
do a kindness to his master? Conf. Ep. 44 Rank and birth :

He who denies that he can, are of no consequence, and p.


says Beneea (18, 2), is ignarus 270, 3.
juris humani. Kefert enim cu- ' Only the wise man is
jus animi sit, qui prsestat, non really free ; all who are not
cujus status nulli prseclusa
: wise are fools.
virtus est, omnibus patet, om-
;.'

330 THE STOICS.

Chap. counter to the social institutions and arrangements


XII.
of their age. Still they could not wholly suppress a
confession that slavery, is unjust,"*- nor cease to aim
at mitigating the evil both in theoryxand practice.^
If all men are, as rational bejngs, equ&l, all men
together form one community. iJeason is tihe com-
mon law for all, and. those who owe allegiance to
one law are members of one state.* If the Stoics,
therefore, compared the wbrid, in its more extended
sense,^to a soci&ty, because df^ the connection of- its
^parts,^ "Wjey must,yith far more' reason, have allowed
th^t the world, in the narrower s^nse of the term,
including all rational beings, forms one community,'

' Diog. 122, at least, calls and Plut. Com. Not. 34, 6, who
5emroTe(a, the possession and makes the Stoics assert tIw k6(t- :

government of slaves, some- fjiov elvaL 7r6\tv koX voKlras roijs


thing bad. aiTTepas. M. Awrel. x. 15 ^T\<tov :

* According to Sen. Benef . . , &>S ip Tr6\et T^ K6fffitfi. iv.


iii. 22, 1, Oic. 1. c, Chrysippus 3 : & K6ff}ios 5)ffave\ ir^Kis.
had defined a slave, perpetuus ' M. Awel. iv. 4, and ii. 16.
meroenarius and hence in-
; do. Fin. iii.
20, 67 Chrysippus :

ferred that as such he ought to asserts that men exist for the
be treated operam exigendam,
: sake of each other quoniamque ;

justa prsebenda. Sen. Bp. 47, ea natura esset hominis ut ei


expresses a very humane view cum genere humane quasi civile
of treating slaves, contrasting jus intercederet, qui id conser-
a man with a slave servi sunt : varet, eum justum,qui migraret,
immo homines. He regards injustxmi fore. Therefore, in
a slave as a friend of lower the sequel in urbe mundove
:

rank, and, since all men stand communi. See 331, 2 and p.
under the same higher power, 312, 2. Sen. De Ira, ii. 31, 7
speaks of himself as conservus. Nefas est nocere patriae ergo :

' M. Awrel. 4 ei rb voepbv iv. : civi quoque ergo et ho- . . .

iifuv Koiyht/, Kot & \6yos Koff* tv mini, nam hie in majore tibi
KoyiKot ia^ev KotvSs e( Tovro, Kal
urbe civis est. Musonius (in
S TTfiOffTCMTlKhs T&V TTOiTIT^aV fj fxi] Stoi. Floril. 40, 9) i/o/i(f [<S :

\6yos Koiv6s toOto, Kal & vofios


ei 4iritK^s'\ elvai voKittjs ttjs tov
Koiv6s. fi TOvro, Tro\7ral iff^ev Aihs v6\sus f) ffvvetTTijKev i^ h.V'
eiTOUTO, tro\iTe^fiaT6s nvos fiere- BpdTTwv re Koi Beav. JEpiet. Diss,
XOfiev 1 T0V70, d K6afios ^iTav(\ iii. 5, 26 ; Ar. Didym. in Eus.
Pr. Bv. XV. 16, 4.
<
See pp. 312, 1, 3 ; 325, 3,
: '

SOCIAL RELATIONS: COSMOPOLITANISM. 331

to which individual communities are related, as the chap.


^^^-
houses of a city are to the city collectively^ -s,
Wise
men, at least, if not others, will estpem this great
community, to which all men belong, far above any
particular community in which the accident of birth
has placed them.^ They," at least, will direct their
efforts towards making all men feel themselves to^ be
citizelis^f one community ; and, instead of framing
exclusive laws and constitutions, will try to live as
one family, under the common governance of reason.'
The platform of social propriety receives hereby a
universal width. Man, by withdrawing from the
outer world into the recesses of his own intellectual
and moral state, becomes enabled to recognise every-
where the same nature as his own, and to feel him-
self one with the universe, by sharing with it the
same nature and the same destiny.
But, as yet, the moral problem is not exhausted.
'
M. Aurel. iii. 11 i.vBpomov : isneither an Athenian nor a
iroXiTTjc ^VTO jr6\ias rfis avmrd- Corinthian, but simply Kiaiuos
TT\s ^s al Xoiirtii Tr6\its &(nrep and uths Qeoii. Muson. 1. c.
oiKiai EiViV. Banishment is no evil, since
* Sen. De Ot. 4 Ep. 68, 2..
; Koty^ Trarpls Avflptiirwz' a-Kdvrtav b
See p. 325, 1. Vit. B. 20, 3 and Kdaitos iarlv. It is, says Cie.
5 : Unum me donavit omnibus Parad. 2, no eril for those qui
[natura rerum] et uni mihi omnem orbem terrarum unam
omnis . . .patriam meam esse uirbem esse ducunt.
mundum sciam , et praesides " Flut. Alex. M. Virt. i.
6, p.
Deos. Tranq. An. 4, 4 Ideo : 329 xol iihv v iro\h Savim^qnivn
;

magno animo nos non unius iro\iTeia rod rrjv ^twikuv aipuriv
urbis mtienibus clusimus, sed in Ka-rafiaKKoiiivov Zi\vmvos eis %v
totius orbis cojnmercium emisi- toBto awTelva xepdKaiov, tva /li)

mus patriamque nobis mundum /cori ir(iA.ij firiSh (card Siifiovs

prof essi sumus, ut lioeret la- oiKuiuei', iSIois emaaroi Sutipiirnevoi


tiorem virtuti campum dare. SiKodois, &AAa vdvras avBp^ovs
Bpict. Diss. iii. 22, 83. lUd. Tiy^iieBa Sjj/iiJtoj koI iroAiTas, tls
i. 9 If the doctrine that man
:
Se fitos ^ itai Kiaiios, &irirep i.ye\ris
is related to God is true, man (Tuvyd/iov p6it^ Koivif Tp6(/>o/*'j/5is.

12 THE STOICS.

Chap. Reason, the same as man's, rules pure and complete


'

in the universe ; and if it is the business of man to


give play'tq reason in his own conduct, and to re-
cognise it inH^at of othei;^, it is also his duty to
subordinate himself to collective reason, and to the
course of the world, over which it\presides. In con-
clusion, therefore, the relation of man to the course
of the world must be considered.
Firmly as the principles of the Stoic ethics in-
sist upon moral conduct, those ethics, judged, by
their whole tone, cannot rest short of requiring an
absolute resignation to the course of the universe.
This requirement is based quite as much upon the
historical surroundings of their system as upon its
intellectual principles. How, in an age in which poli-
tical freedom was stifled by the oppression of Macedo-
nian,and subsequently of Roman domiuion, even that
of the Roman conquerors being suppressed under the
despotism of imperalism, in which Might, like a
living fate, crushed every attempt at independent
action how, in such an age, could those aiming at
higher objects than mere personal gratification have
any alternative but to resign themselves placidly to
the course of circumstances which individuals and
nations were alike powerless to control ? In making
a dogma of fatalism. Stoicism was only following the
current of the age. Atthe same time,, asjyill be
seen from what has been said, it was -only following
the iiecessary .consequences -of its - wa -.principles.
-All that is individual in the world -beiag only the
reBiilt-e-f---general-eoMieefein '^-arufie.aad,_ffect
:

MAN AND THE WORLD'S COVRSE. 333

bein g o nly -a carrying out of a^miyersal Jaw^r^cbaL- Chap.


:remaiii^-pDS8ifele^m.theiace.Qf, JJiia absolute peeefr- ^_
sityrbnt -to-yieW-uiicoiiditioiiaily ? Hott tsarn-yield-
ing baialled_a,_ sacrifice , when the lawJ;a,jjMclL-we
yii4fl~UL^nnf>ii"ng Ipsjs t|ba.n the PYprpssinn f)f jPflfnt) ?
"ifeiree designation to the world's course was a point
chiefly insisted upon in the Stoic doctrine of morality.
Tfag-rei-ses of lmBthe8-,^in'Whtar1ir'gi(rtm.itymth-
out-.ieaetxe.ia the leading, of ,d,estiiiy a-re-a-theBae
repeatedly worked out by the writers of this. SchooL
The virtuous man, they say, will honour- God by re-

signing his will to the divine will ; the divine will


he will think better than his own will ; he will re-
member that under all circumstances we must follow
destiny, but that it is the wise man's prerogative to
follow of his own accord; that there is only one way
to happinessand independence that of willing no-
thing except what is in the nature of thingsji^iil
-fftrnt will 'nnUnn I'trnlf inrlnpnnrlpTifjy pf pyi- will .
Z.-^

' In Epictet. Man. o. 53 i bere se fato. Vit. Be. 15, 5


more fully, Ihid. Diss. iv. 1, Deum sequere. Quas autem .

131; 4, 34; and translated by dementia est, potius trahi quam


ySe. Ep. 107, 11. Seep. 182, 1. sequi? . Quicquld ex uni-
.

The verses are : versi constitutione patiendum


S70U 5e /t' S ZeS Ka\ ah/ t\ ritirpa- est, maguo excipiatur animo.
fi,ivi\ Ad hoc saoramentum adaoti
8iriw TTofl" viuv ei/xi . SioTeroy- sumus, ferre mortalia. In . .

jnej/os

regno nati sumus Deo parere :

is fi|(0|uai y io/ti/os' V Se /i^) libertas est. Ep. 97, 2: Non


gcAoj pareo Deo, sed adsentior. Ex
Ktixbs yei'6ii.ems ovSfy ^rriiv ?i//o- animo ilium, non quia neoesse
^ai. est, sequor, etc. Bp. 74, 20 76, ;

Sen. ProT. 5, 4 and 8 Boni


2 : 23 107, 9. Ejpiatet. Diss. ii.
;

viri laborant, impendunt, im- 16, 42 i6Kii.t)aov ava^Kii^as wphs


:

pendontur, et volentes qui-dem, rhj/ Sebf elireiv, '6ti xpa M"' ^o'r
non trahuntur a fortuna, etc. irhv eis i hv e4\ris- dfioypwfiovu
. . . Quid est boni viri ? Prae- (rot, a6s el{u. oiSip TrapaiTov/icu
THE STOICS.

Chap. Similar expressions are not wanting^ amongst


XII.
other philosophers ; nevertheless, by the Stoie philo-
sophy, the demand is pressed with partic;ular force,
and is Blosely connected with its whole view of the
world. In resignation to destiny, the Stoic picture
of the wise man is completed. Therewith is includea~^
that peace and happiness of mind, that gentleness
and benevolence, that discharge of all duties, _and
that_ harmony of life, which together make up the
_Stoic definition of virtue.' Beginning by recognising
the existence of a general law, morality ends by un-
conditionally submitting itself to the ordinances of
that law.
The one case in which this resignation would give

Twv trot Sq'Koi/VTtMtv' hirov 0e\is, magnitude super omnia effierens


&ye. 7 The virtuous man
i. 12, : sese. Hinc intellecta est ilia
submits his will to that of God, beata vita, secundo defluens
as a good citizen obeys the law. cursu, arbitrii sui tota. Quo-
iv. 7, 20 HpeiTTov yAp iiyovntu t
: modo ergo hoc ipsum nobis
S Bfhs 4e4\t, fl [a] iyii. iv. 1, adparuit 1 Dioam Nunquam :

131, in reference to the verses vir ille perfectus adeptusque


of Cleanthes oBttj ri dShs iv': virtutem fortunse maledixit.
i\fv9plav &yfi, aSxr) ftdpi) iiroA- Numquam accidentia tristis ex-
\ayi) SovKelus. Man. 8 flf'Ae : cepit. Civem esse se universi et
yivftrBat ri ytv6^eva us yiverat militem credens labores velut
Kal eiipoiitreis. Similarly Fragm. imperatos subiit. Quicquid
134, in^oJ.Floril. 108, 60. M. inciderat, non tanquam malum
Awrel. X. 28 : }ii6vtp r^ KoytK^ aspernatus est, et in se casu
^tpip Sedorai rh eicovtriws eveadtu delatum, sed quasi delegatnm
To7s ytvofjievois' rit Si 'Itretrdai sibi. . . Necessario itaque
.

)pt\hv trafrtv avayKoioif. Ibid. magnus adparuit, qui nunquam


viii. 45 ; x. 14. mails ingemuit, nunquam de
Sen. Ep. 120, 11, investi-
' fato suo questus est fecit :

gates the question, How does multis intelleotum sui et non


mankind arrive at the concep- aliter quam in tenebris ]umen
tion of virtue ? and replies. By effulsit, advertitque in se om-
the sight of virtuous men. Os- nium animos, cum asset plaoi-
tendit illam nobis ordo ejus et dus et lenis, humanis divinis-
decor et oonstantia et omnium que rebus pariter asquus, &c.
inter se aotionum concordia et
;
;

MAN AND THE WORLD'S COURSE: SUICIDE. 335

place to active resistance to destiny is when man is Chap.


^^^'
placed in circumstances calling for unworthy action
or endurance.' Strictly speaking, the first case can (2) Sui-
never arise, since, from the Stoic platform, no state
of life can be imagined which might not serve as an
occasion for virtuous conduct. It does, however,
seem possible that even the wise man may be placed by
fortune in positions which are for him unendurable
and in this case he is allowed to withdraw from them u'

by suicide.^ The importance of this point in the


Stoic ethics will become manifest from the language
of Seneca, who asserts that the wise
man's indepen-
dence of externals depends, among other things, on
his being able to leave life at pleasure.' To Seneca,
the deed of the younger Cato appears not onlypraise-

' Conf. BoMmhauer, Vet. tse, breves, faciles. Agamus


Stoicorum Doct.
Phil, prsecipue Deo gratias, quod nemo in vita
de Mor. Volunt. Ut. 1842, p. : teneri potest. Calcare ipsas ne-
220. cessitates licet. Id. Prov. o. 5, 6,
^ Siog. vii. 130 : tbK6yas re makes the deity say Contem- :

tpacrtv i^d^eiv kavrbv rov $iov rhy nite mortem quffi vos aut finit
(_i^ayayit is the standing
tT0(l>hv aut transfert. Ante omnia. . .

expression with the Stoics for cavi, ne quis vos teneret iuvitos.
suicide. Full references for Patet exitus. . Nihil feci . .

this and other expressions are facilius, quam


mori. Prono
given by Baiimhauer, p. 243.) animam loco posni. Trahitur,
Kat inrip irorpfSos Kai imip ^l7\Mv Attendite modo et videbitis,
K&i/ iv <7K\iipoT4pif yeiniTai a\yri- quam brevis ad libertatem et
Sdi'i fl T^piiriaiv J) v6aoii aviirois. quam expedita ducat via, &c.
,ao*. Eel. ii. 226. Conf. the Conf . Ep. 70, 14 He who denies :

comoedian Sopater, in Athen. the right of committing suicide


iv. 160, who makes a master non videt se libertatis viam
threaten to sell his slave to eludere. Nil melius seterna lex
Zeno iv' ^{070175. fecit, quam quod unum in-
' Ep. 12, 10 ': Malum est in troitum nobis ad vitam dedit,
necessitate vivere. Sed in ne- exitus multos. Ep. 65, 22
cessitate vivere neoessitas nulla 117, 21 ; 120, 14 M. Awel. v.;

est. Quidni nulla sit 1 Patent 29 ;


viii. 47 x. 8 and 32 iii. 1
;
;

undique ad libertatem viae mul- JUjnctet. Diss. i. 24, 20 iii. 24, 96. ;
33 THE STOICS.

Chap, worthy, but the crowning-point of success over des-


. 1__ tiny, the highest triumph of the human will.' By
the chief teachers of the Stoic School this doctrine
was carried into practice. Zeno, in old age, hung
himself, because he had broken his finger ; Cleanthes,
for a still less cause, continued his abstinence till he
died of starvation, in order to traverse the whole
way to death and, in later times, the example of
;

Zeno and Cleanthes was followed by Antipater.^


In these cases suicide appears not only as a way
of escape, possible under circumstances, but "abso-
lutely as the highest expression of moral freedom.
Whilst all are far from being advised to adopt this
course,^ everyone is required to embrace the oppor-
tunity of dying with glory, when no higher duties
bind him to life.* Everyone is urged, in case of
need, to receive death at his own hand, as a pledge
of his independence. Nor are cases of need decided
by what makes a man unhappy moral vice
really
or folly. Vice and
folly must be met by other means.

Death is no deliverance from them, since it makes


the bad no better. The one satisfactory reason which
the Stoics recognised for taking leave of life is, when

' De ProT. 2, 9 ; Ep. 71, will of Gtod. ii. 15, 4. Conf.


16. M. Am-el. v. 10.
In the passages already
^ * Muson. in Stob. Floril. 7,
quoted, pp. 40, 2 ; 41, 1 50, ; 24, says : HpiraCe rh koASj diro-
2. 9irli(rKeui Sre l^fcm, fiii litrit fuK-
' See Epictetus's discussion phy -rh /iiv iiroBirllffKfiv o-oi irapf,
of suicide committed simply rh Si Kahus firjiceVi i^y ; and,
in contempt of life (Diss. i. 9, again He who by living is of
:

10), against which he brings to use to many, ought not to


bear the rule (in Plato, Phsd. choose to die, unless by death
61, E.) to resign oneself to the he can be of use to more.
MAN AND THE WORLD'S COURSE. 337

circumstances over which we have no control make Chap.


continuance in no longer desirable.'
life

Such circumstances may be found in the greatest


variety of things. Cato committed suicide because
of the downfall of the republic ; Zeno, because of a
slight injury received. According to Seneca, it is a
sufficient reason for committing suicide to anticipate
merely a considerable disturbance in our actions and
peace of mind.^ Weakness of age, incurable disease,
a weakening of the powers of the mind, a great de-
gree of want, the tyranny of a despot from which
there is no escape, justify us and even, under cir-
cumstances, oblige us to have recourse to this
remedy.? Seneca, indeed, maintains that a philoso-
pher should never commit suicide in order to escape
sufifering, but only to withdraw from restrictions in
following out the aim of his life ; but he is never-
theless of opinion that anyone an may rightly choose
easier mode more painful one
of death instead of a
in prospect, thus avoiding a freak of destiny and
the cruelty of man.'' Besides pain and sickness, Dio-
genes also mentions a case in which suicide becomes
a duty, for the sake of others.* According to another

'
M. Aurel. v. 29 : Even 4lajoii'i)v tif anovZaltf ffvyx'^fov(n
here you may though
live as koX ol ipi\6<ro(poi (i.e. the Stoics),
you were free from the body ; e? ns tov Trpaatreiv avrhir ovrus
4av Si juj) imp4ira(ri, rin koX Ttipiiaiifv [1. oKtiu (TTEp^creiEc],'
TOV ^rjv i^iBf oirras ixevTOi, us us /jLTfiKerl aTroKeKu^dai aUT^/iijSe
liriSev Kaxhv irdcrxuic. 4\iriSa ttjs Trpi^eus.
2 Ep. 70. See p. 338, 3. Ep. 58, 33 ; 98, 16 ; 17, 9 ;

Clem. Strom, iv. 485, A, like- De Ira, iii. 15, 3./


wise calls the restriction of ra- ' See Bp. 58, 36, and 70, 11.
tional action sufficiently de- See p. 335, 2.
cisive reason :airlKa ell\oyov
;

38 THE STOICS.

CnA.v. authority,* five eases were enumerated by the Stoics


. ! in which it was allowed to put oneself to death ; if,

by so doing, a real service could be rendered to others,


as in the case of sacrificing oneself for one's country
to avoid being compelled to do an unlawful action
otherwise, on the ground of poverty, chronic illness,
or incipient weakness of mind.
In nearly all these cases, the things referred to
belong to the which were reckoned
class of things

as indifferent by the Stoics and hence arises the ;

apparent paradox, with which their opponents im-


mediately twitted them, that not absolute and moral
evils, but only outward circumstances, are admitted

as justifying suicide.'' The paradox, however, loses


its point when it is remembered that, to the Stoics,
life and death are quite as much indiiTerent as all
other external things.* To them, nothing really good
' Olympiod. in Phesdr. 3 068' S\as, (pcuriv, oUrai Suy Xpiir-
(Schol. in Arist. 7, b, 25). The itttos oStc noviiv in r^ fil(f -roh
favourite comparison of life to afaSots, oftr' i^ayuy^v roh kokoIs
a banquet is here so carried vapafierpe7if, a\A& to7s fiearois
out, that the five occasions for /corct <t>i<riv. SA Kal rots evSai-
suicide are compared with five fiorova-iyiperat irort KaSrjKov
occasions for leaving a banquet, i^dyetv iavrobs, kbI fiheiv aSflir
' Pint. C. Not. 11, 1 itapi. : 4v r$ fpv tois KoKaSat^oi'oSa'ii'.
rijv %vvoi&v iirriv, Mpuirov $ Ibid. 14, 3. Sen. Ep. 70, 5 :

iravra rayaBb, irdpea-ri Kal /ai- Simul atque occurrunt molesta


Skv 4vSt Trpbt evSainoviav Kal rh et trauquillitatem turbantia,
fuucapiov, roir(f KaBiiKeiv 4^iyeiv emittet se. Nee hoc tantum in
eouT(iv ^Ti Si fiaWoi/, ^ lariSev necessitate ultima faoit, sed
6.yaS6p 4<rrt jutjS' ^arai tA Se Seivk cum primum illi coepit suspecta
TracTtt Kal tA Svffxfpfi (cal KoKct esse fortnna, diligenter circum-
n&pvrri koX Trdpeirrai BiA Te'\ous, spicit, numquid illo die desiuen-
roirifi nil KaBiiKeiv avoKtyeirBai dum sit. Nihil existimat sua
rhu $loy tiv jxi) ri vj) Afa rwv dSia- ref erre, faoiat finem an accipiat.
auTij) Trpoayivi)rat. Ibid, tardius fiat an oitius. Non
22, 7 33, 3
; Sto. Eep.
; 14, 3 ;
tanquam de magno detrimento
Alea;.Ap?ir.DeAR.15S,h;l5S,h. timet: nemo multum ex stilli-
' Plut. Sto, Kep. 18, 5: aKK' cidiopotestperdere.Conf. 77, 6.
:

MAN AND THM WORLD'S COURSE. 339

appears to be involved in the question of suicide. Chap.


XII.
but only a choice between two things morally indif-
ferent one of which, life, is only preferable to death,
the other, whilst the essential conditions for a life

according to nature are satisfied.' The philosopher,


therefore, says Seneca,^ chooses his mode of death just
as he chooses a ship for a journey or a house to live
in. He would leave a banquet
leaves life as he
when it is time. He lays aside his body when it no
longer suits him, as he would lay aside worn-out
clothes and withdraws from Hfe as he would with-
;

draw from a house no longer weather-proof.*


A very different question, however, it is, whether
life can be treated in this way as something indif-
ferent, and whether it is consistent with an uncon-
ditional resignation to the course of the world, to
evade by personal interposition, what destiny with
its unalterable laws has decreed for us. Stoicism
may, indeed, allow this course of action. But in so

'
dc. Fin. iii. 18, 60: Sed Eeque miser est [stultus], nee
cum ab his [the media] omnia diuturnitas magis ei vitam f ugi-
proficiscantur officia, non sine endam facit, non sine causa di-
causa dicitur, ad ea referri om- citur, iis qui pluribus naturali-
nes nostras cogitationes in his ; bus f rui possint esse in vita
et excessum e vita et in vita manendum. Stob. 226 : The
mansionem. Inquoenimplura good may have reasons for
sunt, quEe secundum naturam leaving life, the bad for con-
sunt, hujus officium est in vita tinuing in life, even though
manere in quo autem aut
:
they never should become vrise
sunt plura contraria aut fore o6t yhp t^v aperV icoTe'xEij h
videntui, hujus officium est e t^ (yv, otre t^v Kaxiav iicpiWeiv

vita excedere. E quo apparet, toIj Se koS^ikovsi koI to!s impa rb

et sapientis esse aliquando offi- KoBrJKov fierpetaeai tV


tc (aiiiv
cium excedere e vita, cum bea- Kal -riv B&varov.

tus sit, et stulti manere in vita,


==
Ep. 70, 11.
cum sit miser. .. Etquoniam. 'Teles, in Stob. Floril. 5,
excedens e vita et manens 67, p. 127 Mein.
z 2
340 THE STOICS.

Chap, doing does it not betray how little it had succeeded


'

in the attempt to comhine, without contradiction,


two ma.in-tendencies so different as that of individual
independence and that of submission to the uni-
verse ?
STOICISM AND RELIGION. 341

CHAPTER XIII.

THE RELATION OP THE STOIC PHILOSOPHY TO RELIGION.

It would be impossible to arive a full account of the Chap.


XT TT
philosophy of the Stoics without treating of their
theology ; for no early system is so closely connected ^- G^'neral
with religion as that of the Stoics. Founded as their of Stoio-

whole view of the world is upon the idea of oile *"!^ "^^

Divine Being, begetting from Himself and contain-


ing in Himself all finite creatures, upholding them
by His might, ruling them according to an unalter-
able law, and thus manifesting Himself everywhere,
their philosophy bears a decidedly religious tone.
Indeed, there is hardly a single prominent feature
in the Stoic system which is not, more or less, con-
nected with theology. A very considerable portion of
that system, moreover, consists of strictly theolo-
gical questions ; such as arguments for the existence
of deity, and for the rule of Providence ; inves-
tigations into the nature of Grod, His government,
and presence in the world; into the relation of

human activity to the divine ordinances ; and all

the various questions connected with the terms free-


dom and necessity. The natural science of the Stoics
begins by evolving things from God ; it ends with
342 THE STOICS.

Chap, resolving them again into God. Grod is thus the begin-
;_ ning and end of the world's development. In like man-
ner, their moral philosophy begins with the notion
,

of divine law, which, in the form of eternal reason,


controls the actions of men ; and ends by requiring
submission to the will of God, and resignation to the
course of the universe. A religious sanction is thus
given to all moral duties. All virtuous actions are
a fulfilment of the divine will and the divine law.
That citizenship of the world, in particular, which
constitutes the highest point in the Stoic morality,
is connected with the notion of a common relation-
ship of aU men to God. Again, that inward repose
of the philosopher, those feelings of freedom and
independence, on which so much stress was laid, rest

principally on the conviction that man is related to


God. In a word, Stoicism is not only a system of
i philosophy, but also a system of religion. As such
it was regarded by its first adherents, witness the
fragments of Cleanthes ;
' and as such it afforded, in
later times, together with Platonism, to the best
and most cultivated men, wherever the influence of
Greek culture extended, a substitute for declining
natural religion, a satisfaction for religious cravings,
and a support for moral life.
' The well-known hymn to Kal rov \6yov rod t^s (piXoa-otptaSy
Zeus, in Stob. Eel. i. 30, and ikoi/Ss /ikv i^ayyeWtu' Svt>aii4vou
the verses quoted p. 333, 1. ri flfio xal ImBpiiTriva, fi.ii Ixovtos
Nor is the poetic form used by 5e ifiiAoS tUv Beluv fieyeSSiv \ej6ij
Cleanthes without importance. oMeias. -rci ii4rpa nal rd jucAt) Kal

He asserted, at least according Tobs ^v0fiois us fidXiffra irpo(riKvet-


toJ'AiMem. De Mus. Vol. Here. <r8ai irphs.r^v a\ii6fiav ttjs rZv
i. col. 28 a^ilvovd ye elj/at rit
: Qeiatv Beapias.
TTOiTjTtKit Kai fiooffiK^ TTapaSf f7juaTa
STOICISM AND UELIGION. 343

This philosophic religion is quite independent of Chap.


the traditional religion. The Stoic philosophy con-
tainsno feature of importance which we can pro- (1) Cm-
nounce with certainty to be taken from the popular stoicism
*"'**,
faith. Even the true worship
^ of Grod,' according
to popular
their view, consists only in the mental effort to know foAth.

Grod, and in a moral and pious life.' A really accept-


able prayer can have no reference to external goods ;

it can only have for its object a virtuous and devout


mind.' Still, there were reasons which led the Stoics
to seek a closer union with the popular faith. A
system attaching so great an importance to popular
opinion, particularly for proving the existence of Grod,'
could not, without extreme danger to itself, declare
the current opinions respecting the Grods to be erro-
neous. And again, the ethical platform of the Stoic
philosophy imposed on its adherents the duty of
upholding rather than overthrowing the popular
creed that creed forming a barrier against the

Compare the celebrated


' ^ M. Aurel. ix. 40 We ought :

diotnm of the Stoic in do. N. D. not to pray the Gods to give us


ii. 28, 71 Cultus autem Deorum
: something, or to protect us from
est optimus idemque oastissi- something, but only to pray :

mus plenissimtBque pietatis, ut SiS6vai avtovs rh fi-fire <po$i'!irBal


eos semper pura Integra iucor- n roiToiv liiire e-niBvuftv rtvos roi-
rupta et mente et voce venere- tuv. Diog. vii. 124 "We ought,
:

mnr and more particularly


;
in fact, only to pray for what
Mpict. Man. 31, 1 t^s irepl Tohs
: is good.

Sfovs ei(re$sias IffOi 3ti rb Kvpiti- ' See p. 144, 2. Seart. Math.
ra-rov 4KfTv6 iariv, op8as uTro\ii'liets ix. 28, says that some of the
irepl auTcov ex^iv Kfl (Tavrhv
. younger Stoics (perhaps Posi-
(Is roSro Karamaxivai, rb irel- donius, whose views on the
flca-flai avTo7s Kal flKciv ip ira(n primitive condition have been
Toij yivoiiivoi!, K.T.\. Id. Diss, already mentioned, p. 293, 1)
ii. 18, 19. Further particulars traced the belief in Gods back
on p. 345, 2. to the golden age.
::

344 THE STOICS.

Chap, violence of human passions.' The practical value of

L_ the popular faith may, then, be the cause of their


theological orthodoxy. Just as the Eomans, long
had been lost under the
after all faith in the Grods
Greek culture,^ still found it useful and
influence of
necessary to uphold the traditional faith, so the
Stoics may have feared that, were the worship of the
people's Gods to be suspended, that respect for God
and the divine law on which they depended for the
support of their own moral tenets, would at the
same time be exterminated.
(2) Free Meantime, they did not deny that much in the
'ofvT^lar POP^I^'^ belief would not harmonise with their prin-
lelwf. ciples and that both the customary forms of reli-
;

gious worship, and also the mythical representations


of the Gods, were altogether untenable. So little did
they conceal their strictures, that it is clear that con-
viction, and not fear (there being no longer occasion
for fear), was the cause of their leaning towards tradi-

tion. Zeno spoke with contempt of the erection of


sacred edifices for how can a thing be sacred which
;

is erected by builders and labourers ? ' Seneca de-


nies the good of prayer.* He considers it absurd to

'
In this spirit, Epict. Diss, tifex Cotta, in do. N. D. i. 22,
ii. 20, blames those who
32, 61 ; iii. 2.
throw doubts on the popular ' Plut. Sto. Kep. 6, 1 ; Diog.
Gods, not considering that by vii. 33. See p. 322, 5.
so doing they deprive many of Ep. 41, 1
* Non sunt ad
:

the preservatives from evil, the coelum elevandse manus nee ex-
very same argumentum ab utili orandus sedituus, ut nos ad
which is now frequently urged aures simulacri, quasi magis
against free criticism. exaudiri possimus, admittat
^ Characteristic are the prope est a te Dens, tecum est,
utterances of the sceptic pon- intus est. Nat. Qu. ii. 35, 1
::

STOICISM AND RELIGION. 345

entertain fear for the Gods, those ever-beneficent Chap.


XIII.
beings.' Grod he would have worshipped, not by sa-
criiices and ceremonies, but by purity of life ; not in
temples of stone, but in the shrine of the heart.^
Of images of the Grods, and the devotion paid to
them, he speaks with strong disapprobation ;* of the

What is the meaning of expia- quisquis imitatus est. Fr. 123


unchangeable ?
tions, if fate is (in Lactmit. Inst. vi. 25, 3)
They are only aegrse mentis so- Vultisne vos Deum cogitare
latia. See p. 343, 2. magnum et placidum non . . .

Benef. iv. 19, 1


' Deos : immolationibus et sanguine
nemo sanus timet. Furor est
enim metuere salutaria nee

multo colendum quae enim ex
trucidatione immerentium vo-
quisquam amat quos timet.
luptas est ? sed mente pura,
Not only do the Gods not wish bono honestoque proposito.
to do harm, but such is their Non templa illi congestis in al-
nature that they cannot do titudinem saxis extruenda sunt;
harm. De
Ira, ii. 27, 1 Benef. ; in suo cuique oonsecrandus est
vii. 1, Bp. 95, i9. It hardly
7 ; pectore. Conf . Benef. vii. 7, 3
needs remark, how greatly these The only worthy temple of God
statements are at variance with is the universe.
the Roman religion, in which ^ In Fr. 120 (in Lact. ii. 2,
fear holds such a prominent 14), Seneca shows how absurd
place. pray and kneel before
it is tx)
- Ep. 9S, 47 : Quomodo sint images, the makers of which
Di colendi, solet praecipi ao- : are thought little of in their
cendere aliquem lucemas sab- own profession. On this point
batis prohibeamus, quoniam he expressed his opinion with
nee lumine Di egent et ne ho- great severity in the treatise,
mines quidem delectantur f uli- De Superstitione, fragments of
gine. Vetemus salutationibus which Augugtin. Civ. D. vi. 10,
matutinis fungi et foribus ad- communicates (Fr. 31 Haase).
sidere templorum humana am- : The immortal Gods, he there
bitio istis offioiis capitur Deum : says, are transformed into life-
colit, qui novit. Vetemus lin- less elements. They are clothed
tea et strigiles ferre et specu- in the shape of men and beasts,
lum tenere Junoni : non quserit and other most extraordinary
ministros Deus. Quidni? Ipse appearances and are honoured
j

humano generi ministrat, ubi- as Gods, though, were they


que et omnibus prsesto est. . . . alive, they would be desig-
Primus est Deorum cnltus Deos nated monsters. The man-
credere. Deinde reddere illis ner, too, in which these Gods
majestatem suam, reddere boni- are honoured is most foolish
tatem, &c. Vis Deos propitiare ? and absurd such as by morti-
;

Bonus esto. Satis illos ooluit, fication and mutilation, stupid


'

346 THE STOICS.

;
Chap. unworthy fables of mythology, with bitter ridicule
XIII.
and he calls the popular Gods, without reserve, crea-
tions of superstition, whom the philosopher only in-
vokes because it is the custom so to do.^ Moreover, the
Stoic in Cicero, and the elder authorities quoted by
him, allow that the popular beliefs and the songs of
the poets are full of superstition and foolish legends.*
Chrysippus is expressly said to have declared the dis-
tinction of sex among the Grods, and other features
in which they resemble men, to be childish fancies ;^

and immoral plays, &c. The wise credes et coelo reoipies ? Fr. 39 :

man can only take part in such Omnem istam ignobilem Deo-
acts tanqtiam legibus jiossa, non rum turbam, quam longo sevo
tanquam Diis grata. This view longa superstitio congessit, sic
of worship had been previously adorabimus ut meminerimus
set forth by Heraclitus, who cultum ejus magis ad morem
otherwise was so much admired quam ad rem pertinere.
by the Stoics. N. D. ii. 24, 63 : Alia
' Fr. ligCinZaci. i. 16, 10): quoque ex ratione et quidem
Quid ergo est, quare apud poe- physica fluxit multitude Deo-
tas salacissimus Jupiter desierit rmn ; qui induti specie humana
liberos toUere 1 Utrum sexa- fabulas poetis suppeditaverunt
genarius faotus est, et illi lex hominum autem vitam supersti-
Papia fibulam imposuit 1 An tione omni ref erserunt. Atque
impetravit jus trium liberorum? hie locus a Zenone tractatus
An .timet, ne quis sibi fa-
. . post a Cleanthe et Chrysippo
ciat, quod
ipse Saturno ? Simi- pluribus verbis explicatus est
larly Fr. 39 (in Av^ustin. 1. c.) ;
. .physica ratio non inelegans
.

Brevit. Vit. 16, 6 Vit. Be. 26, ;'


inclusa est in impias fabulas.
6, the ineptige poetarum which, Still stronger language is used
as in the stories of Jupiter's by the Stoic, c. 28, 70, re-
many adulteries, give free rein specting the commentitii et
to sins. ficti Dei, the superstitioues
' Augwstin. 1. o. Fr. 33 Quid : p^ne aniles, the futilitas sum-
ergo tandem ? Veriora tibi vi- maque levitas of their anthro-
dentur T. Tatii aut Romuli aut pomorphic legends.
Tulli Hostiliisomnia? Cloa- ' Pho'drm (ThilodeTaus),col.

oinam Tatius dedicavit Deam, 2 of his fragment, according to


Picum Tiberinumque Romulus, Petersen's restoration. Conf.
Hostilius Pavorem atque Pal- Oic. N. D. ii. 17, 45 Moff. vii. ;

lorem, teterrimos hominum ad- 147 both of; whom assert that
fectus. Hsec numina potius
. . . the Stoics do not think of the
STOICISM AND RELIGION. 347

Zeno to have denied any real existence to the popu- Chap,


XIII.
lar deities, transferring their names to natural ob-
jects and Aristo ^ is charged with having denied
;
*

shape and sensation to the Deity.^


The Stoics were, nevertheless, not disposed to let
the current beliefs quite fall through. Far from it,

they thought to discover real germs of truth in these


beliefs, however inadequate they were in form ; and
they accordingly made it their business to give a re-
lative vindication to the existing creed. Holding
that the name of God belongs, in its full and ori-
ginal sense, only to the one primary Being, they did
not hesitate to apply it, in a limited and derivative
sense, to all those by means of which the objects
divine power is Nay, more,
especially manifested.
in consideration of man's relationship to God, they
found it not unreasonable to deduce from the pri-
mary Being Gods bearing a resemblance to men."*
Hence they distinguished, as Plato had done,

Gods as human in form ; and purpose of disproving it, with


Laetant. De Ir. D. c. 18 : Stoici their real opinion. Conf. Sext.
negant habere ullam fonuam Math. ix. 139.
Deum. Phut. Plac. i. 6, 16, in a de-
The Epicurean
' in Cic. N. scription of the Stoic theology,
D. i. 14, 36. evidently borrowed from a good
2 Olc. 1. c. 37. Conf. Xrische, source The Gods have been re-
:

Forschung. i. 406 and 415. presented as being like men :

' Cfem., indeed, says (Strom. Si6ti rav fifv airdvToiv rb Bdov
vii. 720, D) obi'k aluBriffiwv ahr^
: Kvpi^rarov, twv 5e Cv^v &v0punros
[t^ flecji] Sci, KaOdirep ijpe(X rois KciWiiTToi' /col KeKotriiriiiifov aperp
Sioufidpais kotoi t^v rov coB auni-

Stoiikois, liiMffTO, aKorjs ital 6\fieas

/ij) ykp cam-


Sii/aaSai wore sTepms
oTaaw, (rb Kpirunov probably
XanPiveffBai. But, according to these words should be struck
all accouhts, this must be a mis- out), toTs adv apurrdovai ri
apprehension. Clement con- KpiTiaiov biioius ica! KaXus ^x^tv
founds what Stoic writers have Sieiioit6r)<Tav.

conditionally asserted, for the


348 THE STOICS.

Chap, between the eternal and immutable Grod and Grods


XIII
!_ created and transitory,' between Grod the Creator
and Sovereign of the world, and subordinate Grods ; ^
in other words, between the universal divine power
as a Unity working in the world, and its individual
parts and manifestations.* To the former they gave
the name Zeus ; to the latter, they applied the names
of the other subordinate Grods.
(3) The In this derivative sense, divinity was allowed to
*'*
Pgi many beings by the Stoics, and, in particular, to the
theism. stars, which Plato had called created Grods, which
Ai^otle had described as eternal divine beings, and
the worship of which lay so near to the ancient cultus
of nature. Not only by their lustre and effect on
the senses, but far more by the regularity of their
motions, do these stars prove that the material of
which they consist is the purest, and that, of all

created objects, they have the largest share in the


divine reason.* And so seriously was this belief held
by the Stoics, that a philosopher of the unwieldy piety
of Cleanthes so far forgot himself as to charge Aris-
tarchus of Samos, the discoverer of the earth's motion
round the sun, the Gralilseo of antiquity, with im-
piety for wishing to remove the hearth of the uni-
verse from its proper place.' This deification of the
stars prepares us to find years, months, and seasons

' Phit. St. Eep. 38, 5 ; C. Deorum, and whom ministros


Not. 31, 5 Def. Orac. 19, p.
; regni sui genuit. Sen. Fr. 26,
420. 16 (in Zact. Inst. i. 6, 26).
^ The numina, quse singula ' IHogi. vii. 147.
adoramus et colimus, which are ' See p. 206, 1.
dependent on the Deus omnium ' Plut. De Fac. Lun. 6, 3,
STOICISM AJ^B RELIGION. 349

called Gods,' as was done by Zeno, or at least by Chap.


his School. must be remembered, that the
Still, it '^
Stoics referred these times and seasons to heavenly
bodies, as their material embodiments.^
As the stars are the first manifestation, so the
elements are the first particular forms of the Divine
Being, and the most common materials for the exer-
cise of the divine powers. It is, however, becoming
that the all-pervading divine mind should not only
be honoured in its primary state, but likewise in
its various derivate forms, as air, water, earth, and
elementary fire.*

All other things, too, which, by their utility to


man, display in a high degree the beneficent power
of God, appeared to the Stoics to deserve divine
hono\u:s, those honours not being paid to the things
themselves, but to the powers active within them.
They did not, therefore, hesitate to give the names
ofGods to fruits and wine, and other gifts of the
Gods."
How, then, could they escape the inference that
among other beneficent beings, the heroes of anti-
quity, in particular, deserve religious honours, seeing
that in these benefactors of mankind, of whom le-

gend tells, the Divine Spirit did not show Himself


under the lower form of a I'^ts, as in the elements,

'
Cie. ]Sr. D. i. 14, 36. in partioular, to Zeno's pupil
2 See p. 131. Persaaus. Krisohe (Forsohung.
' do. N. D. i. 15, 39 ; ii. i. 442) reminds, with justice,
26 ; Mog. vii. 147. of the assertion of Prodicus,
'*
Pint. De Is. c. 66 ; Cio. that the ancients deified every-
1. c. ii. 23, 60 ; i. 15, 38, thing which was of use to
where this yiew is attributed, man.
;

350 THE STOICS.

Chap. nor yet as simple <f)V(ns, as in plants, but as a ra-


xm. men had, according to
tional soul ? Such deified
the Stoic view which, on this point, agrees with the
well-known theory of Euemerus in a great measure,
contributed to swell the mass of the popular Grods ;

nor had the Stoics themselves any objection to their


worship.' Add to this the personification of human
qualities and states of mind,^ and it will be seen what
Phtedr. (7hi\oAemvLs),'Sa.t.
' such as the Gods invented by
Be. col. 3, and Cio. N. D. i. 15, Hesiod for the purpose of his
38, attribute this assertion spe-
genealogies Coios, Hyperion,
cially to Persasus and Chrysip- &c. (7) Men who are honoured
pus. Id. ii. 24, 64, after speaking for their services to mankind-
of the deification of Hercules, Hercules, the Dioscuri, Diony-
Bacchus, Eonmlus, &c., con- sus. This list includes not
tinues Quorum cum remane-
: only things which deserve
rent animi atque seternitate divine honours, but all things
f ruerentur, Dii rite sunt habiti, to which they have been ac-
cum et optimi essent et seterni. tually given hence it includes,
:

Diog. vii. 151. See p. 351, 1. besides the pttrely mythical


* This is done in Plut. Plac. Gods, things which the Stoics
i. 6, 9. Belief in the Gods, it is can never have regarded as
there said, is held in three Gods, such as the baleful Gods

forms ^the physical, the my- and emotions, on which
thical, and the form established see p. 345, 1 346, 2.; On the
by law (theologia civUis). All other hand, they could raise no
the Gods belong to seven classes, objection to the worship of
etSri (1) rb ^k toiv (paivon^vbov Ka\
: personified virtues. In the
lieTeipuv: the observation of the above list, the elementary Gods,
stars, and their regularity of such as Here, are grouped, to-
movement, the changes of gether with the Gods of fruits,
season. Sec, has conducted under the category of useful.
many to faith ; and, accordingly, Another grouping was that fol-
heaven and earth, sun and lowed by Dionysius (whether
moon, have been honoured. (2 the well-known pupil of Zeno
and 3) rh $\&jrTov Kol utptKovv: see p. 44,1
or some later
beneficent Beings are Zeus, Stoic, is unknown), who, ac-
Here, Hermes, Demeter: bale- cording to Tertullian (Ad Nat.
ful Beings are the Erinnyes, ii. 2, conf. c. 14), divided Gods
Ares, &c. (4 and 5) irpdy/iaTa, into three classes the visible:

such as 'E\irls, Ai/cjj, Euvo/iio the sun and moon, for in-
and irafli), such as "Epus, 'Aippo- stance the invisible, or powers
;

8iTr), U6Bos. (6) rh ivh tZh of nature, such as Neptune


(that is, natural forces as they
:

STOICISM AND RELIGION. 351

ample opportunity the Stoics had for recognising Chap.


everywhere in nature and in the world of man divine '

agencies and powers, and, consequently, Gods in the


wider sense of the term.' When once it had been
allowed that the name of Grod might be diverted
from the Being to whom it properly belonged and
applied, in a derivative sense, to what is impersonal
and a mere manifestation of divine power, the door
was opened to everything; and, with such conces-
sions, the Stoic system could graft into itself even
the most exceptional forms of polytheism.
With the worship of heroes is also connected the (4) Doc-

doctrine of demons.^ The soul, according to the J^^,^


Stoic view already set forth, is of divine origin, a
part of and emanation from God. Or, distinguishing
more accurately in the soul one part from the rest,

to reason only, as the governing part, this honour


belongs. Now, since reason alone protects man from
eviland conducts him to happiness this, too, was

the popular beUef reason may be described as the
guardian spirit, or demon, in man. Not only by
the younger members of the Stoic School, by Posi-
donius, Seneca, Epictetus, and Antoninus, are the
popular notions of demons, as by Plato aforetime,'

make themselves felt in the i.-itoKiKoiTairnrK^v ii6vovTovAi))i,


elements and in planets) ; and tijtv Trivras KaTora\<rKou(ri robs
those /flscW, or deified men. UfAovs.
'
Plut. Com. Not. 31, 5 ' Conf. Waolismuth, Die
iXKh. XpiaiiTitos kbI K\eov9ijs, Ansiohten der Stoiker iiber
4fvireirK7iK6Te5, as ^ttos eiviiy, Tiji Mantik imd Dilmonen (Berl.
\6yif Seav rhv ovpavhv, riiv yriv, 1860), pp. 29-39.
rhv hipa, tV Bi^arrav, ovSiya ' Tim. 90, A.

Tftil/ TOffOVTOlV &tp6apT0V ou5'


&iSiov
352 THE STOICS.

Chap. explained in this sense,' but the same method is


XIII.
pursued hy Chrysippus, who made svBaifiovui, or
happiness, consist in a harmony of the demon in
man (which, in this case, can only be his own will
and understanding) with the will of God.^ Little
were the Stoics aware that, by such explanations,
they were attributing to popular notions a meaning
wholly foreign to them. But it does not therefore
follow that they shared the popular belief in guar-
dian spirits.' Their system, however, left room for be-

' Posid. in Galen. Hipp, et him each one has taken an oath
Plat. V. 6, p. 469: -rh H tZv of allegiance, as a soldier has
iraBui' aXriov, TovreffTi ttjs re to his sovereign, but ^k fiiy
avoixoXoyias Kal rav KaKoSaifiot'os ofiv{)ovffiv, axnov fi^ irpOTLfj.'fiffeLv

filov, rh fi^ kotA irav etreffdai ry %Tfpov evTavBa 5' avroiis airiivTuy ;
'

^y auT^ Sal^vi ffvyyu/et re bvTt so that, consequently, the


ttal r^v dfjLoiav ip{)ffiv exovTi r^ rhv demon is lost in the airhs
ZKoV K6fffiOV dlOlKOWTlj r^ $6 vrithin. M. Aurel. v. 27 : 6
X^ipovi KoX ^tfdt^et, irtnh ffvviK- SaifjiuVftv kKaartp vpotrriiTTiv Kol
KKivovras pepfirBai, Sen. Ep. 41, riyefidva d Zeiis $Sukv, an6irira(rfia
2, according to the quotation, eavTov. oStos 5 itrnv A eKdcTov
p. 344, 4 Saoer intra nos spiritus
: fovs Kal \6yo?. See ii. 13 and
sedet, malorum bonorumque 17 ; iii. 3 Schl. 5, 6, 7, 12, 16 ;
;

nostrorum obserVator et custos. V. 10; viii. 45. ''

His prout a nobis traotatus est, ' See the passage quoted
ita nos ipse tractat. Ep. 31, from Sioff. vii. 8% on pr 227, 3.
11 Quid aliud voces hunc
: (Diogenes had only just before
[animus rectus, bonus, magnus] named Chrysippus irepl teAous,
quam Deum in corpore humano as source), which receives its
hospitantem ? Just as Kant explanation (if it needs one)
calls the moral idea, a primary from the above words of Posi-
notion which mankind has em- donius.
braced, the moral tone a good ' In this sense, the words of

spirit governing us. , Mpict. Sen. Bp. 110, 1, niustbe under-


Diss. i. 14, 12 : (irlrpoTrov [i stood Sepone in praesentia
:

Zevs] IfcdaT^ 7rop(rT?j(re' rhv quse quibusdam placent, uni-


fKdffrov SaifjLOvaj Kal irapeSaKe cuique nostrum psdagogum
<pv\d(Tfftv avrhv avr^ Kal Tovroy dari Deum, non quidem ordi-
aKoifiriTov Kal &TTapa\6yurTov. He narium, sed hunc inferioris
who retires within himself is uote .itatamenhocseponas
. .

not alone, a\\' 6 iths ^vSov 4<rTl volo, ut memineris, majores


KoX d vfiiTepos Sttifiuv iffri. To nostros, qui crediderunt, Stoioos
STOICISM AND RELIGION. 353

lieving that, besides the human soul and the spirits Chap.
XIII.
of the stars, other rational souls might exist, having
a definite work to perform in the world, subject to
the law of general necessity, and knit into the chain
of cause and effect. Nay, more, such beings might
even seem to them necessary for the completeness
of the universe.' What reason have we, then, to
express doubt, when we are told that the Stoics be-
lieved in the existence of demons, playing a part in
man and caring for him?^ Is there anything ex-
traordinary, from the Stoic platform, in holding that
some of these demons are by nature inclined to do
harm, and that these tormentors are used by the
deity for the punishment of the wicked,* especially

f uisse singulis enim et Genium


: The Stoics believe demons to
et Jimonem dederunt, i.e., the be mortal. Plac. i. 8, 2 &iiKris, :

old Romans, not the Stoics. nvBaydpas, VlKtiTwi/, ol ^TUtKol,


' Conf. Sext. Math. ix. 86. SaiiJLovas virdpx^iy ouffias i^vxifctis.
Amongst other things, quoted A special treatise irep! ripiiav koI
p. 146, 1, it is there said If : proceeded from the pen
Soi^((>'ij)i/

living beings exist on the earth - of Posldonius, probably as was


and in the sea, there must be his wont, containing more
rocpi ftia in the air, which is so learned than dogmatic state-
much purer ; and these are the ments, an extract from which is
demons. given by Macroi. Sat. i. 23, con-
^ Diog, vii. 151 : ^a&l S' ilvai taining the etymology of Satfutiv.
Kai Tivas Sal^iovas kv^pSnuv rv/i- ^ Phtt. Quaest. Eom. 51, p.
irdOftav exovras, iirSnTas twv av- 277 : KaBdirep ol Trepl Xpiffitnrov

BfjUTTsiwv npayfiA'TUV Ka\ ?iptaas


' oXoyrat <t)t\6(roipoi <pav\a SaL^vta
TtepivoffreiVy oXs ol BioX Stifilon

ij/BXir. Plii-t. De360Is. 25, p. : Xptavrai KoKcurrtus 4irl rohs &.vo-


Plato, Pythagoras, Xenocrates, fflovs Kai ciSfKovs hiQpilmovs. Id.
and Chrysippus hold, with the Def. Oracl. 17, p. 419 : <^ai\ovs
old theologians (amongst whom . . . SaifjLOvas ovk 'E^iireioKKTis
Wachsmuth, p. 32, 40, rightly tl6vov . . . wjreKnr^Vj aWht, /cal

thinks of the Orphics), that the Xp^tmr-


nXt^Tftiy Kai ^evoKpdTTis koX

demons are stronger than men,


Kos a statement which, par-
from which the language used ticularly as it is extended to
of them by Chrysippus does not Plato, would prove little. The
follow. Def. Oracl. 19, p. 420 : baleful Gods of mythology (p.
A
:

THE STOICS.

Chap. when in such a strict system of necessity these de-


xiir.
mons could only work, like the powers of nature,
conformably with the laws of the universe and with-
out disturbing those laws, occupying the same ground
as lightning, earthquakes, and drought? And yet
the language of Chrysippus, when speaking of evil

demons who neglect the duties entrusted to them,'


sounds as though it were only figmative and tenta-
tive language, not really meant. Besides, the later
Stoics made themselves merry over the Jewish and
Christian notions of demons and demoniacal posses-
sion.''

Yet, even, without accepting demons, there were


not wanting in the Stoic system objects to which the
popular beliefs could be referred, if it was necessary

to find in these beliefs some deeper meaning. Not


but that these beliefs were often so distorted in the
process ofaccommodation as to be no longer recog-
nised. Thus a regular code of interpretation be-
came necessary, by means of which a philosophic mind
might see its own thoughts in the utterances of com-
monplace thinkers. By the Stoics, as by their Jewish
and Christian followers, this code of interpretation
was found in the method of allegorical interpreta-
tion a method which now received a most extended
350, 2) were explained as being from Stoicism, but from Plato
evil demons by those who did (Eep. X. 615, E) and the Neo-
not deny their existence alto- platonists.
gether. Those demons, how- ' Phtt. Sto. Eep. 37, 2. See
ever, which purify the soul in p. 191, 2.
another world (Sallust. De TeHull. Test. An. 3. after
Mund. c. 19, p. 266, and whom speaking of demons, adds
VUloinn on Cornutns, p. 553, Aliqui Chrysippi seotator illu-
reminds of), are not borrowed dit ea.
; ;

THE ALLEGORISING SPIRIT. 355

application, in order to bridge over the gulf between Chap.


XIII.
the older and the more modern types of culture.'
Zeno, and still more Cleanthes, Chrysippus, and their
successors, sought to discover natural principles and
moral ideas the \6-yoi (fivcriKol, or phytiicse rationes,

in the Grods of popular belief and the stories of these


Grods,^ supposing them to be represented in these
stories in a sensuous form.' In this attempt, they

'
The Stoics are not the first Lampsacus, and other followers
who resorted to allegorical ex- of Anaxagoras (according to
planations of myths. Just as Sesych. even Agamemnon was
before philosophy had broken explained to be the ether). It
away from mythology, a Phere- appears to have been a favourite
cydes, an Empedocles, the method in the time of the
Pythagoreans had, whether con- Sophists {Plato, Theset. 153, c
sciously or unconsciously, veiled Eep. ii. 378, D Phasdr. 229, C
;
;

their thoughts in the language Crat. 407, A, to 530, C ; Gorg.


of legend, and even subse- 493, A Xen. Sym. 3, 6), as ap-
;

quently Plato had used a veil of pears from Euripides and Hero-
poetry so, now that the breach
; dotus. It follows naturally
between the two was open, from the view of Prodicus on
many attempts were made to the origin of belief in the Gods.
conceal its breadth, and indi- Plato disapproved of it. Aris-
vidual beliefs were represented totle occasionally appealed to
as the real meaning of popular it to note glimmers of truth in
beliefs, it being always sup- popular notions without attri-
posed that the original framers buting to it any higher value.
had an eye to this meaning. The founder of cynicism and his
Thus a twofold method of followers pursued it zealously.
treating the myths resulted From the Cynics the Stoics
that by natural explanation, appear to have derived it. They
and that by allegorical inter- carried it to a much greater
pretation. The former method extent than any of their pre-
referred them to facts of history, decessors, and they, too, exer-
the latter to general truths, cised a greater influence on"
whether moral or scientific posterity than the Cynics.
2 ac. N. D. 24, 63 ; iii.
and both methods agreed in 24,
looking for a hidden meaning, 63, see p. 346, 3.
' The definition of allegory :
besides the literal one. This
method of treating myths had iS ykp SWa juej/ ayopeiav rp6iros,
been already encountered erepa Se $v \4yei (TTifjuilyav, iirti)-
among the older teachers, such KaAeTrat (^Hera-
vvfitas aKKi)'yopia

as Democritus, Metrodorus of clit. Alleg. Hom. c. 5, p. 6).

A 2
;
;
;

THE STOICS.

Chap, clung to the poems of Homer and Hesiod, the Bible


XIII.
of the Greeks,' without, however, excluding other
mythology from the sphere of their investigation.
One chief instrument which they, and modern lovers
of the symbolical after them, employed was that
capricious playing with etymologies of which so many
instances are on record.^ Like most allegorisers, they
also laid down certain principles of interpretation
sensible enough theoretically,* but proving, by the
use which was made of them, that their scientific
appearance was only a blind to conceal the most
capricious vagaries. Approaching in some of their
explanations to the original bases of mythological
formation, they were stiU unable to shake off the

Accordingly, it includes every N. D. i. 15, 41). Compare also


kind of symbolical expression. put. Def. Orac. and
12, p. 415,
In earlier times, according to respecting the theological lite-
Phit. Aud. Po. c. 4, p. 19, it was rature of the Stoics ViUoinn on
termed {m6voi.a, whioli term is Cornutus, p. xxxix. Among the
found in Plato, Kep. ii. 378, D, Romans, the same method was
conf lo. 530, D Xen. Symp.
. ; followed by Varro (^Preller,
3,6, Eom. Myth. 29), and from his
Zeno treated in this way
' writings Heraclitus (living
all tlie poems of Homer and under Augustus) derived the
Hesiod (ZWo Chrysost. Or. 53, material for his Homeric Alle-
p. 275 ; Biog. vii. 4 Erisehe,
; gories (edited by Mehler) and
Forsch. .393), and so did Cornutus, for his work on the
Cleanthes (^Diog. vii. 175 nature of the Gods edited by
Phedr. [Philodem.] De Nat. Osann from Villoisin's papers.
De. col. 3 Plut. Aud. Po. 11,
;
2 do. N. D. iii. 24, 63.

p. 31 De Fluv. 5, 3, p. 1003
;
' Corn. c. 17, p. 80 Set : U
Xrisohe, 433) and Perseus. fi^l avyX^^v Toils jUiSflow, fvfjS* 4^

Ctrysippus explained the stories Irepou Tct ov6^Ta i^' erspov


in Homer, Hesiod, Orpheus, fiercKpepetv, firiW ^ mrpoffeirKdirBTj
and Mus8eus (^Phtsdr. col. 3 Tats KaT avTobs irapaSiSofisvais
Galen. Hipp, et Plat. iii. 8, yevea\oylats inrb ruir fi^ avvevrav
vol. V. 349, Erisclie, 391 and & alvlTTOvrai KexpVI''^'""' S" auToir
479), and was followed by &s -rots vKitriitiuriv, aK6ya>s rlBe-
Diogenes {Phced. col. 5 Cie. ; irOat.
THE ALLEGORISING SPIRIT. 357

perverted notion that the originators of myths, fully Chap.


conscious of all their latent meanings, had framed '__

them as pictures to appeal to the senses ; ^ and, in


innumerahle cases, they resorted to explanations so
entirely without foundation that they would have
been impossible to anyone possessing a sound view
of nature and the origin of legends. To make theory
tally with practice, the founder of the School
following Antisthenes, and setting an example after-
wards repeated by both Jews and Christians main-
tained that Homer only in some places expressed
himself according to truth, at other times according
to popular opinion.^ Thus did Stoicism surround
itself with the necessary intruments for the most ex-
tended allegorical and dogmatic interpretation.
Proceeding further to enquire how this method (2) Inter-
*"*
was applied to particular stories, the first point which f ^/jg

attracts attention is the contrast which they draw myths re-

between Zeus and the remaining Gods. From their the gods.

belief in one divine principle everywhere at work, it


followed as a corollary that this contrast, which else-
where in Greek mythology was only a difference of
degree, was raised to a specific and absolute differ-

'Proofs may be found in 276, K. speaking of Zeno's com-


abundance in Heraclitus and mentaries on Homer, says 6 Si :

Cornutus. Conf. Sen. Nat. Qu. Zivav ouScy tuv toS 'O/iiipov
ii. 45, 1 :The ancients did not Ae'^f i, aWa Siriyoi/ifvos Kai StSda-
believe that Jupiter hurled his koiii, in t& fiiv kotc* Si^av, rk Be
thunderbolts broadcast ; sed kbto a\i]eeiav^ yeypaxptv. . . .

eundem, quem nos Jovem in- 6 Se Koyos ovros 'AvTurBfveds


telligunt, rectorem custodem- 4<ttl i:p6Tepov .&AA' 6 fiXv ouk
. .

que universi, animum ac spiri- i^eipydcaro avrhp ou5e Kara tuv


turn mundi, &c. efl /nefJous 4Sii\a(rev.
2 JMo Chrysost. Or. 53, p.
58 THE STOICS.

Chap. ence. Zeus was compared to other Gods as an in-


xm L_ corruptible God to transitory divine beings. To the
Stoics, as to their predecessor Heraclitus, Zeus is the
one primary Being, who has engendered, and again
absorbs into himself, all things and all Gods. He is

the universe as a unity, the primary fire, the ether,


the spirit of the world, the universal reason, the
general law or destiny.' All other Gods, as being
parts of the world, are only parts and manifestations
of Zeus only
names of the one God who special
has many
names.^ That part of Zeus which goes
over into air is called Here (a'^/a) and its lower ;

strata, full of vapours. Hades that which becomes ;

elementary fire is called Hephaestus that which be- ;

comes water, Poseidon that which becomes earth, ;

Demeter, Hestia, and Ehea; lastly, that portion


which remains in the upper region is called Athene
in the more restricted sense. And since, according
to the Stoics, the finer elements are the same as
spirit, Zeus is not only the soul of the universe,

' Special references are Cornutus, who give further au-


hardly necessary after those thorities for the following in
already quoted, p. 148, 1 153, ; the notes on the respective
2; 164, 2; 165, 5. Conf. the passages. The same on Cor-
hymn of CfeaftiAes Chrysippus, ; nutus, p. 6, discuss the deri-
in Stoi. Eel. i. 48 Arat. Phsen. ; vation of 6ebs from flfeic or
Begin. Phit. Aud. Poet. o. H,
; TifleVai; of alBiip from affleii/ or
p. 31 Varro, in August. Civ.
; ael Beew. A portion of these
D. vii. 5 6 9 28 Servius,
; ; ; ; etymologies is well known to
in Georg. i. 6 Heraclit. c. 15,
; be Platonic,
p. 31 c. 23, 49
; c. 24, 50 ;
^ noKvivvjios, as he is called
;

Corn. pp. 7 26 35 38, where


; ; ; by Cleanthes v. 1. Conf. Diog.
Zeis is derived from (^-^v or 147; Corn. c. 9 and 26. The
fe'eii/ and Aiby from Sik, 8ri 8i' further expansion of this idea
out!>i/ Tci irivTa; conf. Villoisin maybe found in the Neoplatonio
and Osann on the passage of doctrine.
;

THE ALLEGOmSING SPIRIT. 359

but Athene, Eeason, Intelligence, Providence.' The Chap.


same Zeus appears in other respects as Hermes, Dio- xm.
nysus, Hercules.^ The Homeric story of the binding
and liberation of Zeus ^ points to the truth, already
established in Providence, that the order of the world
rests on the balance of the elements. The rise and
succession of the elements is symbolised in the hang-
ing of Here ;
* the arrangement of the spheres of the
universe, in the golden chain, by which the Olympians
thought to pull down Zeus.^ The lameness of He-
phaestus goes partly to prove the difference of the

' 1. c. ; do. N. D.
See Biog. Homer, that {HeracUt. 25, 53)
ii. 26, 66 Phied. (PMlodem.),
; Athene is made to be earth.
Fragm. col. 2-5 ; H&i-ael. c. 25, That even Zeno treated indi-
p. 53. On Here, consult Eeracl. vidual Gods in this way, as
c. 15 and 41, p. 85 Corn. c. 3 ;
parts of one general divine
on Hephaestus, Iferacl. u. 26, power or Zeus, is rendered pro-
55 ; 43, 91 ; Cm-n. c. 19, p. 98 ; bable by Erigche, Forsoh. 399,
Plut. De Is. c. 66, p. 377 by a comparison of PJued/r.
(^Diog. 1. c. perhaps confounds with the passages quoted
col. 5,
as Knsche, p. 399, supposes, from Cicero and Diogenes.
common lire with irSp tcxcik!)!', ^ Sen. Benef iv. 8, 1 Hunc
. :

but also possible that the


is- is [Jovem] et Liberum patrem et
artificial God of mythology- Hercnlem et Mercurium nostri
may haye been so explained putant. Liberum patrem, quia
now one way now another in omnium parens sit. Her- . . .

the Stoic school, which is not culem, quia vis ejus invicta sit,
always uniform in its interpre- qiiandoque lassata fuerit operi-
tations) on Poseidon, Heraol.
;
bus editis, in ignem recessura.
c. 7, 15; c. 18, 77 ;c. 46, 117; Mercurium, quia ratio penes
Cm-n. u. 12 PUt. De Is. c. 40, ; ilium est numerusque et ordo et
Schl. p. 367 on Hades, whom ;
scientia. The solution of Helios
Cicero 1. c. makes the repre- into Zeus (^Macrob. Sat. i. 23)
sentative of terrena vis Heraol. ; appears also to be of Stoic
c. 23, p. 50 c. 41, 87 Com. 5 ; ; ;
origin.
on Demeter and Hestia, Corn. ' Heraol. c. 25, 52. Conf.
c. 28, p. 156; Pint. 1. c. on ; n. t. 395.
Athene, Heraol. c. 19, 39; c. ^ Heraol. c. 40, 83 ; II. xv.
28, 59 o. 61, 123
;
Corn. c. 20, ; 18.
103. It is only by forced in- = lUd. c. 37, 73 ; II. viii.
terpretation of a passage in 18.
; ;

60 THE STOICS.

Chap, earthly from the heavenly fire, and partly implies


"

that earthly fire can as little do without wood as the


lame without a wooden support ; and if, in Homer,
Hephsestus is hurled down from heaven, the meaning

of the story is, that in ancient times men lighted


their fires by lightning from heaven and the rays of
the sun.' The connection of Here with Zeus ^ points
to the relation of the ether to the air surrounding
it; and the well-known occurrence on Mount Ida
was referred to the same event.^ The still more
offensive scene in the Samian picture was expounded
by Chrysippus as meaning that the fertilising powers
(\070t airepiiaTLKol) of God are brought to bear upon
matter.'' A similar meaning is found by Hera-
clitus in the story of Proteus,^ and in that of the
shield of Achilles. If Hephsestus intended this shield
to he a representation of this world, what else is
thereby meant but that, by the influence of primary
fire, matter has been shaped into a world ?

' Herael. u. ap-


26, 54, who this explanation is given very-
plies the same methodof in- fully. The occurrence on Mount
terpretation to the legend of Ida is said to represent the
Prometheus (otherwise inter- passage of winter into spring,
preted by Corn. c. 18, 96), Here's tresses are the foliage
Corn.o. 19, 98. On the lameness of trees, &c.
of Hephsestus, Plut. Fao. Ltm.
See JDwg. vii. 187 ; Prooem.
5, 3, p. 922. 6 ; Orig. con. Gels. iv. 48
' According to Eustath. in Tlienphil. ad Autol. iii. 8, p.
n. p. 93, 46, probably following 122, c ; Clement. Homil. v. 18.
a Stoic interpretation, Here is ^ K. 64. Proteus, according

the spouse of Zeus, because the to this explanation, denotes


air is surrounded by the ether unformed matter the forms;

but does not agree with him, which he assumes denote the
because the two elements are four elements,
opposed to one another. Seethe description. Alleg.
= Herael. c. 39, 78 (conf. Hom. 43-51, p. 90, of which
Phit. Aud, Po. p. 19), where the above is a scanty abstract.
;

TSE ALLEGORISING SPIRIT. 361

In a similar way, the Homeric theomachy was Chap.


XIII.
explained by many to mean a conjunction of tlie

seven planets, which would involve the world in great


trouble.' Heraclitus, however, gives the preference
to an interpretation, half physical and half moral,
which may have been already advanced by Cleanthes.^
Ares and Aphrodite, rashness and profligacy, are op-
posed by Athene, or prudence Leto, forgetfulness,
;

is attacked by Hermes, the revealing word ^ Apollo, ;

the sun, by Poseidon, the God of the water, with


whom, however, he comes to terms, because the sun
is fed by the vapours of the water Artemis, the ;

moon, is opposed by Here, the air, through which it


passes, and which often obscures it Fluvius, or ;

earthly water, by Hephaestus, or earthly fire/ That


Apollo is the sun, and Artemis the moon, no one
doubts * nor did it cause any difficulty to these
;

' According to Seraelit. 53, the moral interpretation given


112. by Heraclitus to Homer's Aeo-
' We
learn from Ps. Plut. y^ax^n is quite in the style of
De 5, 3, p. 1003, that
Fluv. the interpretation of the legend
Cleauthes wrote a Bfoiiaxl", a of Hercules, probably borrowed
small fragment of which, con- from Cleanthes.
taining a portion of the Pro- ' Further particulars on
metheus legend in a later Hermes, Alleg. Horn. o. 72,
and evidently apologetically 141.
moulded form, is there pre- * Alleg. Hom. c. 54.
served. The theomachy here ' Conf Heraol.
. c. 6, p. 1 1
explained by Cleanthes (for the Com. 32, p. 191 34, 206; Cie.
;

Stoic appears to be the one N. D. ii. 27, 68 Plimdr. (Philo-


;

here meant) appears not to be dem.) Nat. De. col. 5 and 2.


the Homeric one, but the In Phmd/rus, too, col. 2 (to6s 5c
struggle of the Gods with the t4v 'ATniWio), if ^kiov seems too
Giants and Titans, identical wild, perhaps ipSs should be
with the book irtpl yiyiivToiv substituted for robs, for Apollo
{Dwg. vii. 175). Perhaps on cannot well symbolise the
this occasion he may have dis- earth,
cussed the other. At any rate
362 THE STOICS.

Chap. mythologists to find the moon also in Athene.'


XUI.
Many subtle discussions were set on foot by the
Stoics respecting the name, the form, and the attri-

butes of these Gods, particularly by Cleanthes, for


whom the sun had particular importance,^ as being
the seat of the power which rules the world.' The
stories of the birth of the Lotoides and the defeat
of the dragon Pytho are, according to Antipater,
symbolical of events which took place at the forma-
tion of the world, and the creation of the sun and
moon.* Others find in the descent of two Grods from

' Plut. Fao. Lnn. 5, 2, p. author Macrobius found the


922. The Stoics address the derivation of iriBios from iriBsiv
moon as Artemis and Athene. (because the sun's heat pro-
2 See p. 147, 1. duces decay). Other explana-
' The name Apollo is ex- tions of these as well as of
plained by Cleanthes, in Ma- other epithets of Apollo, of the
orob. Sat. i. 17, i>s btt" &}0\.u>v nal name of Artemis and her
t^s avaroK^s ivoiov-
6.\K(av 't6'Koiv epithets, of the attributes and
jMevov by Chrysippus, as derived
; symbols of these Gods, are to be
from a private and iroXhs, &s found in abundance in Cor-
ovxi- Twy TToWiav Kal tpaiKay nutus, c. 32, 34, and in Macro-
ai/atuf rov inphs 6vTa. The latter bins, 1.who probably got the
c,
explanation is quoted by Plotin. most of them from Stoic sources.
V. 5, 6, p. 525, as Pythagorean, The first of these stories is
and Chrysippus may have bor- explained by Maerob. Sat. i. 17,
rowed it thence, or the later down to the most minute de-
Pythagoreans from Chrysippus. tails, in the sense of the
Cicero, in imitation, makes his cosmical views already given,
Stoic derive sol from solus. The p. 162, 2, and likewise the
epithet of Apollo, Loxias, is story of the slaying of the
referred by Cleanthes to the Pytho, the dragon being taken
A.iiis Koifll of the sun's course, to represent the heavy vapours
or the a.KT'Lves \oJal of the sun ; of the marshy earth, which were
and by OSnopides, to the \o^hs overcome by the sun's heat
xiKKos (the ecliptic). The (the arrows of Apollo). This
epithet AiiKioj is explained by interpretation being expressly
Cleanthes, quod veluti lupi pe- attributed to Antipater by Ma-
cora rapiunt, ita ipse quoque crobius, it appears probable
humorem eripit radiis ; Anti- that the first one came from
pater, &irh Tov \evKalveff0aL niivTa the same source. Another like-
<l>aTl^ovTos Tihiov. In the same wise quoted by him according

THE ALLEGORISING SPIRIT. 363

Leto the simpler thought, that sun and moon came Chap.
XTTT
forth out of darkness.' In the same spirit, Hera-
clitus, without disparaging the original meaning of
the story, sees in the swift-slaying arrows of Apollo
a picture of devastating pestilence ;
^ but then, in an
extraordinary manner, misses the natural sense, in
gathering from the Homeric story of Apollo's recon-
ciliation (II. i. 53) the lesson, that Achilles stayed
the plague by the medical science which Chiron had
taught him.'
Far more plausible is the explanation given of
the dialogue of Athene with Achilles, and of Hermes
with Ulysses. These dialogues are stated to be simply
soliloquies of the two heroes respectively.* But the
Stoic skill in interpretation appears in its fullest
glory in supplying the etymological meanings of the
various names and epithets which are attributed to
Athene.' We learn, for instance, that the name
TpiToysvsia refers to the three divisions of philosophy.

to which the dragon represents Athene are given from aflpelv ;

the sun's course is perhaps also by Heraol. c. 19, 40 Tzetz. in ;

Stoical. ifenod/Ep.Kol'Hjue.TO; Etymol.


' Cornutus, c. 2, p. 10, points Mag. 'Afliji/a from BriKvs or Bit-
to this in explaining Leto as \i^eiv (^h6itvr) = kBii\Ti or i.dr\Xa.
Aijfli, and referring it to night, =^M^ flijXoCouiro), by Pluedr.
because everything is forgotten Nat. D. col. 6 Athenag. Leg.;

in sleep at night. pro. Christ, c. 17, p. 78from


^ c. 8, especially p. 16, 22, flcii/u, because virtue never
28. Ibid. c. 12, p. 24, 28, the allows itself to be beaten
clang of Apollo's arrows is ex- from aie^jp + rafa, so that 'Aflrivofa
plained to be the harmony of = tdeepovam.
the spheres. This explanation had been

'
c. 15, p. 31. already given by Diogenes, ac-
'Ibid. c. 19, 72, p. 39, 141. cording to Phced/r. col. 6. Cor-
'See Corn. c. 20, 105, and nutusalso mentions it (20, 108),
VilloiMn's notes on the passage, but he prefers the derivation
The most varied derivations of from -rpitv.
364 THE STOICS.

Chap. Heraclitus discovers the same divisions in the three


xni.
heads of Cerberus.' Chrysippus, in a diifuse manner,
proves that the coming forth of the Goddess from the
head of Zeus is not at variance with his view of the
seat of reason.^It has been already observed that
Dionysus means wine, and Demeter, fruit;' but, just
as the latter was taken to represent the earth and its

nutritious powers,'' so Dionysus was further supposed


to stand for the principle of natural life, the pro-
ductive and sustaining breath of life ;
' and since
this breath comes from the sun, according to Cle-
anthes, it was not difficult to find the sun represented
by the God of wine.* Moreover, the stories of the
birth of Dionysus, his being torn to pieces by Titans,

'
33, p. 69.
c. col. 2 : T^v A'fifiTiTpa yrtv fl rh 4v
It is to be found in Oahn.
^ aurp y6yevfj.a [ySyi/xov TryevfiaJ,
Hipp, et Plat. iii. 8, p. 849- On Demeter as 71) /vfiTiip or
353, but, according to Plicedr. Ariii liiiTrip,see C(n-n. o. 28, p.
(Philodem.') 1. c, conf. Oe. 156, and Villoison on the pas-
N. D. I. 15, 41, was already
put forward by Diogenes. For ' Plut. 1. i;. ; Dionysus is rh
himself, he prefers the other ySvijuov iri/eujua Kal rp6<pifiov.
explanation, according to which " Macrob. Sat. i. 18 : Clean-
Athene comes forth from the thes derived the name Dionysus
head of Jupiter, because the air from iiaviaai, because the sun
which she represents occupies daily completes his course round
the highest place in the uni- the world. It is well known
verse. Cornut. 0. 20, 103, leaves that, before and after his time,
us to choose between this ex- the identification of Apollo with
planation and the assumption Dionysus was common, and it
that the ancients regarded the is elaborately proved by Ma-
head as the seat of the iiyefio- crobius. Serviiis, too, on Georg.
viKov. Heracl. c. 19, 40, states i. 5, says that the Stoics be-
the latter, ustath. in H. 93, lieved the sun, Apollo, and
40, the former, as the reason. Bacchus and likewise the
' p. 349, 4, CorH. 30, p. 172. moon, Diana, Ceres, Juno, and
' See p. 359, 1, Piut. De Is.
Proserpine to be identical.
c. 40, 367: Demeter
Schl. p. Other etymologies of Aidvmos
and Core are rh Sta tiJs 7^s koI are given by Cm-n. c. 30, 173.
THE ALLEGORISING SPIRIT. 365

his followers,' no less than the rape of Proserpine,^ Chap.


xin.
and the institution of agriculture,' and the names of
the respective Gods, afforded ample material for the
interpreting taste of the Stoics.
The Fates (ixolpai), as their name already indi-
cates, stand for the righteous and invariable rule of
destiny;^ the Graces (j(;o(OtTes), as to whose names,
number, and qualities Chrysippus had given the
fullest discussion,^ represent the virtues of benevo-
lence and gratitude ;
* the Muses, the divine origin of
culture." Ares is war ;* Aphrodite, unrestrained pas-
' Cora,. 30, discusses the Phit. Sto. Eep. 47, 5 Corn. c. 13,
;

point at large, referring both p. 38 and Plato, Kep.x. 617, c.


;

the story and the attributes of ' According to Sen. Benef. i.

Dionysus to wine. He, and 3, 8 ; 4, 4, he had filled a whole


also Heraol. c. 35, p. 71, refer book, probably of a treatise not
the story of Dionysus and Ly- otherwise mentioned on kind
curgus to the vintage. deeds, with these ineptise ita
2 Corn. c. 28, p. 163, who ut de ratione dandi accipiendi
also refers the legend and reddendique beneficii pauca ad-
worship.of Demeter, in all par- modum dicat, neo his fabulas,
ticulars, to agriculture; and sed hsec fabulis inserit. A
the rape of Persephone, to the portion of these was made use
sowing of fruits. Conf Cic. N.. of by Hecato in his work on
D. ii. 26, 66. According to this subject.
Pha. De Is. 66, p. 377, Cleanthes Chrysippus, in Plimdr.
had already called Uepae<p6vri, (Philodemus), col. 4. Further
rb ^ik Tuv KopiT&v <j}ep6fA.evov Kal particulars in Sen. 1. c, and
^ovevSfievoyiryevfia. A somewhat Corn. 15, 55. Somewhat similar
different explanation of the is the explanation of Airoi
rape of Persephone is given in (Cw-K. 12, 37 ; Heraol. 37, 75),
a passage of Mai's Mythograph which at best are only casual
vii. 4, p. 216, quoted by Osann. personifications.
' Corn. 14, 43, who, at the
on Comutus, p. 343.
' The legend of Triptolemus, same time, mentions their
which is explained by Comutus, names and number ; PMlodem.
1. 0. p. 161, historically as re- De Mus. Vol. Here. i. col. 15 ;
ferring to the discovery of Erato indicating the importance
agriculture by Triptolemus. of music for ipariKr) apfrii. Ibid.
' Chrysippus, in Stoi. i. 10, 33, on the 'Erinnyes ; 29,
180; Eus. Pr. Ev. vi. 8, 7 171, on the Horoi.
(jnisodm-et. Cur. Gr. Aff. vi. 14, Herac. 31,
63 ; Plu. Am.
p. 87), see p. 171, 1. Conf. 13, 15, p. 757.
366 THE STOICS.

Chap. sion, or,more generally, absence of control other ;


'

XIII.
interpreters, and among them Empedocles, consider
Ares to represent the separating, Aphrodite the uni-
ting, power of nature.^ The stories of the two deities
being wounded by Diomedes,'' of their adulterous
intrigues, and their being bound by Hephaestus,^ are
explained in various ways morally, physically, tech-
nically, and historically.

In the case of another God, Pan, the idea of the


AUnear was suggested simply by the name. His
shaggy goat's feet were taken to represent the solid
earth, and the human form of his upper limbs im-
plied that the sovereign power in the world resides
above.' To the Stoic without a misgiving as to these
and similar explanations,^ it was a matter of small
Herael. 28, 60; 30, 62, 'In Phit. And. Po. i;. 4, p.
and above, p. 360. 19, the connection of Ares and
2 Ibid. 69, 136. In this Aphrodite is explained as mean-
sense. Aphrodite might be iden- ing a conjunction of the two
tified with Zeus, which was planets. Heracl. 69, 136, gives
really done by Pktsdr. Nat. De. the alternative of referring
col. 1 : av6.Koyov evi/ . . . Bat this connection to the union of
[Petersen suggests euvo/ieicrfloi, <^t\ia and yei/cos, which produces
but probably it should be harmony, or to the fact that
ovojuti^efffloi] rbi' Afo Kal rijv brass (Ares) is moulded in the
Koiv^v ndvTOi]/ tpvffiv Kal elfiap- fire (Hephsestus) into objects
fiei/T]V Kal a.v6.yKyiv koX r^v avr^v of beauty (Aphrodite). The
efj/ai Kal Kvvo^iav KoX AiKr]v koX latter interpretation is given
'Oli.6voiav KoX EipiiUTjv Kal *A(f>po- by Corn. 19, 102, who also ex-
rh TrapawKfitrioj/ Trav.
SIttiv Kal plains the relation of Ares to
' The story of Ares, wibtok Aphrodite to mean the union of
h KEvewva, means, according to strength and beauty.
Heracl. 31, 64, that Diomedes, ' Corn. 27, 148 ; Plut. Krat.

iirl Tct Kfvh rrjs tuv avTejrii\uj/ 408, c.


ri^eus iropeKTcXeic, defeated the " His lewdness was said to
enemy; that of Aphrodite indicate the fullness of the
(oK/ipooiSi/ij, Hid. 30, 62), that, \6yot in nature his
(T-TrepfiaTiKol ;

by his experience in war, he sojourn in the wilderness, the


overcame the inexperienced solitariness of the world.
troops of barbarians.
THE ALLEGORISING SVIRIT. 867

difficulty to make the Titan 'laTreros stand for lan- Chap.


xni.
guage or and Kotos for quality or ttoiottjj.^
'IdijiSTos,

Add to this the many more or less ingenious expla-


nations of the well-known stories of Uranos and
Cronos,^ and we are still far from having exhausted
the resources of the Stoic explanations of mythology.
The most important attempts of this kind have, how-
ever, been sufficiently noticed.
Besides the legends of the Gods, the legends of (3) Alle-
gory ap-
the heroes attracted considerable attention in the plied to
Stoic Schools. Specially were the persons of Her- lieroio

' Com. 17, 91. Conf. Osamn stars. A second explanation is


ad locvim who points out similar given by Corn. 7, 21, after
interpretations, probably of making (c. 3, 10) vain at-
Stoic origin, in the Scholia to tempts at etymological inter-
the theogony, and also in pretations of Cronos and Khea.
Etymol. M. Cronos (from Kpaiveiv) stands
' Besides the etymologies of for the order of nature, putting
oipavis in C<w. c. 1, and the an end to the. all too-violent
observation of Plut. PI. i. 6, 9, atmospheric currents on earth,
that heaven is the father of all by diminishing the vapour-
things, because of its fertilising masses (compare the quotation
rains, and earth the mother, from Chrysippus on p. 161, 2),
because she brings forth every- and he is bound by Zeus, to re-
thing, the words in Cic. N. D. present that change in nature
ii. 24, 63, on which Xrisefte, is limited. Maoroi. Sat. i. 8
Forsch. 397, deserve notice. It (betraying a Stoic pattern by
is there said, probably after Chrysippus's definition of time :

Zeno Uranos is the Ether, and


: certa dimensio quse ex ooeli
was deprived of his vitality, conversione colligetur, conf. p.
because he did not need it for 197, 2), gives another explana-
the work of begetting things. tion Before the separation of
:

Cronos is Time (the same is elements, time was not ; after


said by fferaclit. c. 41, 86, who the seeds of all things had
sees in Bhea the ever flowing flowed from heaven down to
motions), and consumes his the earth in sufficient quantity,
children, just, as Time does and the elements had come
portions of time. Cronos was into being, the process came to
bound by Zeus, the unmeasured an end, and the different sexes
course of time having been were left to propagate animal
bound by the courses of the life.
368 THE STOICS.

Chap, cules and Ulysses singled out, for the sake of illustra-
'__ ting the ideal of the wise man.' But here, too,
various modes meet and cross. Ac-
of interpretation
cording to Cornutus,'' the God Hercules must be dis-
tinguished from the hero of the same name the
Grod being nothing less than Reason, ruling in the
world without a superior ^ and the grammarian ;

makes every effort to unlock with this key his his-


tory and attributes. Nevertheless, with all his re-
spect for Cleanthes,'' he could not accept that Stoic's
explanation of the twelve labours of Hercules. He-
raclitus has probably preserved the chief points in
this explanation. Hercules is a teacher of mankind,
initiated into the heavenly wisdom. He overcomes
the wild bear, the lion, and the bull, i.e. the lusts
and passions of men he drives away the deer, i.e.
;

cowardice he purifies the stall of Augeas from filth,


;

i.e. he purifies the life of men from extravagances ;

he frightens away the birds, i.e. empty hopes ; and


burns to ashes the many-headed hydra of pleasure.
He brings the keeper of the nether world to light,
with his three heads these heads representing the
three chief divisions of philosophy. In the same
way, the wounding of Here and Haides by Hercules
is explained. Here, the Goddess of the air repre-
sents the fog of ignorance, the three-barbed arrow

See p. 292,
'
4, and Sen. and what Vilhison quotes on
Beuef. i. 13, 3. Cornutus, p. 366, from Schol.
^ C. 3] , 187. ApoUon. among the natTiral
' Plvt. DeIs. 44, Schl. p. philosophers, i. e., the Stoics,
367 : He rb irXtixziKbv koI
is Hercules symbolises strength
SiaipcTiicli)' nvivy.a. Sen. Benef. and intelligence,
iv. 8, 1. See above, p. 359, 2, * Pers. Sat. v. 63.
PROPHETIC POWERS. 36

undeniably (so thought the Stoics) pointing to phi- Chap.


losophy, with its threefold division, in its heavenly L
flight. The laying prostrate of Hades by that arrow
implies that philosophy has access even to things
most secret.' The Odyssey is explained by Hera-
clitus in the same strain, he being apparently not the
first so to do.^ In Ulysses you behold a pattern of
all virtues, and an enemy of all vices. ^ He from
flees

the country of the Lotophagi, i.e. from wicked plea-


sures ; he stays the wild rage of the Cyclopes ; he
calms the winds, having first secured a prosperous
passage by his knowledge of the stars ; the attrac-
tions of pleasure in the house of Circe he overcomes,
penetrates into the secrets of Hades, learns from the
Sirens the history of all times, saves himself from
the Charybdis of profligacy and the Scylla of shame-
lessness, and, in abstaining from the oxen of the sun,
overcomes sensuous desires. Such explanations may
suffice toshow how the whole burden of the myths
was resolved into allegory by the Stoics, how little
they were conscious of foisting in foreign elements,
and how they degraded to mere symbols of philoso-
phical ideas those very heroes on whose real existence
they continually insisted.
The Stoic theology has engaged a good deal of C. Pro-

ova: attention, not only because instructive to


it is
^^^.^
compare their views, in general and in detail, with

similar views advanced nowadays, but also because

' HeraoUt. c. 33, p. 67, who, C. 70-75.


in the introduction, expressly ' 0. 70-73, p. 137.
refers to SoRifjuiraToi SrsJiKav.
B B
;

370 THE STOICS.

Chap. it forms a very characteristic and important part of


xni.
their entire system. To us, jnuch of it appears to
be a mere worthless trifling; but, to the Stoics,
these explanations were solemnly earnest. To them
they seemed to be
\ the only means of rescuing
the people's faith, of meeting the severe charges
brought against tradition and the works of the
poets, on which a Greek had been fed from infancy.'
Unable to break entirely with these traditions,
they would not sacrifice to them their scien-
still

tific and moral convictions. Can we, then, won-


der that they attempted the impossible, and sought
to unite contradictions, or that such an attempt
should land them in forced and artificial methods of
interpretation ?

(1) Dim- Illustrative of the attitude of the Stoics towards


nation.
positive religion are their views on divination.^ The
importance attached by them to the prophetic art
appears in the diligence which the chiefs of this
School devoted to discussing it. The ground for the
later teaching having been prepared by Zeno and
Cleanthes, Chrysippus gave the finishing touch to
the Stoic dogmas on the subject.' Particular treatises

' Conf. the way in whicli Laetant. Inst. i. 6, 9) ; Phot.


HeracUtus, 74, 146, expresses Amphiloch. Qusest. {Mont-
himself as to Plato's and Epi- faugon, Bibl.
Coisl. p. 847)
'

curus's attacks upon Homer. Phihydemus, irepl diSov ^layuyyis.


Conf. Waclnmuth^ stieaXise
^ Vol. Here. vi. 49, col. 7, 33 ;
mentioned above, p. 351, 2. and from which Cicero has
' Cie. Divin. i. 3, 6. He borrowed Divin. i. 38, 82 it. ;

there mentions two books 17, 41 49, 101 ; 15, 35


;
63, ;

of Chrysippus on divination, 130 and perhaps De Fato, 7.


;

which are also referred to (as Chrysippus also vreote a book,


Waohsmuth, p. 12, shows) by TTfpl xpi"';""'' {Oie. Divin. i. 19,
Diog. vii. 149 ; Varro (in 37 ; ii. 56, 115 ; 65, 134 ;
;

PROPHETIC POWERS: DIVINATION. 371

respecting divination were drawn up by Sphaerus, Chap.


Diogenes, Antipater, and, last of all, by Posidonius.'
xm.
The subject was also fully treated by Boethus, and
by Panaetius from a somewhat different side.^ The
common notions as to prognostics and oracles could
not commend themselves to these philosophers, nor
could they approve of common soothsaying. In a
system so purely based on nature as theirs,^ the sup-
position that (xod works for definite ends, after the
manner of men, exceptionally annoimcing to one or
the other a definite result in short, the marvellous
was out of place. But to infer thence as their op-
vcoTTiSs) ; and one irtpi oveipav dications a storm.
of Oio.
(Cie. Divin. i. 20, 39 ii. 70, ; Divin. i. 8,14 ii. 21, 47. On
;

144; 61, 126; 63, 130; i. 27, Pansetius's objections to /lapriKii


56 Smd. Tt/iapovvTos). In the
: a word will be presently said.
former, he collected oracular ' Oio. Divin. i. 52, 118
responses in the latter, pro-
; Non placet Stoicis, singulis
phetic dreams. jecorum fissis aut avium cauti-
Dioff. vii. 178, mentions a
' bus interesse Deum ;neque
treatise of Sphaerus Trfpl/uavTiK^j. enim decorum est, nee Diis
(Xc. (Divin. i. 3, 6 ; i. 38, 83 ; dignum, nee fieri ullo pacto
ii. 17, 41 43, 90 ; 49, 101) men-
; potest. IHd. 58, 132 Nunc :

tions a treatise having the same ilia testabor, non me sortileges,


title with that of Diogenes of neque eos, qui qusestus causa
Seleucia, and two books of An- hariolentur, ne psychomantia
tipater irepl tiavTiKrjs, in which quidem . . agnoscere. Simi-
many interpretations of dreams larly in Sen. Nat. Qu. ii. 32, 2
were given. The same writer (see p. 374, 3), the difference
(Divin. i. 3, 6; 20, 39; 38, between the Stoic view and
83; 54,123; ii.70,144; 15,35; the ordinary one is stated to
49, 101) mentions a treatise of be this, that, according to the
Posidonius vipl ;uo>ri/(?j, in five Stoics, auguries non quia
books, Diog. vii. 149 ; Cic. significatura sunt fiant, but
Divin. i. 3, 6 30, 64 55, 125; ; ;
quia facta sunt signiflcent.
57, 130 ii. 15, 35
; 21, 47 De ; ;
In c. 42, it is said to be an
Fato, 3 ; BoetL De Diis et absurd belief that Jupiter
Pr^sens (in Orelli's Cicero, v. 1) should hurl bolts which as often
p. 395. hit the innocent as the guilty,
' Boethus, in his commen- an opinion invented ad coer-
tary on Aratus, attempted to cendos animos impeiitorum.
determine and explain the in-
B B 2
;

372 THE STOICS.

Chap.
XUI.
ponents, the Epicureans, did that the whole art of
divination is a delusion, was more than the Stoics
eeuld do. The belief in an extraordinary care of
God for individual men was too comforting an idea
forthem to renounce they not only appealed to ;
'

divination as the strongest proof of the existence of


Grode and the government of Providence,'' but they
also diew the converse conclusion, that, if there be
Grods, there must also be divination, since the bene-
volence -of the Gods would not allow them to refuse
to mankind so inestimable a gift.' The conception

Conf. Diogenian, in Mis.


' Deos, vicissimque si Dii sint,
Pr. Ev. iv. 3, 5: rh xP^'^^ej esse qui divinent. Arcem tu
airfis (divination) kxI $iu,ipe\is, quidem Stoicorum, inquam,
Si* h Kol jUC^Xitrra Xpuimriros Soxei Quinte, defendis. Tbid. 38,
Afiveiv T71V fiavTtKi\v ; and M. 82 :Stoic proof of divination :

Awrel. ix. 27 ; God cares even Si sunt Dii neque ante declarant
for the vsrioked by means of hominibus quse f utura sunt, aut
prophecies and bv dreams. non diligunt homines, aut quid
2 Oic. N. D. ii. 5, 13, where eventurum sit ignorant, aut
among the four reasons from existimant nihil interesse ho-
which Cleanthes deduced be- minum, scire quid futurum sit,
lief in Gods, the first is prae- aut non censent esse suae majes-
sensio rerum futurarum, ex- tatis praesignificare hominibus
traordinary natural phenomena quae sunt futura, aut ea ne ipsi
pestilence, earthquakes, mon- quidem Dii prjesignificare pos-
sters, meteors, &c., being the sunt. At neque non diligunt
third. lUd. 65, 165 The : nos, &o. Non igitur sunt Dii
Stoic says of divination Mihi : nee significant futura (ovk &pa
videtur vel maxime confirmare, eiffl fiky 6eo\ ov irpoinjfiaivovfft Bk
Deorum providentia consuli the well-known expression
rebus humanis, Sext. Math. ix. of Chrysippus for fleof ciViy,
132 If there were no Gods, all
: ov irpoa-rifiaivovffi, conf. p. 1 14, 1)
the varieties of divination sunt autem Dii :significant
would be unmeaning these ; ergo : et non, si significant,
are nevertheless universally ad- nullas vias dant nobis ad signi-
mitted, die. Divin. i. 6, and the ficationis scientiam, frustra
quotations on p. 175, 3, 4. enim significarent neo, si dant
:

' Cio. Divin. i. 5, 9 Ego : vias, non est divinatio. Est


enim sic existimo si sint ea : igitur divinatio. This proof,
genera di vinandi vera, de quibus says Cicero, was used by Chry-
accepimus quseque colimus, esse sippus, Diogenes, Antipater.
:

PROPHETIC POWERS: DIVINATION. 373

of destiny, too, and the nature of ma,n, appeared to Chap.


PosidoniuS to lead to the belief in divination ;
' if ^
all that happens is the outcome of an unbroken chain
of cause and effect, there must be signs indicating
the existence of causes, from which certain effects
result and if the soul of man is in its nature
; ^

divine, itmust also possess the capacity, under cir-


cumstances, of observing what generally escapes its
notice.' Lest, however, the certainty of their belief
should sufifer from lacking the support of experience,
the Stoics had collected a number of instances of
verified prophecies ;
* but with so little discrimina-
tion, that we could only wonder at their credulity,
did we noftknow the abject state of such historical
criticism as then existed, and the readiness with
which, in all ages, men believe whatever agrees with
their prejudices.'
In what way, then, can the two facts be com-

It may be easily recognised as ^ Cic. 1. c. 55, 126.


belonging to Chrysippus. Cic. ' IMd. 57, 129.
ii. 17, 41 49, 101, again reverts
;
* See p. 370, 3 ; 371, 1.
'

to the same proof. Conf id. .


" do. Divin. i. 27, 56 (

i. 46, 104: Id ipsum est Deos TiiaapovvTos), 135 ii. 65, (

non putaie, quse ab iis signi- ccottIis), ii. 70, 144, quoting
ficantur, contemnere. IHog. from Chrysippus i. 54, 123, ;

vii. 149 : fol ;uV xaX ij.avTiKi)v quoting from Antipater i. 30, ;

vipe(rTii'ai Traai" (ficunv, ei /tol 64, De


Pat. 3, 5, from Posi-
7Tp6voiav cTroi. Some read ^ xal donius gives instances of
in which case the
Trp6voiav elvai, stories to which the Stoics
argument would be reversed, attached great value, whilst
not from providence to divina- their opponents either pro-
tion, but from divination to nounced the stories to be false,
providence. or the prophecies to be de-
'
Cic. Div. i. 55, 125 ceptive, or their fulfilment to
Primum mihi videtur, ut Posi- be accidental ( Cic. Divin. i.
donius facit, a Deo . . deinde a 19, 37; ii. 11, 27 66, 115 De ; ;

fato, deinde a natura vis omnis Fato 3, 5).


divinandi ratioque repetenda.
:

374 THE STOICS.

Chap, bined the belief in prophecy, on the one hand, and,


'__ on the other, the denial of unearthly omens arising
(2) Pro- from an immediate divine influence ? In answer-
TJli/BCU BSD-

plained hy ing this question, the Stoics adopted the only course
a refer-
-jpliich their system allowed. The marvellous, which,
as such, they could not admit, was referred to natural
laws,' from which it was speculatively deduced. The
admirable Pansetius is the only Stoic who is reported
as having maintained the independence of his judg-
ment by denying omens, prophecy, and astrology.^
Just as in modern times Leibnitz and so many others
both before and after him thought to purge away
from the marvellous all that is accidental and super-
human, and to find in wonders links in the general
chain of natural causes, so, too, the Stoics, by as-
suming a natural connection between the token and
its fulfilment, made an effort to rescue omens and
divination, and to explain portents as the natural
symptoms of certain occurrences.* Nor did they con-

' Aristotle, in a somewhat as Wachsmuth rightly observes,


different sense, had explained this denial of Astrology (Divln.
the marvellous by a reference ii.42-46), and he allows, c. 42,
to natural causes, even allowing 88 ; 47, 97, that Pansetius was
the existence of presentiments the only Stoic who rejected it.
within certain limits. ' Sen. Nat. Quse. ii.
32, 3
^ Cic. Divin. i. 3, 6, after Nimis ilium [Deum} otiosum et
the passage quoted : Sed a pusillEe rei ministrum facis, si
Stoicis vel princeps ejus disci- aliis somnia aliis exta, disponit.
plinse Posidonii doctor disci- Ista uihilominus divina ope-ge-
ptilus degeneravit
Antipatri runtur. Sed non a Deo pennse
Pansetius, uec tamen ausus est avium reguntur nee pecudum
negare vim esse divinandi, sed viscera sub securi formantur.
dubitare se dixit. Ibid. i. 7, Alia ratione fatorum series ex-
12; ii. 42, 88; Acad. ii. 33, plicatur .quicquidfitalicujus
. .

107 Biog. vii. 149 Epi])lian.


; ; rei futurse signum est , cujus
. .

Adv. Hser. Cicero appears to rei ordo est etiam prsedictio est,
have borrowed from Panastius, &:c. Cie. Divin. i. 52, 118, after
PROPHETIC POWERS: NATURAL CAUSES. 376

fine themselves to cases in which the connection he- Chap,


tween the prophecy and the event can he proved.' '__

They upon divination in cases in which it


insisted
cannot possibly be proved. The flight of birds and
the entrails of victims were stated to be natural
indications of coming events ; and there was said to
be even a formal connection between the positions
of the stars and the individuals born under those
positions.^ If it was urged, that in this case omens
must be more numerous than they were supposed
far

to be, the Stoics answered, that omens were count-


less, but that only the meaning of a few was known

to men.' If the question were asked, how it is that,


in public sacrifices, the priest should always ofier
those very animals whose entrails contained omens,
Chrysippus and his followers did not hesitate to aflSrm
that the same sympathy which exists between ob-
jects and omens also guides the sacrificer in the
choice of a victim.'' And yet so bald was this hypo-

the passage quoted, p. 371, 3 : As in the passage quoted


'

Sed ita a prinoipio inohoatum from Boethus on p. 371, 2.


esse mundum, nt certis rebus ' Conf. p. 374, 2 ; 379, 1,
certa signa preecurrerent, alia and Cie. Div. ii. 43, 90, ac-
in extis, alia in avibus, &o. cording to whom Diogenes of
Posidonius, ihid. 55, 125 (see Seleuoia conceded so much to
p. 373, 2). Kor wasthe meaning astrology as to alio w that, from
otherwise, when portents (ac- the condition of the stars at
cording to Cio. Divin. ii. 15, birth, it might be known quali
33 ; 69, 142) were based on a quisque natura et ad quam
(TufiiriSea t?s (pvatios (on which quisque maxime rem aptus
see p. 183, 2), an opponent not futurus sit. More he would
without reason doubting whe- not yield, because twins often
ther it existed, for instance, differ widely in their course of
between a rent in the liver of life anddestiny.
a victim and an advantageous ' Sen. IS^at. Qu. ii. 32, 5.
business, or between an egg in ' Cio. 1. c. ii. 15, 35 : Chry-
a dream and treasure trove. sippus, Antipater, and Posi-
;

THE STOICS.

Chap: thesis, that they had, at the same time, a second


xm,
answer in reserve, viz. that the corresponding change
in the entrails did not take place until the victim
had been chosen.' In support of such views, their
only appeal was to the almighty power of God ; but,
in making this appeal, the deduction of omens from
natural causes was at an end.^
Nor, again, could the Stoics altogether quiet a
suspicion that an unchangeable predestination of all
events had rendered individual activity superfluous,'
nor meet the objection* that, on the hypothesis of
necessity, divination itself was unnecessary.^ They
quieted themselves, however, with the thought that
divination, and the actions resulting from divina-
tion, are included among the causes foreordained by
destiny.^

donius assert Ad hostiam :


* Cic. Divin. ii.
8, 20 Dio-
;

deligendam ducem esse vim genian, in Ihis. Pr. Ev. iv. 3, 5


quandam sentientem atque di- Alen. Aph. De Fat. 31, p. 96.
vinam, qus tota conf usa mundo ' Upon the use of divination

sit, as was explained I. 52, depends the whole argument


118. for its reality, based on the
' Cie. ii. . 15, 85 : Hind vero divine kindness. Cic. i. 38, 83,
multum etiam melius, quod . . . and above, p. 872, 1.
dlcitur ab illis (conf. i. 52, Sen. Nat. Qu. ii.
37, 2 38, ;

118) ; cum immolare quispiam 2 Effugiet pericula si expia-


:

velit, tum fieri extorum muta- verit prsediotas divinitus minas.


tionem, ut aut absit aliquid, aut At hoc quoque in f ato est, ut
supersit: Deorum enim numini expiet, &c. This answer pro-
parere omnia. See p. 374, 3. bably came from Chrysippus,
^ (lie. i. 53, 120, defends who, as it appears from Cic.
auguries somewhat similarly by Divin. ii. 63, 130, and PHlodem.
arguing : If an animal can jrtpi flewi" 5107(07^$, Vol. Here. vi.
move its limbs at pleasure, col. 7, 33, defended the use of
must not God have greater expiation. In the above quoted
power over His ? (his body ac- and more general form it is
cording to then! being the found in Alexander and Euse-
whole world). bius, probably also taken from
' See p. 181. Chrysippus, see p. 181.
: ;;

PROPHETIC POWERS: CAUSES. 377

Divination, accordingly, consists in the capacity Chap;


xni.
to read and interpret omens;' and this capacity is,

according to the Stoics, partly a natural gift, and (3) <?

partly acquired by art and study. ^ The natural gift of tion.

prophecy is based, as other philosophers had already


laid down,' on the relationship of the human soul to
Grod.'' Sometimes it manifests itself in sleep, at other
times in ecstasy .' A taste for higher revelations will

be developed, in proportion as the soul is withdrawn


from the world of sense, and from all thought re-
specting things external.^ The actual cause of the
prophetic gift was referred to influences coming to

According to the definition sophy, without, however, de-


in Sea:t. Math. ix. 132, which fending them.
Oic. Divin. ii. 63, 130, attri- ' do. Divin. i. 30, 64 ii. 10,;

butes to Chrysippus, it is an 26 The naturale genus divi-


:

iiriaritint ( Cic. more accurately nandi is, quod animos arriperet


a vis = Sivapus, since besides sci- aut exciperet extrinsecus a,

entific there is also a natural divinitate, unde omnes animos


divination), fltaipijTiK)) koI ^Jijttj- haustos aut acceptos aut llbatos
TiK^ Tuv iy^rh 0euv i.vBpti>TTOis 5iSo- haberemus. Pint. Plac. v. 1
fievtov (TTjfielav, Stob. Eel. ii. where, however, the words kotA
122 and 238 ; -EW. Pr. Ev. iv. 9ei(iTr|Ta Tijs 'I'vxvs are only a

3, 5. gloss on the preceding words


2 Phit. Vit. Horn. 212, p. kotA ri ivOeoy, k.t.\. Galen.
1238 [rf/S iiavTmrjs'] ri fihv
:
Hist. Phil. p. 320.
' Cit;. Divin. i.'50, 115, and
TexvM&v (paffLV flvat ol ^tuikoI.
oioi/ Upo!TKOTriav Kol olavohs KoL tJp Plut. Compare the many
irepl ((i^fioi (col K\-ifi6vas (to! tru/i- Stoic stories of dreams and
presentiments in Cic. i. 27, 56 ;
npoaTiydpevffav Th Si i/r^xvov KaX 30, 64 ; ii. 5, 134 ; 70, 144.
' See besides the passages
aSt&aKTov, rovretrriv iviiriiia koX
ifdovfftafffiois. To the same just quoted, Cic. Divin. i. 49,
effect, Oic. Divin. i. 18, 34; 110 J 50, 113 ; 51, 115 and in
;

ii. 11, 26. particular i. 57. 129. Hence


' Conf. the fragment quoted the prophecies of the dying
in 'Aristotle and the Peri- (itid. 30, 63, according to Posi-
patetics,' p. 300, which throws donius ; conf. Arigt. 1. c), and
light on old and well-known the statement (ibid. 53, 121
views in the spirit of the see p. 380, 1) that true dreams
Platonic Aristotelian philo- come of innocent sleep.
378 THE STOICS.

Chap, the soul partly from Grod or the universal spirit dif-
XIII,
fused throughout the world,' and partly from the
souls which haunt the air or demons.^ External
causes, however, contribute to put people in a state
of enthusiasm.'
Artificial soothsaying, or the art of divination,
depends upon observation and guess-work.* One
who could survey all causes in their effects on one
another would need no observation. Such a one
would be able to deduce the whole series of events

from the given causes. But Grod alone is able to do


this. Hence men must gather the knowledge of
future events from the indications by which their
coming is announced.^ These indications may be of
every variety and hence all possible forms of fore-
;

telling the future were allowed by the Stoics the ;

'Conf. the quotations on Posidonius can only have spoken


p. 375, 4, from do. Divin. ii. of Gods in condescension to
10,26; 15, 35 and his remarks
; popular views; as a Stoic, he
on the instinotus afflatusque would only know of that oon-
divinus. Cic. i. 18, 34. nection with the soul of the
^ According to Oie. Divin. i. universe which is referred to in
30, 64, Posidonius thought pro- the first mode,
phetic dreams were realised in ' Amongst such external
one of three ways uuo, quod : helps, the Stoic in Cic. Divin.
prsevideat animus ipse per sese, i. 50, 114 36, 79, enumerates
;

quippe qui Deorum cognitione the impression derived from


teneatur ; altero, quod planus music, natural scenery, moun-
aer sit immortalium animorum, tains, woods, rivers, seas and
in quibus tauquam insignitse vapotirs arising from the earth,
notse veritatis appareant ; tertio. But it is difficult to understand
quod ipsi Dii cum dormientibus how, on Stoic principles, he
coUoquantur. Of these three can have attached value to
modes, not the first only, but oracles (jMd. 18, 34) by lot or
also the second, correspond with justified them otherwise than
the Stoic hypotheses. Indeed, in the way mentioned on p.
in StoJ). Eol. ii. 122, 238, liavrmii 375, 4.
is defined = ^TTio-T^A") flewprjTiK*) > Oic. i. 18, 34 ; 33,72.
&riiA.elav rav o[7rb BiSiv J) SaiiJ,6vaip ' Ibid. i.56, 127.
PROPHETIC POWERS: CAUSES. 379

inspection of entrails, divination by lightning and Chap,


xni.
other natural phenomena, by the flight of birds, and
omens of every kind.' Some idea of the mass of su-
perstition which the Stoics admitted and encouraged
may be gathered from the first book of Cicero's trea-
tise on divination. The explanation of these omens
being, however, a matter of skill, individuals in this,
as in every other art, may often go wrong in their
interpretation.^ To ensure against mistakes tradi-
tion is partly of use, establishing by manifold expe-
riences the meaning of each omen ; ' and the moral
state of the prophet is quite as important for scien-
tific divination as for the natural gift of prophecy.
Purity of heart is one of the most essential condi-
tions of prophetic success.
In all these questions the moral tone of Stoic
piety is and great pains were taken by the
preserved,
Stoics to bring their belief in prophecy into harmony
with their philosophic view of the world. Never-
theless, it is clear that success could neither be theirs

in making this attempt, nor indeed in dealing with


any other parts of the popular belief. Toiling with

'
Cicero, ii. 11, 26, enu- 9eo\7iiTTMii, affTpotiavrmii nor
merates the above-named va- fioyixii ir^ffir)(rts Si' ovelpav.
rieties, after having previously Maeroh. Somn. Seip. i. 3, gives
(i.33) treated them separately, a theory of dreams ; but in how
Similarly, Ps. Pint. V. Horn, far it represents the views of
212. 8ee above, p. 377, 2. the Stoics, it is impossible to

Stoi. Eol. ii. 238, mentions say. Sen. Nat. Qu. ii. 39, i. 41,
tentatively, as varieties of clearly distinguishes the dis-
littPTudi t6 Tf bvfifoKpiTiKbv, KoL cussion of natural omens from
t!> oiaivoaKoitMiv, koX Bvtik6v. the doctrines of philosophy.
Seait.Math. ix. 132, says If :
' do. i. 55, 12i ; 56, 128.
there were no Gods, there ' Hid. i. 56, 127.
would be neither fiavTMii nor
380 THE STOICS.

Chap, indefatigable zeal in an attempt so hopeless, they


XIII,
proved at least the sincerity of their wish to recon-
cile religion and philosophy. But not less did they
by these endeavours a misgiving that science,
disclose
which had put on so bold a face, was not in itself
but needed support froni the traditions of
sufficient,

religion,and from a belief in divine revelations.'


Probably we shall not be far wrong in referring to
this practical need the seeming vagaries of men
like Chrysippus, who, with the clearest intellectual
powers, could be blind to the folly of the methods
they adopted in defending untenable and antiquated
opinions. These vagaries show in Stoicism prac-
tical interests preponderating over science. They
also establish the connection of Stoicism with Schools
which doubted altogether the truth of the under-
standing, and thought to supplement it by divine
revelations. Thus the Stoic theory of divination is

the immediate forerunner of the Neopythagorean


and Neoplatonic doctrine of revelation.

' Cic. i. 53, 121 Ut igitux


: cernit in somnis ;sic castus
qui se tradet qnieti prteparato animus purusque vigilantis et
animo cum bonis cogitationi- ad astrorum et ad avium re-
bus tunc rebus (for instance, liquorumque signorum et ad
nourishment conf c. 29, 60
; .
;
extorum veritatem est para-
51, 115) ad tranquillitatem tior.
acoommodatis, certa et vera
STOIC SYSTEM AS A WHOLE. 881

CHAPTEE XIV.

THE STOIC PHILOSOPHY AS A WHOLE AND ITS HISTO-


RICAL POSITION.

Having now investigated the Stoic system in detail, Chap.


we shall be in a position to pass a definite judgment '_

on the scope of the Stoic philosophy, the import ^- Inner

and the relation of its various parts, and its his- of the
torical position. Its peculiar character manifests ^o^y-
itself before all things in the three points to which
attention was drawn at the very outset : '
its pre-
eminently practical tone, the deteimining of this
practical tendency by the notions of the good and
virtue, the use of logic and natural science as a
scientific basis therefor. Scientific knowledge is not,

as we have seen, to the Stoics an end in itself, but


only a means for producing a right moral attitude,
all philosophical research standing directly or indi-
rectly in the service of virtue. Both in its earlier

as well as in the later days of its existence the Stoic


School advocated this principle in the most deter-
mined and exclusive manner, nor was it even denied
by Chrysippus, the chief representative of its science
and learning.
See p. 46.
382 THE STOICS.

Chap. If it be then asked what is the right moral atti-


xrv,
tude, the Stoics reply : action conformable to nature
(1) utki- and reason, m other words, virtue. Virtue, however,
,
eal side of ^ , i n , t j.i
implies two things. On the one band it implies the
resignation of the individual to the universe, obe-
dience to the universal law; on the other hand it

involves the harmony of man with himself, the domi-


nion of his higher over his lower nature, of reason
over emotion, and the rising superior to every thing
which does not belong to his true nature. Both
statements may be reconciled, the law of morality
being addressed only to reasonable beings, and this
law being the law of their nature, and only to be
carried into execution by their own exertions. StUl,
in the Stoic Ethics, two currents of thought may be
clearly distinguished, which from time to time come
into actual collision; the one requiring the individual
to live for the common good and for society, the
other impelling him to live for himself only, to eman-
cipate himself from all that is not himself, and to
console himself with the feeling of virtue. The first

of these tendencies brings man to seek the society of


others ; the second enables him to dispense with it.

From the former spring the virtues of justice, socia-


bility, love of man ; from the latter, the inner free-

dom and happiness of the virtuous man. The former


culminates in citizenship of the world ; the latter
in the self-sufficingness of the wise man. In as far
as virtue includes everything that can be required of
man, happiness depends on it alone ; nothing is good
but virtue, nothing is evil but vice ; all that is not
CONNECTION OF THE SYSTEM. 383

connected with the moral nature is indifferent. On Chap.


the other hand, in as far as virtue is based on human ^^'
nature, it stands on the same footing with all else

that is conformable with nature, If its own peculiar


value cannot be surrendered, no more can it be re-
quired that we should be indifferent to the latter,
that it should not have for us some positive or negar-
tive value, or in some way affect our feelings. There-
with the doctrine of things indifferent and the wise
man's freedom from emotions begins to totter. Lastly,
if we look at the way in which virtue exists in man,
we arrive at different results, according as we look at
its essence or its manifestation. Virtue consisting in
acting conformably with reason, and reason being one
and undivided, it appears that virtue forms an undi-
vided unity, and must, therefore, be possessed whole
and entire or not at all. PVom this proposition the con-
trast of the wise and foolish man, with all its blunt-
ness and extravagances, is only a legitimate conse-
quence. Or, again, if we look at the conditions upon
which owing to human nature the acquisition and
possession of virtue depends, the conviction is inevi-
table that the wise man as drawn by the Stoics never
occurs in reality. Hence the conclusion is unde-
niable that the contrast between wise men and fools is

more uncertain than it at first appeared to be. Thus


all the main features of the Stoic ethics may be simply [/

deduced from the one fundamental notion, that ra-


tional action or virtue is the only good. ^ \

Not only does this view of ethics require a pecu- \^) ^^^.
liar theory of the world to serve as its scientific basis, tificsideof
384 THE STOICS.

Chap, but it has a reflex action also, influencing alike the


'.

tone and the results of theoretic enquiry. If the


the Stoic
duty of man is declared to consist in bringing his
actions into harmony with the laws of the universe,
it becomes also necessary that he should endeavour
himself to know the world and its laws. The more
his knowledge of the world increases, the greater
will be the value which he attaches to the forms of
scientific procedure. If, moreover, man Ls required
to be nothing more than an instrument of the uni-
versal law, it is only consistent to suppose an ab-
solute regularity of procedure in the universe, an
unbroken connection of cause and effect, and ulti-
mately to refer everything to one highest all-moving
cause, and to include everything under one primary
substance. If in human life the individual has no
rights as against the laws of the universe, so all that
is of individual occurrence in the world is powerless
against universal necessity. On the other hand, if

in the case of man everything turns upon his strength


of will, then likewise in the universe the acting power
must be regarded as the highest and most exalted.
There arises thus that view of the world as a series
of forces which constitutes one of the most peculiar
and penetrating characteristics of the Stoic view of
nature.' Lastly, if such an excessive importance is
attached to action and practice, as is here done,
that materialistic view of the world is suggested to
speculation, which finds its bluntest expression in
the Stoic Materialism and appeals to the senses.^
' See p. 139. ^ See p. 133.
CONNECTION OF THE SYSTEM. 385

At the same time the Materialism of the Stoics is Chap.


XIV '__
superseded and limited by the thought of the uni-
verse and of a divine all-penetrating power and rea-
son, just as their appeal to the senses is by the
demand for the formation of conceptions, and the
general application of the process of demonstration ;

the truth of knowledge itself is based on a practical


postulate, and the greater or less certainty of the
same ismeasured by the strength of personal convic-
tion. If these elements proved too contradictory to
be harmonised ; if the Materialism of the Stoics was
at variance with their view of the world as a series
of forces ; if appeals to the senses were obviously
in conflict with logical method, it was at least there-
by clearly established that a practical and not a
purely intellectual interest lay at the root of their
system.
Of course this statement must not be taken to (3) Con-

mean that the Stoics first developed their ethical


"If^^^f
principles independently of their theory of the uni- and scien-
"tAfio sl-0~
verse, and afterwards brought the two into connec- ^ents.
tion with each other. On the contrary, it was by this
peculiar connection of theory and practice that Stoi-
cism itself first came into existence. The leading
thought of Zeno consists in the attempt to vindicate
the supremacy of virtue by a scientific knowledge of
the laws of the world ; and he becomes the founder
of a new School only by bringing to Cynicism those
scientific ideas and aims which he had learned him-
self in the School of Polemo, Stilpo, and Diodorus,
and otherwise gathered from a study of ancient phi-
c c
THE STOICS.

Chap, losophy. These elements are not therefore acciden-


XIV.
tally brought together in Stoicism, but they are co-
extensive, and dependent one upon the other. As
in the natural science and theory of knowledge of
the Stoics, the experimental basis on -which their sys-
tem was built may be easily seen, so the peculiar
development of their ethics supposes all those posi-
tions respecting the universeand the powers therein
at work, which form the most important part of
their natural science. Only by a scientific treatment
of this kind was Stoicism at all able to improve upon
the onesidedness of the Cynic ethics, at least to the
extent in which it really did so, and to accommodate
itself to the wants of human nature, so far as to be
able to exercise an influence at large. Upon this union
only of ethics and metaphysics does that religious
attitude of the Stoic system repose, to which it owes
in a great measure its historical importance. There-
by only could it occupy so influential a position in an
age in which intellectual power was indeed declining,
but in which the interest for science was keen. But
that Stoic physics and metaphysics adopted this line,
and no other ; that Zeno and his followers, who draw
on former systems for their own on the most exten-
sive scale, borrowed from these systems these and no
other positions, and expanded them in this and no
other direction ; these results are, doubtless, ulti-

mately due to their moral attitude. All that bore


on the subject of ethics, and supported it, they
appropriated ; all that was opposed thereto they re-
jected. The Stoic system as such may owe its rise
RELATION TO PBEVIOUS SYSTEMS. aS7

to a union of ethical and speculative elements, in Chap.


which both were more deinitely determined by one "

another ; still the ethical platform is the one on


which its formation commences, and which prima-
rily determined its course and results.
In order to obtain a more accurate notion of the B. Rela-

rise of Stoicism, the premises on which itproceeds, ^gi^^,,^


and the grounds on which it is based, we must take a topre-nous
glance at its relations to preceding systems. The
Stoics themselves deduced their philosophical pedi-
latio^nto'
gree dii-ectly from Antisthenes, and indirectly from Socratcx
Socrates.' Clear as is their connection with both Cynics.
these philosophers, it would nevertheless be a mis-
take to regard their teaching as a revival of Cynicism,
still more to regard it as a simple following of Socrates.
From both it undoubtedly borrowed much. The self-

sufficiency of virtue, the distinction of things good,


evil,and indifferent, the ideal picture of the wise
man, the whole withdrawal from the outer world
within the precincts of the mind, and the strength
of moral will, are ideas taken from the Cynics. In
the spirit of Cynicism, too, it explained general

' Whether Diogenes, in con- ing of Antisthenes, says : SomT


necting the Stoics with the Se kk! t^s Si'SpmSeffTcJTTjs irraVK^s
Cynics, was following a Stoic KOTtip|oi . . . olnos Trytia-aro xal
authority or not (vii.), is a ttjs ^loyemus ciiraBdas koI ttjs

moot point nevertheless, the


; KpirriTos iyxparelas koI t^
view comes to us from a time ziivams Kaprepias, airis uiroflc-
in which the relations of the h^dos rf 7r(f\ei to B^iiiKia; and
two must have been well Jwvenal, xiii. 121, calls the Stoic
known, and the quotation from dogmas a Cynicis tunica (the
Posidonius on p. 274, 2, quite common dress in distinction to
accords herewith. Not to men- the tribon) distantia.
tion others, Diog. vi. 14, speak-

C c 2
'
;

388 THE STOICS.

Chap, ideas as simply names. Not to mention many


'

peculiarities of ethics, the contrasting of one God


with the many popular Gods, and the allegorical
explanation of myths, were likewise points borrowed
from Cynicism. The identification of virtue with
intelligence, the belief that virtue was one, and could
be imparted by teaching, were at once in the spirit
of Socrates and also in that of the Cynics. The ar-
gument for the existence of God based on the sub-
ordination of means to ends, the whole view of the
world as a system of means and ends, and the Stoic
theory of Providence, are views peculiarly Socratic ;

and the Stoics followed Socrates in ethics by identi-


fying the good and the useful.
And yet the greatness of the interval which sepa-
rates the Stoics even from the Cynics becomes at
once apparent on considering the relation of Aristo
to the rest of the Stoic School. In refusing to med-
dle with natural or mental science, or even with
ethical considerations at all, Aristo faithfully reflects
the principles of Antisthenes. In asserting the unity
of virtue to such an extent that all virtues are merged
in one, he was only repeating similar expressions of
Antisthenes. In denying any difference in value to
things morally indifferent, and in placing the highest
morality in this indifference, he was, according to
the older writers, reasserting a Cynic tenet.^ Con-
versely, denying these statements as the great majo-
rity of Stoics did, the points are indicated in which

" KHsohe, Forschung. i. 363, ^ On Aristo see p. 59 ; 260


and above, p. 145, 2. 281.
RELATION TO PREVIOUS SYSTEMS. 380

Stoicism differed from Cynicism.' In the feeling of Chap.


moral independence, and in his invincible strength ! -

of will, the Cynic is opposed to the whole world ; he


needs for virtue no scientific knowledge of the world
and its laws ; he regards nothing external to him-
self ; he allows nothing to influence his conduct, and
attaches value to nothing ; but, in consequence, he
remains with his virtue confined to himself ; virtue
makes him independent of men and circumstances,
but it has neither the will nor the power to interpose
effectively in the affairs of life, and to infuse therein
new moral notions. Likewise Stoicism insists upon
the self-sufiiciency of virtue quite as strongly, and
will allow quite as little as Cynicism that anything
except virtue can be a good in the strictest sense of
the term. But in Stoicism the individual is not
nearly so sharply opposed to the outer world as in
Cynicism, The Stoic is too cultivated ; he knows
too well that he is a part of the universe to ignore
the value of an intellectual view of the world, or to
neglect the natural conditions of moral action, as
things of no moment. What he aims at is not only
a negation independence from externals but a
positive position life according to nature and ;

that life only he considers according to nature which


is in harmony with the laws of the universe as well
as with those of human nature. Hence Stoicism is

' Aristo cannot, therefore, he only represents a reaction


be considered (as he is by of the Cynic element in Stoicism
Krisahe, Forsch. 411) the best against the other component
representative of the original parts of this philosophy.
Stoic theory. On the contrry,
599 TEE STOICS.

Chap. not only far in advance of Cynicism by its intellec-

!_ tual attitude, but its moral philosophy also breathes


a freer and milder spirit. How deep-seated the dif-
ference between the two systems is, and how little

Stoicism can be deduced from Cynicism as a philo-


sophic system, will be at once seen; let only the
principles of the Stoics on the necessity and value of
scientific knowledge be compared with the sophis-
tical assertions of Antisthenes, destructive of all

knowledge; or the cultivated logical form of the


intellectual edifice of the Stoics, with the chaotic
condition of Cynic thought or the careful metaphy-
;

sical and psychological researches and the copious


learning of the School of Chrysippus, with the Cynic
contempt for all theory and all learned research.
In ethics, too, the difference of the two Schools
is also fully apparent. Stoic morality recognises, at
least conditionally, a positive and negative value in
external things and circumstances ; the Cynic allows
absolutely no value. The former forbids affection
contrary to reason, the latter any and every kind of
affection.' The former throws back the individual
upon human society, the latter isolates him. The
former teaches citizenship of the world in a positive
sense, requiring all to feel themselves one with their
fellow-men ; the latter in the negative sense, of feel-
ing indifferent to home and family. The former has
a pantheistic tone about it, due to the lively feeling
of the connection between man and the universe,
and a definite theological stamp owing to its taking a
' See p. 290.
;

RELATION TO PREVIOUS SYSTEMS. 391

stand by positive religion ; the latter has a ration- Chap.


alistic character, owing to the enfranchisement of
the wise man from the prejudices of popular be-
lief, with which it has exclusively to do. In all these
respects Stoicism preserved the original character of
the Socratic philosophy far better than Cynicism,
which only caricatured them. Still it departs from
that character in two respects. In point of theory
the Stoic doctrine received a systematic form and
development such as Socrates never contemplated
and in natural science, it cultivated a field avoided
by Socrates on principle, however much its doctrine
of Providence, and its view of nature as a system of
means subordinated to ends, may remind of Socrates.
On the other hand, interest in science, although
limited to the subject of ethics, is with Socrates far
deeper and stronger than with the Stoics, the latter
only pursuing scientific research as a means for solv-
ing moral problems. Hence the Socratic theory of
a knowledge of conceptions, simple though it may
sound, contained a fruitful germ of unexpanded spe-
culations, in comparison with which all that the
Stoics did is comparatively fragmentary. The Stoic
ethics are not only more expanded and more care-
fully worked out in detail than those of Socrates, but
they are also more logical in clinging to the prin-
ciple of regarding virtue alone as an unconditional
good. There are no concessions to current modes of
thought, such as those of Socrates, who practically
based his doctrine of morals upon utility. On the
other hand, the moral science of the Stoics also falls
392 THE STOICS.

Chap. far short of the frankness and cheerfulness of the Socra-


1_ tic view of life. If in many respects it toned down the
asperities of Cynicism, still it appropriated its lead-
ing principles far too unreservedly to avoid accepting
a great number of its conclusions.
(2) Rela- Asking in the next place in how far the Stoics were

Meganans ii^duced by other influences to change and extend


and He- the platform of the Socratic philosophy, we have for

the practical tendency of their system, besides the


general tendency of the post- Aristotelian philosophy,
only to think of the example of Cynicism. Its spe-
culative development, on the other hand, is partly
connected with the Megarians, partly with Hera-
clitus to the Megarians the personal connection of
;

Zeno with Stilpo points, to Heraclitus the fact that


from him the Stoics themselves deduced their views
on natural science, unfolding them in commentaries
on his writings.'
(ffi) The Probably the Megarian influence must not be
Mega-
rians. rated too high. Zeno may have thence received
an impulse to that reasoning tone of mind which
appears with him in a preference for compressed
sharp-pointed syllogisms ;
^ but in post-Aristote-

' Apart from the testimony mentionstreatisesof Cleanthes,


of Numenins (in Eus. Pr. Ev. vii. 174 ix. 15, of Aristo.ix. 5,
;

xiv. 5, 10), to which no great of Sphterus (vii. 178 ix. 15) ;

value can be attached, the ac- treating of Heraclitus and ;

quaintance of Zeno with Hera- Phocdiiis (Philodem.), Fragm.


clitus is established by the fact col. 4, says that Chrysippus ex-
that not only the ethics, but plained the old myths after the
also the natural science of the manner of Heraclitus.
Stoic school owes
origin to
its Instances have often oc-
-

him. See pp. 40, 3 ; 62, 2, 3 ;


curred. See p. 144, 4 145, 1, ;

126, 2 141, 2 ; 144, 4


; 145, 1, ; 2 ;232, 4. Conf. Sen. En.
2 ; 146, 4 148, 2 ; 151, 1. Diog.
; 83, 9.
RELATION TO PREVIOUS SYSTEMS. 893

lian times, contact witli Megarians was no longer Chap.


XIV.
wanted for this, and the greatest reasorier among the
Stoics, Chrysippus, appears not only in no personal
relations to them, but his logic is throughout a
simple continuation of that of Aristotle.
Far greater, and more generally recognised, is the (*) Jlera-
clitiis.
importance of the influence which the doctrines of
the natural philosopher of Ephesus exercised on the
Stoics. A system which laid such emphasis on the
subordination of everything individual to the law
of the universe, which singled out universal reason
from the flux of things as the one thing everlastingly

and permanently the same a system, too, so nearly
must have strongly commended
related to their own,
itself to their notice, and offered them many points
with which to connect their own. If the view of
this teaching, that life is dependent for its existence
on matter, is repulsive to us, it was otherwise to the
Stoics, for whom this very theory possessed special
attractions. Hence, with the exception of the three-
fold division of the elements, there is hardly a single
point in the Heraclitean theory of nature which the
Stoics did not appropriate :
fire or ether as the
primary element, the oneness of this element with
universal reason, the law of the universe, destiny,
God, the flux of things, the gradual change of the
primary element into the four elements, and of these
back to the primary element, the regular alternation
of creation and conflagration in the world, the one-
ness and eternity of the universe, the description of
the soul as fiery breath, the identification of the
394 THE STOICS.

Chap, mind with the demon, the unconditional sovereignty



-<
^
XIV
of the universal law over individuals these and
many other points in the Stoic system, originally
derived from Heraclitus,' prove how greatly this
system is indebted to its predecessor.
Nor yet must it be forgotten that neither is there
any analogy in Heraclitus to the reasoning forms of
the Stoics, nor can their ethical views be referred to
his few and undeveloped hints. Moreover, with all
the importance attached to natiiral science, it is with
the Stoics only subordinate to moral science ; and
the very fact that it is referred to Heraclitus as its

author, proves how subordinate a position it held,


and the want of any independent interest in the sub-
ject. Unmistakeable it also is that even in natural
science the Stoics only partially follow Heraclitus,
and that principles taken from Heraclitus often bear
an altered meaning when wrought into the Stoic
system. Omitting minor points, not only is the
Stoic doctrine of nature in a formal point of view
far more developed, and with regard to its extension,
far more comprehensive, than the corresponding doc-
trine of Heraclitus, but the whole view of the world
of the later system is by no means so completely
identical with that of the earlier as might be sup-
posed. The flux of things, which the Stoics teach
equally with Heraclitus,'' has not for them that over-
whelming importance that it had for him. The
' Besides meteorological Heraclitus' attitude towards
and other points of natural the popular faith also belongs
science, which the Stoics may here,
have borrowed from Heraclitus, ' See p. 101, 2.
RELATION TO PREVIOUS SYSTEMS. 396

matter of which the universe consists may be always Ohap.


'

going ovfer into new forms, but, at the same time, it

is for them the permanent material and essence


of things.' Individual substances, too, are treated
by the Stoics as corporeally permanent.^ Moreover,
from the material they distinguish the active prin-
ciple, Eeason or deity, far more definitely than Hera-
clitus had done, and the same distinction is carried
into individual things in contrast between matter
and quality. Thereby it becomes possible for them
to contrast much more sharply than their predeces-
sor had done the reason of the world, and the blindly
working power of nature. Heraclitus, it would ap-
pear, confined his attention to observing nature and
describing its elementary meteorological processes.
But the natural science of the Stoics embodies the
idea of means working for ends. It sees its object
in referring the whole arrangement of the world to
man, and it pursues this line of thought exclusively,
neglecting in consequence proper science. Hence
the idea of sovereign reason or the universal law had
not the same meaning in the minds of both. Hera-
clitus sees this reason, primarily and chiefly, in the
ordinary sequence of natural phenomena, in the re-
gularity of the course by which to each individual
phenomenon its place in the world, its extent and
duration is prescribed, in short, in the unchanging
coherence of nature. Without excluding this aspect

'
See p. 160, 4, 5; 101, 2; statement of the daily extinction
140, 1. of tlie sun, which every one
2 As an illustration of the must admit would not have
difference, take Heraclitus' been possible in the Stoicschool.
396 THE STOICS.

Chap. in their proofs of the existence of God and the rule


XIV. '.

of Providence, the Stoics attach the chief importance


to the serviceableness of the order of nature. The
reason which rules the world appears in Heraclitus
more as a natural power ; in the Stoics, as intelli-
gence working with a purpose. For Heraclitus
Nature is the highest object, the object of indepen-
dent and absolute interest and hence the infinite
;

Being is no more than the power which forms the


world. The Stoics regard nature from the platform
of humanity, as a means for the weUbeing and ac-
tivity of man. Their deity accordingly does not work
as a simplepower of nature, but essentially as the
wisdom which cares for the wellbeing of man. The
highest conception in the system of Heraclitus is

that of nature or destiny. Stoicism accepted this


conception also, but at the same time developed it

to the higher idea of Providence.


(3) Con- Shall we be wrong if we attribute this modifica-

^mithlris- ^^^'^ ^ ^^ Heraclitean theory of nature by the Stoicsi


totle. partly to the influence of Socrates' and Plato's theory
of final causes, but in a still greater degree to the
influence of the Aristotelean philosophy? To Aris-
totle belongs properly the idea of matter without
qualities, no less than the distinction between a ma-
terial and a formal cause. Aristotle applied the
idea of purpose to natural science far more exten-
sively than any other system had done before ; and
although the mode in which the Stoics expressed
this idea has more resemblance to the popular theo-
logical statements of Socrates and Plato than to
RELATION TO PREVIOUS SYSTEMS. 397

Aristotle, still the Stoic conception of a natural Chap,


power working with a purpose, such as is contained '.

in the idea of artificial fire and 'Ko'yoi, crTrsp/MaTiKol,

is essentially Aristotelean. Even many positions


which appear to be advanced in opposition to Aris-
totle were yet connected with him. Thus the exist-
ence of ether as a body distinct from the four ele-
ments is denied, and yet in point of fact it is asserted

under a new name that of artificial fire. The Peri-
patetic doctrine of the origin of the rational soul is

contradicted by the Stoic theory of development,


and yet the latter is based on a statement in Aris-
totle to the effect that the germ
of the animal soul
lies in the warm air^ which surrounds the seed, warm
air which Aristotle distinguishes from fire quite as
carefully as Zeno and Cleanthes distinguished the
two kinds of fire. Even the point of greatest diverg-

ence from Aristotelean teaching the transformation
of the human soul and the divine spirit into some-
thing corporeal might yet be connected with Aris-
totle, and, indeed, the Peripatetic School here meets
them for this very reason. Had not Aristotle de-
scribed the ether as the most divine body, the stars
formed out of it as divine and happy beings ? Had
he not brought down the acting and moving forces
from a heavenly sphere to the region of earth ? Had
he not, as we have just seen, sought the germ of the
soul in an ethereal matter ? And might not others
go a little further and arrive at materialistic views ?
and all the more so, seeing how hard it is to conceive

' irvtC/ia as with the Stoics.


)8 THE STOICS.

Chap, the extra-mundane intelligence of Aristotle, at once


"
incorporeal, and yet touching and encircling the
world of matter, and in the human soul to harmo-
nise personal unity with an origin in a reason coming
from above ?
More directly had the Aristotelean speculations as

to the origin of notions and conceptions paved the


way for Stoicism. On this point the Stoics did little
more than omit (in conformity with their principles)
what their predecessor had said as to an original pos-
session and immediate knowledge of truth. How
closely their formal logic adhered to that of Aristotle
has been remarked on an earlier occasion. Their
efiforts were confined to building on Aristotelean
foundations, and even their additions have more re-
ference to grammar than to logic. The actual influ-
ence of Peripatetic views on those of the Stoics
appears to have been least in the domain of ethics.
Here the crudeness of the Stoic conception of vir-
tue, their entire suppression of emotions, their abso-
lute exclusion of everything external from the circle

of moral goods, their antithesis between the wise and


the foolish man, their polemic against a purely spe-
culative life, present a pointed contrast to the caution
and many-sidedness of Aristotle's moral theory, to
his careful weighing of current opinions and the pos-
sibility of carrying them out, to his recognition of
propriety in every shape and form, on the one hand,
and to the praise which he lavishes on a purely spe-
culative life, on the other. In ethics, the formal
treatment of the ethical materials and the psycholo-
RELATION TO PREVIOUS SYSTEMS. 399

gical analysis of individual moral faculties, are the Chap.


chief points on which the Stoics are indebted to '__

Aristotle for instruction. On the other hand, in


this province we must, on the contrary, look for
traces of the teaching which Zeno received from
Polemo, and, perhaps, from Xenocrates.
The speculative portions of Plato's teaching could (4) Con-

offer no great attractions to such practical men and ^^;^


materialists as the Stoics, either in their original PT'do.
form or in the form which they assumed in the older
Academy under Pythagorean influence. But, on the
other hand, such points in Platonism as the Socratic
building of virtue on knowledge, the comparative
depreciation of external goods, the retreat from sen-
suality, the elevation and the purity of moral ideal-
ism, and, in the older Academy, the demand for life
according to nature, the doctrine of the self-sufficing-
ness of virtue, and the growing tendency to confine
philosophy to practical issues all these were ques-
tions for a Stoic full of interest. Unfounded as the
notion of the later Eclectics is,' that the Stoic and
Academician systems of morality were altogether the
same, the Stoics, nevertheless, appear to have re-
ceived impulses from the Academy which they car-
ried out in a more determined spirit. Thus the
theory of living according to nature belongs origi-
nally to the Academy, although the Stoics adopted
it with a peculiar and somewhat different meaning.

Besides moral doctrines, the attitude assumed by the

'
So particularly Antiochus and also Cicero in many pas-
sages. See above, p. 39, 2.
400 THE STOICS.

Chap, olderAcademy towards positive religion may also


L_ have had some influence on the orthodoxy of the
Stoics, their most decided representative, Cleanthes,
being in his whole philosophic character the coun-
terpart of Xenocrates. Nor was the new Academy,
although later in its origin than Stoicism, without
important influence on that system, through the per-
son of Chrysippus, but at first only of an indirect
kind, obliging the Stoics by its logical contradiction
to look about for a more logical basis for their sys-
tem, and therewith to attempt a more systematic
expansion of their teaching.' Somewhat similar is
the case with Epicureanism, which by its strong op-
position in the field of ethics contributed to impart
decision and accuracy to the Stoic doctrine, and,
perhaps, in the same way, may have helped to bring
it into existence,

c. The By the aid of these remarks it now becomes pos-


'^i"}!' , sible to give
o a satisfactory
J account of the history
J of
plnlosopMj
asawJtole. Stoicism. Belonging to an age morally debased and
(1) Its politically oppressed, its founder, Zeno, conceived the

jwsitiou. idea of liberating himself and all who were able to


follow him from the degeneracy and slavery of the
age by means of a philosophy which, by purity and
strength of moral wUl, would procure independence
from all external things, and unruffled inward peace.
That his endeavours should have taken this practical
turn, thathe should have proposed to himself not
knowledge as such, but the moral exercise of know-
ledge as the object to be realised, was in part due to

" See p. 46, 1, 2.


STOIC PHILOSOPHY AS A WHOLE. 401

the personal character of the philosopher, and may Chap.


he in part referred to the general circumstances of 1_
the times. On nobler and more serious minds, these
circumstances pressed too heavily not to call forth

opposition and resistance in place of listless contem-


plation. The sway of the Macedonian, and after- -

wards of the Eoman Empire, was far too despotic to

allow the least prospect of open resistance. Nor must


it be overlooked that philosophy itself had reached a
pass at which satisfactory answers to speculative
problems were no longer forthcoming, and hence
attention was naturally directed to questions of
morals.
Haunted by this longing for virtue, Zeno must
have first felt attracted by that philosophy which had
at an earlier period cultivated a similar line with the
greatest decision, the Cynical, and what he doubtless
identified with the Cynical, the old Socratic teaching.'
Anxious, on the other hand, for a more positive mean-
ing and Scientific basis for virtue, he strove to appro-
priate from every system whatever agreed with the
bent of his own mind. By using all the labours of
his and keeping his eye steadily fixed
predecessors,
upon the practical end of philosophy, he succeeded
in forming a new and more comprehensive system,
which was afterwards completed by Chrysippus. In
point of form this system was most indebted to the
' The story in Diog. vii. 3, thought, was referred to Crates,
bears out this view, that Zeno According to the quotations on
was first won for philosophy by pp. 274, 2 387, 1, the Cynics
;

Xenophon's Memorabilia, and were regarded in the Stoic


that on asking who was the school as genuine followers of
representative of this line of Socrates.
D D
03 THE STOICS.

Chap. Peripatetic philosophy ; in point of matter, next to


'
its debt to the Cynics, -which has been already men-
tioned, its chief obligation was to Heraclitus. But
the- moral theory of the Stoics was as little identical
with that of the Cynics, as the natural science of the
Stoics was with that of Heraclitus. If the diverg-
ence was, in the first instance, due to the influence
of the Stoic principles, still the influence of the Peri-
patetic teaching is unmistakeable in the natural and
speculative science of the Stoics, and the influence
of the Academy in their moral science. Stoicism
does not, therefore, appear simply as a continuation
of Cynicism, nor yet as an isolated innovation, but like
every other form of thought which marks an epoch,
it worked up into itself all previous materials, pro-

ducing from their combination a new result. In this


process of assimilation much that was beautiful and
full ofmeaning was omitted everything was absorbed
;

that could be of use in the new career on which the


Greek mind was about to enter.
2)Aiiojie- It was the fault of the age that it could no longer
""'*
"
come up to the many-sidedness of an Aristotle or a
Plato. Stoicism, it is true, approximates thereto
more nearly than any other of the post-Aristoteleau
systems. But in its practical view of philosophy, in
its materialistic appeal to the senses, in its theo-
retical self-sufficiency, the wise man rising superior
to the weaknesses and wants of human nature ; in its
citizenship of the world, throwing political interests
into the background ; and in so many other traits it

is the exponent of an epoch in which the taste


fit

for purely scientific research and the joy fulness of


STOIC PHILOSOPHY AS A WHOLE. 403

practical creation was at an end, whilst amid the Chap.


XIV
overthrow of and their freedom, the idea of
states, L_
humanity was rising to fuller recognition. Of such
an age Stoicism represented most powerfully the
moral and religious convictions, yet not without one-
sidedness and exaggeration. By an exercise of the
will and by rational understanding, man is to become
free and happy. This aim was, however, pursued with
such sternness that the natural conditions of human
existence and the claims of individuality were ignored.
To man, regarded as the organ of universal law, as
little freedom of will was allowed by the Stoic natu-
ral science in face of the inexorable course of nature
as freedom of action by the Stoic ethics in face of the
demands of duty. The universal claims of morality
were alone acknowledged ; the right of the indi-
vidual to act according to his peculiar character,
and to develop that character, was as good as ignored.
'

The individual, as such, dwindled into obscurity, V


whilst a high place in the world was assigned to
mankind collectively. The individual was subor-
dinated to the law of the whole, but by regarding
nature as a system of means and ends, and intro-
ducing the belief in Providence and Prophecy, the
universe was again subordinated to the interests of

man a view against which a more careful research
has many objections to urge. In both respects Epi-
cureanism is most decidedly contrasted with Stoicism,
whilst it otherwise agreed with it in the general tone of

its practical philosophy, and in its aim to make man


independent of the outer world and happy in himself.
D D 2
,

PART III.

TEE EPICUREANS.

CHAPTEE XV.
EPICURUS AND THE EPICDEEAN SCHOOL.'

Chap. Epicurus, the son of the Athenian Neocles,^ was


XV.
born in Samos ^ in the year 342 or 341 B-C* His
A. Jipi- early education appears to have been neglected ; ''

' Consult, on this subject, curus. It was observed (Epi-


the valuable treatise of Stein- curus' Diog. 18) r^irporipa
-will,
hart, in Ersch and Gruber's ScKcirT?Tov ra/n]\twvos. Game-
Encyclopasdia, sect. i. vol. 35, lion being the seventh month
pp. 459-477. of the Attic year, the time of
^ Diog. X. i. He is fre- his birth must have been either
quently mentioned as an Athen- early in 341 B.C., or the last
ian, belonging to the S^os days of 342 B.C.
Gai^ttos. JMog. 1. c. Lucret.
;
' His father, according to

Nat. Eer. vi. 1 Cic. Ad Fam.


; Strabo, was a schoolmaster,
XV. 16 ; JEUan, V. H. iv. 13. and Epicurus had assisted
' Diog. i. ;Strata, xiv. 1 him in teaching (Hermippus
18, p. 638. According to these and Timon, in Diog. 2 ; Athen.
authorities, and Oic. N. D. i. xiii. 588, a). His mother is
26, 72, his father had gone said to have earned money by
there as a xhiipovxos. That repeating charms (Kaflopjuol),
this happened before his birth and Epicurus to have assisted
has been demonstrated by in this occupation (^Diog^ 4)
Steinhwrt, p. 461. Although the latter statement
* Apollodorus (in Diog. x. evidently comes from some
14) mentions 7 Gamelion, 01. hostile authority, it would seem
109, 3, as the birthday of Epi- that his circumstances in early
;

EPICURUS. 40a

and his knowledge of previous philosophic systems Chap.


XV.
was very superficial, even at the time when he first
came forward as an independent teacher. Still he
can hardly have been so entirely self-taught as he
wished to appear at a later period in life. The
names, at least, of the individuals are on record
who him in the systems of Democritus
instructed
and Plato and although it is by no means an
;
'

ascertained fact that he subsequently attended the


lectures of Xenocrates,^ on the occasion of a visit
to Athens,' no doubt can be felt that he was

life were not favourable to a made himself what he was


thoroughly scientific education. without a teacher, and refused
His language in disparagement to own his obligations to those
of culture would lead us to this shown to be his teachers. Oie.
conclusion, even were the ex- N. D. i. 26, 72; 33, 93; Seict.
press testimony of Sext. Math, Math. i. 2, who mentions his
i. 1, wanting iv iroWois yap
: disparagement of Nausiphanes
afiaO^s 'EiriKOvpos eA7X6Ta(, oiide JMoff. 8, 13 JPlut. N. P. Suav.
;

iv Tois KOLfois &fii\iats (in com- V. 18, 4 conf. Sen. Ep. 52, 3.
;

mon expressions, conf. the cen- It is, however, established that


sure passed on him by Dionysius in his youth he enjoyed the in-
of Halicarnassus and Aristo- struction of Pamphilus and of
phanes in Dioff. i, 13) KoBctpeiai'. that Nausiphanes, who is some-
do. Fin. i. 7, 26: Vellem times called a follower of De-
equidem, aut ipse doctrinis mocritus, sometimes of Pyrrho
fuisset instructior est enim (Cic. Sea!t.;I)wg.:K.8; 13; 14;
i

. . non satis politus in artibus,


. ix. 64 69 ; Procem. 15 ; Smd.
;

quas qui tenent eruditi appel- 'EiriK. Clem. Strom, i. 301, d).
;

lantur aut ne deterruisset The names of two other sup-


alios a studils. Athen. xiii. 588, posed instructors are also men-
a : iyKVK\lou iratdelas &,(i6ijros &v. tioned, Nausicydes and Praxi-
' According to his own phanes (^Diog. Procem. 15 x. ;

statement (^IHog. 2), he was not 13), but they almost seem to
more than fourteen (Smd. 'Ettuc. be corruptions for Pamphilus
has twelve) years of age when and Nausiphanes.
2 According to Oio. 1. c, he
he began to philosophise, i.e.,
to think about philosophical denied the fact. Others, how-
subjects probably about chaos
;
ever, asserted it, and, among
following the suggestion of them, Demetrius of Magnesia.
Hesiod's verses. He subse- Uiog. 13.
quently boasted that he had " Whither he came, in his
THE EPICUREANS.
Chap. acquainted with the writings of previous philoso-
XV.
phers, from whom he borrowed important parts of
his doctrine,' and, more particularly, with those of
Democritus.
After having been active as a teacher in several
Schools 2 in Asia Minor, he repaired to Athens about
the year 306 and there founded a School of his
b,c.,*

own.^ The meeting-place of this School was the


founder's garden ,5 and its centre of attraction was

eighteenth year, according to mocritus. Zucret. iii. 370, v.


Heraclides Lembus, in JXog. 1. 620, also speaks of Democritus
Conf. Strabo, 1. c. Tpa<prjvii : with great respect and Philo- ;

<l>a<Tiv ivOdSe (in Samos) ical iv dem,.De Mus. Vol. Here. i. col.
36, calls him
a,v-hp oh (pvffiohoyw-

According to Hermippus
' TttTOS fx6v0V TOiV &pxoLio>v dAAct
(Dioff. 2)Democritus first gave Kol TWV IffTopOV^eVOtV OuBevhs TJT-
him the impulse to pursue TQv voKinrpiyfjLwv.
philosophy but this is only a
; ^ Diog. 1, 15, mentions Colo-

conjecture. Besides Democri- phon, Mytilene,and Lampsacus.


tus, Aristippus is also men- Strabo, xiii. 1, 19, p. 589, also
tioned as a philosopher whose affirms that Epicurus resided for
doctrines he followed (^Diog. 4). some time at Lampsacus, and
Epicurus is even said to have there made the acquaintance
expressed a disparaging opinion of Idomeneus and Leonteus.
of Democritus (^Cie. JS. D. i. ' Diog. 2, on the authority

33, 93 ; JOiog. 8). Nor is this of Heraclides and Sotion. Ac-


denied by Diog. 9 but it pro- ; cording to him, Epicurus re-
bably only refers to particular turned to Athens in the archon-
points, or it may have reference ship of Anaxicrates, 307-6 B.C.
to the attitude of later Epi- In that case the numbers must
cureans, such as Golotes {Ptut. be slightly reduced in the state-
Adv. Col. 3, 3, p. 1108). Plat. ment (^Diog. 15) that he came
1. c, says, not only that Epi- to Mytilene when 32, and taught
curus for a long time called there and in Lampsacus for
himself a follower of Demo- five years.
critus, but he also quotes pas- * Not immediately, how-
sages from Leonteus and Me- ever, since Diog. 2, says, on the
trodorus, attesting Epicurus' authority of Heraclides : lue'xpi
respect for Democritus. Philo- /ie'i/ Tivos kut' ^iri/jLi^iav to7s &\-
dem. irep\ ira^^jifftas, Vol. Here. \ots <pi\0(rotl>f'iy, 6iriT' i5f^ ttojs

V. 2, col. 20, seems to refer to r^v OTT* ouToC KKttdetiTav aXp^aiv


expressions of Epicurus, excul-
pating certain mistakes of De- " On this celebrated garden,
;

EPICURUS. 407

the founder himself, around whom a circle of friends Chap.


XV.
gathered, knit together by a common set of prin-
ciples, by a common affection for a master whom
they almost worshipped, and by a common enjoyment
of cultivated society.' Opponents charged the Epicu-
reans with gross impropriety, because they admitted
not only women,^ but women of loose morality,^ to
this circle of philosophic culture ; but in the then
state of Grreek society, such conduct does not appear
extraordinary. Here Epicurus laboured for six and
thirty years, and in this time succeeded in impres-
sing such a definite stamp on his School as is now
seen unchanged after the lapse of centuries. In
the year 270 b-C* he succumbed to disease, the pains
and troubles of which he bore with great fortitude.*

Out of the multitude of his writings ^ only a few have

after which the Epicureans ( C?o. N. D. i. 33, 93 P&i. Hist,


;

were cailed ol orri twi/ Kii-naiv, Nat. Praef. 29). Conf. IHog. 5;
see Diog. 10, 17 Plin. H. N. ; Philodem. irepl iro/S^Tjir/as, Vol.

xix. 4, 51 ; Cie. Fin. i. 20, 65 ;


Here. v. 2, Fr. 9. Athen. xiii.
V. 1, 3 ; Ad Fam. Sen. xiii. 1 ; 593, b, tells a fine story of self-
Ep. 21, 10; Steinha/rt, p. 462, sacrifice of her daughter Danafi.
45 463, 72.
; Epicurus had * 01. 127, 2, in the archon-

purohased it for 80 minas. ship of Pytharatus, and in his


'
This subject will be dis- seventy-second year. Diog. 15
cussed at a later period. Cic. De
Fat. 9, 19.
2 Such as Themista or The- Diog. 15
= 22 ; ; Cfio. Ad
misto, the wife of Leonteus Fam. vii. 26 Fin. ; 30, 96 ;
ii.

{Diog. 5 ; 25 26 Clem. Strom.


; ; Sen. Ep. 66, 47 ; 92, 25. That
iv. 522, D). he put an end to his own life
' Diog. 4 6 ; 7 Cleomed. ; ; {Baumhaiier, Vet. Philo. Doot.
Meteor, p. 92, Balfor. ; Plut. De Mort. Volunt. 322), Hermip-
N. P. Suav. Vivi. 4, 8 ; 16, 1 and pus {Diog. 15) by no means
6 ; Lat. Viv. 4, 2. The best- implies.
known among these Iraiiooi is According to Diog. Pro.
'

Leontion, who lived with Me- he was, next to Chrys-


16, x. 26,
trodorus, a pupil of Epicurus ippus, the most voluminous
{Diog. 6 23), and wrote with
;
writer of the ancient philoso-
spirit against Theophrastus phers, his writings filling 300
;; '

THE EPICUREANS.
Chap. come down to us, and these are for the most part
XV. ^
unimportant ones.' On the whole, these fragments
bear out the unfavourable opinions which opponents
expressed with regard to his style.^
Among the numerous scholars of Epicurus ^ the
best known are Metrodorus,^ and Polyaenus,* both of

rolls. The titles of his most Greece, however, on Ms own


esteemed works are giyen by testimony, and that of Metro-
Diog. 27. Conf. Fdbnc. Bibl. dorus {Sen. Bp. 79, 15), they
Grse. iii. 595, Harl. attracted little notice.
Three epistles in IDUig. 35
' ' A native of Lampsacus
81 122 and the Kipicu S6^ai,
; ; (Straio, xiii. 1, 19, p. 589), and,
an epitome of his ethics, men- next to Epicurus, the most
tioned by ac. N. D. i. 30, 85, celebrated teacher of the School.
and 139. Of his 37 books irepl (Kcero, Fin. ii. 28, 92, calls him
ipiiretiis, fragments of books 2 psene alter Epicurus, and states
and 11 have been edited (Vol. (Fin. ii. 3, 7) that Epicurus
Hercnl. ii.). gave him the name of a wise
^ Fra.gments in JHog. 5 7. ; man {Diog. 18 Sen. Ep. 52, 3).
;

Besides the testament and the Further particulars respecting


letter to Idomeneus {Diog. 16- him and his writings in Diog.
22), many individual expres- X. 6 ; 18 ; 21-24 ; Phihdem. De
sions of Epicurus have been Vitiis, ix. (Vol. Here, iii.), col.
preserved by Seneca. 12 21
; ;27 Atlieii. vii. 279 ;
;

' Aristophanes (in Diog.


13) Plut. N. P. Suav. Vivi. 7, 1;
calls his style iSnoTiKoiraTT). 12, 2; 16, 6 and 9; Adv. Col.
Cleomed. Meteor, p. 91, com- 3.3, 2 and 6; Sen. Ep. 98, 9;

plains of his awkwaid and bar- 99, 25. Fragments of the letters
barous expressions, instancing are to be found in Plutarch,
ffapKbs tvffTaOTi KaiafTTTitiaTa' to Seneca, and Philodemus. Whe-
.Trepl Tairris iritTTCi iXirifffxaTa' ther the fragments of a treatise
\nrd,iTfJi.a o(p9a\fl5iv^ Upai &vaKpav- irfpl aXaBifiToiv in Vol. vi. of Vol.
ydtTfJiaTa' yapyaXirr/xovs fftiifiaros. Heroul. belong to him, is very
In this respect, Chrysippus may uncertain. According to Diog.
be compared with him. See 23, he died seven years before
above, p. 48, 1. Epicurus, in his lifty-third
See FabHo. Bib. Gr. iii.
' year, and must therefore have
598 Harl. They were, no doubt, been born 830 or 329 B.C. For
very numerous. Diog. x. 9, the education of his children
probably exaggerates theirnum- probably by Leontion, whom
ber in saying the friends of Diog. 23 calls waWoK^, and
Epicurus would fill towns. CKo. Sea. Fr. 45 in Siern. Adv. Jovin.
Fin. i. 20, 65, speaks of magni i. 191 calls his wife, provision

greges amioorum. Plut. Lat. is made by Epicurus in his


Viv. 3, 1, also mentions his will {Diog. 19, 21).
friends in Asia and Egypt. In ' Son of Athenodorus, like-
;

SCHOLARS OF EPICURUS. 409

whom died before their master ; Hermarchus,' upon Chap.


XV.
whom the presidency of the School devolved after
the death of Epicurus ;
^ and Colotes,' against whom
Plutarch, four hundred years later, wrote a treatise.
Many others are also known, at least by name.'' The

wise a native of Lampsaous ' According to what is.


{Biog. 24), a capital mathema- stated in the testament of Epi-
tician, according to die. Acad, curus. Diog. 16.
it. 33, 106 Fin. i. 6, 20. Diog.
; " Colotes, a native of Lamp-

1. c, calls him 6TiiKJ)s koI ipiXii- saous. Dog. 25. I'urther par-
Koot Metrodorus, in PMlodem.
; ticulars about him may be ob-
irepl ira^priaias (Vol. Her. V. a), tained from Pkit. Adv. Col. 17,
col. 6, airotpOeyuttTLa^. Sen. Ep. 5 ; 1, 1 N. P. Suav. Viv. 1, 1
;
;

6, 6, calls him, Metrodorus and Mac7'ob. Somn. Scip. i. 2. Vol.


Hermarohus, viros magnos. Hercul. iv. Introd. in Polystor.
Philademm (Vol. v. b), Fr. 49, p. iii.
praises his frankness towards * In particular,
Keocles, Chai-
his teacher. A
son of his is redemus, and Aristobulus, the
also mentioned in Epicurus' brothers of Epicurus (Dog. 3,
will {D-iog. 19), whose mother 28 Pl-ut. N. P. Suav. Viv. 5, 3
; ;

would appear to have been a where 'Aya86pou\os is evidently


courtesan, according to Pint. a copyist's error; 16, 3; De
N. P. Suav. V. 16, 6. Lat. Viv. 3, 2) Idomeneus, a ;

' This individual's name, native of Lampsacus {Diog. 25 ;

formerly written Hermachus, 22 23 5 Pint. Adv. Col. 18,


; ; ;

appears as Hermarohus in the 3 ;Straio, xiii. 1, 19, p. 589 ;

modern editions of Diogenes, Atlien. vii. 279 PMlodem. irepi


;

Cicero and Seneca. The latter TTa^^-qa-ias. Pr. 72, Vol. Here. v.

form is now established beyond 2 Sen. Ep. 21, 3 and 7


; 22, 5 ; ;

doubt by the Heroulanian frag- Phot. Lex. and Hiiid. IliBia Kal
;

ments from Philodemus (irep! AfiXia),from whose historical


flewv SiaywT^Js, vol. vi. col. 13, writings many fragments are
20; De Vitiis Lx. vol. iii. col. quoted by Muller, Fragm. Hist.
25, 1), and the inscription on a Gr. ii. 489 Leonteus, likewise
;

monument him
(Antiquitat.
to a native of Lampsacus {Dog.
Hercul. V. 17). His birthplace 5 25; Pbit. Adv. Col. 3, 3
;
;

was Mytilene, Agemarchus be- Strabo, 1. c.) Herodotus {Diog.


;

ing his father, {Diog. 17, 15, 4 and 34) Pythocles {Diog. 5
;

24.) Diog. 24, gives a list of and 83 Plut. N. P. Suav. Vi.


;

his books. Epicurus {Dog. 20) 12, L; Adv. Col. 29, 2 P/dU- ;

describes him as one of his dem. irepl Tra^lnt^las, Fr. 6)


oldest and most faithful friends, Apelles {Plut. N. P. Suav. Vi.
in the words /lera toS avyxa-
: 12, 1); Menoeoeus {Dog. 121) ;

rayeyrjpaKdTOS ijfuv iv (piKoaoiplif. Nicanor {Diog. 20) Timocrates, ;

On his character, see Sen. Ep. the brother of Metrodorus, who


6, 6. afterwards fell out with Epi-
;;

410 THE EPICUREANS.


Chat. garden which Epicurus in his will left to the School'
XV.
continued after his death to be the external rallying-
point for his followers. Hermarchus was succeeded
by Polystratus,^ together with whom Hippoclides
is also naentioned^ as president. Hermarchus and .

Hippoclides were succeeded by Dionysius, and Dio-


nysius agairi by Basilides.'* Protarchus of Bargy-
curus (JKog. i and 6 23 and ; standing thereupon, and at
28 Cic. N. D. i. 33, 93 Plut.
; ; that time in ruins (parietinse),
N. P. Suav. Vivi. 16, 9 Adv. ; was in the hands of C. Mem-
Col. 32, 7 Comment, in SesioA.
; mius, a distinguished Roman,
Pr. 7, 1 Philodem.
; irepl Trapjn\- to whom Cicero wrote (Ad
fflas, Vol. Here. v. a, col. 20). Fam. xiii. 1), conf. Ad Att. v.
This Timoorates must not be 11, begging him to restore it
confounded with the Athenian to the School. "Whether he
Timocrates, whom Epicurus was successful is not known
appointed his heir, together from Sen. Ep. 21, 10.
with Amynomaohus {Dioq. 16 ' Diog. 25, does not say that

Cic. Fin. ii. 31, 101). Both the Polystratus was a personal dis-
latter were probably pupils of ciple of Epicurus, but it seems
Epicurus. Other names of pu- probable. Fragments of a
pils are Mithras, a Syrian,
: treatise of his xtpl a,\6yov Kara-
an official under Lysimaohus <^povi]iTfas in the fourth volume
{Diog. 4 and 28 Plut. Adv. ; of Vol. Hercul.
Col. 33, 2 N. P. Suav. Viv. 15, ' According to Valer. Max.
;

5) ; Mys, a slave of Epicurus, i. 8, ext. 17, both these indivi-

on whom he bestowed liberty duals were born on the same


iDiog. 21 3 ; 10 Gell. ii. 18,
; ; day, and passed their whole
8 ; Macrob. Sat. i. 11) the ; lives together with a common
ladies mentioned on p. 407, 2, 3 purse. Lysias, according to
likewise Anaxarchus, to whom the older text of Diog. x. 25,
Epicurus addressed a letter, and was a cotemporary, at whose
Timarchus, to whom Metro- house Hermarchus died, as
dorus addressed one {Phit, Adv. Falrio. Bibl. Gr. iii. 606 be-
Col. 17 3) Hegesianax, who ; lieves, and who is styled in
died early {Plut. N. P. Sua. Vi. Athen. v. 215, b, tyrant of Tar-
20, 5) the poet Menander,
; sus. Coiet, however, reads
wliose wondrous epigram on irapaXiaei instead of iroptk Av(rl:f.
Epicurus is to be found in the * Diog. 25. The Dionysius
anthology and probably Diony- ; referred to can hardly be Diony-
sius 6 jXiToSiiievos. (See above sius i lieraSefifvat (see p. 44,
p. 44, 1.) 1), or Diogenes would have
' Diog. 16. In Cicero's said so. Besides the chrono-
time, the plot of ground, to- logy forbids such an assump-
gether with the tenement tion.
THE ROMAN PERIOD. 411

Hum,' and his pupil, Demetrius the Laconian,'^ appear Chap.


to belong to the second century before Christ ; but the
time in which these philosophers flourished cannot
be established with certainty ; and the same remark
applies to several others whose names are on record.'
Before the middle of the second century B.C. C. Ej)i-
cwreans
Epicureanism is said to have obtained a footing in
of the
Rome.'* It is certain that it was existing there not Roman
period.
long after. C. Amafinius is mentioned as the first

who paved the way for the spread of Epicurean doc-


trines by discussing them in Latin ;
' and it is stated

' Stralo, mv. 2, 20, p. 658. * According to Athen. xii.


He probably the Protarohus
is 547, a JElian, V. H. ix. 12, two
whose sayings are quoted by Epicureans, Alcius and Philis-
Simpl. Phys. 78, a Themist. ; cus, were banished from Eome,
Phys. 27, a. in the consulate of L. Pos-
^ According to Strabo, 1. c, tumius (173 or 155 B.C. see ;

Diog. 26, Seict. Bmpir. Pyrrh. Clinton's Fasti), because of


iii. 137, Math. viii. 3iS, x. 219, their evil influence on youth.
Urotiam, Lex. Hippocr. K\ayy<i- Although the story is obviously
Sr), Demetrius was one of the taken from a hostile authority,
most distinguished Epicureans. in Suid. ('EirfKovpos, T. l,b, 419
"Whether a treatise on mathe- Bern. ) and is told with such ex-
matics, illegible fragments of aggerations as to inspire grave
which are found in Hercula-
mistrust it can hardly be alto-
num (Vol. Here. iv. Introd. in gether without some founda-
Polystr. iii. 2), is his, or belongs tion. Pint. N. P. Suav. V. 19,
to another Demetrius men- 4, says, that in some cities
tioned by Strabo, xii. 3, 16, severe laws were passed against
p. 548, it is impossible to say. the Epicureans, and just at
' Both the Ptolemies of that time there was a strong
Alexandria (^Diug. 25) Dio- ; feeling in Kome against inno-
genes of Tarsus {Biog. vi. 81 ;
vations, witness the well-known
X. 26; 97; 118; 136; 138); enquiry into the Bacchanalia
Orion {Diog. 26) Timagoras
; instituted 186 B.C.
((7ic. Acad. ii. 25, 80); and * According to Cic. Tusc.
also Metrodorus of Stratonice, iv. 3, 6, Amafinius seems to

who went over from Epicurus have come forward not long
to Cameades {Diog. 9) a very after the philosophic embassy
rare thing for an Epicurean to of 156, B.C. nor is this at
;


do may be named among his variance with Diicr. v. 336,
pupils. who claims primus cum primis
;

412 THE EPICUREANS.


Chap. that these doctrines soon found many -eupporterS,
XV.
attracted partly by more often by
their merits, but
the simplicity and the ease with which they could
be understood.'
Towards the close of the second century ApoUo-
dorus, one of the most voluminous writers on philo-
sophy, taught at Athens.'^ His pupil, Zeno of Sidon,
the most important among the Epicureans of that
age, laboured for a long time successfully, both orally
and in writing.^ About the same time Phsedrus is

to have set forth the Epicurean in Fin. 7, 25, the question :


i.

teaching in Latin. His works Cur tam multi sint Epicurei ?


made a great impression at the ^ Surnamed it KniroTipapvos,

time, according to Cic. 1. c. the writer of more than 400


(cujus libris editis commota books. Diog. 25 2 '13 ; vii.
; ;

multitudo contulit se ad earn 181.


potissimum disciplinam). Ac- ' Sioff. vii. 35, x. 25, and
cording to Acad. i. 2, 5, he Procl. in Mvolid. 55, say that
pmrsued natural science, care- Zeno was a native of Sidon,
fully following the views of and a pupil of ApoUodorus
Epicurus. Cicero then com- nor can these statements be re-
plains of him and Eabirius, ferred to an older Zeno, as some
we know not which one is previous writers maintained,
meant, nor whether he was an believing ApoUodorus to be
Epicurean, qui nulla arte ad- called in error a pupil of Epi-
liibita de rebus ante oculos curus by Diog. x. 25, instead of
positis vulgari sermone dis- to the one mentioned by Cicero.
putant nihil definiunt, nihil
: For no trace of such a one
partiuntur, &c. Couf. Tuso. ii. exists ; and Diogenes vii. 35
3, 7. Cassius, too (Cic. Ad would then have passed over
Fam. XV. 12), calls him and the teacher of Cicero without
Catius (see p. 414, 3) maU ver- notice who cannot possibly
borum interpretes. have been unknown to him.
' Cic. Tusc. iv. 3, 7: Post According to Oic. Acad. i. 12,
Amafinium autem multi ejus- 46, Zeno attended the lectures
dem ^rnuli rationis multa cum of Carneades and admired them
scripsissent, Italiam totam oc- and since Carneades died not
cupaverunt,quodquemaxumum later than 129 B.C., Zeno can-
argumentum est non dici ilia not have been bom much later
subtiliter, quod et tam facile than 150 B.C. If, therefore,
ediscantur et ab indoctis pro- Zeno was really the successor
beutur, id illi firmamentum of ApoUodorus, the latter must
esse disciplinae putant. Conf. be placed entirely in the second
;;;

THE ROMAN PERIOD. 413

heard of in Rome and Athens,'and at a little Chap.


XV.
later period Philodemus,^ and Syro or Sciro in
century. But this fact is not Pin. i. 5, 16 ; v. 1, 3 ; Legg. i.
sufBciently established. Cicero, 20, 53) had also studied under
in company with Attious, at- him in Athens, and previously
tended his lectures ( Oio. 1. c. in Rome, where Phsedrus must
Fin. i. 5, 16 Tusc. iii. 17, 38.
;
then have been residing (Ad
In Cic. N. D. i. 2], 58, Gotta Pam. xiii. 1). He was old
says the same of himself), on when Cicero had, for the second
his first visit to Athens, 78 to time, relations with him. Ac-
79 B.C. conf. N. D. i. 34, 93
; cording to Phlegon, in Plwt.
but this cannot possibly be the Bibl. Cod. 97, p. 84, a,, 17, he
same Zeno or Xeno (as however was succeeded by Patron (01.
Krisclte, Porsch. 26 maintains) 177, or 70 B.C.) in the head-
3,
whom Cic. Ad Att. v. 10, 11 ship of the School, after holding
xvi. 3 mentions as living in 50 it only for a very short time ;
and 43 B.C. Cic. N. D. i. 21, but this is not a well -ascertained
calls bim princeps Bpicureorum fact. Cicero, 1. c, praises the
(and Philo of Larissa, cory- character of Phasdrus. He calls
phaeus Epicureorum); Tusc. 1. c, him nobilisphilosophus (Philip.
acrioulus senex, istorum (Epi- V. 5, 13). It was supposed that
cureans) aoutissimus. IHog. x. Cicero's description (N.D. i. 10,
25, callshim iroxiypaipos iviip. 25 15, 41), and that the frag-
;

From Procl. in Ihwlid. 55 59 ; ; ments first published by Drum-


60, we hear of a treatise of mond (Heroulanensia London, :

Zeno, in which he attacked the 1810), and then by Petersen


validity of mathematical proofs. (Phsedri de Nat. De. . . .

J-hilodemus^ treatise -n-tpi i:a^^r\- Fragm. Hamb. 1833), and


:

o-los (Vol. Here. v. a) seems, illustrated by Krische (Por-


from the title, to have been an schungen), were from a treatise
abstract from Cotem-
Zeno. of Phsedrus on the Gods, to
porary with Zeno was that which perhaps do. Ad Att.
Aristio, or Athenio, who played xiii. 39 refers. But Spengel
a part in Athens during the (from the Heroulanean rolls,
Mithridatic war, and is some- Philodemus xcpl euirciScfas. Abh.
times called a Peripatetic, and d. Munch. Akad. Philos-philol.
sometimes an Epicurean {Phd. Kl. X. 1, 127) and Sauppe (De
Sulla, 12 14 23). See Zeller's
; ; Philodemi libro de pietate. . . .

Philosophic der Griechen, vol. Gott. Lections verz. fiir Som-


11. b, 759, 2. Perhaps to the mer, 1864) have shown that the
time of his despotism the state- Neapolitan (Vol. Hero. Coll.
ment may be referred {Deme- Alt. i. ii. 1862) editors are
trius Magnes in Athen. xiii. right in regarding these frag-
611, b) that the Stoic Theo- ments as the remains of a
timus, who wrote against Epi- treatise of Philodemus irspl
cureus, was killed at the instance
of Zeno. ^ Philodemus (see Vol,
' Cicero (N. D. i. 33, 93; Hero. i. 1 ; Ch-os, Philod. Rhet.
; ;

414 THE EPICUREANS.


Chap. Eome,' and Patro,* the successor of Phsedrus, in Athens.
XV.
The number of Epicureans at Eome, known to us
chiefly by Cicero's writings,' is not small, no one of
cxii.; Prellcr, Allg. Encyclc. Att. V. 11; vii. 2; Ad Quint.
Sect. HI. Bd. xxiii. 345) .was a Fratr. i. 2, 4, where besides
native of Gadara,in Coele-Syria him an Epicurean Plato of
(Strabo, xvi. 2, 29, p. 759). He Sardes is mentioned, and above
lived at Rome in Cicero's time, pp. 410, 1 ; 413, 1.
and is mentioned by Cicero as Besides ' Lucretius, the
a learned and amiable man most important among them
(Fin. ii. 3.3, 119 ; Or. in Pison. are T. Albutius, called by Oic.
28). Besides philosophic works, Brut. 35, 131, perfectus Epi-
be also wrote poems (Cio. In cureus (Cic. Brut. 26, 102;
Pis. ; Sat. i. 2, 121).
ffor. A Tusc. V. 37, 108 N. D. i. 33, :

number of the latter, in the 93 Fin. i. 3, 8 [De Orat. iii.


;

shape of epigrams, are pre- 43, 171] In Pison. 38, 92


;

served. Of his philosophical Offic. ii. 14, 50; Orator. 44,


works mentioned by Diog. x. 3 ;
149 In Caecil. 19, 63 Provin.
; ;

24, no fewer than thirty-six Cons. 7, 15; De Orat. ii. 70,


books were discovered in Her- 281), and Velleius, who, as
culaneum, which have, for the Kriaclie (Forsch. 20) proves, by
most part, been published (Vol. a gloss on Nat. De. i. 29, 82 and
Here. iv. Introd. in Polystr. iii. Cic. De N. D. i. 28, 79 (conf.
a portion of which have been Divin. i. 36, 79) was a native of
published). Spengel and Gros Lanuvium, and was considered
have separately edited Khet. the most distinguished Epi-
IV. Sauppe, De VitiisX. and
; ; curean of his time (Oie. N. D.
Petersen and Sauppe, the frag- i. 6, 15 ; 21, 58 ; conf. De Orat.
ments irepl ivffeSelas. 21, 78).
iii. Other Epicurean.3
' (Xo.Acad. ii. 33, 106 Fin. ; were C. Catius, a native of
:

ii. 85, 119; Ad Fam. vi. 11. Gaul, named by Cicero (Ad Fam.
According to Virgil, Catal. 7, 9 XV. 16) as one long ago dead.
10, 1, Donat. Vita Virg. 79, Seii). By Quintilian, x. 1, 124, he is
Ad Eel. vi. 13, ^H. vi. 264, he called levis quidem sed non
was the teacher of Virgil. The injucundus tamen auotor ; ani
name variously written as
is the Comment. Cruqu. iu Hck:
Syro, Siro, Sciro, Scyro. Some- Sat. ii. 4, 1, sS-ys that he wrote
what earlier is the grammarian four books De Rerum Natura et
Pompilius Andronicus, from De Summo Bono ; C. Cassius,
Syria, who, according to Sueton. the well-known leader of the
lllust. Gram. c. 8, lived at Rome conspiracy against Csesar {de.
at the same time as Gnipho, Ad Fam. xv. 16, 19; Plict.
the teacher of Cfesar (^Ibid. c. Brut. 37); C. Vibius Pansa,
7), neglecting his profession for who died as consul at Mutina,
the Epicurean philosophy, and in 43 B.C. {do. Ad Fam. vii. 12
afterwards at Cumae. XV. 19); GaUus (Ad Fam. vii.
' do. Ad Fam. xiii. 1 Ad ; 26) ; L. Piso, the patron oi'

THE ROMAN PERIOD. 415

whom has obtained a higher repute than T. Lucretius Chap.


XA'.
Carus.^ His poem, carefully reproducing the Epicu-
rean notions on natural science, is, therefore, one of
the most valuable sources for the knowledge of their
system. Contemporary with Lucretius was the cele-
brated physican Asclepiades of Bithynia,^ residing at
Eome, but to judge by the views on nature attri-

buted to him, no genuine Epicurean, although con-


nected with the Epicurean School.'
Philodemus ( Oic. in Pis. 28, see from the chief passage Ep. 25,
above, p. 41 3, 2 ; 1. c. 9, 20 16, ; or respecting C. Trebatius from
37; 18,42; 25, 59; Post Red. do. Ad Fam. vii. 12. C. Mem-
6, 14); Statilius (^Plnt. Brut. mius (from the way in which
12) a second Statilius appears
; he is spoken of Cic. Ad. Fam.
to be meant (Cat. Min. 65); xiii. 1) cannot be regarded as a
L. Manlius Torquatus, to whom member of the Epicvirean
Oio. Fin. i. 5, 13, delegates the School, although Lucret. De
representation of the Epi- Ker. Nat. i. 24 v. 9, expressed
;

curean teaching. Moreover, the hope of winning him.


T. Pomponius Atticns, the well- ' Born, according to Hieron.
known friend of Cicero, ap- (in Eus. Chron.), 95 B.C., he
proached nearest to the Epi- died in his 44th year, or 51
curean School, calling its B.C. In Vita Virgilii, 659
adherents nostri familiares ought therefore to be substi-
( Cie. Fin. v. 1, 3) and ooudis-
tuted for 699 A.u.c. It is clear,
cipuli (Leg. i. 7, 21), being a from Nepos, Att. 12, that he
pupil of Zeno and Phasdrus and was dead before the assassina-
a friend of Patro's but his re-
; tion of Csesar. Teuflel (in
lations to philosophy were too Pauly's Eealencycl. iv. 1195)
free to entitle him properly to justly disputes the statement of
be ranked in any one School Hieronymus, that he commit-
(Cic. Pam. xiii. 1). The same ted suicide in a fit of madness.
observation applies also to his According to Seat. Math,
*

friend, L. Saufeius {Nepos, vii. a ootemporary of An-


201,
Att. 12 ;do. Ad Att. iv. 6). tiochus of Ascalon, whose lan-
Still less can C. Sergius Grata guage towards him is there
(^Cic. Fin. ii. 22, 70 Ofe. iii. 16,
; quoted, and reckoned by Galmi.
67; De Orat. i. 39, 178), L. Isag. c. 4, vol. xiv. 683 among
Thorius Balbus (Fin. 1. c), and the leaders of the logical
Postumius (^lUd.) be called Schoolof Physicians. Hismedi-
Epicureans. Nor can anything cal treatises are often referred
be stated with certainty re- to by Galen. Plutarch in his
specting L. Papirius Psetus ( die. Placita often names him.
Ad Fam. vii. 17 to 26), not even ' Known for three things
;

416 THE EPICUREANS.


Chap. In the following century, too, several supporters of
XV.
the practical philosophy of the Epicureans are known
to us,' but no one apparently approaching Zeno or
his theory of atoms, his theory He differs, however, entirely
of the acquisition of knowledge, from Epicurus in denying the
and his resolution of the soul existence of a soul apart from
into matter. body, and in referring every
All bodies, he held, consist kind of notion, including the
of atoms, differing, however, soul itself, to the action of the
from the atoms of Demooritus senses {Sext. Math. vii. 380
in that they owe their origin Pint. Plac. iv. 2, 6; Ccel.
to the meeting and breaking up Atirelian. 1. c. in Fabric, on the
of greater masses, and are not passage of Sext. Tertullian, De
;

in quality alike and un- An. 15). All that is otherwise


changeable (aimiiis). Sext. stated of Asclepiades, apart
Pyrrh. iii. 32; Math. 363; ix. from his medical views, for
X. 318 ; viii. 220 iii. 5 Galen.
; ; instance, that with Heraclitus
1. c. 9, p. 698 Bionys. Alex,
; ; he believed in a perpetual flux
(in Mis. Pr. Ev. xiv. 23, 4); of things, is not at variance
Ccel. Aii/rsUan. De Pass. Acut. with Epicurean principles.
i. See Fabric, on Pyrrh.
14. 'Quint. Inst. vi. 3, 78,k'
iii. 32. The latter is probably names L. Varus as an Epi-
in error in describing the pri- curean, a friend of Augustus,
mary atoms of Asclepiades as perhaps the individual who,
without quality, differing only according to Donat. V. Virg.
in size, form, number and 79, Serv. on Bel. vi. 13, attended
arrangement. Although in this the lectures of Syro, in com-
respect he resembled Hera- pany with Virgil. Horace, nbt;
clides, with whom he is gene- withstanding Ep. i. 4, 15, was
rally classed, and applied, like no Epicurean, but only a man
him, the name oyKoi to atoms, who gathered everywhere what
still it is probable that his he could make use of (Sat. i. 5,
knowledge of Heraclides was 101). In Caligula's time, a
traditionally derived from the senator Pompedius was an Epi-
Epicureans. curean (Joseph. Antiquit. ix. 1,
He also asserted, with Epi- 5); under Nero, AuiidiusBassus,
curus (Antioohus, in SeH:. Math, a friend of Seneca {Sen. Ep.
vii. 201): tAs ij.\v aurOiiffeis 30, 1 and 3 and 5; 14), the
iivTccs Ka\ i\7]9wy &'Tt\^i|/ts elvai, elder Celsus {Orig.c. Cels. i. 8),
?<6ya} 5^ firjSef (iXats Tjfias Kara- and Diodorus, who committed
Aafiffdveiv. he at the same
If suicide {Sen. Vi. Be. 19, 1);
time maintained that our senses under Vespasian or his sons,
cannot distinguish the com- PoUius {Stat. Sllv. ii. 2, 113).
ponent parts of things, even In the first half of the second
Epicurus together with Demo- century, Cleomedes, Met. p. 87,
oritus admitted this in respect complained of the honours paid
of atoms. to Epicurus. In the second
THE ROMAN PERIOD. 417

Phsedrus in scientific importance. Eehabilitated Chap.


XV.
under the Antonines by the establishment of a public
chair in Athens, the Epicurean School outlived most
other systems, continuing to exist as late as the
fourth century after Christ.'
half of the same oentirry lived does not justify us setting down
Antonius, mentioned by Galen. Diodes of Magnesia as an Epi-
De Prop. An. Aifect. v. 1, and curean.
Zenobius, who, according to ' Diog. X. 9, in the first half
Simpl. Phys. 113, b, was an op- of the third century, writes fj :

ponent of Alexander of Aphro- re StSaxv -iraffuy ffx^^^v 4k\1'


disias. In the first half of the irovff&y tSjv lliKKwv ifTaft bia/JLf-

third century lived Diogenes vovtra Koi vripi6/iovs ^PX^^


Laertius, who, if not a perfect cfjroKiSovffa &Wriv 4^ &\\ris tuv
Epicurean himself, was at yraplfiuv. The testimony of
least afriendof the Epicureans. Zactantius, Inst. iii. 17, to the
Amongst other Epicureans, the wide spread of Epicureanism,
names of Athenseus (whose is not so trustworthy, although
epigram on Epicurus is quoted it treats it as still existing. It
by Diog. x. 12), Autodorus may be that he is only following
{Diog. V. 92), and Hermodorus older writers as Cicero does.
(^Xmcian, Icaromen. 16) may be See above p. 412, 1.
mentioned ; but Di^g. x. 11,

E
418 THE EPICUREANS.

CHAPTER XVI.

CHAEACTEE AND DIVISIONS OF THE EPICUREAN


TEACHING : THE TEST-SCIENCE OF TRUTH.

Chap. The scientific value and capacity for development of


Epicureanism is out of all proportion to its exten-


A. Clua- give diffusion and tlie length of time during which
Epicurean it continued to flourish. No other system troubled
mjKtem.
itself SO little about the foundation on which it
(1) it
power of rested ; none confined itself so exclusively to the ut^

7en^r'
terances of its founder. Such was the dogmatism
with which Epicurus propounded his precepts, such
the conviction he entertained of their excellence,
that his pupils were required to commit summaries
of them to memory ; ' and the superstitious devotion
for the founder was with his approval" carried to
' do. Fin. ii. 7, 20: Quls from him: Sis KoKdnns likv avrhv
enim vestrum nou edidicit Epi- (jmtrioXoyoSi'To TrpoaKinAiaufv 70-
curi Kupfas Siijas? Diog. 12 viruv VeoKhris Se i
wfidfievos-
(according to Diodes), Epicu- aSe\<j>hs eiebs 4k iralSai/ airoipal-
rus often exhorted his scholars voito fnjSeva ffotp^repov ^EiriKoipov
(^Jhid. 83 85 35) to commit to
; ; yeyov4vai fintf eJvat * 7] 5e fi-firrip
memory what they had heard. irSfwus ia-x^r 4v airf! tooiStos,
His last exhortation to his oTai <rvpe\6o!i(rat trotphv JtK 4yev-
friends was (Diog. 16): tuv vTia-av. Conf. 7<^. Frat. Am. 16,
SoyiiiTiDv liefivria-eai. p. 487; Adv. Col. 17, 5; Cleomed.
' He speaks of himself and Meteor, p. 89. Not only was
Metrodorus in Cic. Fin. ii. 3, 7, Epicurus' birthday observed by
as wise men. Plut. IS. P. Suav. the Epicurean School during
Viv, 18, 5, quotes, as coming his lifetime, but the 20th of
:

CHARACTER OF THE SYSTEM. 419

such a length, that not the slightest deviation from Chap.


XVT.
his tenets was on a single point permitted. Whereas,
even in Cicero's time, the writings of Epicurus and
Metrodorus found hardly a reader beyond the School,'
it is asserted that as late as the first and second cen-
turies after Christ the Epicureans clung tenaciously
to their master's teaching.^ Probably it was easier
for an Epicurean than for any other thinker to act
thus, he, like his master,' being indifferent to the

every month was celebrated as 6, 3), little as he can agree


a festival, in honour of him and with their tenets, commends
Metrodorus. In his testament, the Epicureans for faithfully
Epicurus especially ordered adhering to their master's
this tvfofold observance for the teaching, a point in which only
future. XHog. 18 ; Cic. Fin. ii. the Pythagoreans are their
31, 101 Plut. N. P. Suav. Viv.
; equals. Of the Epicureans, it
4, 8; PKn. H. N. xxxv. 5. may be said /xt^S' aino7s eiireiv
:

Atlien. vii. 298, d 'Enmoipi6s; woi ivavriov oiSre &\\7i\ot7 oUre


Tij Ei/coSicrT^s. Epicurus' pic- 'EiriKoitpcf firiSev [^fjiriSfva] els
ture is constantly referred to flljShVj '6tOV Kal flVTlffdTJVat &^IQV,
{Cic. Fin. v. 1, 3 PUn. 1. c).
; oW' ffTTiv avTols Trapav6fii]fiaf
The extravagant importance fiaWov Se cure^fld, Kal Karey-
attached to Epicurus in his votarat rb KaiyoTO[jLr}64v. Thus
School is proved by the high the Epicurean School resembles
eulogies in I/ttoret. i. 62 iii. 1 ; a state animated by one spirit,
and lOiO v. 1 vi. 1. Metro-
; ; in which there are no divisions
dorus, in Phit. Adv. Col. 17, 4, of party.
praises t^ ^'ETriKovpov us a\i]0ws ' has been already ob-
It
6e6tj>avTa opyia. served, p. 405, 1 406, 1, that ;

Oc. Tusc. ii. 3, 8. Epicurus ignored his obligations


' Sen. Ep. 33, 4, compares to his teachers Pamphilus and
the scientific independence of Nausicydes, and only confessed
the Stoics with the Epicurean's his debt to Democritus. All
dependence on the founder other philosophers provoked,
Nou sumus sub rege sibi : not only his contempt, but
quisque se vindicat. Apud istos likewise his abuse. JOiog. 8,
quicquid dicit Hermarchus, probably on the authority of
quicquid Metrodorus, ad unum Timocrates, communicates his
refertur. Omnia quse quisquam remarks on Plato, Aristotle, and
in illo contubernio locutus est, others. Vic. N. D. i. 33, 93:
unius ductu et auspiciis dicta Cum Epicurus Aristotelem
sunt. On the other hand, vexarit contumeliosissime,
Numenius (in Mis. Pr. Ev. xiv. PhEedoni Socratico tu,rpissime
E 2
d20 THE EPICUREANS.
Chap, labours of other philosophers, or unable to appreciate
'

their merits.' For us this conduct of theirs has one


advantage ; we can be far more certain that the Epi-
cureans reflect the teaching of their founder than we
can that this is the case with the Stoics. But this
philosophical sterility, this mechanical handing down
of rmchangeable principles, places the intellectual
value of Epicureanism on the lowest level. The
servile dependance of the Epicurean School on its

founder can neither excuse its mental idleness nor


recommend a system so powerless to give an inde-
pendent training to its supporters.

1 2) Aim of The want of intellectual taste here displayed

'aceorMna ^PP^^irs^^^^ i'l ^^ view taken by Epicurus of the


iotitelSjii- aim and business of philosophy. If among the
cwreems.
Stoics the subordination of theory to practice was
frequently felt, among the Epicureans this subordi-
nation was carried to such an extent as to lead to a
depreciation of all science. The aim of philosophy
was, with them, to promote human happiness. In-
deed, philosophy is nothing else but an activity
helping us to happiness by means of speech and
thought.^ Nor is happiness, according to Epicurus,

maledixerit. Pint. N. P. Suav. minus notum est,


vobis, Vellei,
V. 2, 2 Compared with Epi-
: quem ad modum quidque dica-
curus and Metrodorus, Colotes tur ; vestra enim solum legitis,
is polite ; rh yhp ir hvBpdivois vestra amatis, ceteros causa in-
rfffxiffTo piiiiara, /Stu/ioXo^'os, cognita condemnatis. liid. 1.
(rvyayay6vTes
\ilicv6uriiobs, K.r.\. 34, 93 Zeno not only despised
:

'ApiaTorihovs Kai ^aKpdrovs Kal cotemporary philosophers, but


Tlvday6pini Kol TIp<BTay6pov Kal he even called Socrates a scuira
@o<ppd<rTov' Kol 'HpaK\eiSov Kal Atticus, Macrob. Somn. i. 2
'Viriripxav, Kal tIvos yiip oAx' tw (Colotes ridiculing Plato's Re-
inttljavuv, KaretTK^BaiTav. public).
' Cic. N. D. ii. 29, 73 : Nam ' Sext. Math. xi. 169 : 'EttJ -
CHARACTER OF THE SYSTEM. 431

directly promoted by knowledge, but only indirectly Chap.


XVI.
in as far as knowledge ministers to practical needs,
or clears away hindrances to their attainment. All
science which does not serve this end is superfluous
and worthless.' Hence Epicurus despised learning
and and the
culture, the researches of grammarians,
lore of historians, and declared it a piece of good
fortune for simplicity of feeling to be uneontami-
nated by learned rubbish.^ Nor was his opinion dif-
ferent respecting mathematical science, of which he
was wholly ignorant.' The calculations of mathema-
ticians, he maintained, are based on false principles ;*

Kovpos ^\eyf rijv iptKotro^lav iyep' They fetch their philosophers,


yeiav civai \6yots Kal dtaKoyitrtiois like Cincinnatus, from the
rhv evSaifioj/a ^iov trepnroiovffay, plough. In this spirit, Epicurus
Conf. Epic, in IHog. 122 : The (Diiig. 6 Plut.N.P. Suav.T. 12,
;

demand to study philosophy in 1 ) wrote to Pythocles iraiSeiav Si :

youth, as well as in age, is sup- traaav (the Traiieia iyKvuKtoSf the


ported on the ground, that it is learned culture), fiatipie, <ptvyf
never too early nor too late to rh avdriov cipifievos ;and to
be happy. Apelles (_Plut. 1. c. ; At/ten. xiii.
' It was mentioned, p. 408, 588, a) : fiaKapl^u ire. & q^tos^
3, that Epicurus' own education Sti KoBaphs Tritrris cuTias (^Plut,
was defective. Not content explains it : r&v ^By]fiarttiv
therewith, he upholds this de- tLTToffx^^evos) iirX ^iXotrotplav
fectiveness on principle, NuUam S)pnil<ras.Metrodorus asserted
eruditionem, says the Epicurean that it need not be
(^Phit. 1.0.)
in Oic. Fin. i.21, 71, esseduxit, a source of trouble to anyone,
nisi quae beatse vitae disoiplinam if he had never read a line of
adjuvaret. In poets, nulla Homer, and did not know whe-
solida utilitas omnisque pueri- ther Hector were a Trojan or a
lis est delectatio. Music, geo- Greek. The art of reading and
metry, arithmetic, astronomy writing, ypafifiuTutii in the limi-
et a falsis initiis profeota vera ted sense, was the only art re-
esse non possunt, et si essent cognised by Epicurus. Sext.
vera nihil afferrent, quo jucua- Math. i. 49.
dius, i. e. quo melius viveremus. ' Seost. Math.i, 1 j aa. Fin.
2 Oic. 12 Vestri
Fin. ii. i, : i. 6, 20.
quidem vel optime disputant, < ao. Pin. i. 21 (see p.
nihilopusesse enm, philosophus 431, 1), which probably -only
qui futurus sit, scire literas. means, that mathematical ideas
;

422 THE EPICUREANS.


Chap, at any rate, they contribute nothing to human
'
happiness, and it is therefore useless and foolish to
trouble oneself about them.' The theory of music
and poetry he likewise found exceedingly irksome,
although he took pleasure in music itself and the
theatre ; ^ and rhetoric, as an artificial guide to elo-
quence, seemed to him as worthless as the show-
speeches which are the only result of the study
thereof. The power of public speaking is a matter
of practice and of momentary feeling, and hence the
skilful speaker is far from being a good statesman.^
Nor did the greater part of logical enquiries fare
any better in his judgment. Himself no logician,
he set little store by logic. Definitions are of no
use ; the theory of division and proof may be dis-
pensed with; the philosopher does best to confine
himself to words, and to leave all the logical ballast
alone.^ Of all the questions which engrossed the

cannot be applied to pheno- of the 4th Book, Vol. Hero. i.


mena. Hence Acad. ii. 3.3, in particular, rejecting the
106 (conf. Fin. i. 6, 20) Po- : notion that it has a moral
ly^nus Epicure adsentiens
. . . effect, see col. i. 24, 28. He
totam geometriam falsam esse was even opposed to music at
credidit. Conf. Prool. in Micl. table (Col. 38, as Epicurus was
p. 85. in Phit.l. c). The statement
See p. 421, 1 Sext. Math,
'
; of Diog. 121, that onlythe wise
i. 1Epicurus rejects mathe-
: man can give a right opinion
matics oiy rati fiaeriiidTuii firiSfv on poetry and music, is not at
ffvvepyoiiiTiiiv Trphs (To^fu rf\t'm- variance with these passages,
According to Diaff. 93, ' Philodemus, De Bhet.
o-ij/. Vol.
Epicurus calls astronomy tos Hero. iv. col. 3 12. The same
;

ac5pa7ro8(6Seij tSj' liiTTpoKiyav polemic is continued in the


TEx'"'''e>as. Conf. Pwq. 79. further fragments of this trea-
'
Pint. 1. 0. 13, i. Philo- tise. Ibid. V. Col. 6.
demus, in his treatise wepl * Cic. Fin. i. 7, 22 In logic:

lioiKTiKris, discussed had


at istevester plane, utmihiquidem
length the value of music, as videtur, inermis ac nudus est.
we gather from the fragments ToUit definitiones nihil de
:
:

CHARACTER OF THE SYSTEM. 433

attention of Stoic logicians, one only, the theory of Chap.


XVI.
knowledge, was studied by Epicurus, and that in a
very superficial way.'
Far greater, comparatively, was the importance
he attached to the study of nature,^ but even natu-
ral science was deemed valuable, not so much for its
own sake as because of its practical use. The know-
ledge of natural causes is the only means of libera-
ting the soul from the shackles of superstition ; this
is the only use of natural science. If it were not
for the thought of Grod and the fear of death, there
would be no need of studying nature.' The investi-
gation of our instincts is also of use, because it helps
us to control them, and to keep them within their
natural bounds.'' Thus the onesided practical view

dividendo ao partieudo docet. 85 : fi^i &\Ko ri reKos iK rrjs irepl


Non quomodo effioiatur conolu- fjLiredipuv ypcijffeats . . . vofii^eti/

daturque ratio, tradit, non qua Se? elvot ^Trep arapa^lav KoL wlffriv
via captiosa solvantux, am- ^e^aiov KaSdwep Kal i-nl raj/ \oi-
bigua distinguantiir, ostendit. nuif. Ibid. 112 et fniOkv Jifias :

IHd. 19, 63 In dialectioa


: atirepl rStv iji.ere<&puu inroi\/iat i]V(&x~
autem vestra nullam existima- \ovp Ka\ at irepl Qaudrov . , . oiiK
vit [Epic] esse nee ad melius hv irpotreSetfjuefla <pv(no\oyias ; but
vivendum nee ad commodius thisbecomes necessary, since
disserendum viam. Acad. ii. without knowledge of nature,
30, 97 Ab Epieuro, qui totam
: we cannot be perfectly free
dialecticam et oontemnit et from fear. The same in Phit.
inridet. Diog. 31 r'tiv 8io\ek-
: N. P. Suav. Viv. 8, 7; Conf.
TlK^V as irapeKKOvtrajf &TroSoKtfia- JXog. 79 and 143 Oio. Pin. iv. ;

^ovtTiV ' hpKeiv yhp robs (f>v(rtKobs 5, 11 Lucret. i. 62 iii. 14 vi.


; ; ;

^apeii' Kara robs rav irpayiidraiii 9.


<p66yyovs. In ac. Pin. i. 19, 63, the
<

' See p. 424. Epicurean speaks of a iivefold,


2 do. Fin. i. 19, 63: In or, excluding Canonic, of a
physicis plurimum posuit fourfold use of natural science
[Epic.]. Ibid. 6, 17 : In phy- fortitude contra mortis ti-
sicis, quibus maxima gloriatur, morem constantia contra me-
;

primum totus est alienus. tum religionis sedatio animi ;

' Epic, in Dio0. x. 82 and omnium rerum oocultarum ig-


424 THE EPICUREANS.
Chap, of philosophy which we have already encountered in
! Stoicism was carried by the Epicureans to an extreme
length.
(3) mvi- Nor is it otherwise than in harmony herewith
pMhio- *'^^* ^^^^ ^^^ ^^ receive a fuller or more perfect
pJty- treatment in the further development of their sys-
tem. Even the study of nature, going as it did far
more into particulars than logic, was guided entirely
by practical considerations, all scientific interest in
nature being ignored Following the usual method,
however, the Epicm-eans divided philosophy into
three parts ' logic, natural science, and moral science.
Limiting, however, the first of these parts to one
branch of logic, the part which deals with the cha-
racteristics of truth, and which they therefore called
neither logic, nor dialectic, but Canonic, they really
reduced this part to a mere introductory appendage
to the two other parts,' and studied Canonic as a
part of natural science.' Moreover, natxu-al science

noratione sublata moderatio ; p. 423, 4. Hence Sext. Math,


natura cupiditatum generibus- vii. Some reckon Epicurus
14 :

que earum explioatis. amongst those who only divide


' Diog. 29 : SiaipeiTai rolvvv philosophy into natural and
[ri <pi\oao((>ia\ cis Tpla, t6 tc moral science ; whilst, aeoord-
Kavpvmhv Kol (pvtniihv naX ii6m6v. ing to others, he adhered to
Canonic was also called ircpl a threefold division, at the
Kpnriplov ttoi it.pxns ""l ffToix^m- same time rejecting the Stoic
tm6p ; natural science, irepl logic. Sen. Ep. 89, 11 Epi- :

yfvfafus KoJ (pBopas Kol irepl curei duas partes philosophise


(j>iirem ; ethics, irepl atpeTwv koI putaverunt esse, naturalem
^EUKTeSx Kal irepi filav Kol t^Xoui. atque moralem rationalem re-
;

' Diog. 30 rb /iev odv Kavovi-


: moverunt, deinde cum ipsis
Kbv iit)6Sovs iirl t^v irpayiiardav rebus cogerentur, ambigua se-
?Xf'- ceruere, falsa sub specie veri
' Diog. 1. c. : cMfliun /lenTot latentia coarguere, ipsi quod-
rh Kai'oi/iKbi' Sfiov Tip <^u(riK9> fftiv- que locum, quem de judicio et
TciTTeii/, do. Fin. i. 19. See regula appellant, alio nomine
CANONIC. 425

was so entirely subordinated to moral science, that Chap>


^
we might almost tempted to follow some modern
feel

writers in their view of the Epicurean system, giving


'

to moral science the precedence of the two other


parts, or at least of natural science.^ The School,
however, followed the usual order, and not without
reason ;^ for although the whole tendency of the
Epicurean Canonic and natural science can only, like
the Stoic, be explained by a reference to their moral
science, yet their moral science presupposes the test-
science of truth and natural science. We shall, there-

fore, do well to treat of Canonic in the first place,


and subsequently to prove how this branch of study
depends on Ethics.
Canonic or the test-science of truth, as has been B. Canonic

observed, is occupied with investigating the stan- '^J^^^^fS


dard of truth, and with enquiring into the mode of truth.
acquiring knowledge. The whole of formal logic, (i) <*"
,, ,.,^ , iation and
the doctrine of the formation of conceptions and percep-
**""
conclusions, is omitted by Epicurus.* Even the theory
of the acquisition of knowledge assumes with him a
very simple form. If the Stoics were fain, notwith-
standing their ideal ethics and their pantheistic
speculations, ultimately to take their stand on ma-
terialism, could Epicurus avoid doing the same?
In seeking a speculative basis for a view of life
which refers everything to the feeling of pleasure

rationaleminduxeruntisedeum ^ Steinliart in the treatise


aocessionem esse naturalis pai- often referred to.
tis existimant. ' Diog. 29 ; Sext. Math. vii.
22.
' Bitter, iii. 463 ; Sohhier- * do. Fin. i. 7, 22. See p,
maohm; Gesoh. d. Phil. p. 123. 422, 4.

426 THE EPICUREANS.


Chap, or pain, he appealed far more unreservedly tha
XVI.
they had done to sensation. Now, since the sense
can alone inform us what is pleasant or unpleasan'
and what is desirable or the contrary, our judgmeE
as to truth or falsehood must ultimately depend o
the senses. Viewed speculatively, sensation is th
standard of truth ; viewed practically, the feeling c

pleasure or pain.' If the senses may not be trustee


still less may knowledge derived from reason \.

trusted, reason itself being primarily and entire]


derived from the senses. There remains, therefon
no distinctive mark of truth, and no possibility (

certain conviction. We are at the mercy of unl:

mited doubt. If, however, this doubt is contradic


tory of itself forhow can men declare they knov
that they can
know nothing? it is also contradictor
of human nature, since it would do away not on!
with all knowledge but with every possibility of ac

tion, in short, with all the conditions on which huma


life depends.^ To avoid doubt we must allow ths
sensation as such is always, and under all circun
stances, to be trusted ; nor ought the delusions of tl

senses to shake our belief ; the causes of these decej

' Cic. Fin.


22 8ext.
i. 7, ; Liwi: iv. 467-519 ; die. Fin.
Math. -rii. according
203. If, 19, 64. Colotes (in Pint. Ad
to Piog. 31, and Cio. Acad. ii. Col. 24, 3) replies to the C;
46, 142, Epicurus named three renaic scepticism by sayinj
criteria irpi\if^is, aiirSriiris, and /n5)SivaaBai Cv" *")^^ XPVoitu to
irdBv instead of the above two, vpiy/nao'ii'. In this case, as i

it is only an inaccuracy of ex- the case of the Stoics, the doj


pression, ir/)(i\r)i(iis, as we have matism in favour of the sensi
seen, being derived from sen- is based on a practical posti
sation. late, the need of a firm basis (

" Epicurus, in Piog. x. 146; conviction for human life.


;

CANONIC. 427

tions not lying in sensation as such, but in our judg- Chap.


XVI.
ment about sensation. What the senses supply is

only that an object produces this or that effect upon


us, and that this or that picture has impressed our
soul. The facts thus supplied are always true, only
it does not follow that the object exactly corresponds
with the impression we receive of it, nor that it pro-
duces on others the same impression that it produces
on us. On the contrary, many different pictures
may emanate from one and the same object, and
these pictures may be changed on their way to the
ear or eye. Pictures, too, may strike our senses with
which no real objects correspond. To confound the
picture with the thing, the impression made with the
object making the impression, is certainly an error,
but this error must not be laid to the charge of the
senses, but to that of opinion.' Indeed, how is it

possible, asks Epicurus,^ to refute the testimony of


the senses Can reason refute it ? But reason is
?

itself dependent on the senses, and cannot bear tes-


timony against that on which its own claims to be-
lief depend. Or can one sense convict another of
error ? But different sensations do not refer to the
same object, and similar sensations have equal value.
Nothing remains, therefore, but to attach implicit
belief to every impression of the senses. Every such

Epic, in JDiog. x. 50 and


' i. 7, 22 ; N. D. i. 25, 70 ; Ter-
147 Sext. Math. vii. 203-210
; tull. De An. Further par-
17;
vili. 9 ; 63 ; 185 ; Plid. Adv. ticulars below respecting sense-
Col. 4, 3 ; 5, 2 25, 2 Plac. iv.
; ; perception.
9, 2 I/aor. iv. 377-519 ; Cic.
;
' JDiog. x. 31 ; Lacr. iv. 480.
Acad. ii. 25, 79 ; 32, 101 ; Fin.
:

428 THE EPICUREANS.


Chap. impression is directly certain, and is accordingly
XVI.
termed by Epicurus clear evidence {ivdpysia).^ Nay,
more, its truth is so paramount that the impressiouE
of madmen, and appearances in dreams, are true
because they are caused by something real,^ and error

only becomes possible when we go beyond sensation,


(2) No- This going beyond sensation becomes, however.
tions.
a necessity. By a repetition of the same perception
a notion (^TrpoXriyfris) arises. A notion, therefore, ie

nothing else but the general picture retained in the


mind of what has been perceived.' On these notions
retained by memory depends all speaking and think-
ing. They are what commonly go under the name
of things and speech is only a means of recalling
;

definite perceptions* to the memory. Notions are


' Math. vii. 203 and
Sext.
216. In Diog. x. 52, instead of ju^ Trp6Tepov ^yv^Keifiev avrh . . ,

ivepyeias, we should read with ouS* ttv uvoiidtra^ei/ rt /t^ wpdrepot


Cobet empyetat. Besides this avTou HUTCL 7rp6\7j^tv rhv Tinrov
peeuliar expression, Epicurus fiaSdvTis. Hence the exhorta-
uses sometimes aXaBi\(ns, some- tion in Epicuras' letter to
times i/>oi'Ta(rfo ((Sfearf. 1. e.), for Herodotus (in Diog. x. 37)
sensation. An impression on vpSirov fxkv oiv to. vTroTerayfififo
the senses, he calls ipavraaT ik)i Tois <p96yyois Set ei\'ij(f>4uai Uttus
imPo>Ji. Biog. 50. hv T(i 5o|a^a;;iEi'a t) ^riToiiieva fi

" Diog. 32. atropaifuva iviyovrei


6X'"/'e>' f 's ft

' Diog. 33 t)iv 8e : TrpiJXrjifni' Every impres-,


^TriKplveiv, K.T.K.
Keyovtrtv olovel KaTd\7]\ptjf fi S6^av sion must be referred to definite
opdijv ^ ^vvoiav ?) KofloXi/cV v6'i\(nv perceptions apart from per-
;

dvaTroKetfjLeytfV, rovriffri fiv^fLTjv ceptions, no reality belongs to


TovTToWdKis^^uBev (^ayevros. By our impressions or, as it is ex-
;

the help of this passage, Cicero's pressed Semt. Pyrrh. ii. 107,
description, N. D. i. 16, 43, must Math. viii. 13, 258: The Epi-
be corrected. cureans deny the existence oi
* Diog. 1. 0. : S,ua y&,p r^ a XeKTbi/, and that between a
^iiBrivat &if6puiros eiiBbs Kartt irptJ- thing and its name there exists
Xtji|/iv Kol 6 T^nos ainov ifourai a third intermediate something
irporiyovfi4vuj/ tuv alaB'fja'euv. a conception. See also Sext,
ttovtI o^v ov6fj.a7i rh irpt^Twy 5iro- vii. 267.
TiTayfievoy ivapyh iffri
Ktd oiiK
:

CANONIC. 429

presupposed in all scientific knowledge.' Together Chap.


with sensations they form the measure of the truth
of our convictions ; ^ and it holds true of them as it
did of sensations that they are true in themselves
and need no proof.' Taken hy themselves, notions,
like perceptions, are reflections in the soul of things
on which the transforming action of the mind, chang-
ing external impressions into conceptions, has not
as yet been brought to bear.
For this very reason notions are not suflBcient. (3) Ojnn-
""*'
From appearances we must advance to their secret
causes ; from the known to the unknown.^ But far
too little value was attached by Epicurus to the
logical forms of thought, or he would have investi-
gated more accurately the nature of this process of
advancing. Thoughts, in his view, result from sen-
sations spontaneously, and although a certain amount
of reflection is necessary for the process, yet it re-

quires no scientific guidance. The thoughts arrived

Siog. 33.
' Sea^. Math. i. t!> irparov ivvSrtiui Hofl' tKaarov
57 21)
(xi. oSre QtiTtiv otTe
: <p$6Yyov fiXiireaBm Koi /aiSiv iiro-
iiropsiv li7Ti (cttTct rhv a6^ov 'Eir- Seflcus irpuo-SeTo-floi, rfirep i\ofixv
Kovpov ivev irpoXii^fais. Ibid. t!> (nToip.evov fi cnropoipeyor xal

Tiii. 337, p. 521 ; Phd. Be An. Soia(6pievor i(p' i avd^o/iev.


6 : The difficulty, that all learn- Diog. 33 (Conf 38, 104) . :

ing presupposes knowledge, the ircpl tUv aS^Aav 4ir!) tuv (paiyo-
Stoics met by (pvtriKai hvotai, piiywv xph (r-np-eioOaeat.
the Epicureans by vpoKii'f/eis = See p. 422, 4. Steinhart,
which accordingly are the p. 466, goes too far, in saying
natural test of truth. that Epicums defied all law
' See p. 426, 1. Diog. 1. c. and rule in thought.
ivapyeis olv e'uriv at irpoA^ifieis ' Diog. 32 : Koi yhp koI iiri-

leal Ti to^auThy oirb irpoTf'pou yoiai Traaai airh tUv aiirBiiaeav


rtvis ivapyovs l^prirrai, e<p' t ana- ypy6vaai, KOTiiTEirfpiirTai(ni'(pro-
Ae'pocTts Xtyop.ei'. bably; the coincidence of several
" See previous note and sensations to be distinguished
Epic, in IHog. 38 : aviyKt] yh,p from their aivSaris or free com-
430 THE JEPICUREANS:
Chap, at in this way do not stand as a higher genus abovi
XVI.
perceptions, but they are only opinions {yiroKfi^^ii
86^0.) without a note of truth in themselves, an(
depending for their truth upon sensation. Tha
opinion may be considered a true one which is base(
on the testimony of the senses, or is at least not con
trary to the senses, and that a false opinion in whicl
the opposite is the case.' Sometimes we suppose tha

upon certain present impressions other impression


will follow for instance, that a tower which appear
;

round at a distance will appear round close at hand


In that case, if the real perception corresponds witl
our supposition, our opinion is true, otherwise it ii

false.^ At other times we suppose that certain ap


pearances are due to secret causes ; for instance, tha
empty space is the cause of motion. If all appear,
ances tally with their explanations, we may considei

bination) koI av(i\oylai,v koI yelas, Se at re avTifiaprv


ifievSe'is

6^ot6r7]Ta KoL ffiSvOta'ti', ffv/x$a\- ovk iirt^apTvpovfieva


povfxet/ai Koi
Xoiievov Ti Kal rov \oytfffiov. irphs rrjs eyapycias. HitteVy iii
Conf . and the
p. 422, 4 ; 429, 1, 486, observes that these state
corresponding doctrine of the meuts are contradictory. Ac
Stoics, p. 80, with the teaching cording to Sextus, an opiraon ii
of Epicurus, on the genesis of only then true when it can b<
thoughts from sfensations. proved and not refuted accord ;

ZHog. 33
' Kal rh Soiturrhv : ing to Diogenes, when it can b(
&7rb irpoTfpov Tivis ivapyoSs ^pTTj- proved or not refuted. Th(
Toi . . . tV 5e S(j|ai/ Kal uirSKn^iv latter is, however, clearly meani
Xiyovaiv. 0X1)67) T6 (^aat koI by Sextus, and is affirmed bj
ifiEvS^
ti.v fiiv ycbp iiriiiapTvprjrai Epicurus in Diog. 50 and 51.
il /ail iivTinapTvprirai itX7)8ij etvui
^ Epicur. in Si^g. 50 Hid ;

iiiv Sh liii im/iaprvpriTM ti auri- 33 Sext. vii. 212. The object oi


;

^opTup5)Tat>)/6uS^TU7X'^''''. Seixt. a future sensation is called bj


Hath. vii. 211: rav So|ui/ kotA JMog. 38, rh irpo<Tfi4vov. Diog
rhv 'EitiKovpov atiiiv oXTjSeis eiVii' x. 34, himself gives a perverted
ai 5e tfievSfis " &\Tjflj /iiv ot Tt explanation of this term, whicli
avrifjLapTvpo{ifievai Kal ovk Ayri- probably misled Steinhart, p,
fjiopTvpoifievcu nphs rris ivap' 466.
CANONIC. 431

oui- suppositions correct ; if not, our suppositions are Chap.


"
incorrect.' In the first case the test of the truth of
an opinion is that it is supported by experience ; in
the latter that it is not refuted by experience.^ Have
we not here all the leading features of a theory of
knowledge based purely on sensation ? The Epi-
curean's interest in these questions was, however, far
too slight to construct with them a developed theory
of materialism.
Little pains seem to have been taken by Epicurus (4) Stand-

to overcome the difficulties by which his view was 'H'Jjl s,,,i.


beset. If all sensations as such are true, the saying jectire.

of Protagoras necessarily follows that for each indi-


vidual that is true which seems to him to be true, that
contrary impressions about one and the same object
are true, and that deceptions of the senses, so many
instances of which are supplied by experience, are
really impossible. To avoid these conclusions, Epi-
curus maintained that for each different impression
there is a different object-picture. What imme-
diately affects our senses is not the object itself, but
a picture of the object, and these pictures may be
innumerable, a different one being the cause of each
separate sensation. Moreover, although the pictures
emanating from the same object are in general nearly
alike, it is possible that they may differ from one-
'
Sesct. 213.
1. c. true ; our impressions of the
2 The two tests of truth, secret causes of these appear-
proof and absence of refutation, anoes must not be refuted. The
do not, therefore, as Sextus ex- former test applies to opinions
pressly says, refer to the same regarding tS -npoffinivov the
;

cases. suppositions in
Our latter, to opinions regarding -rh
respect of external appearances &ii]\ov. Siog. 38.
must be proved, in order to be
432 THE EPICUREANS.
Chap, another owing to a variety of causes. If, therefore, th
!^ same object appears different to different individuals
the cause of these different sensations is not one am
the same, but a different one, and different picture
must have affected their senses. If our own sensa
tions deceive us, the blame does not belong to ou
senses, as though they had depicted to us unreal ob
jects, but to our judgment for drawing unwarrantec
inferences from pictures as to their causes.
'

This line of argument, however, only removes th(


difficulty one step further. Sensation is said alway
to reproduce faithfully the picture which affects th*
organs of sense, but the pictures do not always re
produce the object with equal faithfulness. Hon
then can a faithful picture be known from one whicl
is not faithful? To this question the Epicurear
system can furnish no real answer. To say that the
wise man knows how to distinguish a faithful fron
an unfaithful picture * is to despair of an absolute
standard at all, and to make the decision of truth oi
error depend upon the individual's judgment. Sucl
a statement reduces all our impressions of the pro-
perties of things to a relative level. If sensatioD
does not show us things themselves, but only those
impressions of them which happen to affect us, it
does not supply us with a knowledge of things as
they are, but as they happen to be related to us. It

' Compare the passages in turbare veri oognitionem, dixit-


Sext. vii. 206, quoted p. 427, 1. que sapientis esse opinionem a
^ Cie. Acad. ii. 14, 45 Nam perspicuitate sejungere, nihil
:

qui voluit subvenire erroribus" profecit, ipsius enim opinionis


Epicurus lis, qui videntur con- errorem nullo modo sustulit.
;

CANONIC. 433

was, therefore, a legitimate inference from this theory Chap


XVI.
of knowledge for Epicurus to deny that colour be-
longs to bodies in themselves, since some only see
colour in the dark, whilst others do not.' Like his
predecessor, Democritus, he must have been brought
to this view by his theory of atoms. Few of the
properties belong to atoms which we perceive in
things, and hence all other properties must be ex-
plained as not belonging to the essence, but only be-
longing to the appearance of things.'^ The taste for
speculation was, however, too weak, and the need of
a direct truth of the senses too strong in Epicurus
for him to be able to turn his thoughts in this direc-
tion for long. Whilst allowing to certain properties
of things only a relative value, he had no wish to
doubt the reality of objects, nor to disparage the
object-pictures which furnish us with sensations.^

' Adv. Col. 7, 2 (Stob.


Pl/ut. t&s Kari XP'^M'"''' "' ''^"^^ x^Moi^^
Eol. 366 Zucr. ii. 795) 6
i. ; : Lucret. 1. c.
'Eirf/coupos ovK elmi \e-/av rh ' Compare the passages al-

Xpt^lio/ra ffvftfpvTJ tois fffi)ixa(nv, ready quoted, on the truth of


aWa yfvvaaSai Karh. iroiAs Tims the impressions of the senses,
T(jeis (tol Bfffsis irpbs riiv Sifiy. and the words of Epicurus, in
For says Epicurus, ouk. oISo 'ivus Diog. 68 kwh. /iijv Ka\ tA. axh-
:

Sei TO cK o-xdrei ToCro 6vra prjirai nara Kal to xpifion-a Kai toj iis-yiBt\
Xpi4;i>aTO exeiv. Often some see koI tb, fidpea ko! Stro &\\a kott;-
colour where others do not yopeiTai koto tov (TiSjuotoj &s ttv
ov tmWov oZv eXEi" ^ M^ ^X^'" *'' "''''^ Ps^tikStu koI irSffii/ ^611-

Xpaiia^vBiliTeTai Tuv (TaiiidTUveKa- to fl tois ipwrots Kol KaTo, t^iv


tXTOv, aXffQfiffiv avT^v yvuffTo7s, ou6' us
' Simpl. Categ 109, /3 (Schol. Kaff iavrds eiVi (pvireis Solao-jeoi/
in Arist. 92, a, 10 ) Since De- : (06 ycip SwaThn ^irixo^o-oi toSto),

mocritus and Epicurus depute oSff 8\us iis ouk eio-lc, oi0' as
all qualities to atoms except 'dTepd tito vpoamdpxovTa Toir(f>
those of form and mode of com- acrd/MTo. oSe' &s fi-opla ToiTov,
bination, Aiyovai tos
iTriyiveirBai a\K' iis Th '6\ov aSifui, Ka86\ov /ley
&\\as xoiiJTTjTas, Tds Te awKas, 4k TodTaiv ivdvTiiiv T'tiv lauToO
oXov 8epii6niTas Kal Aei(JT7)TOS, Kol (jivcrw ix"" 4^'Sioi', k.t.A.
434 THE EPICUREANS.

CHAPTEK XVII.

THE EPICUKBAN VIEWS ON NATURE.

Chap. If Epicukijs and his followers underrated logic, t(

natural science they attached a considerable value


A. General This value was, however, exclusively derived from i

'nature. sense of the practical advantages which a knowledgf


(1) Ohject, of nature confers in opposing superstition. Withoul
menwd of
^^^"^an object the study of nature would hav<
the gtudy seemed wholly superfluous.^ Such being their atti-
tude of mind, the Epicureans were, as might hav
been expected, indifferent about giving a complete
and accurate explanation of phenomena. Their on<
aim was to put forward such a view of nature a;
would do away with the necessity supematurafor
intervention, without at the same time pretending tc
offer a sufiBcient solution of the problems raised b]
science.^ Whilst, therefore, devoting considerable
attention to natural science,^ Epicurus does not seerr

' Epic, in Diog. 143 ou/c %v:


^ oi ykp iSio\oyias xa
Sjj

rhv tpo^oifiivov irepl tuv KupiaiTd- KepTJs S(J|tjs ^ios iifioiv e^e
6
Tdiv \iuv jU^ KaTeiS^ra ris Tj tov ;i^pfoj', &A\ct 70v a6op^$ais 7j/ia.
aifiiravTos (fiiais i,\\' {moTrTev6- Qv. Epic, in Diog. 87.
i).fv6v Ti rSiv Karh. Tois ii.i9ovs. ' I>io^. 27,mentions37booki
Sicrre ovK ^v&vev (pvtrioKoyias of his irepl <pi(retas, besides
i.Kepalas Tckj ^Socas iiroXapfiivav. smaller works.
For further particulars, p. 422.
GENERAL VIEWS ON NATURE. 435

to have considered certainty to be of importance, or Chap.


XVII.
even to be possible, in dealing with details of scien-
tificstudy. Of the general causes of things we can
and ought to entertain a firm conviction, since the
possibility of overcoming religious prejudices and
the fears occasioned by them depends on these con-
victions. No such result, however, follows from the
investigation of details, which, on the contrary, only
tends to confirm prejudices in those who are not
already emancipated from them. In dealing with
details it is, therefore, enough for Epicurus to show
that various natural causes for phenomena may be
imagined, and to offer various suggestions which
dispense with the intervention of the Gods and the
myths of a belief in Providence.' To say that any
one of these expedients is the only possible one, is

in most cases to exceed the bounds of experience


'
Epic, in Diog. 78 koI ivhv : relveiv (how very different from
Koi riiv ^kp rav KvptuTATaif at- Aristotle. See Zellev, Philoso-
riav 4^aKpi$a(rai tl>viru)\oytas %p- pHe der Grieoheu, ii. b, 113, 3;
yov elvai Sei vo/j-i^etv koI rb 114,3; 359, 2), aA\' 6jUows rots
fxaKciptov iv ry nepl roiv fiTetipaiv ip6$ovs ex^tv rohs ravra KaTiS6v-
yvtloffei ivravBa ireTnwKivai' KoX Tas rives 5e at <f>v{Teis ayvoovvras
iv Ty, rives {pvceis at Oeupoifievai Kal rives at Kvpi6rarcu tiuriat,Ka\ ei
Kara to /xereoipa ravrl, koX Stra (as if) fi7] irpoa-ydeffav ravra, rdxa
avyyevi} irphs r^v els ravra aicpi- Se Koi nKeiovs, STav rh 6iifi0os ^k
0eiav en Se Kol rh irKeovaxus iv

rTJs rovrwv irpoKaravoiitreais fii}
rois roioirois e'ivai [evidently jn); Zivt\rai. r^v \i<nv Aa/iPdveiv nark
eJvaijnTistheTead']fKalrh extBexo- r^v irepi ruv Kvpturdrwv oIkovo-
pLevus Kal SxXws ttois exeiv, aW p-iav. (Conf. iMcr.yi. 50; v. 82.)

airXas p/ii eivai ev aipQdprtp Kal 5ih Sij Kal wKelovs airias evplcTKop^v
fiaKapia tp^ffet rS}V Sidnpiirtv viro- rpoirwv, K,r.\. Kal oh Sei vo/ii^eiv
0d\\6vraiv fl ripaxov firiSev Kal ri]v {nrep roiruiv XP^'"" aKpifieiai/
Tovro Karaka^e^v r^ Siavoiif tffrtv p.^ anetKritpevai 3(r?i Trpbs rh &riipa-
aTT\as otras eivai. rh 5' iv rp X"" ""' piaKdpiov rip,S>v avvreivei,
laropit} irewrinKhs rfis Siffeas (ca! k.t.A.. IMd. lOi Kol Kar' &K-
:

avaroXris Kal rpoTTTJs Kal eKKei^lietos \ovs Sh rpiirovs irXelovas 4v5exe-


Kal oaa ffuyyevri rovrois firiBev in rat Kepavvoiis airoTekeiiTBai. ii6uov
irphs rh pLaKdpiov rris yvdiaeats <Tvv- 6 fivdos aTrearai,

F F 2
;

436 THE EPICUREANS.


Chap, and human knowledge, and to go back to the ca-
xvn.
pricious explanations of mythology.' Possibly the
world may move, and possibly it may be at rest. Pos-
sibly it may be round, or else it may be triangular, or
have any other shape. Possibly the sun and the stars
may be extinguished at setting, and be lighted afresh
at their rising. It is, however, equally possible that
they may only disappear under the earth and re-
appear again, or that their rising and setting may
be due to yet other causes. Possibly the waxing
and waning of the moon may be caused by the
moon's revolving; or it may be due to an atmos-
pheric change, or to an actual increase and decrease
in the moon's size, or to some other cause. Possibly
the moon may shine with borrowed light, or it may
shine with its own, experience supplying us with
instances of bodies which give their own light, and
of those which have their light borrowed.* From
these and such-like statements it appears that
questions of natural science in themselves have no

' Ihid. 87 : irivTa fiiv oSi/ ceed on suppositions chosen at


ylvTai affeiarus (tard 7r(i'Tai>', random (&|iii)fJOTa /cei/d koX yo/w-
Kara iiMovaxbti Tp6iTov ixKoBaipo- Setrlai,Epic. 1. c. 86). Conf , 94
fiepuv (Tviitpiivas tois (paivoiisvois, 104 113. Imeret. vi. 703.
;

'irav Tis rh TnBavoKoyoi/ievov vwip ' Epic, in


ZHoff. 88 ; 92-95,
avTun Se6ma>f KaraKliry. 8toc S4 Many other similar instances
Tij t!) fiiv AiroXiTTj), rh Sh 4K$dAri might be quoted. In support of
d/iolas irijMpuvov tn/ t^ (paivo/ihip the view that the sun was ex-
Srj\ov 3ti Kol Ik ravThs iKirlTmi tinguished at setting, Epicurus,
ipvinoXo-yrtjiaTOS iirl Si riy iivBov according to Cleomed. Meteora,
KoTo^^ei. Ihid. 98 : oi Se rb %v p. 89, is said to have appealed
\afi.pivovTes (those who only to the story (respecting which
allow one explanation for every Posidonius in Straho, iii. 1, 5,
phenomenon) tois tc (pavonimis p. 138) that, as it sets, the his-
juiixoi'Tai Kai toC tI SuyoTbi/ &v- sing of the ocean may be heard
Bptiiirifi Oeupri<rai Sia-TreTTraiKaffti'. In on the sea-shore,
investigating nature, they pro-
GENERAL VIEWS ON NATURE. 487

value for Epicurus. Whilst granting that only one Chap.


natural explanation of phenomena is generally pos- '__

sible, yet in any particular case he is perfectly indif-


ferent which explanation is adopted.
Great stress is, however, laid by him on the (2) Me-
general explanation. In contrast with the religious Is^Una-
view which regards the world as a system of means t^on of
leading to ends, the leading business of the natural
science of the Epicureans is to refer all phenomena
to natural causes. To an Epicurean nothing appears
more absurd than to suppose that the arrangements
of nature have for their object the well-being of
mankind, or that they have any object at all. The
tongue is not given us for the purpose of speaking,
nor the ears for the purpose of hearing. As a matter
of fact it would, indeed, be more correct to say, that
we speak because we have a tongue, and hear because
we have ears. Natural powers have acted purely
according to the law of necessity, and among their
various products, there could not fail to be some
presenting the appearance of purpose in their ar-
rangement. In the case of man there have resulted
many such resources and powers. But this result is
by no means intentional it is simply an accidental
;

consequence of natural causes. In explaining nature


all thought of Gods must be put out of sight, whose

happiness is inconceivable, on the supposition that


they care for mankind and his welfare.'

'
The principle is thus ex- Ordine se suo quseque sagaci
panded by iMCvet. i. 1021 : mente locarunt,
Nam certe neque consilio pri- Neo quos quseque darent motus
mordia rerum pepigere prof ecto
438 THE EPICUREANS.
Chap. Confining, as Epicurus did, his interest in nature
XVII.
completely to this general view of things, in carrying
it into details he was all the more inclined to rely
upon some older system. No one, however, appeared
better to correspond with his tone of mind than that
of Democritus, which, moreover, commended itself
to him not only by absolutely banishing the idea of
final cause, but in particular by referring everything
to matter, and by its theory of atoms. As Epicurus
placed in each individual thing taken by itself the
ultimate end of action, so Democritus had theoretic-
ally made all that is real to consist in what is

absolutely individual or in atoms. His natural


science, therefore, seemed to present the most na-
Sed quia multa modis multis Nolities hominum, Dis unde
mutata per omne est insita primum ; . . .

Ex infinito vexantur percita Si non ipsa dedit specimen na-


plagis, tura creandi ?

Omne genus motus et coetus ex-


Conf. iv. 820 ; v. 78 ; 195 419. ;
periundo,
In these views, he is only fol-
Tandem deveniunt in tales dis-
lowing Epicurus. Heavenly-
posituras,
phenomena, says the latter, in
QuaUbus hasc rebus consistit
Diog. 76, ^^re KiiTovpyo\/vr6s rt-
summa creata.
vos vop.i^iv Set yiviffBat Kol Sia-
156:
T. t6.t70vtos ^ StaTa|ai/Toy koX afia
Dicere porro hominum causa T^v irairav /tajcapttiTTjTa exovros
voluisse Deos] parare
[soil. /at' a<p9ap(rlas *
ov yctp (Tv^<puvovai
Prseclaram mundi naturam, &c. irpayfiaTeiai Kol tppopjiSes Kal
Desipere est. Quid enim im- opyaX Kal ;i^(ipiTes t^ ^aKapidrijTi,
mortalibus atque beatis o^a' cLtrdeveic^ Kal ^6^cp Kal irpoff-
Gratia nostra queat largirier Se^iTei TDJj' irK7}aiov ravra yliferai.
emolnmenti, Ibid. 97 : ri Beta ipicrts vpis tuCto
Ut nostra quidquam causa ge- )U7]Sa/.i^ irpoirayetrdu, aAA' a\6(-
rere adgrediantur ? Toipy-fiTOS SiarTipeiaBa Kal iv Trj
Quidve novi potuit tauto post K&ari fiaKapiiryiTi, Ibid. 113.
ante quietos With these passages, Cic. N". D.
Inlicere, ut ouperent vitam mu- i. 20, 52, and Phit. Plac. i. 7, 7
tare priorem 1 . . . (likewise ii. 3, 2 ; Stoi. i. 442),
Exemplum porro gignundis re- are quite in agreement.
bus et ipsa
.

GENERAL VIEWS ON NATURE. 439

tural basis for the Epicurean Ethics. If, therefore, Chap.


the Stoics had already followed Heraclitus in their ;_
views of nature, Epicurus followed Democritus still

more closely, and hence, with the exception of one


single point, the additions made by Epicurus to the
theory of this philosopher are philosophically un-
important.
With Democritus Epicurus agreed in holding (3) Atoms
"'"^ empty
that there no other form of reality except
is ^ that of '
space.
bodily reality. Every substance, he says in the
words of the Stoics, must affect others, and be
affected by them and whatever affects others or is
;

itself affected, is corporeal. Corporeal substance is,

therefore, the oply kind of substance.' The various


qualities of things, essential ones as well as acci-
dental ones, are not therefore incorporeal existences,
but simply chance modes of body, the former
being called by Epicurus crvfi^sffriKOTa, the latter,
avfiTTTw/jLara.^ But a second something is necessary

^
Imct. i.

Prseterea per se quodcumqne


erit ant faciet quid
440 : ^""1

^y-ra, oUr.
'"'""'
toC k^vov.

't^"""
'^"P^X^rai.
MM '
rb 5e

l""!""
K.^K)iv oUre
Si,a.raL,_^l^?,k

0.
^" ""'
A.7<-t
Aut fungi [W<rx.] debe-
aliis ^""i' ^

"<r"<iMT<,^ .i.a, r,;- >|,X^ Moram-


bit agentibus ipsmn, '

Aut erit, ut possint in eo res ^i""''-


"yA^" 7"? ^8raT -
I"
esse seriaue
"" "^''^ '"'''X"" " 'i" roiavTi,.

At facereet fungi sine corpore ," who


^"^^ ^^' ^^- ^f\'-
expresses .rM3e^,dra
449,
nulla potest lis,
Neo ^prsebere locum porro
^ nisi ^y conjuncta and <r.^7rT<MaT
. by eventa. Among the latter,

KT 11 ^
tertia ner se
_, jv, .,
Nulla potest rerum in J.
numero _ ,
-,

and only
,,' ,
i
comes to our know-
,
^^^^^ through motion and rest.
"
j.

,
i '

natnra reUnqui.
natura relinaui
Likewise Epicurus, in Siog. 72
Epic, in JDivff. 67 ko9' eavrh Se
: (conf. Stob. i. 252), shows that
oiiK etTTi voriaai ih aa^iMTOv wKiiv time is composed of days and
440 THE EPICUREANS.
Chap, besides corporeal substance in order to explain phe^
xvn.
nomena, viz. empty space. That empty space exists

is proved by the differences of weight in bodies


For what else could be the cause of this difference ?

It is more conclusively by motion, mo-


proved still

tion being impossible without empty space.'' Mine


as a moving cause, however, seems to Epicurus
altogether superfluous. Everything that exists con-
sists of bodies and empty space, and there is nc

third thing.^
Democritus had resolved the two conceptions o:

body and empty space into the conceptions of bein^


and not being. True to his position, Epicurus dis-
pensed with this speculative basis he holds to th( ;

ordinary notions of empty space, and of a materia,


filling space,* and simply proves these notions bj

nights, and their portions, of ' JJucret. i. 358.


states of feeling or unconscious- ''
Lucret. 1. c. and i. 329
ness, of motion or rest, and IHog. 40 and 67 ; Sext. Math
hence that it is only a product vii.213 viii. 329. Mostofth(
;

(o-ii|U?rTii);na) of these phenomena; remarks va Lucret. i. 846 anc


and these being again a-vinrrci- 582 point to the same funda
time is defined by the
fiara, mental idea: Without vacan
Epicurean Demetrius QSext. interstices, nourishment canno
Math. X. 219; Pyrrh. iii. 187): be diffused over the whol(
aiimraim trvinrTariTuv irapcTri!- bodies of plants or animals
f/.evov Tjfiepais re koI vu^i Koi &paLs nor can noise, cold, fire anc
Kal irdBeffi Kol oTradelais Kuluivii- water penetrate through solic
ireo-i Kol novcus. The distinction bodies, or any body be brokei
between abstract and sensuous up into parts. The same ii
or undivided time {Steinhart, Themist. 40, b ; Simpl. De CceIo
1. c. 466) does not appear to Schol. in Arist. 484, a, 26.
exist in Diogenes. His x?^""^ ' Lucr. i. 440 ; Diog. 39
Sid Klr^ov eeapjirol 47)
(^Diog. Pint. Adv. Col. 11, 5.
are imperceptibly small divi- * Body is defined by Epi
sions of time, tempora multa, curus {Sext. Math. i. 21 ; x
ratio que comperit esse, which, 240 ; 257 ; xi. 226) as t6 Tpixi
according to Luoret. iv. 792, are SiaurraThv nera avrnmlai, or a
contained in every given time. irivoSos kotb idpournhy jUE7e0ou:
; :

GENERAL VIEWS ON NATURE. 441

the qualities of phenomena. For this very reason Chap.


xvn.
Democritus' division of body into innumerable pri-
mary particles or atoms appeared to him most
necessary. All bodies known to us by sensation are
composed of parts,' If the process of division were
infinitely continued, all things, would ultimately be
resolved into the non-existent so Epicurus and
Democritus argue ;
and conversely all things must
have been formed out of the non-existent, in defiance
of the first principle of natural science that nothing
can come from nothing, and that nothing can be
resolved into nothing.^ Hence, we must conclude

Koi ffxht^'^'^os Kal &,VTtTtynlas KoX j8\T)To ^irep fi^ fjteWct irdvTa els
^dpovs. Emptiness is (accord- Ti liii hy <l>6apiiffeff6ai, i,\\' lirxi-
ing to Sext. X. 2) ^ia-is dvaipris ovTa uTFOfiepeiv 4u rais Sia\itT(Ti
or ^pTjfMos Travrbs ff^fiaros. When Ttjov (TvyKplaedtv , . . Sitrre ris
occupied by a body, it is called &px^s &T6fiOvs avayKotov etvai ffU'
.-6iros when bodies pass through
; fjidrtov tft/iffets. Ibid. 56 Ialgt.
;

it, it is x'^P" so that all three


; i. 147 ; ii. 551 ; 751 ; 790. Fur-
expressions, as Stob. Eel. i. 388, ther arguments for the belief
rightly observes, are only dif- in atoms in iMoret. i. 498
ferent names for the same Since a body and the space in
thing. To the same effect is which it is are entirely dif-
the statement in Plut. Plac. i. ferent, both must originally
20. have existed without any inter-
'
Hence, in Diog. 69, &8poi- mingling. If things exist com-
<r/ia and ffuii-neipopiifi.emi' are used posed of the full and the empty,
of bodies; in IHoff. 71, all the full by itself must exist,
bodies are called crufiirTdiixaTa and likewise the empty. Bodies
and according to Epicurus in which there is no empty
(_Sea!t. Math. x. 42), all changes space cannot be divided. They
in bodies are due to local dis- may be eternal, and must be so,
placement of the atoms. Plut. unless things have been pro-
Amator. 24, 3, p. 769, observes duced out of nothing. With-
that Epicurus deals virith a<t>ii out empty space, soft bodies
and a-viiirKoKii, but never with could not exist, nor hard bodies
without something full. If
' Epic, in Diog. 40 ; tSv <rai- there were no indivisible parts,
fidrav TO, jxev iffrt avyKpiffeis ra S' everything must have been
4| Sy cu avyxpifffis iTeiroir}VTai long since destroyed. The re-
TUVTa 5e iffriv &TOixa Kal afierd- gularity of phenomena presup-
;

442 THE EPICUREANS.


Chap, that the primary component parts of things can
!__ neither have come into existence nor cease to exist,
nor yet be changed in their nature.' These primary
bodies contain no empty space in themselves, and
hence can neither be divided nor destroyed, nor be
changed in any way.^ They are so small that they
do not impress the senses, and it is a matter of fact
that we do not see them. Nevertheless they must
not be regarded as mathematical atoms, the name
atoms being only assigned to them because their

bodily structure will not admit of division.' More-


over, they have neither colour, warmth, smell, nor
any other property ;
properties only belonging to
distinct materials;^ and for this reason they must
not be sought in the four elements, all of which, as
experience shows, come into being and pass away.^
They only possess the universal qualities of all

corporeal things, viz. shape, size, and weight.^


poses unchangeable primary ix. 219 x. 318
; ; Stob. Eel.
elements. All that is oompo- i. 306 Plvi. PI.
f
Phil. i. 3,
site must ultimately consist of 29.
simple indivisible parts. If " Epic, in Biog. 41 ; Lucret.
there were no indivisible parts, i. 528 ; Simpl. De
Coelo, Schol,
every body would consist of in Arist. 484, a, 23.
innumerable parts as many in ' Siog. 44 and
55 Iiueret. ;

the smaller as in the greater i. 266, where it is proved, by

body (conf Epic, in Diog. 56).


. many analogies, that there maj
If nature did not reduce things be invisible bodies Stob. 1. c. ;

to their smallest parts, it could Phd Simpl. Phys. 216, a,


1. c. ;

not make new things. These Diog. 44


' 54 Lucr. ii, ; ;

arguments, very unequal in 736 and 841 Pint. 1. u. See ;

value, were borrowed by Lucre- page 433, 2.


tins from Epicurus. Plut. in * Zwcret. v. 235.
]Sus. Pr. Ev. i. 8, 9, quotes, as ' Diog. ; Plut. Plac. i. 3, 29,
an Epicurean principle, that The statement there made, that
vinchangeable Being must be Democritus only allowed to
at the bottom of everything. atoms size and shape, and that
' Epicurus and Lucretius, Epicurus added weight, is not
1. c. Zucr. i. 529 Sext. Math,
; a correct one.
GENERAL VIEWS ON NATURE. 443

Not only must atoms, like all other bodies, have Chap.
-^^^
shape, but there must ex;ist among them indefinitely
many varieties of shape, or it would be impossible
to account for the innumerable differences of things.
There cannot, however, be really an infinite number
of such shapes, as Democritus maintained, in any
limited body, as is intelligible of itself, nor yet in
the whole universe,' since an unlimited number
would make the arrangement of the world impos-
sible, in the world everything being circumscribed
by certain extreme limits.^ Again, atoms must be
different in point of size ; for all materials cannot
be divided into particles of equal Yet even to size.

this difference there must be some bounds. An atom


must neither be so large as to become an object of
sense, nor can it, after what has been said, be in-
finitely small.' From difference in point of size
the difference of atoms in point of weight follows.^
In point of number atoms must be unlimited, and
in the same way empty space must be unbounded
also. For since everything bounded must be bounded
by something, it is impossible to imagine any bounds
of the universe beyond which nothing exists, and
hence there can be no bounds at all. The absence

'
Biog. 42 ; Lucr. ii. 333 figures as great as the nvimber
and 478 ; Plut. Plac. i. 3, 30 of atoms. {Hitter, iv. 101.)
(where, however, it would he ^ Lucret. i. 500.

against the sense to substitute ^ Diog. z. 55Lucr. ii. 381.


;

il for as Steinliwrt 1. c. p. 473


fi.'ti
' See the passages quoted,
note 94 does)'; Alex. Aphr. in p. 442, 6, and 445, 5. The
JPAi tf^. Gen. et Corr. 3, b ; Cic. text of Stoiceus, Eel. i, 346,
N. D. i. 24, 66. It does not, must be corrected by the aid of
however, appear that Lucret. these passages. Plvt. Plac. i.
ii. 333, made the variety of 12, 5.
444 THE EPICUREANS.
Chap. of bounds must apply to the mass of atoms quite af
xvn.
much as to empty space. If an indefinite numbei
of atoms would not find room in a limited space
conversely a limited number of atoms would be losi
in empty space, and never able to form a world.' Ii

all these views Epicurus closely follows Democritus


no doubt, agreeing with him also in explaining th(

qualities of things by the composition of their atoms.]


B. The In deducing the origin of things from theii
wwld.
primary causes, Epicurus, however, deviates widel]
(1) The
sreertiing from his predecessor. Atoms so it was taught b]
aside of
atoms.
both have by virtue of their weight been eternall]
engaged in a downward motion.' That all bodiei

' Epic, in Diog. 41 : aK\a follows too as a matter o:


fjL^v Koi rb Trap iwetpdv iari' rh course, that he referred all thj
yap Treirepafffievov &Kpov Ixet rh
properties of bodies to thi
5' &Kpov Trap' Tep6y ti Oeapeirat. shape and arrangement of the
SiiTTt oiiK ixov 6,Kpov vepas ouk atoms. Whenever he found ii
exei, irepas S' ohK Xov &Treipov ctv the same body different quali
eJfjj Kol ov Treirepair/i4voy. The tiescombined, he assumed tha
same argument is used by Zu- it was composed of differen
cret. i. 951 1008-1020. He; kinds of atoms. For instance
continues 984, 1021: If space he asserted of wine ovk eha :

were limited, all bodies would depfihv avTorehus rhy oivov, c(\A
collect towards its lower part Ixf" Tivas ar6tiOus iv ofrr^i Bep/ia
by reason of their weight, and ^las OTTOTeXeo-TiKcij, iTfpoi 5' a
their motion cease. Un-
would tf/vxp^TriTos. According to thi
less the quantity of matter diiference of constitution, i

were unlimited, the amount has on some a cooling, on other


lost by bodies in their mutual a heating efEect. Plut. Qu
contact could not be supplied. Conviv. iii. 5, 1, 4 Adv. Col ;

Oonf. also Plut. Adv. Col. 13, 6. This agrees with the re
3 in Mis. Pr. Bv. i. 8, 9 ; Plac.
; marks made on Democritus ii

i. 28 Alex, in Simpl. Phys.


3, ; vol. i. 597.
107, b, who mentions the argu- 47 CSc. N. E
Mog. 43 i
;

ment of Epicurus quoted above i. 20, 54. What


idea Epicuru
as the chief argument of the formed to himself of motioi
Epicureans. we are not told. We learn
' We have but little infor- however, from IJiemist. Phys
mation but it has been al-
; 52, b, that he replied to Aris
ready shown, p. 433, 2, and totle's proof of motion, that m
.

THE WORLDATOMS. 4A5

should move downwards in empty space seemed to Chap.


Epicurus a matter of course ; for whatever is heavy ^^""

must fall unless it is supported.' He was therefore


opposed to the Aristotelian view that heaviness shows
the form of attraction towards a centre,
itself in

and consequently to his further supposition that


downward mode of motion only belongs to certain
bodies, circular motion being for others more natural.^
The objection that in endless space there is no above

or below he could only meet by appealing to ex-


perience,^ some things always appearing above our
heads, others beneath our feet.* But whilst Demo-
critus held that atoms in their downward motion
meet together, thus giving rise to a rotatory motion,
no such view commended itself to Epicurus. Nay
rather all atoms will fall equally fast, since empty
space oflfers no resistance, and falling perpendi-
cularly it is impossible to see how they can meet.'
To render a meeting possible he supposed the

constant quantities can be com- a, 7. The latter writer inac-


posed of indiyisible particles curately groups Epicurus toge-
(Phys. vi. 1), by saying What- : ther with others (Democritus
ever moves in a given line and Strato). The same point,
moves in the whole line, but not according to Simjil. Phys. 113,
in the individual indivisible b, divided Alexander of Aphro-
portions of which the line con- disias and the Epicurean Zeno-
sists. With reference to the bius, at the close of the second
same question, the Epicureans, century after Christ,
' ks Aristotle had already
according to /Smj?2. Phys. 219, b,
asserted that everything moves done.
equally quickly through indivi- Diog. 60 conf Plut. Def
; .

sible spaces. Orao. 28, p. 425.


'
do. Fin. i. 6, 18 ; Lucret. = Epic, in Diog. 43 61; ;

i. 1074. Lti^r. ii. 225 ; Phd. C. Not. 43,


^ lAtor. ii. 1052 (the text 1, p. 1082. This objection was
being faulty) ; Simpl. De Coelo, borrowed from Aristotle by
Schol. in Arist. 510, b, 30 ; 486, Epicurus.
;

446 TRE EPICUREANS.


Chap, smallest possible swerving aside from the perpei
^^^^'
dicular line in falling. This assumption seemed t

him indispensable, since it would be otherwise in


possible to assert the freedom of the human wil
For how can the will be free if everything fal'

according to the strict law of gravity ? And for th


same reason this swerving aside was not supposed t

proceed from any natural necessity, but simply froi

the power of self-motion in the atoms.' In cor


sequence of their meeting one part of the atom
rebounds so Democritus also taught ; the lighte
ones are forced upwards, and from the upward an
downward motions combined a rotatory motio
arises.^ When motion takes place a clusterin
this
of atoms is the consequence, which by their ow
motion separate themselves from the remainin,
mass, and form a world of themselves.^ Atom
being eternal and unchangeable, the process c

forming worlds must go on without beginning o


end;' and inasmuch as they are also infinite i:

number, and empty space is infinite also, there mus


be an innumerable number of worlds.' In th
' Lucr. 316 251
ii. do. ; ;
* do. Fin. i. 6, 17. See j
Fin. i. 6, 18
N. D. i. 25, 69
; Hi, 3.
De Fato, 10, 22 Plut. An. ;
= j)igg ^5 .
73 .
i,^^,,^ ;
Procr. 6, 9, p. 1015 Solert. ; lOiS ; Pint. Plac. ii. 1, 3. ]

Anim. 7, 2, p. 964 Plac. i. 12, ; need hardly be remarked tha


5 ; 23, i Stobtsus, Eel. i. 346,
; by worlds world-bodies ai
394. hardly meant. In IHog. 8(
2 Dioff. 44 62 90
; oonf . ; ;
Epicvirus defines the world as
Plut. Plac. i. 12, 5 Fac. Lun. ; part of the heaven, surroundin
4, 5, p. 921 Stoi. i. 346
; Lu- ; the earth and stars, having
cret. V. 432. definite shape, and, toward
Diog. 73 ; Z^ior. i. 1021.
' other parts of the heaver
See above p. 437, 1 ; Plwt. Def. bounded.
Or. 19, p. 420.
; ;

THE WOBLBITS ORIGIN. 447

character of these worlds the greatest possible va- Chap.


'

riety may be most imlikely


supposed, since it is

that the innumerable combinations of atoms all


brought about at random will fall out alike.
Equally impossible is it to assert that all these
worlds are absolutely dissimilar. In general, Epi-
curus assumed that they are extremely different both
in point of size and arrangement, and that here and
there one may be similar to our own.* Moreover,
since eternity affords time for all imaginable com-
binations of atoms, nothing can ever be brought
about now which has not already existed.'' In one
respect all worlds are alike ; they come into existence,
are liable to decay, and, like all other individual
elements, are exposed to a gradual increase and
decrease.' So we might have assumed from other
positions in his system. Between the individual
worlds both Democritus and Epicurus insert in-
termediate world-spaces, in which by the clustering
of atoms from time to time new worlds come into
being.^
The origin of our world is thus described. At a (2) Origin

certain period
t^
of time Lucretius' believes at no "-^
*^f
world.
very distant period a cluster of atoms of varying
'
Diog. 45 74 ; 88
; ; Plut. world is proved
elaborately
Plao. ii. 2, 2 7, 3
;
Stoh. ; 490 i. Cic. Fin. i. i. 418
6, 21. Stoh. ;

do. N. D. ii. 18, 48 ; Acad. ii. Epicurus makes the world de-
40, 125. cay in the greatest variety of
" Plut. in Ens. Pr. Bv. i. 8, ways. Plut. Plac. ii. 4, 2.
* Diog. x. 89.
9 Epicurus says, 8ti ouSev ^ivov
:

airoTEAeiTai iv rif vavrl irapi rhv ' v. 324, arguing that his-

fiS-q yeyeim/iivov xp6vov &ireipov. torical memory would other-


' Mog. 73 ; 89 ; Lucret. ii. wise go much further back, and
1105 ; V. 91 and 235, where the arts and sciences be of much
transitory character of the greater antiquity.
448 THE EPICUREANS.
Chap, shape and size was formed in this definite portion o;
^^'^"
space. These atoms meeting, there first arose froir
the pressure and rebound of the quickly-falling

, particles motions of every variety in every direction


Soon the greater atoms pressing downwards, by dini
of weight forced upwards the smaller and lighte:
atoms, the fiery ones topmost and with the greatest
impetus to form the ether, and afterwards thos(
which form the air.' The upper pressure ceasing
these masses under the pressure of particles stil

joining it from below, spread forth sidewards, anc


thus the belts of fire and air were formed. Nex
uprose those atoms out of which the sun and star
are formed into the heights, and at the same timi

the earth settled down, its inner part being partiall;


exhausted in those places where the sea now is. B;
the influence of the warmth of the ether, and th
sun-heat, the earth-mass was bound together mor
closely, the sea was pressed out of it, and the surfao
assumed an uneven character.^ The world is shu

On this point see Lucret,


' views of Epicuius on the foi
ii. 1112. The principle that mation of the world do nc
similar elements naturally con- entirely agree with those c
gregate is there explained in Democritus. It was probabl
this way. with an eye to Democritr
^ Luor. V. 416-508 Phit.
; (compare the extracts in vol.
Plac. i. i. The latter view has 608 from Orig. Philosoph. ]

been referred, in vol. i. 604, to 17) that Epicurus, in Diog. 9i

the Atomists. It would now denied that the world could I


appear that it must be deduced from without, or thi
increfised
from Epicureanism, and its sun and moon could in this wa
agreement with the views attri- be possibly absorbed in o\
buted to Leucippus in other world. I/iicret. ii. 1105, hovj
places explained by the well- ever, supposes an increase (

tnown connection between Epi- the world from without to I


ourus and Democritus. The possible.
;

THE WORLDITS ARRANGEMENT. 449

off from other worlds and from empty space by thoKe Chap.
xvn.
bodies which form its external boundary, I

Asking, in the next place, what idea must be (3) Ar


formed of the arrangement of the world, we are met ^y"^^'

by the two principles which Epicurus is never weary


of inculcating ; one, that we must deduce nothing
from an intentional arrangement by deity, but refer
everything simply and solely to mechanical causes
the other, that in explaining phenomena the widest
possible scopemust be given to hypotheses of every
kind, and that nothingis more absurd than to abridge

the extensive range of possible explanations by ex-


clusively deciding in favour of any one.^ Thereby
the investigation of nature loses for him its value as
such, nor is it of any great interest to us to follow
his speculations on nature into detail. On one point
he enters a protest, viz., that the framework of heaven
must not be considered the work of God,^ nor must
life and reason be attributed to the stars.* Other-
wise, on nearly all the questions which engaged the
attention of astronomers at that time, he observes
the greatest indifference, treating the views of his
predecessors, good and bad alike, with an easy super-
ficiality which can only be explained by supposing
him altogether careless ^ as to their truth. The state

On these moenia mundi,


' * In Diog. 77 81 Imcret.
; ;

which, according to Lucretius, v. 78 and 114, where the con-


coincide with the ether or fire- trast is more fully brought out.
belt, see Epic, in Diog. 88 ; Id. By C^a oipdvta, in Plwt. Plac. v.
irepl ^iaeios, xi. (Vol. Here, ii.) 20, 2, we must by no means
col. 2 ; Plut. Plac. ii. 7, 3 ; Luer. think of the stars.
i. 73; ii. 1144; v. 454. " Exampleshave already
2On this point see page 434. been met with, p. 436. A com-
'See p. 437, 1. plete review of the Epicurean
G G
450 THE EPICUREANS.
Chap, of his own astronomical knowledge can, moreover
^^^"
be easily seen by recalling the notorious assertion
that the sun, the moon, and the stars are either noi
at all, or only a little larger, and may possibly b(

even less than they appear to be. The Epicureans


alsothought to support their theory that the earth
borne by the air, reposes in the middle of the work
a theory which on their hypothesis of the weight
of bodies is impossible ^by the gradual diminutioi
in weight of the surrounding bodies.^ It would b(

impossible here to go through the treatment whicl


they gave to atmospheric and terrestrial phenomena
particularly as the principle already indicated wa
most freely used, and many explanations were givei
as being all equally possible/
astronomy is not worth our with tire. According to Lticrel
while. It may be studied in v. 471, sun a;nd moon stan(
the following passages For the : midway between ether an<
substance of the stars, consult earth in point of density.
PUt. Plac. ii. 13, 9 for their ;
"^
It is still more difficult ti

rising and setting, Biog. 92; imagine the world as stationary


iMcr. V. 648 ; Cle&med. Met. p. which is tacitly assumed. I
87 ; for their revolution and would then be bounded by end
deviation, Dioij. 92 112-114 ;
; less space, and soon come inti
Lucr. V. 509 ; 612 ; for the ap- collision with other masses,
pearance of the moon, Diog. " Iaiot. v. 534. Conf. Epic
94, and Imcr. v. 574, 703 for ; in Biog. 74, and Tfpl ^ia^ws, xi
eclipses of sun and moon, Biog. col. 1. In the latter passage
96 Lucr. v. 749 for changes
; ; Epicurus appeals to the fac
in the length of day, Biog. 98 ;
that the earth is equidistan
Lucr. V. 678. from the bounds of the world.
' Biog. 91 do. Acad. ii.
; Further particulars oi :

26, 82 ; Fin. i. 6, 20 Sen. Qu. ; clouds, Biog. 99 Lucr. vi. 451


;

Nat. i. 3, 10 Cleomed. Met. ii.


; Plut. Plac. iii. 4, 3 ; on rair
1 ; Phd. Plac. ii. 21, 4 ; 22, 4 ;
Biog. 100 Lucret. vi. 495 ; o
;

imcr. V. 564. The body of the thunder, Biog. 100; 103; i*


sun was considered by Epicurus cret. vi. 96 ; on lightning, Bioi
{Plut. Plac. ii. 20, 9 Stoh. i. ; 101 ; Ltiar. vi. 160 on sirocci
;

530) to consist of earth-like Biog. 104 laicr. vi. 423 Pla(


; ;

and spongy matter, saturated iii. 3, 2 on earthquakes, Bim


;
MANKIND: THEIR ORIGIN. 451

Out of the newly-made earth plants at first grew,' Chap.


and afterwards animals came forth, since the latter, !_
according to Lucretius, can by no possibility have (*) -P^*

fallen from heaven.^ In other worlds, likewise, living rnals.

beings came into existence, though not necessarily in


all.' Among these beings were originally, as Einpe-
docles had previously supposed,^ all sorts of compo-
site or deformed creatures. Those, however, alone
continued to exist which were fitted by nature to find
support, to propagate, and to protect themselves from
danger. Eomantic creatures, such as centaurs or
chimaeras, can never have existed here, because the
beings of which they are compounded would require
conditions of life * altogether different.
Aiming, as the Epicureans did, at explaining the C. Man-
kind.
origin of men and animals in a purely natural man-
ner, they likewise tried to form an idea, equally ac- of the
cording to nature, of the original state and historical
development of the human race, ignoring in this

105 ; Zncr. vi. 535 ; Plao. iii. Otherwise, we learn that the
15, 11 ; Sen. Nat. Qu. vi. 20, 5 ;
Epicureans attributed to plants
on winds, i)!o<7. 106; on hail, a soul, just as little as the
Biog. 106 ; Plac. iii. 4, 3 ; on Stoics. Pint. Plac. v. 26, 3.
snow, thaW, ice, frost, JDiog. 'Lucr. ii. 1155 v. 787, giv-
;

, 107-109 on the rainbow, Diog.


; ing further particulars as to
109 on the halo of the moon,
; the origin and maintenance of
Diog. 110; on comets, Biog. living beings, and the subse-
111; on shooting- stars, Biog. quent abatement of the produc-
114. Explanations are given tive powers of earth,
by Lucretius of volcanoes (vi. ' Epic, in Biog. 74.
639), of the overflow of the * Anaximander, Parmenides,
Nile (vi. 712), of Lake Avernus Anaxagoras, Diogenes, of Apol-
(vi. 738-839), of the magnet Ionia, and Democritus, all
( vi. 906-1087), of the reputed taught the procreation of living
chilling of the springs in sum- beings from earth,
mer (vi. 840). ' Lucr. v. 834-921.

' Litcret: ii. 1157; v. 780.


G o 2
452 THE EPICUREANS.
Chap, attempt all legendary notions. On this point, not-
1_ withstanding their leaning towards materialism, they
Miman q^ i)^q whole advocated perfectly sound views. The
race.
men of early times, so thought Lucretius, were
stronger and more powerful than the men of to-day.
Eude and ignorant as beasts, they lived in the woods
in a perpetual state of warfare with wild animals,
without justice or society.' The first and most im-
portant step in a social direction was the discovery
of fire, the learning to build huts, and to clothe
themselves in skins, when marriage and domestic
life began,'' when speech, originally not a matter of
convention, but, like the noises of animals, the na-
tural expression of thoughts and feelings, was deve-
loped.* The older the human race grew, the more
they learned of the arts and which minister to skill

the preservation and eigoyment of life. These arts


were by experience, under the pressure of
first learnt
nature, or the compulsion of want. What had thus
been discovered was completed by reflection, the
more gifted preceding the rest as teachers.* In ex-
'
V. 92^-1008. Conf. Plato, tA ?6j/7) Tct rSia Tcfl?</ai irpbs il
Polit. 274, B ; Arist. Polit. ii. -ras SijXtio-eis ^ttov aiJupifi6\ovs
8, 1269, a, 4 ; Horace, Serm. i. yevia9ai i.Wi\\oLs Koi avvroim-
3, 99, appears to have had an repair SijAou/ieVas. He who in-
eye to Lucretius. vents any new thing puts, at
iMor.
^ 1009-1025. V. the same time, new words into
' Epicurus, in IHog. 75, thus circulation. Luoret. v. 1026-
sums up his views on the origin 1088, explains more fully that
of language t& ovdfiara 4^ : language is of natural origin,
apxv^ M^ fleirei yev4iT6ai, dx\' On the voice, Itid. iv. 522
aiTos Tcks (piffeis tS>v SivSpanriov Plut. Plac. iv. 19, 2.
Kci6' eKoiTTo iSvTt fSio naaxo^'f^s * Epic, in Diog. 75 : aX\^ jutji
irddr] KoX iSia \afj.Pavovffas <^av- {nroKTjTrreov Koi ri]i/ twv avOptSiiriai
Ttto'^uaTa iSiws itv h.4pa iKirefitreiv tpifftv ttoWcl koL iravTota {nrh rai
, . vffrepov 5e Koivws Kaff UKatrra atrr^v Trepietrrc^ay trpaynATWv Si
MANKIND: THE SOUL. 463

actly the same way civil was developed. Indi-society Chap.


XVII.
and made themselves rulers.
viduals built strongholds,
In time the power of kings aroused envy, and they
were massacred. To crush the anarchy which then
arose, magistrates were chosen, and order established
by penal laws.' It will subsequently be seen that
Epicurus explained religion in the same way by na-
tural growth.
The apotheosis of nature, which has been appa- (2) TU
soul.
rent in Epicurus's whole view of history, becomes
specially prominent in his treatment of psychology.
This treatment could, after all that has been said, be
only purely materialistic. The aoul, like every other

real being, is a body. In support of this view the

Zax'Srtval re Koi ava.yKaiTBriva.i ' T^tv men how to work


in metal (v.
Se Koyiffiihv rh inrh rairtjs irapey- 1239-1294). Horses and ele-
yvri&^vTa Kol vffTepov 4TraKpi&ovv phants were used for help in
Kal irpotre^evpifTH.^lv, iv fxev Tifft war, after attempts had been
QarTov iv 5e tun Ppad6repov. previously made with oxen and
Lucr. v. 1450 :
all arts wild beasts (v. 1295). Men
first dressed themselves in
tJsus et impigiEe simul experien-
skins; afterwards they wore
tia mentis
twisted, and then woven ma-
Paulatim docuit. terials (v. 1009; 1348; 1416).

Um. 1103 : The first ideas of planting and


agriculture were from the na-
Inqiae dies magis hi viotum vi-
tural spread of plants (v. 1359).
tamque priorem The first music was in imitation
Commutare novis monstrabant of birds the first musical in-
;
rebu' benigni
strument was the pipe, through
Ingenio qui prsestabant et corde which the wind was heard
vigebant. from this natural
to whistle ;

In harmony with these pre- music, artificial music only gra-


mises, Lucretius then tries to dually grew (v. 1377). The

explain various inventions. The measure and arrangement of


first fire was obtained by light- time was taught by the stars
ning, or the friction of branches (v. 1434)and, comparatively
;

in a storm. The sun taught late, came the arts of poetry


cooking (v. 1089). Forests on and writing (v. 1438).
fire, melting brass, first taught ' iMor. v. 1106.
454 TRE EPICUREANS.
Chap. Epicureans appealed to the mutual relations of the
XVII
L_ body and the soul, agreeing on this point with the
Stoics.' The body of the soul, however, consists of
the and most easily-moved atoms, as
finest, lightest,

is manifest from the speed of thought, from the in-


stantaneous dissolution of the soul after death, and,
moreover, from the fact that the soulless body is as
heavy as the body in which there is a soul.'' Hence
Epicurus, again agreeing with the Stoics, describes
the soul as a material resembling fire and air,* or,

more accurately, as composed of four elements, fire,

air, vapour, and a fourth nameless element. It con-


sists of the finest atoms, and is the cause of feeling,"
and according as one or other of these elements pre-
ponderates, the character of man is of one or the
other kind.' Like the Stoics, Epicurus believed that
the soul-element is received by generation from the
parents' souls,^ and that it is spread over the whole
body,^ growing as the body grows.' At the same
time he makes a distinction somewhat similar to
that made by the Stoics in their doctrine of the

' Liter, iii. 161 ; Siog. 67. ' Liicr. iii. 288.
See p. 439, 1. According to Plut. Plao.v.
"

^ Liier. iii. 177 Diog. 63.


; 3, 6, he considered the seed an
' Diog. 63 : n i/iux^) aani iari andairaarim ^vxvs Kol etijxaTos ;

Kivroiiifiis trap' i\ov rh &6pouxiia and, since he believed in a fe-


(the body), Trapeairafiiivov
vpo- minine afipua, he must have
irefi(/)peVTaTov 54 iri/erJ/iOTi Stpfiou regarded the soul of the child
Tina Kpa(Tiv fx""''''- S6 ii aTi/iuv : as formed by the intermingling
avT^v (TvyKeifrSai Xeiordrui/ Ka\ of the soul-atoms of both
trTpoyyvKordTav iroW^ tivl 5(o- parents. Xbid. V. 16, 1.
^epouo-Si" TMy ToC Truprfi, ' Diog. 63; iwCT'rf. iii.
216;
* Liwr. iii. 231 269 Plut. ; ; 276 323 370.
; ;

Plac. iv. 3, 5 (Stoi. i. 798), conf. Metrodor.


' irepl ai<rei}rm
Alex. Aphr. De An, 127, b. (Vol. Here, vi.), col. 7.
MANKIND: THE SOUL. 466

sovereign part of the soul (j^ysfioviKov).^ Only the CnAP.


XVII.
irrational part of the soul is diffused as a principle
of life over the whole body ; the rational part has its

seat in the breast.^ To the rational part belongs


mental activity, sensation, and perception, the motion
of the will and the mind, and in this latter sense life

itself; both parts together make up one being, yet


they may exist in different conditions. The mind
may be cheerful whilst the body and the irrational
soul feel pain, or the reverse may be the case. It is

even possible that portions of the irrational soul may


be lost by the mutilation of the body, without detri-
ment to the rational soul, or consequently to life.'
When, however, the connection between soul and
body is fully severed, then the soul can no longer
exist. Deprived of the surrounding shelter of the
body, its atoms are dispersed in a moment, owing to
their lightness ;and the body in consequence, being
unable to exist without the soul, goes over into cor-
ruption.'' If this view appears to hold out the most
> Ztior. iii. 98, contradicts ' Mog. and Zuor. In sleep,
the assertion that the soul is a portion of the soul is supposed
the harmony of the body Epi- ; to leave the body (JDuw. iv.
curus having already replied 913, conf. Tertull. De An. 43),
(in Philop. De An. B. 1) to one whilst another part is forcibly
of the objections urged against confined within the body. Prob-
it by Plato. ably this is all that is meant
Diog. 66 ; Tmct. iii. 94 ;
2 by JOiog. 66.
136 396 ; 613 Plut. Plac. iv.
; ; Epic, in Diog. 64. Luer.
'

4, 3. Lucretius calls the ra- iii.417-827, gives an elaborate


tional part animus or mens, and proof of the mortality of the
the irrational part anima. The soul. Other passages, Phit.
statement, PI. Phil. iv. 23, 2, N. P. Suav. Vivi. 27, 1 and 3 ;
that Epicurus made feeling re- 30, 5 Sext. Math. ix. 72, hardly
;

side in the organs of sense, be- need to be referred to. Ob-


cause the T\yf)ju>viK>>ii was feel- serve the contrast between Epi-
ingless, can hardly be correct, oureanism and Stoicism. In

456 THE EPICUREANS.


Chap, gloomy prospect for the future, Epicurus considers
XVII.
that it cannot really be so. With life every feeling
of evil ceases,' and the time when we shall no longer
exist affects us just as little as the time before we

existed.^ Nay, more, he entertains the opinion that


his teaching alone can reconcile us to death by re-
moving all fear of the nether world and its terrors.^

Allowing that many of these statements are na-


tural consequences of the principles of Epicurus, the
distinction between a rational and an irrational soul
must, nevertheless, at seem strange in a
first sight
system so thoroughly materialistic as was that of the
Epicureans. And yet this distinction is not stranger
than the corresponding parts of the Stoic teaching. If
the Stoic views may be referred to the distinction
which they drew in morals between the senses and the
reason, not less are the Epicurean ethics marked by
the same contrast between the general and the sen-
suous side of the mind. Hence Epicurus shares the
Stoic belief in an etherial origin of the human race ;''

stoicism, the soul keeps the oiK iffiitv. Id. in Sent. Pyrrh.
body together; in Epicurean- iii. 229 (_Alex. Apli/r. Anal. Pri.
;,ism, the body the soul. In 117, Top. 9. Gell. N. A. ii. 8,
Stoicism, the soul sumves the 1 ; Stob. Serm. 118, 30) 6 eiva- :

bady ; in Epicureanism, this is tos ouSek xpbs T]ii.as rb yhp Sia-


impoSsible. In Stoicism, the \v6hv avaia^SiiTf!, rh Sk avaiarBii-
mind js^J^nower over the world, toCv ovS^ii irphs rjiias, Z/uer, iii.
and henc&over the body in ; 828-975.
Epicureanism, it is on a level ^ lAior. iii. 830.

with the body, and dependent ' Diog. 81 142 ; Lucr. iii.
;

on it. 37.
' Epic, in Diog. 124-127, for ' IJuor. ii. 991 :
instance t!) fpiicmSfaTaTov oiv
: Denique coelesti sumus omues
Tmv KaKuv i Bdvaros oiSiv irpbj semine oriundi, &c.
fifjicis' iireihiyirep Sray jiiv Tjfiels 999 ;

Sliev b BdvuTos oh iriptaTiv


Cedit item retro de terra quod
STav 8^ i idvaros irapfi T<iS' ^jUfis fuit ante
MANKIND: SENSATION. 467

and although this belief as at first expressed only Chap.


implies that man, like other living beings, is ^
composed of etherial elements, yet there is connected
with it the distinction already diseased in the case
of the Stoics between the higher and the lower
parts of man, which ultimately comes to be simply
another mode of expressing the difference between
mind and matter.
Among the phenomena of the soul's life sen- (3) Senm-
sation is made to harmonise with the general prin-
ciples of the Epicurean view of nature by the aid
of Democritus' doctrine of atom-pictures (sl'SfuXa).

From the surface of bodies this is the pith of that


doctrine the finest possible particles are constantly
being thrown off, which by virtue of their fineness,
traverse the furthest spaces in an infinitely short
time, hurrying through the void.' Many of these
exhalations are arrested by some obstacle soon after
their coming forth, or are otherwise thrown into
confusion. In the case of others the atoms for a
long time retain the same position and connection
which they had in bodies themselves, thus presenting
a picture of things, and only lacking corporeal
solidity. As these pictures are conveyed to the soul
by the various organs of sense, our impressions of
things arise.^ Even these impressions, which have

In terras : et quod missum est of this theory, makes them


ex setheris oris mould the air.
Id rursum coeli rellatum tem- ^ Epic, in Biog. 46-50 ; 52 ;

pla receptant. and in the fragments of the


' Democritus, from whom second book irepl tjiiaeus ; Lucr.
Epicurus has borrowed the rest iv. 26-266 722 vi. 921.
; ; Oio. Ad
;

458 THE EPICUREANS.


Chap, no corresponding real object, must be referred t
'_ such pictures present in the soul.' For often pic
tares last longer than things themselves ^ and ofte;
;

by a casual combination of atoms pictures are formei


in the air resembling no one single thing. Some
times, too, pictures of various kinds are combined o
their way to the senses ; thus, for instance, th
notion of a Centaur is caused by the union of th
picture of a man with that of a horse, not only i:

our imagination, but already previously in the atom


picture.^ If, therefore, sensation distorts or im
perfectly represents real objects, it must be explaine
as being due to some change or mutilation in th
atom-pictures before they reach our senses.''

In thus explaining mental impressions, the Epi


cureans do not allow themselves to be disturbed b
the fact that we can recal at pleasure the ideas c

all possible things. The cause of this power wa


rather supposed to be the circumstance that we ar
always surrounded by an innumerable number c
atom-pictures, none of which we perceive unless ou
attention is directed to them. Likewise the seemini

Famil. xv. 16; Pint. Qu. Con- PZwf.Def. Orao. 19,p. 42C
^

viv. viii. 10, 2, 2; Plac. iv. 3, 1; ei


^P^ yeXav iv (/nAo(ro<(>(a r
Se
19, 2 ; Hext. Math. vii. 206 ("SaKa yiXnuneov rk Ranpk k(
Gell. N. A. V. 16 Macrob. Sat. ; Tv^pKa Kal &i\ivx^a, h. iroi/iafi/oua-i
vii. 14 ;the remarks of lAicr. [sc. of 'EirofoiipEioi] hitXiTov^ h-i
iv. 267 568 Plut. Plac. iv. 14,
; ; irepMovs iii.ipaiv6ixiva koi ireptvoa
2, on reflected images and the tovvto. ir&vni ra nii/ %ti (Jiina
echo belong likewise to the ri Si viKai KoraKaii'Toiv ^ ki
doctrine of idola. TaffaTrfvruv ano^^v^vra.
^ For instance, the impres- ' Luer. 1. c.
sions in the minds of dreamers ' iSext. 1. c. ; Liter, ii
and madmen. Diog. 32 Lucr. ; 351.
iv. 730.
MANKIND: THE WILL. 459

motion of forms which we behold in dreams is Chap.


explained by the hasty succession of similar atom- '_^

pictures, appearing to us as changes of one and the


same picture.' But besides receiving pictures sup-
plied from without, spontaneous motion with regard
to these pictures takes place on our part, a motion
connected in the first instance with the soul's

motion when it receives the outward impression,


but not to be regarded as a simple continuation
thereof. This independent motion gives rise to
opinion, and hence opinion is not so necessary or so
universally true as feeling. It may agree with feel-
ing, or it may not agree with it. It may be true or
it may be false.^ The conditions of its being true
or false have been previously investigated.^
Impressions also give rise to will and action, the (4) Will.

soul being set in motion by impressions, and this


motion extending from the soul to the body.'' Into
the nature of will, however, Epicurus does not
appear to have instituted a more careful psycho-
logical investigation. It was enough for him to

assert the freedom of the will. This freedom he


considers absolutely indispensable, if anything we
'
Iiucr. iv. 766-819 ; and on iviiiapTup-qBy fi avTiixafnufyne^ rb
the incessant streaming forth ifietSos yiveTai, 4av Se iirtjiap-
of images, v. 141 Dioff. 48.
; TupTjflJ ^ nil oi/Ti/iapTupjiSp rh
Epic, in XHoff. x. 51 rh Se
''
: iAijAw.
ovK hv tntripxev, ei " As to terminology, Bpi-
SifinapTTififvov
nil i\aii.$dyoiJLev Kol fiWiji/ Tivck curus, according to Plut. Plac.
niuriiriv 4v ri/uv avTois ffvvi\fLiiiv7iv iv. 8, 2, Diog. 32, called the
li.(v, iiiK-rp^iv [al. SuiKu-^a/] S' faculty of sensation rfo-fljjo-ii,
exoMav Kara Si Toririjv rifv and sensation itself, iTraladritia,

T^ {pavraiTTiK^ i-rri-
ffuvTjfifievqj/
* I/iwr. iv. 874 ; conf. Galen.
PoX^ [impression on the senses], De Hipp, et Plat. v. 2, vol. v.

Siihrpfiiv S' ix""""''' ^^^ >"' i"^ ^^^' ^-


460 THE EPICUREANS.
Chap, do is to be considered our own, if we are nc
L_ prepared to despair of moral responsibility altogethei
and to resign ourselves to a comfortless and inexoj
able necessity.' To make freedom possible, Epicuru
had introduced accident into the motion of atoms z
we have seen, and for the same reason he denies th
truth of disjunctive propositions which apply to th
future.'* In the latter respect, he, no doubt, onl
attacked the material truth of two clauses, with on
impugning the formal accuracy of the disjunction,
i.e., he did not deny that of two contradictory cas

either one or the other must happen, nor did h


deny the truth of saying To-morrow Epicurus wi :

either be alive or not alive. But he disputed th


truth of each clause taken by itself. He denied th
truth of the sentence, Epicurus will be alive ; an
equally that of the contradictory, Epicurus will nc
be alive ; on the ground that the one or the oth
statement only becomes true by the actual realisatio
of an event at present uncertain.^ For this h
' Diog. 133: rb Se Trap' yifias least says, referring to the abov
dSeffTToTov
^ KoX -rh fiefiwrhv Kol question : Nisi forte voluimi
rh 4]/avTiovTrapaKo\ovde7t''ir4<^vKv. Epicureorum opinionem seqn
^Trel KptiTTov ^v Tif TTEpl Oeuv liiBtp qui tales propositiones nee vers
Ka.TaKo\ov6itv fi Tp tUv ^vtrMuv nee falsas esse dicunt, aut cui
iixapp.ivTi SouKiieiv. id pudet illud tamen dicun
^ N. D. i. 25, 70 [Epi-
Cic. : quod est impudentius, vera
Gurus] pertimuit, ne si conces- esse ex coutrariis disjunctione,
sum esset hujusmodi aliquid : sed qu in his enuntiata esser
aut vivet eras aut non vivet eorum neutrum esse verun
Epicurus, alterutrum fieret ne- Cicero indeed adds : admirs
cessarium totum hoc
; aut ; bilem licentiam et miserabilei
etiam aut non negavit esse ne- inscientiam dicendi but h
I

cessarium. Acad. ii. 30, 97 ;


has no reason for this exclams
De Fat. 10, 21. tion; for the proposition
' Steinluwt, p. 466. Either A or B must follow i

* Cic. De Fato, 16, 37, at not identical with the propos:


MANKIND: THE WILL. 461

deserves little blame. Our real charge against him Chap.


^^^^-
is that he did not more thoroughly investigate the
nature of the will and the conception of freedom,
and that he treats the subject of the soul as scantily

and superficially as he had treated the subject of


nature.

tion It
: may be stated either of allow the former and deny the
A or of B that it will follow, latter. In so doing he is really
Epicurus could, therefore, justly following Aristotle.
.

462 THE EPICUREANS.

CHAPTER XVIII.

TIEWS OF EPICUKUS ON RELIGION.

Chap. Satisfied with the results of his own enquiries int


XVIII
nature, Epicurus hoped by his view of the causes (

A. Criti- things not only to displace the superstitions of


the gods polytheistic worship, but also to uproot the prejudic
and the
j^ favour of Providence. Indeed,' these two obiec
populm- _
'

faith. were placed by him on exactly the same footinj

So absurd did he consider the popular notions r(

specting the Grods, that far from blaming those wl


attacked them,' he believed it impious to acquiesc
in them. Eeligion being, according to. Lucretiu
the cause of the greatest evils,^ he who displaces
to make way for rational views of nature deservi
praise as having overcome the most dangeroi

' Diog. X. 123 : otovs 8' oi- In terris oppressa gravi sub r<
Toifs [toiis 06oi5] ol ttqWoX Void- ligione,
^OhSiv ovK elalii- oti yiip (pv\aT- Quffi caput a coeli regionib
roviTiv aiiTohs o'tovs vofil^ovcnv. osteudebat
affefiiis Se oxix ^ Til's Tto;' iroW&v Horribili super aspeotu mort
6eovs avuipat/ ctAA.' S rks ruy iroX- libus instans, &c.
K^, S^l' 9^5 ^po(r<iTto^. Conf
Cic. N. D. 1. 16, 42.
^^ ^^^ ^ ^o 101 :-
'
iii. U
49 and, spe-
; vi. ;
Tantum relhgio potuit suadc
cially, the celebrated passage
maiorum.
i. 62 : Conf. Epic, in Diog. 81, ai
Humana ante oculos foede cum above, p. 423, 3 437, 1.
;

vita jaoerst
:

THE GODS OF POPULAR FAITH. 463

enemy of mankind. All the language of Epicurus Chap.


xvin.
in disparagement of the art of poetry applies in a
still higher degree to the religious errors fostered by
poetry.' Nor is it better with belief in Providence
than with the popular faith. This belief is also
included in the category of romance and the doc- ;
^

trine of fatalism, which was the Stoic form for the


same belief, was denounced as even worse than the
popular faith.' For how, asks the Epicurean, could
divine Providence have created a world in which evil
abounds, in which virtue often fares ill, whilst vice
is triumphant ? How could a world have been made
for the sake of man, when man can only inhabit a
very small portion of it ? How could nature be in-
tended to promote man's well-being when it so often
imnerils his and labour, and sends him into the
life

world more helpless than any animal ? How can we


form a conception of beings ruling over an infinite
universe, and everywhere present to administer every-
thing in every place ? * What could have induced these
how and whence could
beings to create a world, and
they have known how to create it, had not nature
supplied them with an example?' In fine, how
'
Heraclit. AUeg. Horn. c. 4 Cic. N. D. i. 8, 18, the Epicurean
['ETrUoupos] airaaav d/iov ironjTi- calls irpdvoia anua fatidica, to
(cJlv Sffirep oKiSfiov f>.i%mv d4\ttp which it was often reduced, no
a^aa-ioifievos. Ibid. c. 75. doubt, by the Stoics.
2 Plut. Def. Orac. 19, p. ' See p. 460, 1.
420: 'EiriKuupeiW Si x'^^"'^!^"^' * Luer. v. 196; ii. 1090;
Kol 7e'\wTas otiTi <)>o;87)TV oTj T0\- Plut. Plac. i. 7, 10. Conf. the
fiuai xi"!"^"'^ '"'' ""'''' ''^^ "''"'" disputation of the Stoic and
voias liVeoy avT^v airoKoAovvTcs. Epicurean in iwcmre, Jup. Trp.g.
v;. 35, and especially c. 46.
N. P. Suav. Viv. 21, 2; 8iaj3a\-
* Zucr. v. 165 ; conf.
Xovres T^v wp6miav Sxrwep iraialv p. 437,
"Efivavcrav ^ Xloiiniv aMrriptdSri 1 ; Plut. Plao. i. 7, 8.
KOI TpayiKr>)V ^viyeypann^vTiv. In
464 THE EPICUREANS.
Chap. could God be the happy Being He must be if tl
XVIII.
whole burden of caring for all things and all even
lay upon Him, or He were swayed to and fro togeth
with the body of the world ? ' Or how could we fe

any other feeling but that of fear in the presence


such a God who troubles himself about everything
B. Tlie With the denial of the popular Gods, the denial
gods ao-
cvrding to
demons,^ of course, goes hand in hand, and, togeth
Mpio^i/rris. with Providence, the need of prayer^ and of prophei
(1) Rea- is at the same time negatived.' All these notior
sons for
his belief. according to Epicurus, are the result of ignoraui
and fear. Pictures seen in dreams have been c6:

founded with real existences; regularity of motion:


the heavenly bodies has been mistaken by the ign
God 'events which accidental
rant for the work of ;

happened in combination with others have bei


regarded as portents phenomen ; terrific natural
storms and earthquakes, have engendered in mer
minds the fear of higher powers.^ Fear is therefo
the basis of religion ;
^ and, on the other hand, fre
dom from fear is the primary object aimed at 1

philosophy.
For all that, Epicurus was unwilling to renoun^
> Diog. 76; 97; 113; seep. = Biog. 135; lAicr. v. 37

437, 1; Cic. N. D. i. 20, 62; Plut. Plac. V. 1, 2 Cic. N. ; D


Pint. Plac. i. 7, 7. 20, 55 ; Divin. ii. 17, 40 ; Tt
2 Cic. 1. c. 54. tull. De An. 46.
' Phit. Def. Or. 19; Plac. Lucr. V. 1159-1238 coi
;

i. 83. iv. 33 vi. 49 Sext. Math, ; ; i

* Conf. the captious aigu- .25 vi. 19 Biog. 98 115. ; ; ;

ment of Hermarchus, in Prod. ' This view is especial


in Tim. 66, E If prayer is ne- prominent in Lucretius.
: S
cessary for everything, it is p. 462, 2. Oonf. Plut. N".
necessary for prayer, and so on, Suav. Viv. 21, 10 do. N. D. ;

ad infin. 20, 54.


THE GODS OF POPULAR FAITH. 465

belief in the Grods,' nor is it credible that this un- Chap.


XVIII.
willingness was simply a yielding to popular opinion.^
The language used by the Epicureans certainly gives"
the impression of sincerity; and the time was past
when avowed atheism was attended with danger.
Atheism would have been as readily condoned in the
time of Epicurus as the deism which denied most
unreservedly the popular faith. It is, however, pos-
sible to trace the causes which led Epicurus to
beUeve that there are Gods. There was first the
general diffusion of a belief in Grods which appeared
to him to establish the truth of this belief, and hence
be declared the existence of Gods to be something
directly certain, and grounded on a primary notion
{irpoXTj^jni).^ Moreover, with his materialistic theory
of knowledge he no doubt supposed that the primary
notion which convinces us of the existence of Gods
arisesfrom the actual contemplation of divine beings,
and from the perception of those atom-pictures from
which Democritus had already deduced the belief in
Gods.'' And in addition to these theoretical reasons,

'
He drew up separate trea- gens aut quod genus hominum
tises irepl Beuv and Trtpl dtrtSTTiros. quod non habeat sine doctrina
Biog. 27 Cic. N. D. i. 41, 115 ;
;
anticipationem quandam Deo-
Pint. N. P. Suav. Viv. 21, 11. rum ? quam appellat Trp6\ri\fiiv
^ Posidonius, in Cic. N. D. Epicurus, &c. These statements
i. 44, 123; Conf. 30, 85; iii. must, however, be received with
1, 3 Pint., 1. c.
;
some caution, since Cicero ap-
' Epic, in Diog. 123 fleol /iw : pears to give up his own views
y6.p fifft ' iyapyi]s juev ydp iariv as to innate ideas. Inasmuch
avTav ri yvuKris. The Epicurean however as he expressly refers
in Cic. N. D. i. 16, 43 : Solus to Epicurus' treatise irfpl Kav6-
enim [Epicurus] vidit, primum vos, we may assume that belief
esse Deos quod in omnium ani- in Gods with Epicurus rests on
mis eorum notionem impressis- a general Trp6\ri'fiis.
set ipsa natura. Quae est enim * In support of this view,

H H
46& TRE EPICURHANS.
Chap. Epicuras had also another, half assthetical, half
XVIII.
religious- the wish to see his ideal of happiness realised
in the person of the Gods," and it is this ideal which
determines the character of all his notions respect-
ing the Grods. His Gods are therefore, throughout,
human beings. Eeligious belief only knows beings
such as these, or, as Epicurus expresses it, only such
beings come before us in those pictures of the Gods
which present themselves to our minds, sometimes
in sleep, sometimes when we are awake. Eeflection,
too, convinces us that the human form is the most
beautiful, that to it alone reason belongs, and that
it is the most appropriate form for perfectly happy
beings.^ Epicurus even went so far as to attribute
to the Gods difference of sex.' At the same time
everything must be eliminated which is not appro-
priate to a divine being.
see do. N. D. i. 1 8, 46. It is na esset et beatissima . . . et
there said of the form of the metus omnis a vi atque ira
Gods : A natura habemus omnes Deorum pulsus esset. IHd. 20,
omnium gentium speciem nul- 56 : We
do not fear the Gods,
lam aliam nisi humanam Deor- et pie sanoteque colimus na-
um. Quffi enim alia forma oo- turam excellentem atque prte-
cuirit umquam aut vigilanti stantem. IKd. 41, 115. Sen
cuiquamautdormienti? ipviriK^ Benef.iv. 19,3; Epicurus denied
here referred to sen-
Trp6\ri^is is all connection of God with th
sations derived from efSuAa. world, but, at the same timO;
Ibid. 19, 49 and Zucr. vi. 76
; : would have him honoured as i
De corpore quae sanoto simu- father, propter majestatemejui
lacra feruntur eximiam singularemque natu.
In mentis hominum divinse ram.
nuntia formse. ^ Cio. N. D. i. 18, 46 ; Divin
IHog. 121.
' Cic. N. D. i. ii. 17, Sext. Pyrrh. iii. 218
40 ;

17, 45 Si nihil aliud quasrere-


: Plut. PI. Phil. i. 7, 18 (^Stoi. i
mus, nisi ut Deos pie coleremus 66); PJtcsdr. (Philodem.) Fragm
et ut superstitione liberaremur, col. 7 Metrodot-ns, ircpl niVSr;
;

satis erat dictum nam et prses-


: ruv (Vol. Here, vi.), col. 10
tans Deorum natura hominum col. 16, 21.
pietate ooleretur, cum et seter- ^ Cic. N. D i. 34, 95.
; ;

THE GOBS OF POPULAR FAITH. 467

The two essential characteristics of the Gods, Chap.


according to Epicurus, are immortality and perfect/^
happiness.' Both of these characteristics would be (2) -^'a-

impaired were we to attribute to the bodies of the the Ejnmi,-


Grods the same dense corporeity which belongs to our ''^'^"^ S^As.

own. We must, therefore, only assign to them a


body analogous to our body, etherial, and consisting
of the finest atoms.'^ Such bodies would be of little
use in a world like ours. In fact, they could not
live in any world without being exposed to the tem-
poral ruin which will in time overwhelm it, and,
meantime, to a state of fear, which would mar their
bliss. Epicurus, therefore, assigns to them the space
between the worlds as their habitation, where, as
Lucretius remarks, troubled by no storms, they live
under a sky ever serene.^
Nor can these Grods be supposed to care for the
world and the affairs of men, else their happiness
would be marred by the most distressing occupations
but perfectly free from care and trouble, and abso-
lutely regardless of the world, in eternal contem-
plation of their unchanging perfection, they enjoy
the most unalloyed happiness.'' The view which the
'
Epic, in Diog. 123 TrpuTov : Epicurus has, as Cicero re-
liiv liv Behv Qfov &(pBapTOv KaX marks, monogrammos Deos his ;

It-axapiov voij.l(a}v . . . firiSiy /iiiTe Gods have only quasi corpus


TTjs lupeapa-las aKKdrpiov /liirerfis and quasi sanguinem. They
liaicapi6rrrros avo'iKnov avT$ irpba- are perlucidi and perflabiles, or,
aiTTe, K.T.\. /W(Z. 139. Cic.N. D. according to Lucr., tenues, so
i. 17,45; 19, 51; Imcr. ii. 646 that they cannot be touched,
V, 165. and are indestriictible.
" hid. N. D. ii. 23, 59 ; i. 18, ' do. Divin.ii.17, 40; Luor.
49 ; 25, 71 ; 26, 74 ; Divin. ii. ii.646 iii. 18
; v. 146
; ; Sen.
17, 40 ; Lucr.Y. 148 ; Metrodor. Benef. iv. 19, 2.
Pint. 1. ^. ' Epic, in Hiog. 77 97
irepl aia&ifrav, col. 7 ; ; :

H H 2
;
;

468 THE EPICUREANS.


Chap. School formed to itself of this happiness we learn
xvin.
from Philodemus.' The Gods are exempt from sleep,
sleep being a partial death, and not needed by beings
who live without any exertion. And yet he believes
that they require nourishment, though this must, q\

course, be of a kind suited to their nature. Thej


also need dwellings,'^ since every being requires some
place wherein to dwell. Were powers of speech tc

be refused to them, they would be deprived of th(

highest means of enjoyment the power of convers-


ing with their equals. Philodemus thinks it pro-

bable they use the Greek or some other closely-aUiec


language.' In short, he imagines the Gods to be i

society of Epicurean philosophers, who have every-


thing that they can desire everlasting life, no care
and perpetual opportunities of sweet converse. Onlj
such Gods, the Epicureans thought," need not b
feared. Only such Gods are free and pure, and wor-
139 do. N. D. i. 19, 51
; assigned that \4yoinai ij.ii iro^i
(amongst other things nos : Staipepoiffais Kara ras apBpdffei.
autem beatam vitam in animi XP^^^^^ ^uvats, koX fi6vov oXSafie]
securitate et in omnium vaca- jGyovdras Seohs 'EX\7jj/iSt yAt^TTi
tione munerum ponimns, both XP'"!"^'''""- The first statemeni
of which features must there- seems to refer to the words &.
fore be attributed to the Gods) the divine language quoted bj
Iiegff. i. 7, 21 ; Imcr. ii. 6i6 Homer ; the second statement,
iii. 1092 ; iv. 83 ; vi. 57 ; Sen. to stories of appearances of the
Benef iv, . 4, 1 ; 19, 2. Conf .
p. Gods. For the whole tone o:
436 464, ; 1 ; 466, 1. the system militates againsi
' In the fragments of his our thinking of men who havf
treatise irtpl rfis tZv BeSiv ei(r- afterwards become Gods. Th(
Toxov/i4vris5iayayyris,KaTii.Z-fivuvaf sceptical question, Whethe:
col. 12. the Gods possess speech ? raisec
^ The KXfcrm discussed by by Carneades in Sext. Math, ix
Hermarchus and Pythocles, col. 178, appears to refer to thii
13, 20, had reference to these, fivBoKoyla 'Evixoipov.
and not to ordinary feasts. " Cic. N. D. i. 20, 54 ; Sen
' Col. 14: The reason being Benef. iv. 19, 1.
THE GODS OF POPULAR FAITH. 469

shipped because of this very perfection.' Moreover, Chap.


XVIII.
these Gods are innumerable. If the number of
mortal beings is infinite, the law of counterpoise re-
quires that the number of immortal beings must not
be less.^ If we have only the idea of a limited num-
ber of Gods, it is because, owing to their being so
much alike,^ we confound in our minds the innume-

Philodem. De Mus. iv. (V.


' these words appears to be, that
Here, i.) col. 4, says that the ideas of the Gods are not formed
Gods do not need this worship, in the same way as the ideas of
but it is natural for us to show other solid bodies, by a number
it : ix6Xi<TTa fxii/ btriais irpoKii^eaiv, of similar pictures from the
eiretTa Se KaX Tots /caret rb Koi.Tpiov same object striking our senses
napaSiZofiivois Kd(Trtp rSiv Kara (nee soliditate nee ad numerum,
fJL^pOS. Diog. X. 95), but by single pic-
2 do. the sen-
1. 0. i. 19, 50, tures emanating from innumer-
tence, interimant,
et si quae able divine individuals, all so
belonging, however, to Cicero much alike, that they leave be-
only. For Epicurus cannot hind them the impressions of
have described his ease-taking perfect happiness and immor-
Gods as sustainers of the uni- tality. The passage of Diog.
X. 139, ought probably to be
Cie. N. D. i. 19, 49 (Epi- : corrected by that in Cicero.
curus) docet earn esse vim et It runs y &\7^is Si <\>t\in, robs
:

naturam Deorum ut primum 6eobs \6ytp 6eup717obs elvai- ots


non sensu sed mente cernatur : fiev Kar^ apt0fihv v(pe(rTUTas, ots
nee soliditate quadam nee ad Se tcar^ 6iJ.oeiSiav iK Trjs truvexoSs
numerum ut ea, quae ille prop- ^nt^^direws twv dfjLolav eiStiiKuv ^irl
ter firmitatem aTipiiivta appel- rb avrh d7roTT6Aeo'/Aej/ous avdpai-
lat, sed imaginibus similitudine TToeiSSis. The similarity of most
et transitione perceptis: cum of the expressions leaves no
infinita simillimarum imagin- doubt that Diogenes followed
um species ex innumerabilibus the same authority as Cicero
individuis exstat et ad Deos (probably the same as Pint,
(probably instead of Deos, Plae. i. 7, 18 followed), but in
which gives no sense, we should the words ois fih k.t.\., it asserts
read nos. See the commenta- the very opposite of this and
tors in the editions of Moser the Epicurean teaching. There
and Kreuzer) affluat, eum maxi- must, therefore, be some error
mis voluptatibus in eas ima- here, either due to Diogenes
ginesmentem intentam infix- or a copyist. This error does
amque nostiam intelligentiam not apparently belong to the
capere quEe sit et beata natura words kot' apiOfihv, which Cicero
et seterna. The meaning of renders ad numerum, so that
:

470 THE EPICUMEANS.


Chap, rable pictures of the Gods which are conveyed to our
xvni. ,
souls.

Pridinsr themselves in contrast to the Stoics on


their agreement by means of this theology with the
anthropomorphic views of the popular belief, and
even outdoing polytheism in the assumption of in-
numerable Gods,' the Epicureans were willing to
join in the customary services of religion,^ with-
out being nearly so anxious as the Stoics to prove
themselves in harmony with the popular creed.
Whilst the Stoics in their anxiety to do this had
plunged head over heels into allegory, no such ten-
dency is observed on the part of the Epicureans.

Only the poet of the School gives a few allegorical


interpretations of mythical ideas, and does it with
more taste and skill than is usual with the Stoics.^

SteinliaH's suggestion, p. 477 natural substances of the Stoics


Knfl' ap^nbj/ or /cafl' ap^uoiir is clearly resemble Gods (col. 9) to fleio :

wrong. It is more probably to ToiauTo KaraKelirovcnv h Koi yiv-


be found in the words ofiy fiiv vnra koI <{)8apTci (palverai, ro7s S<
o6s 8e. "We might suggest iracnv rifieTs aKohovSais aiilovs Kaifi-

for oOs jLie^. ou fjisvTOL. Bdprovs elvai Soy^Ti^ofiev. Here


In Plued/rus {PJdlodeni.
' we have a phenomenon wit'
Trepl u(r/3e(oj),Fragm.col.7(10) nessed in modern times, Deisti
it is said in answer to the Stoics and Pantheists mutually accus
^7ri^eiKvvaQoiua.v Tois troWols 'iva ing one another of atheism
)i6vov {Bibv] aitarra. AeyovTes oiiSe the former missi\ig personality
vivras Sffous ri Koix-)) </)^/i)j irape- the latter missing activity ii
SwKGy, T]fji5ii/ ou ^6vov '6ffovs ^aaXv the deity of their opponents.
o( Tlav4Wf\ves ctAA.^ itaX vKftovas " See
p. 469, 1.
elvai heydvruif ^Treifl' (Jti toioiJtous * I/iiC7'. ii. 598, explains thi

ouSe fxefivKaffiv airoKelTreiv, oiovs Mother of the Gods as meanini


ffE/SocTai TtivTcs Kol riixits dfio- the earth, ii. 656, he allow
Koyovnev. avdpuiiroeiSeTs yap iKe7- the expressions, Neptune, Geres
mi ov voiiiQovaiv aWb, afpa iial Bacchus, for the sea, corn, an(
jtvevp-ara icai al94pa, liar' eytoye wine. iii. 976, he interpret
Ka! Tefla^^ijudTws fliraiiii toutouj the pains of the nether-worli
iiay6pov /laWov -nKtifiiieXeiv, It as the qualms now brought O]
is then shown how little the by superstition and folly.
THE GODS OF POFULAR FAITH. 471

On other points the Epicureans, not excluding Lu- Chap.


cretius, observe towards the popular faith a negative ;

attitude, that of opposing it by explanations ; and


by this attitude, without doubt, they rendered one
of the most important services to humanity.
472 THE EPICUREANS.

CHAPTEE XIX.
THE MORAL SCIENCE OF THE EPICUKEANS. GENERAL
PHINCIPLES.

Chap. Natural science is intended to overcome the preju-


XIX.
dices which stand in the way of happiness ; mora]
A. Plea- science to gire positive instructions as to the nature
sure.
(1) Pha- and means of attaining to happiness. The specula-
ture the
tive parts of the Epicurean system had already worked
higliest
good. out the idea that reality belongs only to individual
things, and that all general order must be referred
to the accidental harmony of individual forces. The
same idea is now met with in the sphere of morals,
individual feeling being made the standard, and in-
dividual well-being the object of all human activity.
Natural science, beginning with external phenomena,
went back to the secret principles of these pheno-
mena, accessible only to thought. It led from an
apparently accidental movement of atoms to a uni-
verse of regular motions. Not otherwise was the
course followed by Epicurus in moral science. Not
content with human feelings alone, nor with selfishlj
referring everything to the individual taken by him-
self alone, that science, in more accurately defining the
conception of well-being, ascertained that the same
;

PLEASURE THE HIGHEST GOOD. 473

can only be found by rising superior to feelings and Chap.


'

purely individual aims, and by that very process of


referring consciousness to itself and its universal
being, which the Stoics declared to be the only path
to happiness. It is for us now to portray this deve-
lopment of the Epicurean platform in its most pro-
minent features.
The only unconditional good, according to Epi-
curus, is pleasure ; the only unconditional evil is

pain.' No proof of this proposition seemed to him


to be necessary ; it rests on a conviction supplied by
nature herself, and is the ground and basis of all our
doing and not doing.^ If proof, however, were re-
quired, he appealed to the fact that all living beings
from the first moment of their existence pursue plea-
sure and avoid pain,^ and that consequently pleasure
is a natural good, and the normal condition of every

being.'' Hence follows the proposition to which Epi-


curus in common with all the philosophers of plea-

1
Epic, in iMo^. 128 :tV^S<'- 23; 9, 30; ii. 10, 31; Sext.
i.px^v Kcl teAos \4yonsv elxai
v'tiv Pyrrh. iii. 194 Math. xi. 96.
;

ToS liaxafiai Q,v . TrpuTov . .


" Stob. Bcl. ii. 58 tovto S' :

ayaBhv tovto koI O'i/iipmov . . . [the teAos] ol kut' 'EAoupof


ircura. olv ^5oi/j) . . . ayMv. . . . <jii?^oa-o<povvTes ov irpoo-Se'xoi'Tai

Ka.66.Tref /col &Kyr\ii>v iraffa KaK6v. Xiynv ivepyoijifvov, 5i& t!i iraSij-
lUd. 141. Cic. Fin. i. 9, 29 tmIv uiroTifleo-eai rii tc'Aos, ob
Tusc. V. 26, 73 : Cum prseser- vpaKTm6v ifiov^ ydp HBsp Kal
tim omne malum dolore defi- t^iv ivvoiav a7roS/S(fain toS teAous,
niat, bonum voluptate. rb omsIws SiareBeTa-eai i^ coutoO
' '
Sioff. 129 Tairnvyiip i.ya9hv
: irphs airhv X"p"'S t^* ^''''' &^>^o re
irpwTOv Ka\ (TvyyevtKhv eyvafiev airda-ris iiriffoKTis. Alex. Aplir.
Kal &Tri> Tairris KaTapxi/^^Ba vda-ris De An. 154, a : tois Se irepl "Etti-
alpeaeas Kai (tiivyvs Kal eVl Tairriv Kovpov riSoyii Tb irpSnov o'ikuov
KaTavTH/iev its Kavivi t^ iriBa l5o Jex eli/ni aTrAcSi irpoiivTav Si
t6 &7oebv KpivovTfs. Pint. Adv. SLapBpovaBai TaliTi\v t'Iiv iiSoviiv

Col. 27, 1. *"''-


' Diog. 137 ; do. Fin. i. 7,
474 THE EPICUREAm.
Chap, sure appealed, that pleasure inust be the object of
1_ life.

(2) Free- At the same time, this proposition was restricted


domfrom
paAn,. m
. .

the Epicurean system by several considerations.


. -. .

In the first place, neither pleasure nor pain are simple


things. There are many varieties and degrees of
pleasure and pain, and the case may occur in which
pleasure has to be secured by the loss of other plea-
sures, or even by pain, or in which pain can only be
avoided by submitting to another pain, or at the cost
of some pleasure. In this case Epicurus would have
the various feelings of pleasure and pain carefully
estimated, and in consideration of the advantages
and disadvantages which they confer, would under
circumstances advise the good to be treated as an
evil, and the evil as a good. He would have plea-
sure forsworn if it would entail a greater correspon-
ding pain, and pain submitted to if it holds out the
prospect of greater pleasure.' He also agrees with
Plato in holding that every positive pleasure pre-
supposes a want, i.e. a pain which it proposes to

remove and hence he concludes that the real aim


;

and object of all pleasure consists in obtaining free-


dom from pain,^ and that the good is nothing else
' Diog. 129 Cio. Fin. i. 14,
; -rov aiinaros ir/Uiav Kol -r^v Tr\s
48 ; Tusc. v. 33, 95 Sen. De ; '^vxns arapa^lav. eirel tovto toS
Otio, 7, 3. /xaKapiais Cv^ ^^"^^ t4kos. roirov
Epic, in Biog. 139 (^Gell.
''
ykp xipiv SjrarTa wpdrToiiiv Sirms
N. A. ii. 9, 2) bpos rov /j.ey48ous
: tii\Tea\yu^sv liAirs rap^a^Liv 'drav
'

rwv Tidovwv 71 Ttavr})<! rod aXyovv- Se Sttr^ tovto wepi i]fias yei/TjToi
Toy inre^aipefTls. Id. in Diog. \uTat iray b t^s ^"X^^ x^^f^^v
128: ToiroiV yhp [raiv i^iBvu.iSov'^ ovk ^^ot'Tos tov ^t^ov ^dSiCetf us
aiT\av^s Qeapia traoav atpetriv Kal trphs iv^idv ri .
. tots ykp
.

ipiiy')]v i-jravayayiiv olSev ivl t^iv ^Soc^s xP^^"'" ^X"/*^"? ''rav eK tow
;

PLEASURE IS FREEDOM FROM PAIN. 476

but emancipation from evil.' By a Cyrenaic neither Chap.


repose of soul nor freedom from pain, but a gentle 1_
motion of the soul or positive pleasure was proposed
as the object of life and hence happiness was not
;

made to depend on man's general state of mind, but


on the sum-total of his actual enjoyments. But
Epicurus, advancing beyond this position, recognised
both the positive and the negative side of pleasures,
both pleasure as repose, and pleasure as motion.^
Both aspects of pleasure, however, do not stand on
the same footing in his system. On the contrary,
the essential and immediate cause of happiness is
repose of mind arapa^ia. Positive pleasure is

only an indirect cause of arapa^ca in that it re-


moves the pain of unsatisfied craving.^ This mental
repose, however, depends essentially on the character
of a man's mind, just as conversely positive pleasure
in systems so materialistic must depend on sensuous
attractions. It was consistent, therefore, on the part
of Aristippus to consider bodily gratification the
highest pleasure ; and conversely Epicurus was no

/AT/ irapilvai t^v 7}5oj/^v aKywfiev


'
of ivefr/eia/^yapyeic}, but ivepyeit^
Srac Sf fj.il a\yaiiv ovKiTi rrjs gives a very fair meaning they :

^Boi/ijs 8e(!|Uefla. Hid. 131 ; Hi appear actually in motion. Sen.


oonf. Plut. IS. P. Sua. Viv. 3, Ep. 66, 45: Apud Bpiourum
10 ; Stoi. Serm. 17, 35 ; Zuei: duo bona sunt, ex quibus sum-
ii. 14; fifj. Fin. i. 11, 37. mumilludbeatumquecomponi-
' Epicurus and Metrodorus, tur, ut corpus sine dolore sit,

in Plut. 1. c. 7, 1. animus sine perturbatione.


2
Dioff. 136, quotes the words
' Hence Sun. Brevit. Vit. 14,
of Epicurus ri /a-h jhp arapa^ia
: 2 : Cum Bpicuro quiescere.
Kal airovia KOTaffTjj/iOTiitof eiaiv Benef iv. 4, 1 Quffi maxima
. :

riSovai, v Se x^P" i"*' eiiippocrivTi Bpicuro felioitas videtur, nihil


Kara Khrjo-iv ivepyela fiXenofrai. agit.
Ritter. iii. 469, sugg'ests instead
476 TEE EPICUREANS.
Chap. less consistent in subordinating it to gratification of
xrx.
mind.
In calling pleasure the highest object in life, says

Epicurus, we do not mean the pleasures of profligacy,


nor, indeed, sensual enjoyments at all, but the free-

dom of the body from pain, and of the soul from dis-

turbance. Neither feasts nor banquets, neither the


lawful nor unlawful indulgence of the passions, nor
the joys of the table, make life happy, but a sober
judgment, investigating the motives for action and
for inaction, and dispelling those greatest enemies of
B. Intel- our peace, prejudices. The root from which it springs,
leetual
happiness.
and, therefore, the highest good, is intelligence.' It
(1) Intel- is intelligence that leaves us free to acquire posses-
ce.
sion thereof, without being ever too early or too late.'
Our indispensable wants are simple, little being ne-
cessary to ensure freedom from pain ; other things
only afford change in enjoyment, by which the quan-
tity is not increased, or else they rest on a mere sen-
timent.* The little we need may be easily attained.
' Dwg. 131. Similar views <t>cov oihe yap &upos oi/Sels iffnv
are expressed by Metrodorus, oijT Trdpwpos irpbs rh Kara 4'uxV
in Clement, Strom, v. 614, B, in iyiaivoy. He who says it is too
praise of philosophers who early or too late to study philo-
escape all evils by rising to the sophy means irphs eiSaiiiovtav fi

contemplation of the eternal fjL'fiTTU t^v &pav ff


Tcapeiifai fitiKeri
Kadapol KaX atr'fifiavTOi roi/Tov, h Svai. Id. in Sen. Bp. 8, 7:
vvv ffufia neptfpepoures ovofxd^oiiev. Philosophiae servias oportet, ut
Id. in Plut. Adv. Gol. 17, i: tibi contingat vera libertas.
'jroi'fi(rci}fjLef Tt KoKhf ^irl Ka\oiSf ' Epic, in Diog. 127 rwv iiri- :

lx6vov oh KaraSivTes Ttus dfioiotra- Qvfiiuv at fi4v eiffi <pv(rtKaX at Se


Beiats Kol anaJtLXayepTes ix tov Kevai' Kal tSiv (pvatKwv at /liv
XaM''^ ^'^'*^ ^'^ '^^ 'ETTi/coi/pou ws hvayKoiat al 6^ tpvfftKol ^6vov. ruv
a\Tjdus 0e(J(^avTa &pyta. Sk SivayKaiav at jitcc irpbs v5a-
' Epic in Diog. 132 /ii^re v4os
: fioviav ehrlv avayKoiai, at Se irphs
Tis &j/ fxeWfTu <pt\0(ro(t}eii/ fi'fjre riiv TOV aiiimros u.oxKri<rlav, at 5e
yepuv i)TT6,px^v KiyiriiiTco ^i\o{ro- irphs aiirh t6 fpf. Ibid. 149,
;
; ;;

INTELLECTUAL HAPPINESS: INTELLIGENCE. 477

Nature makes ample provision for our happiness, Chap


XIX.
would we only receive her gifts thankfully, not for-
getting what she gives in thinking what we desire.'
He who lives according to nature is never poor ; the
wise man living on bread and water has no reason to
envy Zeus ;^ chance has little hold on him with him ;

judgment is everything,^ and if that be right, he


need trouble himself but little about external mis-
haps.^ Not even bodily pain appeared to Epicurus
so irresistible as to be able to cloud the wise man's
happiness. Although he regards as unnatural the
Stoic's insensibility to pain,' still he is of opinion that
the wise man may be happy on the rack, and can
smile at pains the most violent, exclaiming in the
midst of torture. How sweet !
^ A touch of forced
sentiment may be discerned in the last expression,
and a trace of self-satisfied exaggeration is manifest
even in the beautiful language of the dying philo-
sopher on the pains of disease.' Nevertheless, the

further particulars are given as koX Kvpit^Tara 6 ^y^oytfffihs Sic^KT]tte.

to the classes. Ibid. 144; Lucr. The like in Stob. Bel. ii. 354;
ii. 20 ; da. Fin. i. 13, 45 Tusc. ; Cic. Fin. i. 19, 63 Sea. De ;

V. 33, 94 Plut. N. P. Sua. Viv.


; Const. 15, 4 ; Epicurus and
3, 10 Mostrat. Eth. N. 48, b
; Metrodorus in do. Tusc. v. 9,
Sen. Vit. Be. 13, 1. 26, and Plut. Aud. Po. 14, p.
'
Sen. Benef. iii. 4, 1 Epi- : 37.
euro .qui adsidue queritur,
. .
' Diog. 135 : Kpurrov eTi/ai

quod adversus prteterita simus vofiiCav evKo-yi(rTas viTvxe'!vfia\o-


ingrati. Epic, in Sen. Ep. 15, yla-Tas einvxeiv.
10 Stulta vita ingrata est et
:
= Phd. N.
P. Sua. Tiv. 20, 4.
trepida, tota in futurum f ertur Diog. 118 ; Plut. 1. c. 3, 9
'

and Iaict. iii. 929. Sen. Ep. 66, 18 67, 15 ; Cic. ;

2 Diog. 11 130 144 146;


i ; ; Tusc. v. 26, 73.
Stob. Floril. 17 23 30 34; ; ; ;
' Diog. 22 Cic. Fin. ii. 30,
;

Sen. Ep. 2, 5; 16, 7; 25,4. 96; Tusc. ii. 7, 17; M. Aurel.


' IKog. 144 Ppax^'ia (ro<p$
: ix. 41 Sen. Ep. 66, 47 92, 25
; ;

rixv irapeii-irlirTet, tA (/.eyiara. U Plut. N. P. Sua. Tiv. 18, 1, the


.

478 THE EPICUREANS.


Chap, principle involved is based in the spirit of the Epi-
L_ curean philosophy, and borne out by the testimony
of the founder. The main thing, according to Epi-
curus, is not the state of the body, but the state of
the mind ; bodily pleasure being of short duration,
and having much about it to unsettle mental enjoy- ;

ments only being pure and incorruptible. For the


same reason mental sufferings are more severe than
those of the body, since the body only suffers from
present ills, whilst the soul feels those past and
those to come.' In a life of limited duration the
pleasures of the flesh never attain their consum-
mation. Mind only, by consoling us for the limited
nature of our bodily existence, can produce a life

complete in itself, and not standing in need of un-


limited duration.^
(2) Bea- At the same time, the Epicureans, if consistent

riitw''
^^''^ their principles, cannot deny that bodily plea-
superiorto sure is the earlier form, and likewise the ultimate
source, of all pleasure, and neither Epicurus nor his
favourite pupil Metrodorus shrunk from making this
admission ; Epicurus declaring that he could form

latter perverting Epicurus' 33, 96. Tlie Epicureans desig-


words to a terrible extent. nated bodily pleasure by 5)Sfo--
' Biog.lST: ^TmphsToiisKv- Bai, mental by x'^^P^'"- Pint.
fnjva'iKobs Bia(pepTai. oi fxev yctp 1. c. 5, 1
X^Lpovs T^s aoifiariKas a\y7td6yas ^ Diog. 145. Epicurus ap-
Keyovai -rav ^iXiK&v Se
. . . iS pears to have first used trApf to
ihs ^f/vx'iids. tV 70E1' a-apxa Sia express the body in contrast to
rb vaphy jiivov x^'f^<^C^"'t ''''hv Se the soul, iru/ta, in his system,
^vxh" K"! 5'^ t!) TrapfABhv Koi rh including the soul. See Diog.
iraphv Koi rh iiiWov. oStids oZv 137 140
; 144 ;Metrodor. in
;

Kol fxel^ovas ^Soccis elvai ttjj if/u- Plut. Colot. 31, 2. (^Pliit. in
Xijs. Further particulars in N. P. Suav. v. 16, 9 Plut. has ;

Phtt. 1. c. 3, 10 : Cic. Tusc. v. yaaTpX instead of (rapKi.)


;

INTELLECTUAL HAPPINESS. 479

no conception of the good apart from enjoyments ' Chap.


XIX.
of the senses Metrodorus asserting that everything
;

good has reference to the belly .^ Still the Epicu-


reans did not feel themselves thereby driven to give
up the pre-eminence which they claimed for goods
of the soul over those of the body. Even the Stoics,
notwithstanding the grossness of their theory of
knowledge, never abated their demand for a know-
ledge of conceptions, nor ceased to subordinate the
senses to reason, notwithstanding their building a
theory of morals on nature. But all character has
vanished from their joys and their pains. Their only
distinctive feature can be found in the addition either
of memory, or of hope, or of fear ' to the present feel-
ing of pleasure or pain ; and their greater importance
is simply ascribed to the greater force or duration
belonging to these ideal feelings as compared with
the attractions which momentarily impress the senses.*

' Diog. X. 6, from Epicurus T^jy aKporoiTfiv x^P^" "' fiefiaio-


TTCpi T\ovs : oil yhp c7W7e eX" ri TdTT]V e^^t Tois ^TviKoyi^i<rQa.f. Suca-
voiiffoi Tctyoflbv iupaifitbv iiiv ris fievois. IMd. 5, 1 : ri fi^v t}^6-
Sta x^Kwv '/]Soj/a,s, atpatpwu Se Kol fievov Trjs capKh^ Ttfj x*^^P*"'t* "^V^
Ttks Si' atppoSLfriwv Kol ras 5i' ctKpo- ^UXVS uirepeiSocres, aSQis S' iK tov
aiidruv Kal ras 5ii ^op<pas {-rjs'). X'^'P^^TOS elj -rh 7]S6iJLepov rp
The like, in a more expanded iXiriSt reKevruvras.
form, in Cic. Tusc. iii. 18, 41. ' Conf., besides the extracts
= Pint. 1. c. 9 iis Kal
16, : on p. 478, 1 and 2, Cic. Fin. i.
ix'^P't" I""' iBpacrvpdfiTiv ire ifiaSov 17, 55 : Animi autem voluptaa
irop' "Eirmoipov opBas yanTpl (see et dolores nasci fatemur e .cor-
previous note) x'P'f'''^' > and : poris voluptatibus et doloribus
Trep! yaarepu yiip, S> <j>vcno\6ye it isonly a misapprehension on
Ti^(i/cpaTs, tIi aya66y. Conf. the part of several Epicureans
ibid. 3, 1. to deny this fact. Mental plea-
8ee p. 478, 1, and Epic, in
" sures and pains may therefore
Plut. N. P. Suav. V. 4, 10 rb : be the stronger ones for the
yhp fia-iaeis (rapKhs KaTiar-niw, reasons assigned above.
Koi t6 irepX Tairris marhv iKiriaiia
: ;

480 THE EPICUREANS.


Chap. Only accidentally is the remembrance of philosophic
XIX.
discourses mentioned ' as a counterpoise to bodily

pain ;
properly speaking, mental pleasures and pains
are not different from other pleasures in kind, but
only in degree, by reason of their being stronger and
more enduring. Accordingly Epicurus cannot es-
cape the admission that we have no cause for reject-
ing gross and carnal enjoyments if these can liberate
lisfrom the fear of higher powers, of death, and of
sufferings ^ and so the only consolation he can offer
;

in pain is the uncertain one that most violent pains


either do not last long, or else put an end to our life
and the less violent ones ought to be endured since
they do not exclude a counterbalacing pleasure.'

Hence victory over the impression of the moment


must be secured, not so much by a mental force
stemming the tide of feeling, as by a proper esti-
mate of the conditions and actions of the senses.
(3) ViHve. In no other way can the necessity of virtue be
established in the Epicurean system. Agreeing with
the strictest moral philosophers, so far as to hold
that virtue can be as little separated from happi-
ness as happiness from virtue,^ having even the tes-
timony of opponents as to the purity and strictness

' In his last letter (Siog. i. 15, 49 ; Plut. And. Po. 14, p.
22), after describing his pain- 36 ; M. Aurel. vii. 33, 64.
ful illness, Epicurus continues Diog. 140: ovk effTiK ^Se'ws
*

avTLirapeTdrTeTO Se Tram Tovrois ^fv &vev rod (jtpovifiws Kol KaKus


Kol SiKaius oiiSi (ppovlfitos Kal 5i-
yeyov6ra)v Tjfui/ ZtaKoyiffiiSov fivij' Kalas &vv Tov ri^eus. The same
MI)- p. 132, 138. Cic. Tusc. v. 9,
2 JKog. 142 ; Cie. Fin. ii. 7, 26 Fin. i. 16, 50
; ; 19, 62 ; Sen.
21. Ep. 85, 18.
= IHog. 140 ; 133 ; do. Fin.
INTELLECTUAL HAPPINESS. 481

of his moral teaching, which in its results ditfered CsIAP.


in no wise from that of the Stoics ; XIX.
' Epicurus, never-
theless, holds a position strongly contrasted with that
of the Stoics as to the grounds on which his moral
theory is based. To demand virtue for its own sake
seemed to him a mere phantom of the imagination.
Those only who make pleasure their aim have a real
object in life.' Only a conditional value belongs to
virtue ' as a means to happiness or, as it is other- ;

wise expressed,'' Not virtue taken by itself renders a


man happy, but the pleasmre arising from the exer-
cise of virtue. This pleasure the Epicurean system
does not seek in the consciousness of duty fulfilled,
' Sen. Vit. Be. 13, 1 (conf. ' Dioff. 138 Sia Se
: ttj^ ^Soi/jj;/
12, 4) In ea quidem ipse sen-
: Kal Tas apcTas Se7v alpe7(r$ai oif Si*

tentia sum (iuvitis nee nostris auris &<rirep rijv larpiKTiv 5ta t^*

'

popnlaribus the Stoics di- vyieicof, Ka6d (fyrjiri Kal Atoy^vits.


cam), sancta Epicurum et rec- Cic. Fin. i.42 rconf. ad Att.
13,
ta praBcipere, et si propius ac- vii. 2) : Ist enim vestr* exi-
eesseris tristia: voluptas enim mias pulcKeque virtutes nis|
ilia ad parvum et exile revoca- voluptatem efficerent, quis eas
tur, et quam nos virtuti legem aut laudabiles aut expetendas
dicimns earn ille dicit voluptati arbitraretur ? ut enim medi-
. . Itaque non dico, quod
. corum scientiam non ipsius
plerique nostrorum, seotam artis sed bonse valetudinis caiffia
Epicuri flagitiorum ministram probamus, &c. sic sapien- . . . ;

esse, sed illud dico male audit, : tia, que ars vivendi putanda
Infamis est, et immerito. Ep. non expeteretur si nihil e<li-
est,
33, 2 : Apud me vero Epicurus ceret nunc expetitur quod ept
;

est et fortis, licet manuleatus tanquam artifex conquirendse


sit. Seneca not infrequently et oomparandse voluptatis.
quotes sayings of Epicurus, and Alex. Aphr. De An. 156, b: [^
calls (Ep. 6, 6) Metrodorus, h.perk{\ Trepi r^y iK\(yyi\v ecri Tuy

Hermarchus and Polyaenus, /jSduv Kar' 'ETriKOvptiv.


magnos viros. Conf. Cic. Fin. ' Sen. Ep. 85, 18 Epicurus :

ii. 25, 81. quoque judioat, cum virtutem


2 Epic, in Pint. Adv. Col. habeat beatum esse, sed ipsam
17, 3 : iyi) 5' 4^' riSoi/as trwex"' virtutem non satis esse ad bea-
KOfaKaKii, koX ob iir' operckj, Kevas tam vitam, quia beatum efEoiat
Koi fiaraias Kal rapaxt^Sety ^xoiiffas voluptas que ex virtute est, non
TTtov KapTTuy TCLs iKviSas. ipsa virtus.
I I
;

483 THE EPICUREANS.


Chap, or of virtuous action, but in the freedom from dis-
XIX.
quiet, fear,and dangers, which follows as a conse-
quence from virtue. Wisdom and intelligence con-
tribute to happiness by liberating us from the fear
of the Gods and death, by making us independent
of immoderate passions and vain desires, by teaching
us to bear pain as something subordinate and pass-
ing, and by pointing the way to a more cheerful and
natural life.' Self-control aids in that it points out
the attitude to be assumed towards pleasure and
pain, so as to receive the maximum of enjoyment
and the minimum of suffering ; ^ valour, in that it
enables us to overcome fear and pain;' justice, in
that it makes life possible without that fear of Gods
and men, which ever haunts the transgressor.^ To
the Epicurean virtue is never an end in itself,but
only a means to an end lying beyond it a happy
life but withal a means so certain and necessary,
that virtue can neither be conceived without happi-
ness, nor happiness without virtue. Little as it

may seem to be required, still even he would ever


insist that an action to be right must be done not
according to the letter, but according to the spirit
of the law, not simply from regard to others, or by
compulsion, but from delight in what is good.

'jDio^. 132; C?c. Fin. i. 13, v.1152: The criminal can never
43 ; 19, 62. rest,and often in delirium or
^ do. Fin. i. 13, 47. sleepbetrayshimself. Epicurus,
' Cie. 1. c. 13, 49. Diog. however, refused to answer the
120: TJ)v SJ &vSpelav ^vaei /u); question, Whether the wise man
7iVe(rfloi, Aoyurn^ S^ toO iru^fe- would do what is forbidden, if
povTos. he could be certain of not be-
* Oio. Fin. i. 16, 50; JHoff. ing discovered? Phit. co\ 34,
144 Plut. N. P. Sua. Viv. 6, 1
; 1.
Sen. Ep. 97,' 13 and 15. Lucr. ' Philodemus, De Ehet. Vol.
THE WISE MAN. 483

The same claims were therefore advanced by Epi- Ch.\i>.

curus on behalf of his wise man as the Stoics had ^


urged on behalf of theirs. Not only was a control C. Til

over pain attributed to him, in nothing inferior to


the Stoic insensibility of feeling, but he endeavoured
himself to describe his most perfect and satis-
life as

factory in itself. Albeit not free from emotions, and


being in particular susceptible to the higher feelings
of the soul, such as compassion, he yet finds his phi-
losophic activity in no wise thereby impaired.' With-
out despising enjoyment, he is altogether master of
his desires, and knows how to restrain them by in-
telligence, so that they never exercise a harmful
influence on life. He alone has an unwavering cer-
tainty of conviction ;^ he alone knows how to do the
right thing in the right way he ; alone, as Metro-
dorus observes,^ knows how to be thankful. Nay,
more, he is so far exalted above 'ordinary men, that
Epicurus promises his pupils that, by carefully ob-
serving his teaching, they will dwell as Gods among
men;'' so little can destiny influence him, that he
calls him happy under all circumstances.' Happi-
ness may, indeed, depend on certain external condi-

Herc. T. a, col. 25: The laws The Stoic assertion of the


ought to be kept rm /n); t^ Sttcpur- equality of virtues and vices
liiva fi6viiv, aWi. Kol ra t^v dpLo- was, however, denied by the
eiSeiai/ auTois exovra Sia!l>v\dT- Epicureans. Dioff. 120.
Ten/, KaKeiva iJiii /iSmv ffuveMrav,
* IHoff. 135 ; conf Plut. .

aWa kSv KaMvoiyLcv ct7ra|iirai'- N. P. Sua. Vi. 7, 3 LvM". iii. ;

ras, Kol luff riSoviJ!, ou Si' a.vdyKvi', 323.


Koi Pffiaias, 4XX' oi ffoAeuojucVuis. = Oic. Fin. i. 19, 61 ; V. 27,
'
Dioff.117; 118; 119. 80: Semper beatum esse sa-
2 Plut. Adv. Col. 19, 2. pientem. Tuso. v. 9, 26 Stub. ;

' JHog. 118 Sen. Bp. 81,


;
11. Serm. 17, 30. See p. 477.
I I 2

484 THE EPICUREANS.


Chap, tions ; it may even he allowed that the disposition
XTX.
to happiness is not found in every nature, nor in
every person ;
' but still, when it is found, its sta-

bility is sure, nor can time affect its duration. For


wisdom so Epicurus and the Stoics alike believed
is indestructible,^ and the wise man's happiness can
never be increased by time. A life, therefore, bounded
by time can be quite as complete as one not so
bounded.'
Different as the principles, and different as the
tone of the systems of the Stoics and of Epicurus
may be, one and the same endeavour may yet be
observed in both. It is the tendency which cha-
racterises all the post-Aristotelian philosophy the
wish to place man in a position of absolute indepen-
dence by emancipating him from connection with
the external world, and by awakening in him the
consciousness of the infinite freedom of thought.''

' Diog. 117. of an involuntary loss of wis-


- Diog. 117: nhv iira^ycvi- dom, perhaps through madness.
fifvov (Totphv utiKiri riiv ivavriav ' Diog. 126 ; 145 ; (Xc. Fin.
\aii$iv(iv Biieiaiv /iiiS' iiraWdr- i. 19, 63.
Tcif fK6vra. The latter words * See also page 476, 2.
appear to admit the possibility
THE lyVIVIDUAL. 485

CHAPTEE XX.
THE EPICUREAN ETHICS CONTINUED: SPECIAIi POINTS.

The general principles already laid down determine Chap.


-^^-
likewise the character of particular points in the
moral science of the Epicureans. Epicurus, it is A. Thein-

true, never developed his moral views to a systematic


theory of moral actions and states, however much
his pupils, particularly in later times, busied them-
selves with morality and special points in a system of
morals.' Moreover, his fragmentary statements and
precepts are very imperfectly recorded. Still, all that
is known corresponds with the notion which we must
form in accordance with those general views. All
the practical rules given by Epicurus aim at con-
ducting man to happiness by controlling passions
and desires. The wise man is easily satisfied. He
sees that little is necessary for supplying the wants

'
"We gather this from the criticism of Xenophon's and
fragments of Philodemus' trea- Aristotle's omovoiuk6s. It is ob-
tise irepl Kama' icaX tUv tiv- jected to the latter that the
TiKei/isvav iryaSav Kol t&v h oh master of the house is there
eiVl (cal irepl S. The 10th book made (col. ii. 30) to rise earlier
of this treatise gives a portrait than his servants, and to go to
of the and kindred
uTTfpiiipavos, bed later than they do, such
faults, after the manner of conduct being_ ToKalirwpon /cal
Theophrastus the 9th, a mild
; iiyolKtiov <pL\oir6<pov,
;

486 THE EPICUBEANS.


Chap, of nature, and for emaneipatiug from pain that ;

XX.
imaginary wealth knows no limit, whereas the riches
required by nature may be easily acquired ; ' that
the most simple nourishment aflfords as much enjoy-
ment as the most luxurious, and is at the same time
far more conducive to health ;
^ that therefore the re-
wants rather than the increase of posses-
striction of
sions makes really rich;' and that he who is not
satisfied with little will never be satisfied at all.'' He
therefore can with Epicurus live upon bread and
water,^ and at the same time think himself as happy

' mog.lii; 146; UO; Stob. one of his letters, asserts that
Floril. 17, 23 ;Sen. Ep. 16, 7 ; he spent a mina every day on
Lncr. ii. 20; iii. 59; r. 1115; bistable. If this statement be
Philod. De Vit. ix. col. 12 tpiXo- : not a pure invention, it must
(r6(p(p 5'
ttKovtou jxiKp6v' S
iffrl refer to the whole circle of his
irapeS(iKaiiev aKoKoiiOus [for thus friends. It could otherwise
and not by evKaipaa must the only have happened at such a
defective as be represented] time as the siege of Athens by
rois Ka6'fiyeii6(Tiv if Tois irepX Demetrius Poliorcetes, when a
irXoirov \6yois. Conf. p. 476, modius of wheat cost 300
3 ; 477. drachmae, and when Epicurus
2 Biog. 130. counted out to his friends the
Stab. Floril. 17, 24 and 37 beans on which they lived.
Sen. Bp. 21, 7 ; 14, 17 2, 5 ; : Pint. Demetr. 33. The further
Houesta, inquit, res est Iseta statement of Timocrates
paupertas. Ep. 17, 11 Multis : {Diog. 6) mrhv 81j ttjs r/ufpas
parasse divitias non finis mise- ififTv oTrb Tpv^rjs')is certainly
riarum fuit, sed mutatio. an unfounded calumny. The
*
Stoi. Flor. 17, 30. Conf. moderation of Epicurus is ad-
Sen. Ep. 9, 20: Si cui sua non mitted hj Sen. Vit. B. 12, 4 13, ;

videntur amplissima, licet to- 1 ;and Epicurus flatters him-


tius mundi dominus sit tamen self,in Sen. Ep. 18, 9 Non :

miser est. toto asse pasci, Metrodorum,


IKog. 11 Stob. Floril. 17,
; qui nondum tantum profecerit,
34 ao. Tusc. v. 31, 89 Sen.
; ; toto and, in Diog. 11, because
;

Ep. 25, 4. Epicurus lived very he was satisfied with bread and
abstemiously. The charge of water. JMd. he writes ire'iuijfov :

luxury brought against him fiot Tvpov Kvdvluv, ?]/' &Tat/ ^oi-
was fully disposed of by Gas- Ktofiai iroKVTiXeiaaffBai, Siyufiai.
sendi, De Vit. et Mor. Epic. 153. Still less have we any reason
Timocrates, on the strength of to connect the diseases of which
THE INBIVIDUAL. 487

as Zeus.' He eschews passions which disturb peace Chap.


of mind and the XX.
repose of life ; considering it foolish

to throw away the present in order to obtain an un-


certain future, or to sacrifice life itself for the means
of a life, seeing he can only once enjoy it.^ He
therefore neither gives way to passionate lovej nor to
forbidden acts of profligacy.' Fame he does not
Epicurus and some
of his 1, not only discusses the most
scholars died (as Plut. N. P. suitable time for the enjoy-
Suav. V. 5, 3 does, herein fol- ment of love, but quotes as the
lowing Timocrates in Diog. 7) words of Epicurus ei ^hav a :

with their presumed luxurious- a'o<lths S>v KaX ii^ ^vva^isvos ttKti-
ness. fftd^eiu eTi Ta7s rwv KaXuv aipais
Stab. Floril. 17, 30.
' See Xii^'P^' Kal (N. P.
tj'r]\tt<j>iicr((ny

p. 477, 2. Suav. V. 12, 3). These enjoy-


2 Epicurus and Metrodorus, ments, according to Epicurus,
in Stub. Floril. 16, 28; 20. Conf. are only then allowed when
Pint. Tran. An. 16, p. 474: i they do not entail any bad con-
T^j aljpiot/ ^Kiffra Se6fievoSf S)S sequences {Diog. 118), or pro-
(jyriffitt 'Ewi/coupos, ^Biffra irp6(rt(ri duce passionate states of feel-
irphsr^v aijpLov. ing. Hence he not only forbids
Serious charges on this
' unlawful commerce (^Diog. 118),
subject, against which Gassendi but declares ouk 4paaSi]ireadai.
in Diog. 6, defends him, are rhv co<p6ii. Dioq. 118 ; Stoh.
preferred against Epicurus by Floril. 63, 31. Eros is defined
Timocrates, in Diog. 6j but (_Alex. Aplir. Top. 1h) aivravoi =
neither the testimony of Timo- 3pe|is SuppoSialotv. Conf. Plut.
crates, nor the fact that a Amat. 19, 16, p. 765. It is con-
woman of loose morality (see sequently a passionate and dis-
above p. 406) was in his society, turbing state, which the wise
can be considered conclusive. man must avoid. The Stoics,
Chrysippus in Stob. Floril. 63, on the contrary, allowed Eros
31, calls Epicurus kvaiaBjiTos. to their wise man. The same
Epicurus is, however, far below view is taken of Eros by Lucre-
our standard of morality. Thus, tius, who cannot find words
in the quotation on p. 479, 1, strong enough to express the
he reckons T\iova\ ZC a^poiuritav restlessness and confusion en-
among the necessary ingre- tailed by love, the state of de-
dients of the good. By Eustrat. pendence in which it places
in Bth. N. 48, such pleasures man, and the loss to his fortune
are included among ^uaiKoX (see and good name. His advice is

p. 476, 3), not among ^8ool to allay passion as quickly as


oca7Korai. They are treated in possible by means of Venus
the same light by Lucr. v. 1050 ;
volgivaga, and to gratify it in
and put. Qu, Oonviv, iii, 6, 1, a calm way.
438 THE EPICUREANS.
Chap, covet; and for the opinions of men he cares only so
^^'
wish not to be despised, since being despised
far as to

would expose him to danger.' Injuries he can bear


with calmness.^ He cares not what may happen to
him after death ; * nor envies any for possessions
which he does not himself value.*
It has been already seen how Epicurus thought
to rise above pains, and to emancipate himself from
the fear of the Gods and death.^ And it has been
further noticed that he thinks to secure by means of
Ins principles the same independence and happiness
which the Stoics aspired to by means of theirs. But
whilst the Stoics thought to attain this indepen-
dence by crushing the senses, Epicurus was content
to restrain and regulate them. Desires he would not
have uprooted, but he would have them brought into
proper proportion to the collective end and condition
of life, into the equilibrium necessary for perfect re-
pose of mind. Hence, notwithstanding his own sim-
plicity, Epicurus is far from disapproving, under all

circumstances, of a fuller enjoyment of life. The


wise man will not live as a Cynic or a beggar.^ Care
for business he will not neglect ; only he will not

' JDiog. 120 140 Cic. Tuso.


; ; <f>lKuv avvrtyi, koI ovk f(f>B6vfi t?j
ii. 12, 28 ; Lucr. iii. 69 993. ; vfioaayar/ris toC fiypoti r^ BSpanri,
' Sen. De Const. 16, 1. koI tuv iaxiruv tfeoxXiovs \6yaf
' Diog. 118 oiSe to^^s ^pov-
: rp (itEri SaK-
ftt/iVTi/ievos irliKeTO
nf'iv. piav iiSovji. It is true that a
* Zucr. iii. 7i. certain mawkishness and self-
' See p. 479, 455. A further conceit may be detected in this
argument may, however, be language,
here quoted. In Plvt. N. P. JHog. 119; PMlodem.
De
Kuav. Viv. 16, 3, he says 8ti : Vit. \x. ool. 12; 27, 40.
v6ai( voaav anKlrf Tii'&s ktJTiiatis
THE mDiriDUAL. 4S9

give himself too much trouble therewith, and will pre- Chap.
XX.
fer the business of education to any and every other.'
Nor will he despise the attractions of art, although he
can be content when obliged to dispense with them.^
In short, his self-sufficiency will not consist in using
but in needing little and it is this freedom
little, ;

from wants which will add flavour to his more luxu-


rious enjoyments.' Nor is his attitude towards death
a different one. Not fearing death, rather seeking
it when he has no other mode of escaping unendu-
rable suffering, still, the cases in which he will re-
sort to suicide will be rare, since he has learnt to
be happy under all bodi'y pains. The Stoic's re-
commendation of suicide finds no favour with the
Epicurean.*
'Diog. 120 ; xriifffas irpovoi\- [dolores] feramus, sin minus,
treffBai Kai tov /ieWovros, 121 : ffiquo animo e vita, cum ea non
;i;p?;^T(r6(r6ai re atrh fi6v7]s ffotpias placeat, tanquam e theatro exe-
hiropiiaaiiTa. The limitation im- amus. Epic, in Sen. Ep. 12,
plied in the text would, however, 10 Malum est in necessitate
:

seem to require /idyris. Pliilo- vivere, sed in necessitate vivere


dem. in the same sense 1. c. 23, necessilas nulla est. On the
23, says that Epicurus received other hand, Ep. 24:, 22 Objur- :

presents from his scholars. gat Epicurus non minus eos qui
Conf. Plvt. adv. col. 18, 3, also mortem concupiscunt, quam
col. 15, 31. eos, qui timent, et ait: ridicu-
^ Diog. 121: fiK^vasT^hvaB^' lum est currere ad mortem
any ei ixoi aSuupdpas c^etv tiv
' tsedio vitae, cum genere vitse ut
nil ffxoiv (Cobei, not intelli- currendum esset ad mortem
gibly : aSia<t)6p<iis ttv (rxo(r;s). effieceris. Diog. 119, the older
" Epic, in IHog. 130 : ko! riiv editions read kh! irnpuBAs ras
:

avripKeiay Se iLyaBby p.iya vn^i- fj}j/is fieB4^eiv avrhv rov piov.


^OfjLu ovx Vva TrdvTois rois oKlyois Cobet: fjLerd^e.v auThv rov $iov.
Xpti/ifBa, aW' Situs ihv ni) ixmin^v Instead of Tnjptij6i)s TrfipuBivra is
rh TToWa toIs oKlyois xP'^f S" read, or as we might prefer in-
veirnrrfiivoi yvriffiajs 3x1 r^SiffTO stead of fueTd^em lierd^et. Sui-
iro\vTf\e'.as airo\aiovtTivct ^Kurra cide was only allowed by Epi-
curus in extreme oases. In
* The Epicurean in (Xe. Ein. Seneca's time, when an Epi-.
. 16, 49 : SI tolerabiles sint curean, Diodorus, committed
400 THE EPICUREANS.
Ohap. Fully as the wise man can suffice for himself,

\ still Epicurus would not separate him from connee-


B. Cvril
tion with others. Not,' indeed, that he believed with
society _ _ _

and the the Stoics in the natural relationship of all rational

(\T&M ^si'^gs-' Yet even he could form no idea of human


society. life except in connection with human society. He
does not, however, assign the same value to all forms
of social life. Civil society and the state have for
him the least attraction. Civil society is only an
external association for the purpose of protection.
Justice reposes originally on nothing but a contract
entered into for purposes of mutual security.^ Laws
are only made for the sake of the wise, not to prevent
their committing, but to prevent their suffering in-
justice.' Law and justice are not, therefore, bind-
ing for their own sake, but for the general good ;

nor is injustice to be condemned for its own sake,


but only because the offender can never be free from
fear of discovery and punishment.'' There is not,
therefore, any such thing as universal, unchangeable
justice. The claims of justice only extend to a
limited number of beings and nations those, in
fact, which were able and willing to enter into the

social compact. And the particular applications of


justice which constitute positive right differ in dif-

suicide,hisfellow-soholars were ' Diog. 150; 154. From


unwilling to allow that suicide this point of view, Lucr. v,
was permitted by the precepts 1106, gives a long description
of Epicurus {Sen. Vit. B. 19, 1). of the rise of a state.
' Epiat. Diss. ii. 20, 6 "E7r.
:
Stoh. Floril. 43,
139.
Kovpos Srav avatpttv 9i\xi tV ' Diog. 150; IAuir.\.
1149;
<l)vaM^v KoiviaAav inepdirois irpbs Sen. Ep. 97, 13, and 15 ; Plut.
aWijKoiis, K.r.\. Ad. Col. 84, See p. 482, i.
SOCIAL HELATIONS. 491

ferent cases, and change with circumstances. What Chap.


XX.
is felt to be conducive to mutual security must pass
for justice; and whenever a law is seen to be inex-
pedient, it no longer binding.' The wise man will
is

therefore only enter into political life in case and in


as far as this is necessary for his own safety. The
sovereign power is a good, inasmuch as it protects
from harm. He who pursues it, without thereby at-
taining this object, acts most foolishly.'^ Private
individuals living as a rule much more calmly and
safely than statesmen, it was therefore natural that the
Epicureans should be averse to public affairs ; public
life, after all, is a hindrance to what is the real end-
in-chief wisdom and happiness.' Their watchword
is therefore KdOs ^idacras* To them the golden
mean seemed by far the most desirable lot in life.*

They only advise citizens to take part in affairs of


state when special circumstances render it necessary,*
or when an individual has such a restless nature that

Diog.
' 150-153. * Plut. De Latenter Viven-
Diog.
2 140. do, c. 4. In this respect, T.
' Plut. Adv. Col. 31 ; 33, 4 ;
Pomponius Atticus is the true
N. P. Sua. Viv. 16, 9 ; Epietet. type of an Epicurean, on
Diss. 23, 6; Lucr. v. 112S;
i. whose conduct during the civil
Cic. pro Sext. 10, 23. Philodem. war and withdrawal from public
irepl jnfTopMfis (Vol. Hero, iv.) life, see Nepoi, Att. 6.

col. 14: ouSe xoi"''*'')"' hyoiniBa Metrodorus,ini%oi.Floril.


*

i7\v iroKiriK^v Suca/iiy, oUt^ abrois 45, 26 ; 4v viKet ju^re as \4wv


ro7sKKTT]fiet'Ots,oljTeTaLS'tr6K(riVj avaffTp4<pou ij/fire us la&j/uifi' ri
ai/riii/ Kad' a^i}V ' aWa iroWiKis fi^v yap iK-KaT^iTat rit 5e KaipQ<pj>-
oiiiav KaX avtitpopuv h.vi}Ki<n<aVt XoKeirai.
when combined with upright- " Seneca well expresses the

ness, it benefits the community, difference on this point be-


and is sometimes useful at ; tween Epicureans and Stoics in
other times, harmful to states- the passage quoted, p. 320, 3.
men themselves.
; ;

492 TEE EPICUREANS.


Chap, he cannot be content with the quiet of private life.'
XX,
Otherwise they are far too deeply convinced of the
impossibility of pleasing the masses to wish even to
make the attempt.^ For the same reason they appear
to have been partisans of monarchy. The stern and
unflinching moral teaching of the Stoics had found
its political expression in the unbending republican
spirit, so often encountered at Eome. Naturally the
softand timid spirit of the Epicureans took shelter
under a monarchical constitution. Of their political
principles so much at least is known that they did
not consider it degrading for a wise man to pay court
to princes, and under all circumstances they re-
commended unconditional obedience to the powers
that be.'
Family life is said to have been deprecated by Epi-
curus equally with civil life.'' Stated thus baldly, this
is an exaggeration. So much, however, appears to
be established, that Epicurus believed it to be gene-
rally better for the wise man to forego marriage and
the rearing of children, since he would thereby save
himself many disturbances.^ It is also quite credible
Pint. Tranq. An. c. 2, p. Quamregereimperioresvelle
465. et regna tenere.
= Epic, in Sen. Ep. 29, 10: * ^ici.Dissri. 23, 3 (against

Nunquam volui populo placere Epicurus) Smrl knoavn^ovMUis


:

nam qua ego scio non probat ts3 aoip^ reKvorpotpeti' ; tI (poPy
populus, quse probat populus TaCra els Kiwas iiiuriari
liii Sin;

ego nesoio. Similar expressions ii. 20, 20 'EirfKoupoj ^k /iev av-


:

from Stoics have been pre- Sphs Ttivr' ctireK(Ji).aTo Koi to oiko-
viously quoted. Seairdrou Kal <j>i\ov the last
' JKog. 121 nal iiSvapxov iv
: words proving how cautiously
Kaipcf Btpanteianv [rby ao(piv\. these statements must be under-
Lwor. V. 1125 : stood.
Ut satius multo jam sit parere Diog.
'^
119. The passage
quietum, is, however involved in much
FRIENDSHIP. 493

that he declared the love of children towards parents Ohap.


to be no inborn feeling.' This view is, after all, only ^f^'
a legitimate consequence of his materialism ; but it

did not oblige him to give up parental love altoge-


ther. Nay, it is asserted of him that he was any-
thing but a stranger to family affections.''

The highest form of social life was considered by c. Fnend-


Epicurus to be friendship a view which is distinc- '^'^P-

tive in a system regarding the individual as the


atom of society. Such a system naturally attributes
more value to a connection with others freely en-
tered upon and based on individual character and
personal inclination, than to one in which a man
finds himself placed without any choice, as a mem-
ber of a society founded on nature or history. The
basis, however, on which the Epicurean friendship

rests is very superficial, regard being had mainly to

its advantages, and in some degree to the natural

effects of common enjoyments ;* but it is also treated

obscurity, owing to a difCerence nuptiis. Like riches, honours,


of reading. The earlier text health, ita et uxores sitas in
was Kol firiv Ka\ yaniiativ koI
: bonorum malorumque conlinio,
riKV(moii\ffetv rhv ffoiiibv. us 'Eiri- grave aut esse viro sapienti
Koupos iv Toit SioTopiois Kal h venire in dubium, utrum bonam
Tais irepi </)ii(Tctis. Kara Trtpf'i raffti/ an malam ducturus sit.
5e TTOTC /3iou oi ^ofi-^o-em. Cohet Plut. Adv. Col. 27, 6,-De
'

reads instead Kal lUTjSe yaiataeiv


: Am. Prol. 2, p. 495 Jllpictet. ;

ft-qSe TfKpoirofiiffeii/ rhv iToip6v . . , Diss. i. 23, 3.


Konh TieplaTMriv Si ttot* fiiov Diog. 10: ^ Tt vphs robs
'

yafji^iretv. What
the MS. autho- yovsas evxapiCTia xal ri irpbs rovs
rity for this reading is, we are o!c\<pois tuiroiia. Diogenes
not told. In sense it agrees himself appeals to Epicurus'
with Hieron. Adv. Jovin. i. 191, testament, ibid. 18.
quoting from Seneca, De Matri- " Diog. 120 Kal ; tV <pi\iav
monio Epicurus
: raro dicit . . . 5io raj xP^ias [yivtaiai] . . .

sapienti ineunda conjugia quia (rwla-TcurSai SJ o4tJ)i/ koto koipu-


multaincommodaadmixta sunt riav in toij ^Soi/ois. Epic. Ibid.
:

494 THE EPICUREANS.


Chap. in such a way, that its scientific imperfection has no
XX,
influence on its moral importance. Only one portion
of the School, and that not the most consistent,
maintained that friendship is pursued in the first in-
stance for the sake of its own use and pleasure, but
that it subsequently becomes an unselfish love.' More-
over, the assumption that among the wise there exists
a tacit agreement requiring them to love one another
as much as they love themselves, is clearly only a lame
shift.* Still, the Epicureans were of opinion that a
grounding of friendship on motives of utility was not
inconsistent with holding it in the highest esteem.
Friendly connection with others affords in short so
pleasant a feeling of security, that it entails the most
enjoyable consequences ; and since this connection
can only then exist when friends love one another as
themselves, it follows that self-love and the love of a
friend must be equally strong.^
Even this inference sounds forced, nor does it

148 (also in Cic. Fin. i. 20, 68) quern ipse oircumventum hostili
Kai T^v iv auToTs rots upttrfievois custodia liberet. Oic. Fin. i.
i.ff<t>dKfia/ </>i\fas fuiKiara kt^<ti 20, 66 : Cum solitudo et vita
SeTvoiil^fiy (TvvTe\ov/j.4vnv. ( Cobit, sine amicis insidiarum et metus
however, reads : ^iKias fui\urTa plena sit, ratio ipsa monet ami-
KaTtSe7v elvai ffvvTeKvfieyiji/f in citias comparare, quibus partis
which case (l>i]\.l(} should be sub- confirmatur animus et a spo
stituted for <pi\ias or else KT^crsi pariendarum voluptatum se-
for KOTi56i>'.) Sen. Ep. 9, 8: jungi non potest, etc. On the
The wise man needs a friend, same grounds, Philodem. De
non ad hoc quod Epicurus dice- Vit. ix. (V. Here, iii.) col. 24,
bat in hac ipsa epistola (a letter argues that it is much better
in which Stilpo's cynical self- to cultivate friendship than to
cintentment is blamed), ut withdraw from it.
habeat, qui sibi segro adsideat, '
CUb. Fin. i. 20, 69.
succurrat in vincula conjecto ' IMd. 70.
vel inopi ; sed ut habeat ali- ' do. Fin. i. 20, 67.
quern, cui ipsi aegro adsideat,
FRIENDSHIP. 495

fully state the grounds on which Epicurus's view of Chap.


^-^-
the value of friendship reposes. That view, in fact,
was anterior to all the necessary props of the system.
What Epicurus requires is primarily enjoyment. The
first conditions of such enjoyment, however, are in-
ward repose of mind, and the removal of fear of dis-
turbances. But as to trusting his own powers for
satisfying these conditions, Epicurus was far too
effeminate and dependent on externals. He needed
the support of others, not only to obtain their help
in necessity and trouble, and to console himself with
this view for the uncertainty of the future, but still

more, to make sure of himself and his principles


by having" the approval of others, thus obtaining an
inward satisfaction which he could not otherwise have
had. Thus, the approval of friends is to him the
pledge of the truth of his convictions. In sympathy
with them his mind first attains to a strength by
means of which it is able to rise above the changing
circumstances of life. General ideas are for him too
abstract, too unreal. A philosopher who considers
individual beings as alone real, and perceptions as
absolutely true, cannot feel quite happy and sure of
his ground, unless he finds others go with him.'
The enjoyment which he seeks is the enjoyment
of his own cultivated personality and wherever ;

this standard prevails, particular value is attached

'
The same need finds ex- tern, that so he may live, as it
pression in the advice given by were, perpetually under his
Epicurus {Sen. Ep. 11, 8; 25, eye. Man requires a stranger
5) Let every one choose some
:
to give him moral support,
distinguished man as his pat-
406 THE EPICUREANS.
Chap, to the personal relations of society, and to friend-
"

ship.'

Hence Epicurus expresses himself on the value


and necessity of friendship in a manner far exceed-
ing the grounds on which he based it. Friendship
is unconditionally the highest of earthly goods.^ It
is far more important in whose company we eat and
drink, than what we eat and drink.' In case of emer-
gency the wise man will not shrink from sufifering
the greatest pains, even death, for his friend.*
It is well known that the conduct of Epicurus
and his followers was in harmony with these pro-
fessions. The Epicurean friendship is hardly less
celebrated than the Pythagorean.* There may be an
offensive mawkishness and a tendency to weak mutual
admiration apparent in the relations of Epicurus to
his friends, but of the sincerity of his feelings there

' As illustrations in modern untrustworthy, (pi\av te oJSty


times, the reunions of the Kri\aea6ai.
B^rench freethinkers, or the ' Sen. Ep. 19, 10, with the
societies of Rousseau, Mendels- addition Nam sine amico vis-
:

sohn, Jacobi, may be mentioned, ceratio leonis ac lupi vita est.


It deserves notice that in these * Plut. Adv. Col.
8, 7 ; Diog,
societies, as amongst the Epi- 121. We have no reason to
cureans, an important part was suppose, with Ritter, iil. 474,
played by women. This is that this was not the expres-
quite natural, when philosophy sion of a real sentiment. That
is confined to cultivated inter- it is inconsistent we can well
course and conversation. say.
' Diog. 148 : Si- i\ noipla rrapa- ' The Epicureans in Cic.
(TKeuafeToi eis tV toS b\ov piov Fin. i. 20, 65 At vero Epi-
:

HaKapidritra iro^ii ii4yi<rr6v lariv curus una in domo et ea quidem


Tl rris (piAlas KTTJiris. die. Fin. angusta quam magnos quanta-
ii. 25, 80 ; Epicurus exalts que amoris oonspiratione con-
friendship to heaven. In Diog. sentientes tenuit amicorum
1 20, Cobet reads instead of the greges, quod fit etiam nunc ab
usual (pl\ov re oiSha (cT^ffftrfloi Epicureis. Ihid. ii. 25, 80.
[rii/ croiphv'}, which is altogether " Instances have already
:

FRIENDSHIP. 497

can be no doubt. One single expression, that refer- Chap.


XX.
ring to the property of friends,' is enough to prove
what a high view Epicurus held of friendship and ;

there is evidence to show that he aimed at a higher

improvement of his associates.^


In other respects Epicurus bore the reputation
of being a kind, benevolent, and genial companion.'
His teaching, likewise, bears the same impress. It
meets the inexorable sternness of the Stoics by in-
sisting on compassion and forgiveness,^ and super-
sedes its own egotism by the maxim that it is more

occurred, p. 418, 2, of the ex- Oet^tret Trap^ rb redefiuTfievov.


travagant honours required by Compare the remarks on p.
Epicurus nor did he fail to
; 488, 3.
eulogise his friends, as the Diog. 11: t6v tg ^KiriKovpov
^

fragments of his letters to Leon- fiil els rb Koivbv KararWe-


a^iovv
tion, Themista, and Pythocles ffdair^s oi/ffias KaQdnep rbv Hv-
(^IHog. 5) prove. When Metro- 6ay6pav Kotvh ret tuv <^i\wv
dorus had tried to obtain the \4yovTa. aTTiffroivToiv yhp elvai rb
release of a captive friend, Epi- TotovTOj/ ' el S" aiFiiTTav ovSe
curus applauds him {Plwt. N. P. tfiiKwv.
Sua. Yit. 15, 5, Adv. Col. 33, 2) ' PMlodem. irepl iraf^riatas
&1S 6Te KaX vtaviKws i^ &irreus (V. Here. v. 2), Fr. 15 ; 72 ; 73,
otAaoe Kare^ri MlBpcp t^ ^iptfi $otJ' mentions Epicurus and Metro-
S-iliTav. Ibid. 15, 8, he expresses dorus as patterns of genial
his thanks for a present : Sata>s frankness towards friends.
T6 Kal fieyaXoTrpeirSJs ^7re/A6\^0T7T6 Probably the words in iSen. Bp.
TifiSiv Tct Trepl r^v tov itItov ko/iL' 28, 9
initium salutis est noti-
d}]v, Kal ovpavofi-iiK-n ffTjfieia ivSeSet- tia peccati
are taken from a
X^e rrjs irphs ejite euvoias He moral exhortation addressed to
wrote of Pythocles before he a friend.
was 18 o&k eJvat (f}ii(rtv iv '6\ri
:
' Not only does Diogenes
T^ 'EWdSt a^elvu, Kal repariKas (9) praise his unsurpassed bene-
avrhp eS ctirayyeWeLj/, zeal Trd(rxeiy volence, his kindness to his
ad rh TUy yvvaiKtJov, eiixofj-eyos ave- slaves, and his general geniality,
trdyra KaX aveirltpOova
/AeffTjTO eluai but Cicero calls him (Tusc. ii.

rTJS vnep^oKTJs tov peavtaKOv 19, 44) vir optimus, and (Fin.
{PlMt. Adv. Col. 29, 2); and ii. 25, 80) bonum virum et co-
he also said {Plmlodem. irepi mem et humanum.
na^^narlas, Fr. 6, V. Here. v. ' Diog. 118 oSre KoKiffeiv
:

2, 11): as Sm TIvBoK\4a Tixv oiKeras i\eii(Tetv /aeVtoi, Kal truv-

KK
498 THE EPICUMEANS.
Chap, blessed to srive than to receive.' The number of
XX "

such maxims on record is, no doubt, limited ; never-


theless, the whole tone of the Epicurean School is

a pledge of the humane and generous character of


its moral teaching.^ To this trait the Epicurean
School owes its g;reatest importance in history. By
its theory of utility it undoubtedly did much harm,
partly indicating, partly helping on the moral de-
cline of the classic nations. Still, by drawing man

away from the outer world within himself, by teach-


ing him to look for happiness in the beautiful type
of a cultivated mind content with itself, it contri-

buted quite as much, after a gentler fashion, as Stoi-


cism by its sterner tone, to the development and
the extension of a more independent and more uni-
versal morality.

yviitriv TivX efeiv tuv ffirovSalav. ipse boiras vir fuit et multi
121 :

SiopSd/Mari.
iirixaplireiT9al rtvi M Tij? Eplcurei fuerunt et hodie sunt,
et in amicitiis fideles et in omni
' Phot. N. P. Sua. Vi. 15, 4 vita constantes et graves neo
(similarly C. Princ. Philos. 3, voluptate sed officio cousilia
2, p. 778):_auTo! Se S^tou \4yov- moderantes. Atticus isawell-
(Ttv Sis rb eS Troieii/ {JSiiiv iffri toO known example of genuine
wdiTx"''- Conf. Aleo!. Aphr. human kindness and ready self-
Top. 123. A
similar maxim is sacrifice, and Horace may be
attributed by JEUan. "V. H. xiii. also quoted as an illustration
13, to Ptolemy Lagi. Conf. of the same character. Sei
Acts XX. 35. Steinhart's remarks, I. c. p. 470.
'^
do. Fin. ii. 25, 81: Et
COHERENCE OF THE SYSTEM. 499

CHAPTER XXI.
THE EPICUKEAN SYSTEM AS A WHOLE : ITS POSITION

IN HISTORY.

It has often been urged against the Epicurean philo- Chap.


XXI '_
sophy, that it is deficient both in coherence and con-
sistency.Nor is this objection without foundation. A. laney-

Ifwe come to the study of this philosophy with the of the


demand for a complete scientific groundwork, or a ^''''

strictly logical development, there will certainly re-


sult therefrom a feeling of dissatisfaction. It is not
show in what contradictions Epicurus was
difficult to

involved in professing to trust the senses wholly and


;

entirely, and yet going beyond the senses to the


hidden causes of things ; in despising logical forms
and laws, and at the same time building up his whole
system on deductions ; in holding that all sensations
are true, but yet maintaining that a portion of the
realitieswhich they represent as belonging to things
is only relative. Nor were other inconsistencies want-

ing; his acknowledging at one time only natural


causes and laws, and ignoring any such thing as free
will and imagination, and yet at another time, by
the doctrine of the swerving aside of atoms and of
the human will, elevating unexplained caprice to the
K K 2
500 THE EPICUREANS.
Chap, rank of law ; his referring all pleasures and pains to
^
bodily sensations, and yet calling mental states the
higher and more important states ; nay, more, his
deducing from a basis of selfishness rules and pre-
cepts of humanity, justice, love, faithfulness, and
devotion. It ought not, however, to be forgotten
that the Stoics, to whom the claim of clear and con-
sistent thought cannot be denied, were involved in
similar difficulties. The Stoics, like the Epicureans,

built up a rational system on a basis of the senses.

They, too, constructed an ideal theory of morals on a


material groundwork of metaphysics. They, too, de-
clared that universal law is the only active power,
whilst they maintained that reality belongs only to
the world of matter. They, too, deduced a strict

theory of virtue from the principle of self-preserva-


tion ; not to mention the inconsistent attitude which
they assumed towards the popular religion. To deny
to the Stoics a unity and connectedness of system,
because of these scientific defects and inconsisten-
cies, would be felt to be doing them an injustice.

And can Epicureanism be fairly condemned, when its


faults are essentially of the same kind (though a
little more obvious) as those of the Stoics, without a
single extenuating plea being admitted on its behalf?
The strongest plea to be advanced in its favour
is that the development of the Epicurean system
does not pretend to rest upon an intellectual plat-
form. Epicurus sought in philosophy a path to
happiness, a school of practical wisdom. For him
knowledge has only a secondary value, as contribu-
COHERENCE OF THE SYSTEM. 601

ting to this end, and indeed, both the tone and the Chap.
'V""V'T
'
results of his intellectual activity were determined
by a reference to this end. In the case of the Stoics,
however, it has been already seen that the compara-
Logic and Natural Science to
tive subordination of
Moral Science, the going back to the older view of
nature, the vindication of the truth of the senses
and of the reality of matter, grew out of their pecu-
liarly one-sided view of the scope of philosophy. In
the case of Epicurus the same results appear, and all

the more markedly, since Epicurus did not, like


the Stoics, look for happiness in subordination to a
universal law, but in individual gratification or plea-
sure. For him the recognition of a universal law
had not the same value as for the Stoics and conse- ;

quently Epicurus did not feel the same need of a


scientificmethod as they had done. He could there-
fore more exclusively content himself with the im-
pressions of the senses, regarding them as the only
unfailing source of knowledge. No necessity com-
pelled him to advance from pure materialism to a
view of matter in which it is described as possessing
a soul and made to be the bearer of reason. In fact,

the more exclusively everything was referred by him


to mechanical causes, the more easily could he regard
the individual with his pursuit of happiness as in-
dependent of all superhuman forces, and left entirely

to himself and his natural powers. No system in


ancient times has so consistently carried out the
mechanical view of nature as that of the Atomists.
None, therefore, afforded such a strong metaphysical
502 THE EPICUREANS.
Chap, support to the Epicurean views of the absolute
L_ worth of the individual. It was, therefore, as natu-
ral for Epicurus to build on the teaching of Demo-
critus as for the Stoics to build on that of Heraclitus.
But Epicurus, influenced probably more by practical
than by scientific considerations, allowed himself, by
his theory of the swerving aside of atoms, to destroy
the consistency of the theory of Democritus.^
It is hardly necessary to notice here how the dis-
tinctive features of the Epicurean morals were deve-
loped out of their theory of happiness, in marked
contrast to the Stoic teaching. The happiness of
Epicurus, however, does not depend upon sensual
gratification as such, but upon repose of mind and
cheerfulness of disposition. Hence his theory of
morals, notwithstanding its foundation in pleasure,
bears a nobler character, which is seen in its lan-

guage as to the wise man's relations to the pains and


desires of the body, to poverty and riches, to life and
death, no less than in the mild humanity and the
warm and hearty appreciation of friendship by the
Epiciu-ean School. Certainly the rationalising spirit
of that School was opposed to any religious belief
which supposed an intervention of Grod in the course
of the world, or the world's influence on man for weal
or woe but its appeal to the senses without criti-
;

cism raised no objection to admitting divine beings,


from whom no such intervention need be feared.
Nay, more, this belief seemed the most natural
ground for explaining the popular belief in Gods. It

' See p. 445.


HISTORICAL POSITION. 5C3;

satisfied an inborn and apparently keenly-felt want Chap.


'
by supplying an appropriate object of devotion, and
a standard by which to test the accuracy of moral
ideas. Hence, notwithstanding scientific defects and
contradictions, the whole system of Epicurus bears a
definite stamp. All the essential parts of that sys-
tem are subservient to one and the same end. The
consistent working out of a scientific view of nature is

looked for in vain ; but there is no lack of consis-


tency arising from an undeniable reference of the
individual to a definite and practical standard.
Looking to the wider historical relations of the
Epicurean system, the first point which calls for re- b. His-

mark is the relation of that system to Stoicism. *''".^f^


.10/1
^
The contrast between the two Schools is obvious ; of Ji^picu-

attention having been already drawn to it on all the m'Sa-


more important points. It is likewise well known tion to

that a constant rivalry existed between the two


Schools during their whole careers, that the Stoics
looked down on the Epicureans, and circulated many
calumnies with respect to their morals. For these
statements proofs may be found in the preceding
pages. Nevertheless, the two Schools are related
in so many respects, that they can only be regarded () Points
as parallel links connected in one chain, their dif- "{^J^'i''''''

ferences being varieties where the same main ten-


dency exists. Both agree in the general character
of their philosophy. In both practical considerations
prevail over speculation. Both treat natural science

and log^e as sciences subsidiary to ethics natural


science especially in view of its bearing on religion.
604 THE EPICUREANS.
Chap. Both, however, attach more importance to natural
'__ science than to logic. If the Epicurean neglect of
scientific rule forms a contrast to the care which the
Stoics devoted thereto, both parts are at least agreed
in one thing in displaying greater independence
in investigating the question as to a test of truth.
By both this standard was placed in the senses ; and
to all appearances both were led to take this view by
the same cause ; appeals to the senses being a conse-
quence of their purely practical way of looking at
things. Moreover, both employed against scepticism
the same practical postulate the argument that
knowledge must be possible, or no certainty of action
would be possible. They even agree in not being
content with the phenomena supplied by the senses
as such, although Epicurus as little approved of the
Stoic theory of irresistible impressions as he did of
their logical analysis of the forms of thought. With
such appeals to the senses how could there be any
other result but materialism both in the Stoic and
Epicurean systems ? But it is strange that the ma-
terialism in both Schools should be based on the
same definition of reality, corresponding with their
practical way of looking at things.'
(&) Points In the expansion and more detailed setting forth
"iince.' of materialistic views the systems diverge, more
widely, perhaps, than the philosophers themselves,
whose leading they professed to follow. These dif-
ferences appear particularly on the subject of nature,
the Stoics regarding nature as a system of design,
> Couf. p. 126, 2, with 439, 1.
;

HISTORICAL POSITION. 506

the Epicureans explaining it as a mechanical product. Chap.


Whilst the Stoics adhered to fatalism, and saw Grod '

everywhere, the Epicureans held the theory of atoms,


and the theory of necessity. Whilst the Stoics were
speculatively orthodox, the Epicureans were irreli-
gious freethinkers. Both meet again in that branch
of natural science is most important in re-
which
spect of morals the part dealing with man. Both
hold that the soul is a fiery atmospheric substance.
Even the proof for this view, derived from the mu-
tual influence of body and soul, is common to both.
Both distinguish between the higher and the lower
parts of the soul, and thus even the Epicureans in their
psychology allow a belief in the superiority of reason
to the senses, and in the divine origin of the soul.

The arena of the warmest dispute between the


two Schools is, however, ethics. Yet, even on this
ground, they are more nearly related than appears
at first sight. No greater contrast appears to be
possible than that between the Epicurean theory of
pleasure and the Stoic theory of virtue ; and true it

is that the two theories are diametrically opposite.


Nevertheless, not only are both aiming at one and
the same end the happiness of mankind but the
conditions of happiness are also laid down by both
in the same spirit. According to Zeno virtue, ac-
cording to Epicurus pleasure, is the highest and only
good ; ]jut the former making virtue consist essen-
tially in withdrawal from the senses or insensibility
the latter seeking pleasure in repose of mind or im-
perturbability, are both expressing the same belief.
506 THE EPICUREANS.
Chap.
V-Y T
Man can only find unconditional and enduring satis-

faction,when by means of knowledge he attains to a


condition of mind at rest with itself, and also to an
independence of external attractions and misfortunes.
The same unlimited appeal to personal truth is the
common groundwork of both systems. Both have
expanded this idea under the same form that of
the ideal wise man for the most part with the same
features. The wise man of Epicurus is, as we have
seen, superior to painand want; he enjoys an ex-
cellence which cannot be lost and he lives among
;

men a very God in intelligence and happiness. Thus,


when worked out into details, the difference in the
estimate of pleasure and virtue by the Stoics and
Epicureans seems to vanish. Neither the Stoic can
separate happiness from virtue, nor the Epicurean
separate virtue from happiness.
But, whilst recommending a living for society,
both systems take no real interest in social life. The
recognition of a natural society amongst mankind,
of certain positive relations to state and family, above
all, a clear enunciation of a citizenship of the world,
characterise the Stoics. The pursuit of friendship,
and the gentle humanity of their ethics, characterise

the Epicureans. Together with these peculiarities


one common feature cannot be ignored. Both have
renounced the political character of the old propriety
of conduct, and diverting their attention from public
life, seek to find a basis for universal morality in the
simple relation of man to man.
The united weight of all these points of resem-
HISTORICAL POSITION. 507

blance is sufScient to warrant the assertion that, Chap.


notwithstanding their differences, the Stoics and Epi- ^
cureans stand on the same footing, and that the {.c)'Fliere-

sharpness of the contrast between them is owing to greater

their laying hold of opposite sides of one and the *^*'*


same principle. Abstract personality, and self-con-
sciousness developed into a generic idea, is for both
the highest aim. Compared with it not only the state
of the senses, but the scientific knowledge of things,
and the realisation of moral ideas in a commonwealth,
are of minor importance. In this self-consciousness
happiness consists. To implant it in man is the ob-
ject of philosophy, and knowledge is only of value
when and in as far as it ministers to this end. The
point of difference between the two Schools is only
their view of the conditions under which that cer-
tainty of consciousness is attained. The Stoics hope
to attain it by the entire subordination of the indivi-
dual to universal law. The Epicureans, on the other
hand, are of opinion that man can only then be con-
tent in himself when he is restrained by nothing
external to himself. The first condition of happiness
consists in liberating individual life from all depen-
dence on others, and all disturbing causes. The for-

mer, therefore, make virtue, the latter make personal


well-being or pleasure, the highest good. By the
Epicureans, however, pleasure is usually conceived
of as of a purely negative character, as being free-
dom from pain, and is referred to the whole of hucnan

life. Hence it is always made to depend on the mo-


deration of desires, on indifference to outward ills,
::
;

608 THE EPICUREANS.


Chap. and the state of the senses, on intelligence and actions
XXI.
conformable with intelligence, in short, on virtue and
wisdom. Hence, too, the Epicureans arrive by a
roundabout course at the same result as the Stoics
the conviction that happiness can only be the lot of
those who are altogether independent of external
things, and in the enjoyment of perfect inward har-
mony.
(2) Itla- Towards the older philosophy Epicureanism bears
tion to
Ariatip- nearly the same relation as Stoicism. True it is that
pus. Epicurus and his School would not recognise their
obligation to either one or other of his predecessors.'

'
It has been already stated, his friends and admirers does
p. 405, 1, 4, that Epicurus ad- not exclude hatred and injus-
mitted his debt to Democritus, tice towards his predecessors,
but not without some reserve, see p. 418, 2, of whom a fair
otherwise claiming to be en- estimate was rendered impos-
tirely self-taught. With this sible by the superficial nature
exception, he professed to have of hisknowledge and the one-
learned nothing from the an- sidedness of his point of view.
cient teachers, and expressed Sext. Math i. 2, attests ttji' irpis
himself with such conceit and robs TTfp] \l\dTaiiia Hal 'ApurTOreKi]
scorn, as to spare neither them Kol Toiis Sf>.olovs SviTiiivetav ; Plut.
nor their writings. JMog. 8, Adv. Col. 26, 1, mentions a
besides mentioning his abuse of false objection to Arcesilaus
Nausiphanes (sup. 342, 1), refers and Cic. N. D. i. 33, 98, says
also to his calling the Platonists Cum Epicurus Aristotelem vex-
Aiovv(Toi<6\ajcas, Plato himself arit contumeliosissime, Phse-
in irony the golden, Plato, Hera- doni Socratico turpissime male-
clitus KuKijTTn, Democritus Atj- dixerit, etc. The rude jokes
p6KpiTos, Antidorus ^atviSupos, mentioned by Diogenes are in
the Cynics ix^P"^^ t^j 'EWtiSos, harmony with a man whom
the Dialecticians Tro\v^0ovepovs, Cic. N. D. ii. 17, 46, calls homo
Pyrrho i/MBris and dirai'SeuTos, non aptissimus ad jooandum
and charging Aristotle and Pro- minimeque resipiens patriam.
tagoras with vices in their On these jokes he apparently
youth. Diogenes refuses to prided himself as well as on
allow that any of these state- a certain bombastic elegance.
ments are true, Bpicurus'friend- See p. 496, 6. In this Epicurus
liness being well known. But was followed by his pupils. Cie.
the devotion of Epicurus to N. D. i. 34, 93, says of Zeno
HISTORICAL POSITION. 509

But far from disproving the influence of previous Chap.


'

systems on his own, this conduct only shows the per- '

sonal vanity of Epicurus. Epicureanism, like Stoi-


cism, starts with the object of bringing down science
from metaphysical speculation to the simpler form of
a practical science of life. Both systems of philo-
sophy, therefore, turn away from Plato and Aristotle,
whose labours they notably neglect, to Socrates and
those Socratic Schools which, without more exten-
sive meddling with science, are content with ethics.
Circumstances, however, led Epicurus to follow Aris-
tippus as Zeno had followed Antisthenes. Not only
in morals did Epicurus derive his principle of plea-
sure from the Cyrenaics; he likewise derived from
them his theory of knowledge, that the sense-im-
pressions are the only source of ideas, a,nd that every
feeling is true in itself. Nor can he altogether deny
the assertion that feelings only furnish direct infor-
mation respecting our personal states, and hence re-
specting the relative properties of things. With the
Cyrenaics, too, he taught that true pleasure can only
be secured by philosophic intelligence, and that this
intelligence aims, before all things, at liberating the
mind from passion., fear, and superstition. At the
sime time, he is by no means prepared to follow the
Cyrenaics unreservedly. His theory of morals dif-

fers, as has already been seen, from the Cyrenaic

Non eos solum, qui tunc erant, Cic. Brut. 85, 292, Epicurus
Apollodoriiin,Silum,ceterosfige- had already expressed a dis-
bat maledictis, sed Socratem paraging opinion of the Socratic
ipsum . . . scurram Atticum irony), Chrysippum nunquam
fuisse dicebat (according to nisi Chrysippam vocabat.

510 THE EPICUREANS.
Chap. theory in this important particular, that not sensual
XXI.
and individual pleasure, but mental repose and the
whole state of the mind is regarded as the ultimate
end, and the highest good in life. It was thus im-
possible for him to be content, as the Cyrenaics were,
with feelings only, with individual and personal im-
pressions. He could not help pursuing a conviction
reposing on a real knowledge of things, since only on
such a conviction can an equable and certain tone of
mind depend.
(3) Rela- Epicurus, therefore, not only differed from Aris-
tion to De-
tippus with regard to feelings, in referring all feeling*
vuicritus.
to impressions from without, of which he considered
them true representations, but he felt himself called
upon to meet the Cyrenaic contempt for theories of
nature, just as the Stoics had met the Cynic contempt
for science. To the physics of Democritus he looked
for a scientific basis for his ethics, just as they had
looked to the system of Heraclitus. But the closer
he clung to Democritus, owing to the weakness of
his own interest in nature, the more it becomes ap-
parent that his whole study of nature was subser-
vient to a moral purpose, and hence of a purely
relative value. Accordingly, he had not the least
by as-
hesitation in setting consistency at defiance,
suming the swerving aside of atoms and the freedom
of the will. It is not only altogether improbable that
Epicurus was only a second edition of Democritus
for historyknows of no such repetitions but as a
matter of fact it is false. A more accurate observa-
tion proves that even when the two philosophers
HISTORICAL POSITION. 511

agree in individual statements, the meaning which Chap.


they attach to these assertions and the whole spirit
of their systems is widely divergent. Democritus
aims at explaining natural phenomena by natural
causes. He wishes, in short, for a science of nature
purely for its own sake. Epicurus wishes for a view
of nature able to avert disturbing influences from
man's inner life. Natural science stands with him
entirely in the service of ethics. If in point of sub-
stance his system is borrowed from another system,
yet its whole position and treatment supposes an en-
tirely new view of things. The Socratic introspec-
tion, and the Sophistic resolution of natural philo-
sophy into personal rationalising, are its historical
antecedents ; and it owes its existence to the general
aversion of thought for pure theory, which consti-
tutes the common peculiarity of all the post-Aristo-
telian philosophy.
Excepting the systems named. Epicureanism is (4) SeU-
connected with no other previous system, so far as is
^^J^^^
known. Even its attack upon those systems ap- and Plato.

pears to have consisted of general dogmatic and


superficial statements. Still it must not be forgotten
that Epicureanism presupposes the line of thought
originated by Socrates, not only as found in the col-
lateral Cyrenaic branch, but as found in the, main line

of regular development by Plato and Aristotle. The


view of Plato and Aristotle, distinguishing the im-
material essence from the sensible appearance of
things, and attributing reality only to the former,

is undoubtedly attacked by Epicurus as by Zeno, on


512 THE EPICUREANS.
Chap, metaphysicsl grounds, by his materialism. Prac-
'__ tically, however, he approaches very much nearer to
this view in all those points in which his teaching
deviates from the Cyrenaic, and resembles that of
the Stoics.
It has been observedon a former occasion that
the indifference to the immediate conditions of the
senses, the withdrawal of the mind within itself, the
contentment with itself of the thinking subject,

which Epicurus required no less than the Stoics and


cotemporary Sceptics, is nothing but a consequence
of the idealism of Plato and Aristotle. Even the
materialism of the post-Aristotelian systems, it is

said, was by no means a going back to the old pre-


Socratic philosophy of nature, but only a one-sided
practical apprehension of that idealism. These sys-

tems only deny a soul in nature or a soul in man,


because they look exclusively to consciousness and
to personal activity for independence of the senses.
The correctness of this observation may be easily

proved from the Epicurean teaching, notwithstand-


ing the severity and harshness of its materialism.
Why was it that Epicurus relentlessly banished
from nature all immaterial causes and all idea of
purpose ? And why did he confine himself ex-
clusively to a mechanical explanation of nature ?

Was it not because he felt afraid that the admission


of any other than material causes would imperil the
certainty of consciousness ; because he feared to lose
the firm groundwork of reality by admitting invi-
sible forces, and to expose human life to influences
HISTORICAL POSITION. 613

beyond calculation if lie were to allow of anything Chap.


^^^'
immaterial ? Yet how slightly, in his view of life,

does he adhere to present facts, since his wise man


is made to enjoy perfect happiness by himself alone,
independent of everything external. The same ideal
is reproduced in the Epicurean Grods. In their iso-
lated contemplation of themselves, what else do they
resemble but the Grod of Aristotle, who, aloof from
all intermeddling with the world, meditates on him-
self alone ? No doubt the independent existence of
the thinking mind is held only by Aristotle in a pure
and dignified manner. By Epicurus it is pourtrayed
in a sensuous, and, therefore, a contradictory form.
But the connection of the views of both cannot be
ignored. A similar relation exists generally between
the Epicurean philosophy and that of Plato and
Aristotle.' Little as the former can be compared
with the latter in breadth and depth, it must not,
therefore, be regarded as an intellectual monstrosity.
Epicureanism is a tenable though one-sided expres-
sion of a certain stage in the development of the in-
tellect of Greece.

'
Compare in this connection the quotations from Metrodorus
on p. 476, 1.

I. h
:

514 THE SCEPTICS.

PAKT IV.

THE SCEPTICSPYRRHO AND THE OLDER


ACADEMY.

CHAPTEE XXII.

PTKRHO.

Chap. Stoicism and Epicureanism are alike in one respect


XXII.
they commence the pursuit of happiness with definite
'
A. His- dogmatic statements. The Sceptic Schools, however,
torieal
position of attempt to rea,ch the same end by denying every
Scepti-
cism.
dogmatic position. Varied as the paths may be,
(1) Its re- the result is in all cases the same ; happiness is made
lation to
to consist in the exaltation of the mind above all
porary external objects, in the withdrawal of man within
dogmatic
systems. his own thinking self. Moving in the same sphere
as the cotemporary dogmatic systems, the post-Aris-
totelian Scepticism takes a practical view of the
business of philosophy, and estimates the value of
theoretical enquiries by their influence on the state
and happiness of man. It moreover agrees with
cotemporary systems in its ethical view of life ; the
object at which it aims is the same as that at which
those systems aim repose of mind, and imperturba-
HISTORICAL POSITION. SI 5

bility. It differs, however, from them, none the less ; Chap


^^'''
for the Epicureans and Stoics make mental repose to
depend on a knowledge of the world and its laws,
whereas the Sceptics are of opinion that it can only
be obtained by despairing of all knowledge. Hence,
with the former, morality depends on a positive con-
viction as to the highest Good ; with the latter,
morality consists in indifference to all that appears
as Good to men. Important as this difference may be,
it must not therefore be forgotten that Scepticism

generally revolves in the same sphere as Stoicism and


Epicureanism, and that in renouncing all claim to
knowledge, and all interest in the external world,
it is only pushing to extremes that withdrawal of
man into himself which we have seen to be the' com-
mon feature of these Schools. Not only, therefore,
do these three lines of thought belong to one and
the same epoch, but such is their internal connec-
tion, that they may be regarded as three branches of
a common stock.
More than one point of departure was offered to (2) Caase.)
^'<'*''*'
Scepticism by the earlier philosophy. The Mega-
rian criticism and the Cynic teaching had taken up
a position subversive of all connection of ideas, and
of all knowledge. Pyrrho, too, had received from
the School of Democritus an impulse to doubt.' In

' Democritus had denied 1088, a), although, notwith-


all truth to sensuous impres- standing his usual agreement
sions. The same sceptical tone with the physical views of De-
was more strongly apparent in mocritus {Plut. in Mus. 1. c. i.
Metrodorus (Aristocl. in Mis. 8, 11 id. Fac. Lun. 15, 3, p.
;

Pr. Ev. xiv. 19, 5; Sext. Math. 928; Sen. Nat. Qu. vi. 19), he
vii. 88; Epijihan. Exp. Fid. cannot be considered a full
610 THE SCEPTICS.

Chap. particular, the development of the Platonic and Aris-


XXII.
totelian speculations by those who were not able to
follow them, had made men distrustful of all specu-
lation, until they at last doubted the possibility of
all knowledge. Not seldom do Sceptical theories
follow times of great philosophical originality. Still

stronger in the sequel was the impulse given by tlie

Stoicand Epicurean systems. Eelated as these sys-


tems are to Scepticism by their practical tone, it was
natural that they should afford fuel to Scepticism. At
the same time the unsatisfactory groundwork upon
which they were built, and the contrast between their
moral and physical teaching, promoted destructive
criticism. If, according to the Stoics and Epicu-
reans, the individual and the universal elements in
Sceptic. Scepticism appears from the senses; greater de-
to have passed from Mm
to pendence is, however, placed
Pyrrho, Anaxarchus being the on thought. We must there-
middleman (see p. 518, 2, 3), fore take the statement on
and herewith maybe combined TTavra iffTlv & &y rts itoi)ffai sub-
the Sceptical imperturbability. ject to this limitation. Anax-
This doctrine of imperturbabi- archus is said (Sea*. Math. vii.
lity being held by Epicurus, 87) to have compared the world
the pupil of Nausiphanes, it to a stage-scene, which involvet
might be supposed that before no greater scepticism than the
Pyrrho's time a doctrine not similar expressions used by
unlike that of Pyrrho had been Plato as to the phenomenal
developed in the School of De- world. However much, there-
mocritus, from whom it was fore, these individuals may
borrowed by Epicurus. The have contributed to Pyrrhonism,
connection is, however, uncer- a simple transference of Scep-
tain. We have seen that the ticism from Democritus to
doubts of Democritus only ex- Pyrrho not to be thought of.
is
tended to sense-impressions, And as regards imperturbabi-
not to intellectual knowledge. lity, Epicurus may have bor-
Tlie case of Metrodorus was rowed the expression from
similar. His sceptical expres- Pyrrho, whom, according to
sions refer only to the ordinary Diog. ix. 64 and 69, he both
conditions of human know- knew and esteemed.
ledge, that of ideas derived
;

HISTORICAL POSITION: PYRRHO. 517

the personal soul, the isolation of the individual as Chap.


an independent atom, and his being merged in a pan- '_

theistic universe, stand over against one another


without being reconciled ; among the Sceptics this
contrast has given place to neutrality. Neither the
Stoic nor the Epicurean theory can claim acceptation ;

neither the unconditional value of pleasure, nor yet


the unconditional value of virtue ; neither the truth
of the senses nor the truth of rational knowledge
neither the Atomist's view of nature, nor the Pan-
theistic view as it found expression in Heraclitus,
can be vindicated. The only thing which remains
certain amid universal uncertainty is abstract per-
sonality content with itself, a personality forming at
once the starting-point and the goal of the two con-
tending systems.
The important back-influence of Stoicism and
Epicureanism upon Scepticism may be best gathered
from the fact that Scepticism only attained a wide
extension and a more comprehensive basis in the
New Academy after the appearance of those systems.
Before that time its leading features had been indeed
laid down by Pyrrho, but they had never been deve-
loped into a permanent School of Scepticism, nor
given rise to an expanded theory of doubt.

Pyrrho was a native of Elis,' and may therefore (z-)p,jrrlio

have early made the acquaintance of the Elean and


'
5'*'^ '**''

followars.

' Aristocl. in Eus. Pr. Ev. Antigonus the Garystian, Apol-


xiv. 18, 1; Diog. ix. 61. We lodorus, Alexander Polyhistor,
are indebted almost exclusively Diocles, &c., are the chief au-
to Diogenes for our informa- thorities drawn upon by Dio-
tiou respecting Pyrrho. Besides genes.
;;

518 THE SCEPTICS.

Chap.
XXII.

Megarian criticism that criticism, in fact, which
was the precursor of subsequent Scepticism. It can,
however, hardly be true that Bryso was his instructor.'
To Anaxarchus, a follower of Democritus, he attached
himself, accompanying that philosopher with Alex-
ander's army as far as India.^ Still he is less indebted
to Anaxarchus for the sceptical than for the ethical
parts of his teaching.^ At a later period he resided
' Attention has been drawn expression. According to other
to the chronological difficulties accounts, he belonged to the
in ' Socrates and the Socratic School of Democritus. Pint.
Schools,' p. 255, note 1 (2nd Tranq. An. 4, p. 466. In Valer.
edition). Either Pyrrho is Max. viii. 14, ext. 2, he pro-
falsely called a pupil of Bryso, pounds to Alexander the doc-
or Bryso is falsely called the trine of an infinite number of
son of Stilpo. The former worlds and Clemens, Strom, i.
;

seems more probable, Diug. 287, B, quotes a fragment, in


ix. 61, having derived his state- which, agreeing with Demo-
ment from Alexander's SiaSoxar, critus, he observes that iroXu-
and it is quite the style of the fiaBla is only useful where it is
compilers of SiaSoxaX to assign properly made use of. Like
a Megarian teacher to a Sceptic Epicurus, Anaxarchus followed
whose connection with that Democritus, calling happiness
School was suiEciently obvious. the highest object of our desire
''
Dioff. ix. 61 ; Aristocl. 1. c. and this assertion probably
18, 20 ; 17, 8. We gather from gained for him the epithet 6
them that Pyrrho was origin- evSai/xovLKhs ( Clemens, 1. c.
ally a painter. Suidas Tlip^av Athen. vi. 250 ; xii. 548, b; ^Z.
only copies the present text of V. H. ix. .37). In other res-
Diogenes with a few mistakes. pects, he differed from Demo-
' Besides the passage quoted critus. For first he is charged
from Sextus, p. 515, 1, which is by Clearch. in Athen. xii. 548,
littleknown, we have no proof b, with a luxurious indulgence
of the sceptical tone in Anax- far removed from the earnest
archus which Sextus, Math. vii. and pure spirit of Democritus
48, ascribes to him, and since and according to Plut. Alex.
the latter quotes no proofs, it 52, he had, when in Asia, re-
may be assumed that he had nounced the independence of a
none. Anaxarchus appears to philosopher for a life of plea-
have been unjustly included sure and Timon, in Plut. Virt.
;

among the Sceptics, like so Mor. 6, p. 446, says he was led


many others who were called away by ^iins riSovoirXi)^ con-
Sceptics by later writers on the trary to his better knowledge.
strength of a single word or Again, he is said to have com-
HISTORICAL POSITION: PYRRHO. 619

in his native city,' honoured by his fellow-citizens,* Chap.


XXII.
but in poor circumstances,' which he bore with his
characteristic repose of mind.'' He died, it would
appear, at an advanced age,' between 275 and 270
B.C., leaving no writings behind.* Even the ancients,
therefore, only knew his teaching by that of his
pupils, among whom Timon of Phlius was the most
mended in Pyrrho (^Diog. ix. ' Diog. 66 ; 62.
63) an indifference which went Examples in Diog. 67. It
a good deal beyond the imper- sounds, however, highly im-
turbability of Democritus and ; probable and doubts were ex-
;

Timon commends him for his pressed by.^nesidemus whether


KiviKov liivos. He meets external his indifference ever went to
pain with the haughty pride the extent described by Anti-
expressed in his much-admired gonus. Ibid. 62, of not getting
dictum under the blows of Ni- out of the way of carriages and
tocreon's club
Dioff. ix, 59 ; precipices, so that he had to be
Pint. Virt. Mot. c. 10, p. 449 ; preserved from danger by his
Clemens, Strom, iv. 496, D; friends. He must, moreover,
Valer. Max. iii. 3, ext. 4 pMa. ; have enjoyed a special good
Hist. Nat. vii. 87; Tertull. Apol. fortune to attain the age of 90,
60 Dio Chrysog. Or. 37, p. 126,
; notwithstanding such senseless
K. But he treats men with conduct.
the same contempt'; and whilst ^ All the dates here are very

meeting the Macedonian con- uncertain. Neither the date of


queror with an air of indepen- his death nor of his birth is
dence, he spoils the whole by given, and the notice in Suidas
adroit flattery. Conf. Plut. that he lived after the 111
Alex. 52 ; Ad Princ. Iner. 4, Olympiad (336-332 B.C.) is of no
p. 781; Qu. Conv. ix. 1, 2, 5j avail. If, however, as Dicg. 62,

.^l. V. H. ix. 37 Atlien. vi. ; says, he attained the age of 90,


250. His indifference was, at and if he joined Anaxarchus at
any very much lacking in
rate, Alexander's first invasion of
nobOity. Eespecting Anaxar- Asia, being then between 24
chus, see iMsac. Leet. Att. 181. and 30, the statements above
' Diog. ix. 64 ; 109. given are true.
2 According to Diog. 64, Diog. Pro. 16 102 Aris-
; ;

they made him head-priest, tocl. in Em. Pr. Ev. xiv. 18, 1 ;

and, on his account, allowed to better authorities than Seast.


philosophers immunity ftom Math, i. 282, or Plut. Alex.
taxation. According to Dioeles Fort. 1. 10, p. 331. Neither
(_Dwg. 65), the Athenians pre- does Sextus say that the sup-
sented him with citizenship for posed poem on Alexander was
his services in putting a Thra- extant. The whole statement
cian prince Cotys to death. is evidently untrustworthy.
520 THE SCEPTICS.

Chap. important.' Besides Timon several other of his


XXTI.
pupils are known by name.^ His School, however,
was short-lived.* Soon after Timon it seems to have
' Timon (see WacJismuth, latter, p. 51, has collected the
De Timone Phliasio, Leipzig, fragments.
1859) was a native of Phlius 2 Biog. 67-69, mentions, be-

(Diog. ix. 109). A


public dancer sides Timon, a certain Eury-
at first (JDiog. 109 Aristocl. in
;
lochus as his pupil, who, how-
E%is. Pr. Ev. xiv. 18, 12), when ever, was not very successful in
tired of this mode of life he the way of keeping his temper;
repaired to Megaia, to hear also Philo, an Athenian, He-
Stilpo (^Biog. 109). Stilpo being catsus of Abdera, the well-
alive in the third century, and known historian (on whom see
Timon's birth having happened Jl&7ter,Fragm.Hist. Grr.ii.384);
approximatelybetween 325-315 and Nausiphanes, the teacher
B.C., the connection is not so of Epicurus. The last asser-
impossible as Wachsmuth, p. tion is only tenable on the sup-
5, and Preller, Hist. Phil. Gr. position that Nausiphanes ap-
et Kom. 398, suppose, though peared as a teacher only a few
in the uncertainty of chronolo- years after Pyrrho, for Pyrrho
gical data it cannot be posi- cannot have returned to Blis
tively stated. Subsequently before 322 B.C., and Epicurus
Timon became acquainted with must have left the School of
Pyrrho, and removed with his Nausiphanes before 310 B.C.
wife to Elis, leaving his staunch See p. 406, 3. According to
admirers {Biog. 109, 69 Aris- ; Biog. 64, Epicurus must have
tocl. 1. 0. 11, 14, 21). He then become acquainted with Pyrrho
appeared as a teacher in Ghalcis, whilst a pupil of Nausiphanes.
and, having amassed a fortune, Nausiphanes is said not to have
concluded his. life in Athens agreed with Pyrrho, but only
(^JDiog. 110; 115). It appears to have admired his character
from Biog. 112 and 115, that {Biog. 1. c), so that he cannot
he survived Arcesilaus (who properly be called his pupil.
died 241 B.C.), having nearly Numenius, mentioned by Biog.
attained the age of 90. His 102 (Conf. 68), among I^rho's
death may therefore be ap- (Tuv^flets, is suspicious, J5nesi-
proximately fixed in 230, his demus being named at the
birth in 820 B.C. For his life same time, and it may be ques-
and character, see Biog. 110; tioned whether he as well as
112-115 Athcn. x. 438, a, Ml.
; jEnesidemus does not belong
V. H. ii. 41. Of his numerous to a later period of Scepticism.
writings, the best known is a ' According to Biog. 115,
witty and pungent satire on Menodotus (a Sceptic belong-
previous and cotemporary phi- ing to the latter half of the
losophers. Respecting this second century after Christ)
satire {Biog. 110) consult asserted that Timon left no
Wachtmuth, p. 9 and 3. The successor^ the School being in
;

TEACHING OF PYRRHO. 621

become Those who were disposed to be


extinct.' Chap.
now joined the New Academy, towards whose ^^^^-
sceptical
founder even Timon made no secret of his grudge.^
The little which is known of Pyrrho's teaching B. Teach-
may be summed up in the three following state- p,^,.""^

ments We can know nothing as to the nature of


: (l) Impus-

things Hence the right attitude towards them is to


:
"knoKUdge.
withhold judgment The necessary result of suspend-
:

ing judgment is imperturbability. He who will live


happily for happiness is the starting-point with the
Sceptics must, according to Timon, take these
things into consideration : What is the nature of
things ? What ought our attitude to things to be ?

What is the gain resulting from these relations ? *

To the first of these three questions Pyrrho can only


reply by saying that things are altogether inacessible
to knowledge, and that whatever property may be
attributed to a thing, with equal justice the oppo-

abeyance from Timon to Ptole- was a pnpil of Ms QSieid/Aparos


mWs, i.e., until the second conf. i?ie^. ix. 113), he wascer-
half of the first century B.C. tainly not an a,clhereut of his
Sotion and Hippobotus, how- views. See p. 43, 2.
ever, asserted that his pupils ' In Diog. 116, Enbulus is
were Dioscurides, Nicolodius, called a pupil of Euphranor,
Euphranor, and Praylus. His also on the authority of Sotion
son too, the physician Xanthus, and Hippobotus. If Ptole-
likewise followed his father. mEeus is named as the next one
(Uwg. 109.) That, however, after him, no philosopher of
Timon was himself a physician, Pyrrho's iyaryii can have been
as Wachimwth, p. 5, supposes, known for 150 years,
does not follow with certainty Sing. 114.
''

= Aristocl, in Mis. Pr. Ev.


from the words larfiKhv ^S(8aje,
:

since these only mean he had xiv. 18, 2 i Se yi ime-iyrTis oiroS


:

been instructed in medicine. On TifuDv f rjirl Suv rbv )ii\KovTa ev-


the other hand, according to Saifiovkimv els rpta radra 0\4-
Sliid. ni^^iDV, the second Pyrrho, ireii' irpaTov /ikv Imdla iriipuKe tJi

called Timon's pupil, was a rpiynaTcf^ deirepov U, -rim xpri


changeling. If Aratus of Soli Tpi-nov Tijihs vphs abtk JiaKeiffflof
:

622 THE SCEPTICS.

Chap, site may be predicated.' In support of this statement


^ Pjrrrho appears to have argued that neither the senses
nor reason furnish certain knowledge.^ The senses
do not show things as they are, but only as they ap-
pear to be,' Eational knowledge, even where it

seems to be most certain, in the sphere of morals,


does not depend upon real knowledge, but only upon
tradition and habit.*' Against every statement the
opposite may be advanced with equal justice.* If,

however, neither the senses nor reason alone can fur-


nish trustworthy testimony, no more can the two
combined, and thus the third way is barred, by which

we might possibly have advanced to knowledge.^ How


many more of the arguments quoted by the later
Sceptics belong to Pyrrho it is impossible to say.
The short duration and diffusion of Pyrrho's School
renders it probable that with him Scepticism was not

TcXeOTaiOi' Se Ti irepUffTOt toTs SIkoiov otfre &^iKov, Koi Sfxoius iiel

oiirws ^x^^^^'^- irdvrav^ fi'q^%v gfi/ai tt7 a\Tj6et(f,


* Aristocl. 1. O. : t& fxhv oiv vdfitp Se koL e6ei irdvra tous av-
TrpdyfjLard (priffiu avrhv (Pyrrho) Qp^irous irpdrreiv, ou yap fiaWov
CLTTO^aivetv iiriaTjs aiidifyopa KoCl T(J3 ft TiiSe eJyai eKaffTOV, Scxt.
affrdQfiTiTa Kol avswlKpLra, 8tct Math. xi. 140 : oUre ayad6v ri
TovTO [t5] jU^TE Tcw alffQ-fjcTfis itrrt tpitrsi oijre Kafcbi/, aWct irphs
Tj^uv iJ.'flTe ras Srf^as dXTjSeueti/ audpdjwav ravTa v6tf KeKpirat Kara
^ ^peiSetrdai. Diotj. ix. 61 ov : rbi/ Tifiava.
yhp fiaWov T6Se f) T6Sf ihai In this sense the words of
'^

fKaiTTov. Gell. xl. 5, 4 : Pyrrho is JiJnesidemus, in Diog. ix. 106,


said to have stated ou p,a\\ov oB- must be understood : oviiv ipriaiv
Tusex^iTdSefi^Kslvojs^ovBeTepws, dpi^eiv fhv Tivpfiwa SoynartKUS
2 See the above-quoted pas- Ji^ tV ai/Ti\oytav. See note 1.

sage of Aristoeles and IHog. ix. ' Bioff. ix. 114, on Timon
114. iTuyeX" Te ^TTiXe'-yeij' titiBfl irohs
Timon, in Siog. ix. 10.5 : roiis riis aiirfl^ireij /ier' ivipLapru-
rh fjL^Ki '6ti ^(TtI y\vKv oil rlSrifit

povvros tov vov iyKpivovTas' ffvv-
Tb S' 8ti iptdvfTai ijxoXoySi. ijXflei/ 'Krvayas re koI Noviiiivios.

" Diog.ix. 61 olSivyhp iipa-


: The meaning of this proverb
ffKiv aire KaAhv oUri cuffxphv aire has been already explained.
TEACHING OF PYRMHO. 528

far advanced. The same result appears to follow Chap.


from its further development in the Academy. The L
ten rpoTToi,, or aspects under which sceptical objec-
tions were grouped, cannot with certainty be attri-
buted to any one before jEnesidemus.' Portions of
the arguments used at a later day may be borrowed
from Pyrrho and his pupils,''' but it is impossible to
discriminate these portions with certainty.
Thus, if knowledge of things proves to be a (2) WWi-
failure,there only remains as possible an attitude of mdgme.rd.
pure Scepticism and therein is contained the answer
;

to the second question. We know nothing whatever


of the real nature of things, and hence can neither
believe nor assert anything as to their nature. We
cannot say of anything that it is or is not ; but we
must abstain from every opinion, allowing that of all

which appears to us to be true, the opposite may with


equal justice be true.' Accordingly, all our state-

'
Bwg. ix. 79 refers these sceptical statement Aiiyoi or rpif-
Tp6irai to Pyrrho, but inasmuch iroi Xlv^pdveioi. That they can-
as he was there describing not belong to Pyrrho in the
Sceptic views, the author of form in which they are pre-
which to his mind was Pyrrho, sented by Sextus and Diogenes
nothing follows from his state- is clear," since they obviously
ment. &a!t. Pyrrh. i. 36 gene- refer to later views,
rally attributes them to the ' Sext. Math. vi. 66 x. 197 ;

ancient Sceptics, by whom, ao- quotes an argument of Timon


cording to Math. vii. 345, he against the reality of time, and
understood .Slnesidemus and further states (Math. iv. 2) that
his followers. Aristocles, 1. c. Timon, in his conflict with the
18, 11, refers them to ^nesi- philosophers of nature, main-
demus, and they may easily tained that no assertion should
have been referred to Pyrrho bemade without proof in other :

by mistake, since ^nesidemus words, he denied dogmatism,


himself (i>itfy.ix. 106) and sub- every proof supposing some-
sequent writers (Favorin. in thing established, i.e. another
Gell. xi. 5, 5; Philostr. Vit. proof, and so on for ever.
Soph, i, 491) call every kind of * Aristocl, 1. o. 18, 3 : Sii
524 THE SCEPTICS.

Chap, ments (as the Cyrenaics taught) only express indi-


XXII.
vidual opinions, and not absolute realities. We can-
not deny that things appear to be of this or the
other kind ; but we can never say that they are so.'

Even the assertion that things are of this or the


other kind, is not an assertion, but a confession by
the individual of his state of mind.^ Hence, too, the

universal maxim of being undecided cannot be taken


as an established principle, but only as a confession,
and, therefore, as only problematical.' It must, how-
ever, remain a matter of doubt how far the captious

turns of expression by which the Sceptics thought


to parry the attacks of their opponents, come from
Pyrrho's School. The greater part, it is clear, came
into use in the struggle with the Dogmatists, the
lively play of which is not older than the develop-

TovTO ovp fjLTiSf TTia'Teieit' avTa7s yiyd}^Ko^iv, iriDs 5' Spufisv fi trus
Self,dAA' aSo^tiffrovs KoX 6.K\tveis voov^cv ayvoovfxev Ktti 8ti riSe
Kol &KpaBdi/TOvs fhai Trepi Ij/bs \evKhv (palneraL SinyriiJ,aTiKas \4-
iKitrrov KiyovTOS 8ti ov p,aWoy yajx^v ov StaPefiaLoi/jLevoi el Kal
Hanv ^ oi)K eiTTij', ^ Kai ^crrt Kal 61/Ttos iffri . yap rh ipaivS-^
. Koi
oiiK fOTiv, ^ oi-re ^<mv oSt' ovk fuevov TiBe/ieSa 06^ wi tnl toioCtoi'
ItTTiy. Dioij. ix. 61. Hid. 76: iv Ka\iirnTvpKaUiaiada.v6ii.e9a-
oi fiaWov means, according to ei Se (j>vaiv ex^i Kavarmiiv, lirc-
Timon, rb juijSez/ dpi^eiv aW^ XOM^''*
s
OTrpofffleTeii'. Dio(/. 1. c. : irepl St ttjs OiiSh
' .Snesidem. in IHoff. ix. Spi^ca (puivrjs Ka! rav S/wtiav \7o-
106 : ovSiv dpi^eiv rbv Tlhppwva fiev ct'S ov 5oyp.dT(i)v
ov y&p flstv '

SuynaTMois 8ii ri/v &VTiKo-yiaii, ii^uoia t^


\iyeiy 8ti (T^aipoflSiis
To7s Si <j>aiiiOfii,4vots aKo\ovBe7v, iariv 6 /tiiir^os aWJi yitp rb /tec
Timou, Zind. 105. Seep. 522, 3. SSijAoi/, al Se
i^oiioAoyhaeis elalv.
' Diog. ix. 103 : vepl niv S>v 4v ^
otv Xiyojiev lufiev ipi^etv
iis&vBpuwoiTrdtrxOfiev &fi.o\oyoiifJl.ev ovS' airh tovto 6pi(6fii.e6a. Diog.
. . . irepl Se Sv 01 S071UOT11C01 5ia- sta*es even this view in its
Pe^aiovvrat tij) \6y</) <pdfi.evoi Ka- later form, probably following
Te(\7)(/)9oi iircxofiev vepl roirav is Seait. Pyrrh. i. 197, but agreeing
dS^\Bv
n6va 5 tA Triflrj yiviiTKo- in substance with the quota-
fi-fv. -rh p.iv yhp 3ti ipafxev S/io- tions from Timou and Pyrrho,
hayoviiev nal rh 5x1 rdSe I'oai'^Kei'
:

TEACHING OF PYRRHO. 625

ment of the Stoic theory of knowledge by Chrysippus, Chap.


and the criticism of Carneades to which it gave rise. \_
In this despairing of anything like certain convic-
tion consists a(f>a(Tia, aKaToXrjyjna or siroyr], the
withholding judgment or state of indecision
of
which Pyrrho and Timon regard as the only true
attitude in speculation,' and from which the whole
School derived its distinctive name.^
From this state of indecision, Timon, in reply to {T) Mental
the third question, argues that mental imperturba- ,

j^^j/^i^^''
bility or arapa^ia proceeds, which can alone conduct
to true happiness.' Men are disturbed by views and
prejudices which mislead them into efforts of pas-

sion. Only the Sceptic who has suspended all judg-


ment is in a condition to regard things with abso-
lute calmness, unrufHed by passion- or desire.'' He
Diog. Ix. 61 and 107: Aris-
' Apathy is substituted for ata-
tocl. u.1.The expressions ai/ia- raxy in Diog. 108; Cic. Acad.
ala, dicoTa\Tn|/(a, liroxh, invari- ii. 42, 130.
ably mean the same thing. Timon. in Aristocl. I.e. 18,
Later writers use instead of 14, speaking of Pyrrho;
them, a^/3e;p(a, ayvmcia t^s aA.7i- aA\' olov rhv Arvfjiov iyii tSov ^S'
Belas, K.T.\. If, according to iSd/j-atrrov
Aristooles and Diog. 107, Timon Tramv, Strots SdfivavTai d^us &(f)a-
first mentioned iupairia on occa- toi re (parol t( (conf. M'aohs-
sion of the third of his ques- mmth, p. 62)
tions, this statement is ob- \aSiv iBvea Kovipa, $apvv6iicv'' eyfla
viously inaccurate. . Kal evda
2 Uv^^clivetoL^ o-KiTTTtKol, aTiGpT}- 4k iraQewv ^6^11$ re Kol eiKcd-ris vo-
TlKol, 4<peKTlKo'i, flJTTJTlKof. Conf. /lofl^KrjS.

^^^- p.- , , - . - Id. in Sext. Math. xi. 1 : The


' Aristocl 2 jo^s^^vroi ^ ^^^ ^^^^_
1. c. :

dloKeifj.ej'ots ovTQi vepteffeffHai Ti- ^ ^

Hai> (bna\ TvpuTOV fih atpaaiav P?:"'"^ M^fl riauxiris


Itoto 5' a.Tapa.{,iav. Biog. 107 ' &<ppwTtffTas Kal d<(ij/i)s

(TKeTTTiKol (pan t^v Kora toutA


t4\os Sk ot

iiroxhv, V "1"''^ ^P'*'""' ^'""^''- '"' ^PO'^^X"" SeiAois r]Sv\6yot,


iro(|)(r|j.
fli ri arapa^la, Us (paaiv o'l te irtpl _

rhv TiV"''" ""^ Ali'e(TiSrifu)v. Id. in Dioi/, 65.


526 THE SCEPTICS.

Chap. knows that it is a fond delusion to suppose that one


XXII.
external condition is preferable to another.' In reality
only the tone of mind or virtue possesses value.^ Thus,
by withdrawing within himself, man reaches happi-
ness, which is the goal of all philosophy.^ Absolute
inactivity being, however, impossible, the Sceptic
will act on probabilities, and hence follow custom;^
but at the same time he will be conscious that this
conduct does not rest on a basis of firm conviction.'
To this province only of uncertain opinion all posi-
tive judgments respecting good and evil belong.
Only in this conditional form will Timon allow of
goodness and divine goodness as standards of con-
duct.^ The real object of this Scepticism is, there-
fore, a purely negative one indifference. It cannot
even be proved' that Pyrrho's School so far acom-
' ao. Fin. ii. 13, 43 Quas : T^ ipatvifjLvoif Travrl (TBivei oSirep
(externals) quod Aristoni et ttv l\er,. (Conf. Se.rt. Math,
Pyrrhoni omnino visa sunt pro vii.
30.) IHd. 106, of Pyrrho :

nihilo, ut inter optime valere Toty S^ tpaivofA^vots aKoXovdeiv,


et gravissime aagrotare nihil See p. 519, 4.
prorsus dioerent interesse. iii. * See p. 524, 1, 2.
3, 11 Cum Pyrrhone et Aris-
:
SfiH. Math. xi. 20 : Kara U
tone qui omnia exsquent.
'
Acad. ii. 42, 130 Pyrrho aiitem : fisi' edos dyaShi' fj Koxbv ^) aSki-
ea ne sentire quidem sapientem, <f>opov Trpoaar/opimiv
KaSdirip Kai
qusttTTiifleionominatur. Epictet. S Tlfuav iv Tots iviaKpiots loi/te
Fragm. 93 (in Stol). Serm. 121, ^i)\ovv Hrav <J3^
28): Tlu^^Qiv ^Keyev fATiSey itatpe-
^ yiip iyiiv ipiu &s fiot KOTO$a-
peiy ^yv fi nQvAvai,
verat ett/at
2 'do. Fin. iv. 16, 43 Pyrrho :
/ivBov a\7i6iiTis opBhv exan xavi-
. . . qui virtute constituta nihil
va-
omnino quod appetendum sit &s Tov Beiov Te
7} ipviTis Koi Toiya-
relinquat. The same Ibid. ii. Qov atei,
13, 43 ; iii. 4, 12.
= See p. 521, 3 ; 525, 3.
Plos.
' Diog. 105 i : Tlfiaii iv t$
Tl66tavi fpTiai jU^ ^KjSejSijK^i'ot [rhv According to an anecdote
'

Ui^^tava] T^v (rijvi]9etap. koL iy preserved by Antigonus of Ca-


Tois iySa\fio7s oStw \iyef ciAAa rystus (Aristocl. 1. o. 18, 19;
TEACJIING OF PYRRHO. 527

modated itself to life, as to make moderation rather Chap.


XXTT.
than indifference the regulating principle for una-
voidable actions and desires. In this direction the
School seems to have done but little.

Diog. ix. 66), Pyrrho apologised between the apathy required


for being agitated by saying ; by his system and practical
It is difficult to lay aside hu- needs. Neither do the remarks
manity altogether. This lan- of Ritter, iii. 451 prove that the
,

guage only proves what his doctrine of moderation belongs


aim was, and that he had to Pyrrho and his school.
found no mediating principle
528 THE SCEPTICS.

CHAPTEE XXIII.

THE NEW ACADEMY.


Chap. Plato's School was the first to put Scepticism on a
firmer footing, and to cultivate it as a system. It

laus^^' ^^^ ^^^'^ already remarked that after the time of


(l) Denial Xenocrates this School gradually deserted specula-

ledge. ^^^^ enquiries, limiting itself to Ethics. To this new


tendency it consistently adhered, when shortly after
the beginning of the third century before Christ it

took a fresh lease of life. Instead, however, of simply


ignoring theoretical knowledge, as it had hitherto

done, assumed towards knowledge an attitude of


it

opposition, hoping to arrive at security and happi-


ness in life by being persuaded of the impossibility
of knowledge. How far this result was due to the
example set by Pyrrho it is impossible to establish
authoritatively. But it is not in itself probable that
the learned originator of this line of thought in the
Academy should have ignored the views of a philo-
sopher whose work had been carried on at Elis in
his own lifetime, and whose most distinguished pupil,
a personal acquaintance of his own, was then work-
ing at Athens as a prolific writer.' The whole tone
' Conf. Dioy. ix. 114. Ten- iv. 190), that Arcesilaus arrived
nemann's view (Gesoh. d. Pliil. at his conclusions indepen-
ARCESILAUS. 629

and character, moreover, of the Scepticism of the Chap.


XXIII.
New Academy betrays everywhere the presence of
Stoic influences. By the confidence of its asser-
tions it provokes contradiction and doubt, without
its being necessary to seek an explanation by impro-
bable conjectures as to the personal relations of Arce--
silaus and Zeno.'
This connection of the New Academy with Stoi-
cism can be proved in the case of its first founder,^
Arcesilaus.^ The doubts of this philospher are directed

dently of Pyrrho, does not ap- 'Arcesilaus (see Geffers,


pear to be tenable. De Arcesila. Gott. 1842, Gymn.
Numen. in Eus. Pr. Ev.
' Progr.) was born at Pitane, in
xiv. 6, 10 6, 5, says that Zeno
; iEolia (^Strabo, xiii. 1, 67, p. 614 ;
and Arcesilaus were fellow- Biog. iv. 28). His birth year is
pupils under Polemo, and that not stated but as Lacydes
;

their rivalfy whilst at school {Diog. iv. 61) was his successor
was the origin of the later in 240 B.C., and he was then 75
quarrels between the Stoa and years of age (^Diog. 44), it must
the Academy. The same may have been about 315 B.C. Hav-
have been stated by Antiochus, ing enjoyed the instruction of
since Cic. Acad. i. 9, 35, ii. 24, the mathematician Autolyous
76, appeals to him to prove in his native town, he repaired
their acquaintance at school. to Athens, where he was first a
Still the assertion is valueless. pupil of Theophrastus, but was
There can be no doubt that gained for the Academy by
both Zeno and Arcesilaus were Grantor {Biog. 29 Numen. in
;

pupils of Polemo, but it is Mis. xiv. 6, 2). With Grantor


hardly possible that they can he lived on the most intimate
have been under him at the terms but as Polemo was the
;

same time; nor if they were, president of the Academy, he is


would the intellectual differ- usually called a pupil of Polemo
ences of the two schools be re- (Oic. De Orat. iii. 18, 67; Fin.
ferred simply to their personal V. 31, 94; Straio). On the
relations. death of Polemo, he was pro-
^ ac. De Orat. ii. 18, 68; bably a pupil of Crates but it ;

Diug. iv. 28 ; Bus. Pr. Ev. xiv. is not asserted by Biog. 33, or

4, 16 ; Sext. Pyrrh. i. 220. Cle- Numen. in Mt^. 1. c. xiv. 5, 10,


mens, Strom, i. 301, c, calls that he was -, pupil of either
Arcesilaus the founder of the Pyrrho, Menedemus, or Dio-
New (second or middle) Aca- dorus. If Eusebius seems to
demy. imply it, it would seem to be a
MM
; ::

5ao THE SCEPTICS.

Chap. not only to knowledge derived from the senses, but


xxin.
to rational knowledge as well.' The principal object
of his attack was, however, the Stoic theory of irre-
sistible impressions and in overthrowing that theory
;
^

Arcesilaus, it would seem, believed he had exploded


every possibility of rational knowledge for the Stoic ;

appeal to the senses he regarded as the only possible


form of a theory of knowledge, and the theories of

misunderstanding of the state- retirement (^Diog. 39), esteemed


ment that he made use of their even by opponents for his pure,
teaching. Fortified with ex- gentle, and genial character
traordinary acuteness, penetra- (^Diog. 37 quoting many indi-
;

ting wit,' and ready speech vidual traits, 44 vii. 171 ix:.
; ;

(JHog. 30; 34; 37; CSc. Acad, 115 do. Fin. v. 31, 94 Pint.
; ;

ii. 6, 18;Numen. in Mts. xiv. 6, De Adulat. 22, p. 63 Coh. Ira, ;

2; Pint. De Ranit. 7, p. 126; 13, p. 461. ^lum, V. H. xiv.


Qu. Conv. vii. 5, 3, 7 ii. 1, 10, 4
; 96). On his relations to Clean-
Stoi. Ploril. ed. Mein. iv. 193, thes, conf. Piog. vii. 171 Plut. ;

28), learned, particularly in De Adulat. 11, p. 55. He left no


mathematics {Diog. 32), and writings {Piog. 32 Plut. Alex. ;

well acquainted with native Virt. 4, p. 328).


poets {JDiog. 30, who mentions > Cie. De Orat. iii. 18, 67
his own attempts at poetry, Arcesilas primum ... ex variis
quoting some of his epigrams), Platonis libris sermoniliusque
he appears to have early dis- Socraticis hocmaxime arripuit,
tinguished himself. PromPfei. nihil esse certi quod aut sensi-
Adv. Col. 26, p. 1121, it appears bus aut animo percipi possit
that in Epicurus' lifetime, con- quem ferunt . . . aspernatum
sequently before 270 B.C., he esse omne animi sensusque ju-
had propounded his sceptical dicium, primumque instituisse
views with great success. Apol- .nou quid ipse sentiret os-
lodorus, however, appears to tendere, sed contra id, quod
have placed his career too early quisque se sentire dixisset, dis-
(^Biog. 4.5), in making his dxiAi putare. This is, in fact, the
between 300 and 296 B.C. On calumniandilicentia with which
the death of Crates, the con- Augustin., herein doubtless fol-
duct of the School devolved lowing Cicero, c. Acad. iii. 17,
upon Arcesilaus (JOiog. 32), 39, charges him, contra omnia
through whom it attained no velle dicere quasi ostentationis
small note {Strabo, i. 2, 2, p. causa.
15 Diag. 37 Numen. in Em.
; ; ^ Conf. Numen. in Eus. Pr.
xiv. 6, 14). From public mat- B V. xiv. 6, 12, and above, p. 86, 4.
ters he held aloof, and lived in
ARCESILAUS. 631

Plato and Aristotle he ignored altogether. Indeed, Ohap.


V"V"TTT
no peculiar arguments against knowledge are referred 1_

to him. The old sceptical arguments of Plato and


Socrates, of Anaxagoras, Empedocles, Democritus,
Heraclitus,and Parmenides, are repeated,' all of
which apply only to the knowledge of the senses, and
not to rational knowledge. Nevertheless, Arcesilaus
aimed at overthrowing the latter along with the for-
mer.^ For the opinion that he only used doubt as a
preparation to or means for concealing genuine Plato-
nism/ is opposed to all credible authorities. It ap-
pears, however, all the more clearly, that to him it

seemed unnecessary to refute the theory of a know-


ledge existing independently of the senses.
The Stoic arguments in favour of irresistible im-
pressions Arcesilaus met by asserting that an inter-
mediate something between knowledge and opinion,
a kind of conviction common to the wise and the
unwise, such as the Stoic KaTaXrj'f'is, is inconceivable ;

the wise man's conviction being always knowledge,


and that of the fool always opinion.^ Going then
farther into the idea of (pavTacria KaraXTjirTiicij, he en-
deavoured to show that it contained an internal con-
tradiction ; for to conceive {KaraKtj^is) is to approve

'
PlMt. Adv. Col. 26, 2 Cio.
;
^ die. De Orat. iii, 18. Sea
Acad. i. 12, 44. Ritter's view p. 530, 1.
of the latter passage that Arce-
' SeM. Pyxrh. i. 234 ;
Dio-
silans dwelt on the diversities cles of Cnidus, m Numen, in
of philosophic teaching in the Eus. Pr. Bv. xiv. 6, 5 ; Aui/ustin.
view of refuting it (iii. 478) c.Acad. iii. 17, 38. GefEers re-
appears to be so entirely with- gards Arcesilaus as a true fol-
out foundation, that he rather lower of the older Academy,
* Sesd. Math. vii. 163.
appealed to its unanimity to
confront doubt.
M M 2
632 THE SCEPTICS.

Chap. {avyKaraBea-is), and approval never applies to sensa-


XXIII.
tion, but only to thoughts and general ideas.' Lastly,
if the Stoics regarded force of conviction as the dis-
tinctive mark of a true or irresistible conception, and
as belonging to it in distinction from every other, the
Sceptic rejoined that such conceptions do not exist,
and that no true conception is of such a nature, but
that a false one may be equally irresistible.^ If no
certainty of perception is possible, no knowledge is

possible.' And since the wise man on for this


point Arcesilaus agrees with the Stoics must only
consider knowledge, and not opinion, nothing re-
mains for him but to abstain from all and every
statement, and to despair of any certain conviction.''

' SoBt. Math. 1. c. 154. 'kpKiulKaos. oBtb yiip Kol ave-


2 Cic. Acad. ii.24, 27. Zeno 'KtfT'n\^OiT{}VT] TIJS itrtlTT'fllxTJS atTia
asserted An : irresistible or ipai/eiTcu. All that is here attri-
conoeptional perception is such buted to Arcelaus is the asser-
an impression of a real object tion that eTTurrTjrhv is the cause
as cannot possibly come from of ^irio-Ti^^r), and that it is so
an unreal one. Arcesilaus en- vrhen produces a (pavraala
it
deavoured to prove nullum tale KoTo^TjTrTiK^. The connection
visiim esse a vero, ut non ejus- in which these statements were
dem modi etiam a falso posset made by Arcesilaus was pro-
esse. The same vievir in Sesnt. bably this If there is such a
:

1. c. To these may be added thing as knowledge, there must


discussions on deceptions of the be objects which produce it.
senses and contradictions in These objects, however, do not
the statements of the senses exist, there being no object
in Sext. vii. 408, and otherwise which does not admit a false
attributed to the Academicians. opinion equally well with a true
Conf Cic. N. D. i. 25, 70 Ur-
. : one.
gebat Arcesilas Zenonem, cum ' Sext. 155 ^u)) ofo-ijj 8e Karo-
:

ipse falsa omnia diceret, quae KvrTiKTJs (jmvraatas ovSi Karixii-


sensibus viderentur, Zenon au- t)j ytvtiireTaf tiv y&p (taToATj-
tem nonnulla visa esse falsa, TTTiKp (pavTatri^ (TiryKOTcffletris. ^i]
non omnia. To these attacks oSarts 5 KaTa\ii^eQis vdvTa effra*
on Zeno Plut. De An. (Kr. vii.) &KaTd\7iirTa.
1, probably refers 8ti ov rh : * Sext. 1. u. ; Cic. Acad. i.
4iri(rrriThv alrioy ttjs iiriariinii! iis 12, 45 ; ii. 20, 66 ,-
Pint. Adv.
ARCESILAUS. 533

It is therefore impossible to know anything, nor can Chap.


XXIII.
we even know for certain that we do not know any-
thing.' It was quite in accordance with this theory
for Arcesilaus to lay down no definite view in his
lectures, but only to refute the views of others.^
Even his disparaging remarks on dialectic,^ sup-
posing them to be genuine,'' are not at variance with
this conduct. He might consider the arguments of
the Stoics and the sophisms of the Megarians as
useless, whilst, at the same time, he was convinced
that no real knowledge could be attained by any
other means. He might even have inferred from
their sterility, that thought leads to truth quite as
little as the senses. There is no real difference be-
tween the result at which he arrived and that of
Pyrrho.' ,

Col. 24, 2 Mus. Pr. Ev. xiv. 4,


;
long more fittingly to the Chian
16; 6, 4. By Sext. Pyrrh. i. Aristo (see p. 59) than to Ar-
233, it is thus expressed Ar- : cesilaus. Still, if Chrysippus
cesilaus regards itroxh as being condemned the dialectic of the
a good in every case, o-iy/coTo- Sceptics (according to p. 66, 1),
fleo-is as an evil. Arcesilaus may very well have
' Cic. Acad. i. 12, 45. condemned that of the Stoics
2 Cic. Fin. ii. 1, 2; v. 4,11; and Megarians. Does not even
De Orat. iii. 18, 67 ; Diog. iv. Cic. Acad. ii. 28, 91, probably
28 ; Conf . Pliit. C. Not. 37, 7. following Cameades (see p.
Stoi. Floril. 82, 4 'Apirea-i-
: 541, 4), object to dialectic, be-
Kaos 6 tpiKiaotpos e^rj robs SiaXc/c- cause it furnishes no know-
TiKous ioucc'yol Tois tpnipOTralKTais
* This fact is not only re-
(jugglers), o'hives xapUvras wapa-
\oylQovTai and, Tbid. 10 (under
;
cognised by Numen. in Mis. Pr.
the heading 'ApK<rt\dov ix rav : Ev. xiv. 6, 4, but by Seint.
S^piivou avonviiiiaveufiiraii') : 6ia- Pyrrh. i. 232. Nor does the
XeicTi/cV Se (pedye, avyxvic^ r&va difference apply to Arcesilaus
Kfirw. (see p. 533, 1) which the later
' The authority is a very Sceptics made between them-
uncertain one, particularly as selves and the Academicians,
Arcesilaus left nothing in writ- viz. that they asserted the prin-

ing, and they would seem to be- ciple of doubt tentatively,


534 THE SCEPTICS.

Chap. If opponents asserted that by denying knowledge


xxm. Arcesilaus declined
all possibility of action is denied,'
(2) Praia- to accede to this statement. No firm conviction is,
hility.
as he maintained, necessary for a decision of the will;
for an action to come about a perception influences
the will immediately, leaving the question as to its

truth entirely out of sight.^ In order to act sensibly


we need no knowledge. For this purpose probability
isquite enough anyone can follow probability, even
;

though he is conscious of the uncertainty of all know-


ledge. Thus probability is the highest standard for
practical life.* We are but scantily informed how
whereas the Academicians had and influences the will without
asserted absolutely.
it Even avyKwriBctris. Since this state-
Sextus asserts it with some dif- ment was controverted by
iidence (irh^iv et ^)i \iyoi ris '6ti Chrysippus (_Plut. Sto. Rep. 47,
K.T.K.). On account of this 12. See above 87, 1), there can
connection with Pyrrho, the be no doubt that it was pro-
Stoic Aristo called Arcesilaus pounded by Arcesilaus.
(following H. vi. 181) TTp6ir8e :
' Heart. Math. vii. 158 : aW
iirel fierce raiha eSei Kal irepl ttjs
AtiSapos. Sexft. 1. c. ; Numen. TOV $iov Sie^ayayTis ^t)TUv $J ris
in Bus. Pr. Ev. xiv. 5; 11 ; Diog. ov xwpls KpiTTjplou TretpuKev diro-
iv. 33. SiSoffOai, d<f>' oS Kal 7j si'SaifjLoyia,
' has been already seen
It TOvrdffTi rh tov ^lov t4\os, ^prij-
that this was the key to the fievr]v ex^i T-^v iriffTiv, <pTi(rly &
position which the Stoics and 'ApKe(ri\aos, Srt 6 trepl irdvTtev
Epicureans took up against the ei:4x<av Kavovikl t^s alpso'eis koL
Sceptics. ipvycts Kal Kotvus Tcky Trpd^eis t^
" Pint. Adv. Col. 26,
3, pro- ev\6y(j}, Kara tovt6 re itpoepx^-
tecting Arcesilaus against the fievos rh Kpiriipiov Karopd^fret'
attacks of Kolotes, says: The T^v fxkii yap eifBaifioviav irepi^
opponents of Scepticism cannot yivetrdat 5tct rris tppovfjffews, r^v 5e
show that ^irox^i leads to inac- (t>p6v7i(nv KLveiaOoA ivro7s learopQ^.
tivity, for irivTO. ireipCiffi /col (rrpf- fuaai, rh Be KaT6p9a.'p,a elvai (ac-
tpovatv avTois oi/x (nri]Kovffiv t] cording to the Stoic definition)
dpfji^ yev4(r$ai ffvyKardBecris ouSe ^irep TrpaxBiv eilKoyov exel r^v
TTJs ^oirris dpxhv JSe^aro t^i' aJftr- dTToKoyiay. 6 irpoff^x^^ oiv r^ if-

^i lauTijs aywyhs iirX


flrjinj', d\\' \^ytp KaropBdiffii koX euSaijuov^irci.
tas irpi^eis ^<pdvTj fi^ SiOfi4v7i tov It is a mistake to suppose, with
TTpoaTiBeadai. Perception arises Numen. in Eus. Pr. Ev. xiv. 6,
'

CARNEADES. 635

Areesilaus applied this principle to the sphere of mo- Chap.


XXIII.
rals, but a few of his utterances are on record,' all

bearing witness to the beautiful spirit of moderation


in the moral theory of the Academy, which was
otherwise exemplified in his own life.^

Comparing with the theory of Areesilaus, that B. Car-


neades.
which was propounded by Carneades a century later,
the same leading features are found to be underly-
ing but all points have been more carefully worked
;

out, and placed on a wider footing. Of the imme-


diate followers of Areesilaus * it can only be stated

4, that Arcesilaias denied pro- theory of a Kpaais Si' 'i\ov, that


babilities. his criticism of dogmatism ex-
' In Pint. Tran. An. 9, g, B, tended to natural science.
p. 470, he gives the advice 2 Conf. p. 529, 3
g, B.
rather to devote attention to ^ Geffers, De Aroesilse Suc-
oneself and one's own life than cessoribus (including Carnea-
to works of art and other ex- des) Gott. 1845.
: Areesilaus
ternal things. In Stoi. Floril. was succeeded by Laoydes- of
95, 17, he says Poverty is bur-
: Gyrene, who died 240,B:C.,'after
densome, but educates for vir- presiding over the School for
tue. Ibid. 43, 91 Where there
: 26 years, having entrusted it in
are most laws, there are most his lifetime (probably only
transgressions of law. Plut. shortly before his death) to the
Cons, ad Apoll. 15, p. 110, has care of the PhocEeans Telecles
a saying of his as to the folly and Buandros {Biog. iv. 59-61).
of the fear of death. Id. De The statements made in Diog.
Sanit. 7, p. 126, Qu. Conv. vii. 1. c, Numen. in JSns. Pr. Bv.

5, 3, 7, records a somewhat xiv. 7, Phtt. De Adul. 22, p. 63,


severe judgment on adulterers JSttan, V. H. ii. 41, Atlien, x.
and prodigals. Quite unique 438, a, xiii. 606, c, PUii. H. N.
is the statement in Tertull. Ad X. 22, 51, referring particularly
Nation, ii. 2 Areesilaus held
: to individual peculiarities
that there were three kinds of which he appears to have had,
Gods (in other words he divided must be received with caution,
the popular Gods into three and particularly the smack
classes): the Olympian, the which Diog, 59 passingly men-
stars, andthe Titans. It implies tions and Numeuius depicts
that he criticised the belief in with intolerable garrulity. Diog.
the Gods. It also appears by calls him av^ip i7niv6ra.Tos Kal
the language used in Pint. C. oiiK oKiyovs iff)(7iKiiis ^T}\ur<i.s

Not. 37, 7, respecting the Stoic <pl\6irOJ'6s T iK ViOV KOi TTeVTJi


636 THE SCEPTICS.

Chap. that they clung to their teacher. It may be pre-


xxin.
sumed that they did little in the way of expansion,
since the ancients are silent as to their labours, only
Carneades ' being mentioned as the continuer of the
neades. Respecting these in-
To his admirers belongs Atta- dividuals nothing is known be-
ins I. of Pergamum. A
visit to yond the names.
his court was however declined ' Carneades, the son of Epi-
in skilful language (^Diog. 60, comus or Philocomus, was born
which Geffers, p. 5 clearly mis- at Cyrene {Biog. iv. 62; Strabo,
understands). In doctrine, he xvii. 8, 22, p. 838 ; Cic. Tusc.
deviated little from Arcesilaus, iv. 3, 5), and died, according
and, having been the first to to Apollodorus (^Biog. 65), 129
commit to writing the teaching B.C., in his 8oth year. Imoian,
of the New Academy (^Sidd. Macrob. 20 assigns to him the
AoK ' typa^e ^iKdco^a Koi "Jrepl same age. With less probabi-
<l>v<rfus the latter is somewhat lity Cic. Acad. ii. 6, 16, Valer.
extraordinary for a Sceptic) Max. viii. 7, 5, extend his age
was by some mistake called its to 90, making his birth year
founder 50).
(^JDiog. According 213 B.C. Later admirers find
to Biog. vii. 183, see p. 46, 1, he a remarkable fact in his birth-
appears to have taught in the day happening, like Plato's, on
Academy during Arcesilaus' the Carnean festival (^Plut. Qu.
lifetime. Panaretus {A then. xii. Conv. viii. 1, 2, 1). Little is
552, d j^l. V. H. x. 6), Demo-
; known of his life. He was a
phanes, and Ecdemus or Ecde- disciple and follower of Hegesi-
lus (Pluta/i-cli. Philopon. 1 Arab. nus, but at the same time re-
5, 7) are also called pupils of ceived instruction in dialectic
Arcesilaus. The most distin- {do. Acad. ii. 30, 98) from the
guished pupil of Lacydes, aq- Stoic Diog'enes, and studied
cording to Eus. xiv. 7, 12, was with indefatigable zeal {Biog.
Aristippus of Cyrene, also men- 62) philcsophic literature, and
tioned by Biog. ii. 83. Another, in particular the writings of
Paulus, is also mentioned by Chrysippus {Biog. 62 Plvt. ;

Timotheus, in Clemens, Strom. Sto. Kep. 10, 44 Mas. Pr. Ev.


;

496, D. His successors were xiv. 7, 13). In 1 56 B.C. he took


Teleoles and Euandros, who part in the well-known associa-
jointly presided over the School. tion of philosophers, and pro-
Buander, however, according to duced the greatest impression
Cie. Acad. ii. 6, 16, Biog. 60, on his Roman hearers by the
Ens. 1. u., having survived his force of his language and the
colleague, was followed by He- boldness with which he attacked
gesinus (^Biog. 60 do. 1. c.) or
; the current principles of morals.
Hegesilaus (as he is called by Shortly before his death, pro-
Clemens, Strom, p. 301, c), the bably also at an earlier period,
immediate predecessor of Car- he became blind {Biog. 66),-
;

CARNEADES.

Academic Scepticism. The importance attaching to Chap


Carneades therefore all the greater, and he XXII]
is is in
consequence called the founder of the third or New
Academy.' Nor is this done without reason, witness
the admiration which his talents called forth among
cotemporaries and posterity,' and the flourishing con-

He left no writings, the pre- his name), to be a special fa-


servation of his doctrines being vourite of Apollo, but that tra-
the work of his pupils, in par- dition said an eclipse of the
ticular of Clitomachus (Biog. moon (Suid. Kapv. adds an
66, 67; de. Acad. ii. 31, 98; eclipse of the sun) comme-
32, 102). Respecting his cha- morated his death ; a-v/jardS^iay,
racter, we may
gather from a ttjs ttv ettroi ris, aiviTTOixevov tov

few expressions that, whilst jiAffl' ^\iov KaWltTTOv TUi/ liffrpwv

vigorous in disputation (_Diog. (,Diog. 64). Straio, xvii. 3, 22,


63 Gell. N. A, vi. 14, 10), he
; p. 838, says of him: oZtos 8J
was not wanting in a repose of Twv i^ 'AKoS-rifiias Apiirjos <j)lKo{t6'
mind harmonising with his dfi.o\oyehai and there was
<\)a>v ;

principles (Diog. 66). That he only one opinion among the


was a just man, notwithstand- ancients regarding the force of
ing his speech against justice, his logic, and the power and
we can well believe (^Qnintil. attraction of his eloquence,
xii. 1, 35). aided as these were by un-"
The quotation in Ding. 64 usually powerful organs (see
(t] ffvtniiffaffa ipixris nai Siahiaei) the anecdotes in I'lut. Garrul.
does not indicate fear of death, 21, p. 613; JHffg. 63). Conf.
but simple resignation to the Diog. 62 CUc. Fin. iii. 12, 41
;

course of nature. Still less so De Orat. ii. 38, 161 iii. 18, 68; ;

does his language on Antipater's Gell N. A. vi. 14, 10 Nnmen. ;

suicide (and also what is quoted in Emeiius, Pr. Bv. xiv. 8, 2


in Stob. i'loril. 119, 19) indicate and 5 Laetant. Inst. v. 14
;

a faint-hearted attempt at imi- Plut. Cato Maj. 22. The latter,


tation afterwards abandoned, speaking of his success atKome,
but only a not very witty ridi- says fi&Kiara, S' tj KapvedSov x<^pts,
:

culing of an action which ap- ^s Siyafils T6 irXeiffTTi KoL S6^aTris


peared to Carneades eminently SvvdfJietos ovK airoSeoutra , &s . .

mad. T^v irdMi/ tjxV^ ei/eVXTjo-g.


Tivivjia
'
Se^. Pyrrh. i.220; Mis. Kal K6yos Kareix^^^ ^^ av^p^E^Arju
Pr. Ev. xiv. 7, 12 ; Lucian. Ma-
croi. 20. \vv Kol ;^eipotl/Aei/o$, epura Seivhif

His School held him in


2

such esteem, that it not only &\Kav TjSoyciv Kai dtarpL^Siv iK-
considered him, together with KeffdiiTes ivQovfft&ffi Trepl piKQOQ-'
Plato, because of his birthday
(TOless the idea grew out of
538 THE SCEPTICS.

Chap, dition in which he left his School.' Himself a pupil


L of Chrysippus, and resembling him in tone of mind,^
Carneades expanded not only the negative side of
the Sceptical theory in all directions with an acute-
ness entitling him to the first place among the ancient
Sceptics, but he was also the first to investigate the
positive side of Scepticism, the doctrine of proba-
bility,and to determine the degrees and conditions
of probability. By his labours in both ways he car-
ried the philosophy of Scepticism to its greatest
scientific perfection.

(1) Nega- As regards the negative side of these investiga-


tweddeof ^^JQ^g^ qj- the refutation of dogmatism, the attacks of
iitg. Carneades were directed partly against the formal
possibility of knowledge, and partly against the chief
actual results of the knowledge of his day, and in
both respects he had mainly to do with the Stoics,'
little as he confined himself to them.
{a) Denial To prove the impossibility of knowledge in ge-
ofposd- jjeral, he appeals sometimes to experience.
There is
fm-mal no kind of conviction which does not sometimes de^
mw ge.
^gj^g ^g . consequently there is none which guaran-

tees its own truth.* Going then further into the

' de. Acad. ii. 6, 16. system. The Stoics were, how-
* See p. 536, note. ever, the chief object of his at-
' i%a*. Math. vii. 159 toBto: tack. Cic. Tusc. v. 29, 82;
KOI & 'ApKealKaos. i Sk KapvedS-qs N. D. ii. 65, 162 I'lut. Garrul.
;

ou fxivov Tots ^Ta'iKois aAAct koL 23, p. 514 Augustin. c. Acad.


;

KaxTtTOiS'Kph avrovavTi^i^TOLffffeTO iii. 17, 39.


TTfpl ToS In Math. ix.
KpiTiipiov. * Sext. 1. o. koX S^ TrpSnos
.

1, Sextus charges the School of n^v abrif koX Koivhs nphs Tr(ii'Tas
Carneades with unnecessary cVt! \6yos KaB' %v iraplaraTai 8ti
diifuseness in discussing the obSh ia-nv airhus i,\i]6(ias Kpiri)-
f uudamental principles of every pioi', ov \6yos o&k a1ir9ii<rts o4 (pav-
;

CASNJEADES. ,639

nature of our notions, he argues, that since notions Chap.


XXIII.
consist in the change produced on the soul by im-
pressions from without, they must, to be true, not
only furnish information as to themselves, but also
as to the objects producing them. Now, this is by
no means always the case, many notions avowedly
giving a false impression of things. Hence the note
of truth cannot reside in an impression as such, but
only in a true impression.' It is, however, impossible
to distinguish with certainty a true impression from
one that is false. For independently of dreams,
visions,and the fancies of madmen, in short, of all
the unfounded chimeras which force themselves on
our notice under the guise of truth,^ it is still unde-
niable that many false notions resemble true ones
most unmistakably. The transition, too, from truth
to falsehood is so gradual, the interval between the
two is occupied by intermediate links so innume-
rable, and gradations so slight, that they impercep-
tibly go over one into the other, and it becomes im-
possible to draw a boundary line between the two
opposite spheres.^ Not content with proving this

Tiuria otiK SXSa ti tuv ovrav tioohus, whose immediate ad-


Trdi/To yip toDto avWii^Si]!/ Sia- versary was Carneades.
rfieiiStTat Tjiius. ' According to Cic. Acad.
'
Sext. 1. c. 160-163. ii. 40; 26, 83, the Academic
13,
2 Conf Sext. vii. 403
. Cio. ; system of proof rests on the
Acad. ii. 15, 47 28, 89 Carne-
; four following propositions :

ades being undoubtedly meant, (1) that there are false notions
although not mentioned by (2) that these cannot be known,
name. For the further scepti- i.e. be recognised as true ; (3)

cal arguments in Cicero tally that of two indistinguishable


with those which Sextus attri- notions, it is impossible to know
butes to Carneades, and those the one and not the other (4) ;

here quoted are refuted by An- that there is no true notiou by


540 THE SCEPTICS.

Chap. assertion in regard to the impression of the senses,


XXIII.
Carneades went on to prove it with regard to general
notions based on experience and intellectual concep-
tions.^ He showed that it is impossible for us to
distinguish objects so much alike as one egg is from
another; that at a certain distance the painted surface
seems raised, and a square tower seems round ; that
an oar in the water seems broken, and the neck-
plumage of a pigeon assumes dififerent colours in
the sun ; that objects on the shore seem to be moving
as we sail by, and so forth ; ^ in all of which cases
the same strength of conviction belongs to the false as
to the true impressions.^ He showed further that this
applies equally to purely intellectual ideas; that
many logical difficulties cannot be solved ; * that no

the side of which a false one percipi possit. Haec autem


cannot be placed not distin- universa etiam concidunt minu-
guishable from it. The second tius.
and third of these propositions ^ Sext. vii. 409 ; Cie. Acad,
not being denied at all, and the ii. 26, 84 ; 7, 19
25, 79
J
Nu- :

firstone only being denied by- men. in Euis. Pr. Ev. xiv. 8, 5.
Epicurus in regard to impres- Therewith is probably con-
sions on the senses, all impor- nected the statement in Galen,
tance attaches to the fourth De Opt. Doct. c. 2, vol.i. 45, K,
proposition, to which Sextns, to the effect that Carneades
vii. 16-t and 402, and Numen. persistently denied the axiom
in Eus. Pr. Ev. xiv. 8, 4, look that things that are equal to a
as the pith of the proof. third are equal to one another.
' Cie. Acad. ii. 13, 42 : Divi- His assertion probably comes
dunt enim In partes et eas to this that it may be possible
quidem magnas primum in : to distinguish two things as
sensus, deinde in ea, quse du- unequal, which cannot be dis-
cuntur a sensibjas et ab omni tinguished from a third, that
oonsuetudlne, quam
obscurari therefore two things may ap-
volunt (the against
ffvviiQita pear equal to a third without
which Chrysippus already di- being or appearing equal to
rected severe attacks. See p. one another.
46, 2 ; 91, 2) turn perveniunt Sext. 402 and 408.

ad earn partem, ut ne ratione * The fallacy called ^eM-

quidem et conjectuia ulla res Items ia carefully investigated


CARNEABBS. 541

absolute distinction can be drawn between much and Chap.


little, in short, between all differences in quantity ; L
and that it is the most natural course in all such
cases to follow Chrysippus, and to avoid the danger-
ous inferences which may be drawn by withholding
judgment.' Arguing from these facts, Carneades
concluded at first in regard to impressions of the
senses, that there is no such thing as ^avraa-ia
KardXrj-jniKi} in the Stoic sense of the term, in other
words, that no perception contains in itself cha^
racteristics, by virtue of which its truth may be
inferred with certainty.^ This fact being granted,
the possibility is in his opinion precluded of there
residing in the understanding a standard for the
distincition of truth from falsehood. The under-
standing and this belief was shared by his oppo-
nents must derive its material from the senses.*

Logic tests the formal accuracy of combinations of


thought, but gives no insight into their import.''
Direct proofs of the uncertainty of intellectual con-
victions are not therefore needed. The same result
may also be attained in a more personal way, by
raising the question, how individuals obtain their

in Cic. Acad. ii. 30,95 (by Car- Cie. Acad. ii. 28,. 91, who
neades as he saj'S, 98), as an here appears to be following
instance in point. Philo, and, subsequently, Gar-
Sext. 416 Cic. 1. c. 29, 92.
'
;
neades as well. Carneades also
Since Chrysippus tried to meet gives utterance to a similar
the chain-argument, it may be view of dialectic in Stoh. Floril.
supposed that this fallacy had 93, 13 (conf. Phd. C. Not. 2,
been used by Arcesilaus against 4), comparing it to a polypus
the Stoics. consuming its own tentacles.
2 Sext. vii. 164; Augmtin. It is able, he conceives, to ex-
c. Acad. ii. 5, 11. pose fallacies, but not to dis-
' Sext. 165. cover truth.
'

542 THE SCEPTICS.

Chap, knowledge. He can only be said to know a thine


XXIII . .

. '_ who has formed an opinion respecting it. In the


mean time, until he has decided in favour of some
definite opinion, he has still no knowledge. And
what dependence can be placed on the judgment of
one who has no knowledge ?
(J) Attack In these formal enquiries into the possibility of

"^ftaifio
knowledge, Carneades had chiefly to deal with the
hnmvledge Stoics, with whom he holds a common ground in his

tinte. appeal to the senses. The Stoics were also his chief
(o) The opponents in his polemic against the material results
^^ ^'^ dogmatic philosophy. Natural science having
'^v^ms'of
tJui Stoics throughout the period of the post-Aristotelian phi-
losophy been subordinated to ethics, ethics likewise
engaged more attention at the hands of Carneades
than science.^ In as far as he studied Natural science,
he appears to have been entirely opposed to the Stoic
treatment of the subject, and to this circumstance
we owe it, that better information is forthcoming
regarding his scientific, or rather his theological in-

vestigations, than regarding his moral views. The


Stoic theories of God and of final causes ' afforded
ample scope for the exercise of his ingenuity, and
from the ground he occupied it cannot have been
difficult for him to expose the weak points of that

' ac. Acad, ii.36, 117. Car- Oic. N, D. i. 2, 5, after a

neades is not mentioned by brief description of the Stoical


name, but there can be no views of Gods Contra quos
:

doubt that the reference is to Carneades ita multa disseruit,


some Academician, a,nd it is ' ut excitaret homines non so-
probable that it was the work cordes ad veri investigandi cu-
of Carneades. piditatem.
" JMoff. iv. 62.
CARNEABES. 543

theory. The Stoics had appealed in support of the Chap.


God ^^'
belief in to the consensus gentium. How close
at hand was the answer,' that the universality of
this belief was neither proved to exist, nor as a
matter of fact did it, but that in no case could the
opinion of an ignorant multitude decide anything.
The Stoics thought to find a proof of divine provi-
dence in the manner in which portents and prophe-
cies come To expose the delusion, no very ex-
true.
panded criticism of divination was necessary.^ Going
beyond this, Cameades preceded to call in question
the cardinal point of the Stoic system the belief
in God, the doctrine of the soul and reason of the
universe, and of the presence of design in its arrange-
ments. How, he asks, is the presence of design
manifested ? Whence all the things which cause
destruction and clanger to men if it be true that
God has made the world for the sake of man ? ^ If
reason is praised as the highest gift of God, is it not
manifest that the majority of men only use it to
make themselves worse than brutes ? In bestowing
such a gift God must have been taking but little

' do. N. D. i. 23, 62 iii. ; Stoics the existence of vermin,


4,11. Here, too, Cameades is of poisonous plants, of beasts of
not mentioned by name, but prey. In answer to Ciirysippus'
the reference to him is clear by assertion, that the final cause
Cicero's remarking that he is of a pig is to be killed, Carne-
quoting the Academic view. ades argues: A pig, therefore,
^ Conf. Cic. N. D. iii. 5, 11. by being killed, must attain
' The Academician in Cic. the object for which it was
Acad. ii. 38, 120. That these ar- destined it is always beneficial
;

guments were used by Cameades for a thing to attain its object


is clear from Plut. in Porpkyr. therefore it must be benefi-
ce Abst. iii. 20, where the cial to a pig to be killed and
latter vindicates against the eaten.
;

644 THE SCEPTICS.

Chap, care of this maioritv.' Even if we attribute to mar


XXIII
L direct blame for the misuse of reason, still, why has
G-od bestowed on him a reason which can be so muci
abused ?^ Moreover, the Stoics themselves say thai
a wise man can nowhere be found? They admit,
too, that folly is the greatest misfortune. How, then,
can they speak of the care bestowed by God on men,
when on their own confession, the whole of mankind
issunk in the deepest misery ? ^ But allowing that
the Gods could not bestow virtue and wisdom upon
all, they could, at least, have taken care that it

should go well with the good. Instead of this, the


experience of a hundred cases shows that the upright
man comes to a miserable end ; that crime succeeds
and that the criminal can enjoy the fruits of his
misdeeds undisturbed. Where, then, is the agency
of Providence ? ^ The facts being entirely different to
what the Stoics suppose, what becomes of their in-
ferences? Allowing the presence of design in the
world, and granting that the world is as beautiful
and good as possible, why is it inconceivable that
nature should have formed the world according to
natural laws without the intervention of God ? Ad-
mitting, too, the connection of parts in the universe,
why should not this connection be the result simply
of natural forces, without a soul of the universe or a
deity?* Who can pretend to be so intimately ae-

' N. D. iii. 25, 65-70.


Cic. ' lUd. 31, 76.
It is here presumed that the ' Hid. 32, 79.
leading thoughts in Cicero's ' Cio. N. D. iii. 32, 80.
description belong to the School ^ Cio. Acad. ii. 38, 1 20 N. D.
;

pf Carneades. iii. 11, 28.


CARNEADES, 545

quainted with the powers of nature, as to be able to Chap.


XXIII '_
prove the impossibility of this assumption ? Zeno
argued that rational things are better than things
irrational, that the world is the best possible, and
must therefore be rational. Man, says Socrates, can
only derive his soul from the world ; therefore the
world must have a soul. But what, replies the Aca-
demician,' is there to show that reason is best for
the world, if it be the best for us ? or that there must
be a soul even in nature for nature to produce a
soul ? What man is not able to produce, that, argues
Chrysippus, must have been produced by a higher
being by deity. But to this inference the same objec-
tion was raised by the Academicians as to the former
one, viz., that it confounds two different points of
view. There may, indeed, be a Being higher than
man. But why must there needs, be a rational
man-like Being ? Why a God ? Why not nature her-
self ? Nor did the argument seem to an Academi-
^

cian more conclusive, that as every house is destined


to be inhabited, so, too, the world must be intended for
the habitation of Grod. To this there was the obvious
reply :^ If the world were a house, it might be so;
but the very point at issue is whether it is a house
constructed for a definite purpose, or whether it is

simply an undesigned result of natural forces.


Not content with attacking the conclusiveness (/3) T/iec-

of the arguments upon which the Stoics built their ^^If^g


belief in a God, the scepticism of the Academy Stoics at-
tacked,


ac. N. D. iu. 8, 21 ; 10, " Ibid. 10, 25.
26; 11, 27. ' L. 0.

N N
646 THE SCEPTICS.

Chap. souffht to demonstrate that the idea of God itself

was an untenable one. The line of argument which


Carneades struck out for this purpose is essentially

the same as that used in modern times to deny the


personality of Grod. The ordinary view of Grod re-
gards Him as an the same time, as
infinite, but, at

a separate Being, possessing the qualities arid living


the life of an individual. To this view Carneades
objected, on the ground that the first assertion
contradicts the second ; and argues that it is impos-
sible to apply the characteristics of personal exist-
ence toGod without limiting His infinite nature.
Whatever view we may take of God, we must regard
Him as a living Being ; and every living being is

composite, having parts and passions, and is hence


destructible.' Moreover, every living being has a
sense-nature. Far, therefore, from refusing such a
nature to God, Carneades attributed to Him, in the
interest of omniscience, far more organs of sense
than the five we possess. Now, everything capable
of impressions through the senses is also liable to
change ; sensation, according to the definition of
Chrysippus, being nothing more than a change of
soul and every such being must be capable of plea-
;

sure and pain, without which sensation is incon-


ceivable. Whatever is capable of change is liable to
destruction ; whatever is susceptible to pain is also

liable to deterioration, pain being caused by dete-


rioration, and is also liable to destruction.^ As the

o. N. D. iii. 12,29; 14, ' C!ic. N. D. iii. 13,32. More


34. fully Sext. Math. ix. 139-147.
CAJRNEADES. 647

capacity for sensation, so too the desire for what is Chap.


-'^^^""
in harmony with nature, and the dislike of what is
opposed to nature, belong to the conditions of life.
Whatever has the power of destroying any being is
opposed to the nature of that being, everything that
livesbeing exposed to annihilation.' Advancing
from the conception of a living being to that of a
rational being, all virtues would have to be attri-
buted to God as well as bliss. But how, asks Car-
neades, can any virtue be ascribed to God ? Every
virtue supposes an imperfection, in overcoming which
it consists. He only is continent who might pos-
sibly be incontinent, and persevering who might be
indulgent. To be brave, a man must be exposed to
danger ; to be magnanimous, he must be exposed to
misfortunes. A being not feeling attraction for
pleasure, nor aversion for pain and difficulties, dan-
gers and misfortunes, would not be capable of virtue.
Just as little could we predicate prudence of a being
not susceptible of pleasure and pain ;
prudence con-
sisting in knowing what is good, bad, and morally
indifferent. But how can there be any such know-
ledge where there is no susceptibility to pleasure or
pain ? Or how can a being be conceived of capable of
feeling pleasure, but incapable of feeling pain, since
pleasure can only be known by contrast with pain,
and the possibility of increasing life always supposes
the possibility of lessening it. Nor is it otherwise

Here too Garneades is expressly were dealing with his views,


mentioned. But without being Oie. IMd. Further proofs
'
;

mentioned the agreement with of the transient nature of all


Cicero would show that we earthly beings are there given.
N N 2
548 THE SCEPTICS.

Chap, with intellieence


C3
(evBovKla).\.
He only is intelligent
-y^Y'TTT
1_ who always discovers what will subserve his purpose.
If, however, he must discover it, it cannot have been
previously known to him. Hence intelligence can

only belong to a being who is ignorant about much.


Such a being can never feel sure that sooner or later
something will not cause his ruin. He will there-
fore be exposed to fear. A being susceptible of plea-
sure and exposed to pain, a being who has to contend
with dangers and difficulties, and who feels pain and
fear, must inevitably, so thought Carneades, be finite
and destructible. If, therefore, we cannot conceive
of God except in this form, we cannot conceive of
Him at all, our conception being self-destructive.'
There is yet another reason, according to Car-
neades, why God cannot have any virtue ; because
virtue is above and there can be nothing
its possessor,

above God.^ Moreover, what is the position of God


in regard to speech ? It was easy to show the ab-
surdity of attributing speech to Him,' but to call

Him speechless {a(f)a>vos) seemed also to be opposed


to the general belief.'' Quite independently, how-

' Sext, Math. ix. 152-175, ment has a look of sophistry


quotes the same argument for about it. It alludes to the im-
ffoxpitoffipri, and so does Oio. N. portant question which engaged
D. ill. 15, 38, both without men- so much attention in the middle
tioning Carneades by name, but ages, viz. How in Deity the
since both writers introduce universal side is related to the
these proofs in the same posi- individual, whether goodness
tion of a longer argument, in and reason are for God a law
which Carneades is expressly independent of His will or not.
mentioned both before and ' As Epicurus did. See p.
after, there can be no doubt 468, 3.
that to him they refer. * Sext. 178.
2 Sext. Ix. 176. The argu-
;

CARNEADE8. 549

ever, of details, the inconceivableness of God appears. Chap.


^^^^^'
so soon as the question is raised, whether the deity
is limited or unlimited, material or immaterial. God
cannot be unlimited ; for what is unlimited is neces-
sarily immoveable because it has no place and
soulless since by virtue of its boundlessness it can-
not form a whole permeated by a soul ; but God we
ordinarily think of both as moving and as endowed
with a soul. Nor can God be limited ; for all that
is limited is incomplete. Moreover, God cannot be
immaterial, for Carneades, like the Stoics, held tliat

what is immaterial possesses neither soul, feeling,


nor activity. Neither can he be material, all com-
posite bodies being liable to change and destruction,
and simple bodies, fire, water, and the like, possess-
ing neither life nor reason.' If, then, all the forms
under which we think of God are impossible. His
existence cannot be asserted.
Easier work lay before the Sceptics in criticising (7) Poly-

and their defence by


polytheistic views of religion jv-s ai-
the Stoics. Among the arguments employed by Car- tacked.

neades to overthrow them, certain chain-arguments


are prominently mentioned, by means of which he
endeavoured to show that the popular belief has no
distinctive marks for the spheres of God and man.

Sext. 1. c. 148-151 ; 180.


' Sextus himself seems to refer
That SexCus here refers to Car- not only individual arguments,
neades is clear from his agree- but the whole series of them,
ment with Oio. N. D. 12, 29-31 to Carneades, when he oon-
14, 34. Cicero introduces his tinues, 182: ^ptSTriyraiSJ Kal w6
remarks with the words Ilia : toC Kafv^iSov Ka\ aupniKus rttifs,

autem, qu^ Carneades affere- k.t.A.

tat, quemadmodum dissolvitis?


550 THE SCEPTICS.

Chap. If Zeus is a Grod, he argues, his brother Poseidon


xxili
must likewise be one, and if he is one, the rivers and
streams must also be Gods. If Helios is a Grod, the
appearance of Helios above the earth, or day, must
be a Grod and, consequently, month, year, morning,
;

midday, evening, must all be Gods.^ Polytheism is

here refuted by establishing an essential similarity


between what is accepted as God and what is avow-
edly not a God. It may readily be supposed that
this was not the only proof of the acuteness of Car-
neades' reasoning.^
Divination, to which the Stoics attached especial
importance,^ was stoutly assailed. Carneades proved
that no peculiar range of subjects belonged thereto,
but that in all cases admitting professional judgment
experts pass a better judgment than diviners.^ To
know accidental events beforehand is impossible;
it is useless to know those that are necessary and
unavoidable, nay, more, it would even be harmful.'
No casual connection can be conceived of between
a prophecy and the ensuing realisation.^ If the
Stoics met him by pointing to fulfilled prophecies,
he replied that the coincidence was accidental,' at

' /SfeiT*. 182-190. More fully same name. The whole drift
in do. N. D. ill. 17, 43. Sex- of this argument shows that it
tus also observes, 190 xaX SaXous: was borrowed from some Greek
S^ toioiStous fftjopiiras ^pterSxriv treatise.
01 iTfpl tiv KapvedSriv eis ri (i); ' See Cfic. Divin. i. 4, 7 ; 7,
ehai eiois. 12.
2 To him, or probably to his * Ibid. ii. 3, 9.
School, belongs the learned arr '>
Ibid. v. 13 ; but Carne-
gument in Cfio. N. D. iii. 21, 53, ades is not here mentioned by
to 23, 60, proving the want of name.
unity in traditional myths by * Ibid. i. 13, 23 ; 49, 109.
the multiplicity of Gods of the ' 6?o. I.e. and Divin. ii. 21,48.
:

CABNEABES. 551

the same time declaring many such stories to be Chap.


xxiii.
without doubt false.'

Connected probably with these attacks on divina- (S) Moral


tion was the defence by Carneades of the freedom of "* "(
'
the atoics
the will. The Stoic fatalism he refuted by an appeal attacUA.
to the fact that our decision is free ; and since the
Stoics appealed in support of their view to the law
of causality, he likewise attacked this law.^ In so
doing his intention was not to assert anything posi-
tive respecting the nature of the human will, but
only to attack the Stoic proposition, and if for his
own part he adhered to the old Academic doctrine
of a free will, he still regarded that doctrine as only
probable.
Less information exists as to the arguments by
which Carneades sought to assail the current prin-

ciples of morality. . Nevertheless, enough is known


to indicate the course taken by his Scepticism within
this sphere. In the second of the celebrated speeches
which he delivered at Eome in the year 156 B.c.,^ he
denied that there is such a thing as natural right
all laws are only positive civil institutions devised by
men for the sake of safety and advantage, and for

the protection of the weak and hence he


; is regarded
as foolish who prefers justice to interest, which after

'
Cic. 1. c. ii. 11, 27. He will therefore confine it to
2 Cie. De
Fato, 11, 23 ; 14, '

bodily motion, and not allow it *

31. The freedom of the will, unconditional validity,


he there says, may be asserted " Laet. Instit. v. 14, follow-
even granting that every mo- ing Cic. De Bep. iii. 4 Plut. ;

tion is referred to a cause, for Cato Maj. c. 22 QvAntil. In-


;

it is not necessary that this law stit. xii. 1, 35.

should hold good of the will.


.

652 TEE SCEPTICS.

Chap, all is the only unconditional end. In support of


xxin.
these statements he appealed to the fact that laws
change with circumstances, and are different in dif-
ferent countries. He pointed to the example of all
great nations, such as the Eomans, all of whom
attained to greatness by unrighteous means. He
impressed into his service the many casuistical
questions raised hy the Stoics, expressing the
opinion that in all these cases it is better to commit
the injury which brings advantage for instance, to
murder another to save one's own life rather than
to postpone advantage to right, and hence inferred
that intelligence is a state of irreconcileable opposi-
tion to justice.*
This free criticism of dogmatic views could not
fail to bring Carneades to the same result as his
predecessors. Knowledge is absolutely impossible.
A man of sense will look at everything from all
sides and invariably withhold judgment, thus guard-
ing himself against error.* And to this conviction
' Laetatit. \. \&
c.Cie. De ; Kiiov,Tipbs Tolniiv yip ^aaiviiims
Eep. iii. 8-12 ; 14 17 Fin. ii.
; ; oiKtias Ix"" 'rpdrrip, fin-Te ;ui)5eK

18, 59. On the above oasuisti- irpoirirTaieiv. oirToxria or iwpo-


cal cases see De Off. iii. 13; irTai<r/a is, according to the Stoic
23, 89, and above, p. 299, 2. definition {Diog. vii. 46) = ^iriir-
Probably Carneades was the t^/iijtoD Tnire Sei o-wTKoravMf-
canse of the study of casuistry trBai koI |U^j. It consists, there-
among the later Stoics. fore, in not giving a hasty
^ do. Acad. ii. 34, 108 conf ; assent to any proposition. Ac-
31, 98.In Id. Att. xiii. 21, he cording to the Sceptics, this is
compares this itroxh to the only possible, and you are only
drawing up of a charioteer, or then safe from error, when you
to the guard of a pugilist. No give assent to none whatever,
doubt it is with reference to aTrpoirjrTMirIa becomes then iden-
Ivoxh that AUx. Aphr. De An. tioal with ivoxt] or fi7vom, which
154 a, says The Academicians
: Max. Tyr. Diss. 35, 7, speaks
consider airTaaia the irpwrov oi- of as the ultimace end of Car>
CARNEADES. 553

be clings so persistently that he altogether refuses to Chap.


listen to the objection that the wise man must be '_

a,t least convinced of the impossibility of any firm


conviction.' The earlier Sceptics, far from attri- (2) Pod-
buting an equal value to all notions on this account, tlwteaah,-
had not dispensed with reasons for actions and ^pi "^

thoughts. This point was now taken up by Car- . , ,

neades, who in attempting to establish the conditions ofprola-


and degrees of probability, hoped to obtain a clue ***'

as to the kind of convinction which was still per-


mitted in his system. However much we may
despair of knowledge, some stimulus and ground-
work for action is needed. Certain suppositions
must therefore be assumed, from which the pursuit
of happiness must start.^ To these so much weight
must be attached that they are allowed to decide our
conduct, but we must be on our guard against con-
sidering them to be true, or to be something really
known and conceived. Nor must we forget that
neades. Hence Carneades, as esset, si probabile nihil es-
Arcesilaus had done before him, set, et sequitur omnis vitie
spoke for and against every . . . eversio. Ibid. 101 32, ;

subject, without expressing a 104 Nam : cum placeat, eum


decided opinion, die. N.D. I. qui de omnibus rebus contineat
5, 11 Acad. ii. 18, 60 Divin.
; ; se de assentiendo, moveri ta-
ii. 72, 150 Kep. iii. 5, 8 ; Tuso.
;
men et agere aliquid, reliquit
V. 4, 11 5 Jihis. Pr, By. xiv. 7, ejusmodi visa, quibus ad ac-
12. tlonem excitemur, etc. Hence
'
<Mc. Acad. ii. 9, 28, the assurance {Hid. 103 Stol. ;

2 Seiet. Math, vii. 166 : aira- Floril. ed. Mein. iv. 231) that
To^jne>/os5eaiauTi)s[i KapxeiJSijj] the Academicians do not wish
Ti Kpiriiptov irpis re rijp tov $iov to go into the question of per-
Sie|a7u7-))v Koi vphs tV ttjj fu- ception. They accept it as a
Satfiovlas irepi/CTrjiriJ' Sufifuy ait- phenomenon of consciousness,
mayKiCerai xal Kaff avrhp repl and a basis of action, but they
Ti/iTov SioTaTTto-flai, k.t.\. do. deny that it strictly furnishes
Acad. ii. 99 (of Clitoma-
31, knowledge. The senses are
cbus) : Htenim contra naturam iyifts, but not ciKpifieTs,
554 THE SCEPTICS.

Chap, even the nature of our true ideas is such as that of


XXIII.
false ones may be, and that the truth of ideas can
never be known with certainty. Hence we shall

withhold all assent, not allowing any ideas to be true,


but only to have the appearance of truth {d\r)6r]

(jiaivsadai) or probability {efju^acns, iriOavoTrjs).^

In every notion two things need to be considered,


the relation to the object represented which makes it

either true or false, and the relation to the subject


who has the notion, which makes it seeT/i either true
or false. The former relation is, for the reasons
already quoted, quite beyond the compass of our
judgment; the latter, the relation of a notion to
ourselves, falls within the sphere of consciousness.''
So long as a notion seemingly true cloudy and in- is

distinct, like an object contemplated from a distance,


it makes no great impression on us. When, on the
contrary, the appearance of truth is strong, it pro-
duces in us a belief^ strong enough to determine us
to action, although it does not come up to the im-
pregnable certainty of knowledge.''

Sext. and Cic. 1. o.


' sen^ujrum (aliquando, as the
Sext. 1. 0. 167-170.
^ latter passage adds) non per-
Ibid. 171-173 or, as It is
^ ; cepto, i.e. opinaturum sapien-
expressed by Cicero, Acad. ii. tern.
Conf. Augugtin.
24, 78 It is possible nihil per-
: c. Acad,
oipere et tamen opinari. It is ii. 26 (undoubtedly in point
11,
of no importance that Philo of matter and probably in terms
and Metrodorus saidCameades following Cicero) Idprobabile:

had proved this statement, vel verisimile Academioi vo-


whereasClitomachus had stated, cant, quod nos ad agendum
hoc magis ab eo disputatum sine adsensione potest invitare.
quam probatum. Acad. ii. 48, Sine adsensione autem dico, ut
148; 21, 67, attributes the state- id quod agimus non opinemur
ment to Carneades, without any verum esse aut non id scire ar-
qualification, adding only : Ad- bitremur, agamus tamen. To
CAENEADES. 655

Belief, however, like probability, is of several Chap.


xxni.
degrees. The lowest degree of probability arises
when a notion produces by itself an impression of
truth, without being taken in connection with other
notions. The next higher degree is when that im-
pression is confirmed by the agreement of all notions
which are related to it. The third and highest
degree is when an investigation of all these notions
results in producing the same corroboration for all.

In the first case a notion is called probable {iriOav^) ;

in the second probable and undisputed {iriOavr) km


dtrspLcnraa-Tos) ; in the third probable, undisputed, and
tested (jridavrj kuI diripienraa'Tos koI TTspLaSsvfisvr]).^
Within each one of these three classes difierent

gradations of probability are again possible.^ The


distinguishing marks, which must be considered in
the investigation of probability, appear to have
been investigated by Carneades in the spirit of the
Aristotelian logic.^ In proportion to the greater or
less practical importance of a question, or to the
accuracy of investigation which the circumstances
allow, we must adhere to one or the other degree of
probability.'' Although no one of them is of such a

nature as to exclude the possibility of error, this


circumstance need not deprive us of certainty in
the same effect, Miseh. Pr. Ev. cernvmt, omnia se reddere in-
xiv. 7, 12 Carneades declared
:
certa, quod nolunt ea dioo iu-
;

it impossible to withhold judg- certa, qu^ &Sn\a Gr^oi.


ment on all points, and asserted ' Sext. 1. o. 173; 175-182;
irivra fhai aKardhwra, oil
iiev Pyrrh. i. 227 conf Cio. Acad.
; .

irdvra ii Conf. Cic.


&Sr,Ka. U. 11, 33; 31, 99; 32, 104.
^ Sext. 1. c. 173 ; 181.
Acad ii 17, 54, where the ob-
jection is raised to the New
Hid. 176 183.
;

Academicians : Ne hoc quidem Ibid. 184.


556 THE SCEPTICS.

Chap. respect to actions, provided we have once convinced


XXIII.
ourselves that the absolute certainty of our practical
premisses is not possible.' Just as little shall we
hesitate to affirm or deny anything in that con-
ditional way which is alone possible after what has
been stated. Assent will be given to no notion in
the sense of its being absolutely true, but to many
notions in the sense that we consider them highly
probable.''
(i) Moral Among questions about which the greatest possible
and re-
ligious
certainty is felt to be desirable, Carneades, true to
view of his whole position, gave a prominent place to prin-
lije.
ciples of morals ;
' life and action being the principal
things with which the theory of probability has to
do.'' We hear, therefore, that he thoroughly dis-

cussed the fundamental questions of Ethics, the


question as to the highest Grood.^ On this subject he

> Seart. 1. o. 174 ; dc. Aoad. ' Sext. Pyrrh. i. 226 : ayaShv
ii.31,99. ydp ri fpcwiv elvat ol ^AKaSrifiaiKol
2 I. u. 32, 103
Cio. 48, 148. ;
Kol KaKbi/, ovx &ffirep TifiHS, aWA
This explanation does away juerct rov TretreiffOat '6ti inBavov
with the charge of inconsistency iffrt fuiWov h Keyovffip flvuu aya-
which is brought against Car- 6bv viriipxeii' fl rh evavriov ; Kal
neades in do. Acad. ii. 18, 59 ;

21, 67 24, 78 (see p. 554, 3), on


;
* See p. 553, 2 ; 554, 4.
the ground that he allowed, in " Here the question arises :

contradistinction to Arcesilaus. Whence does the Sceptic derive


that the wise man will some- his conviction as to probabili-
times follow opinion, and will ties in morals 1 and as percep-
give his assent to certain state- tion is not available for the
ments. Numen. in Eus. Pr. Ev. purpose, GefEers concludes (De
xiv. 8, 7, even asserts that he Arc. Successor. 20) that Carne-
expressed hjs own convictions ades assumed a peculiar source
to his friends in private but ; of conviction in the mind. For
this assertion is no more true such an assumption, however,
of him than of Arcesilaus (see our authorities give no proof.
p. 531, 3), as may be seen from It cannot be gathered from the
the passage on p. 557, 2. hypothetical language respeot-
CARNEABES. 657

distinguished six, or relatively four, different views. Chap.


If the primary object of desire can in general only '_

consist of those things which correspond with our


nature, and which consequently call our emotions
into exercise, the object of desire must be either
pleasure, or absence of pain, or conformity with
nature. In each of these three cases two opposite
results are possible : either the highest Good may
consist in the attainment of a purpose, or else in the
activity which aims at its attainment. The latter is
the view of the Stoics only, and arises from re-
garding natural activity or virtue as the highest
Grood. Hence the six possible views are practically
reduced to four, which taken by themselves alone, or
else in combination, include all existing views re-
specting the highest Good.' But so ambiguously
did Carneades express himself as to his particular
preference of any one view, that even Clitomachns
declared he was ignorant as to his real opinions.'' It

was only tentatively and for the purpose of refuting


the Stoics, that he propounded the statement that
the highest Good consists in the enjoyment of such
things as afford satisfaction to the primary impulses

ing the freedom of the will in fact that certain things are far
Cie. De Fato, ii. 23. See p. more agreeable or disagreeable,
551, 2. Nor is it, indeed, neoes- and either promote or disturb
sary that Carneades, who never happiness.
pretended to hold any psycho- ' Cic. Pin. v. 6, 16, to 8, 23 ;
have had
logical theory, should Conf Tuso. v. 29, 84 ; Bitter,
.

any opinion on the subject, iii.686, has hardly expressed


Supposing he did have it, he with accuracy Carneades' divi-
might have appealed to ex- sion, which he would otherwise
perience quite as readily or hardly have accused of being
more so than the Stoics, and inaccurate and superficial,
^ Cie. Acad. ii. 45, 139.
have been content with the
;

658 THE SCEPTICS.

Chap, of nature.' Nevertheless, the matter has often been


xxin.
placed in such a light as though Carneades had
propounded this statement on his own account and ;

the statement itself has been quoted to prove that


he considered the satisfaction of natural impulses
apart from virtue as an end in itself.^ It is also
asserted that he approximated to the view of Callipho,
which does not appear to have been essentially dif-
ferent from that of the older Academy.* The same
leaning to the older Academy and its doctrine of
moderation appears in other recorded parts of the
Ethics of Carneades. The pain caused by mis-
fortune he wished to lessen by thinking beforehand
of its possibility ;
* and after the destruction of
Carthage he deliberately asserted before Clitomachus
that the wise man would never allow himself to be
disturbed, not even by the downfall of his country.'

> Cic. Acad. ii. 42, 131 In- :


' CSe. Acad. ii. 45, 139 Ut:

troducebatetiamCarneades,non Calliphontem sequar, cnjusqui-


quo probaret, sed ut oppoaeret dem sententiam Carneades ita
Stoicis, sumnmrn bonum ease studiose defensitabat, ut earn
frui rebus, quas primas na-
ids probare etiam videretur. Cal-
tura conciliavisset (yutuow'). lipho is reckoned among those
Similarly Fin. v. 7, 20 Tusc. ; who consider honestas cum ali-
V. 30, 84. This view differs
qua accessione or, as it is
from that of the Stoics, because said, Fin. t. 8, 21 ; 2.5, 73
it makes the highest Good con- Tuso. v. 30, 85, voluptas cum
sist not in natural activity as
honestate the highest Good,
such, but in the enjoyment of * Pint. Tranq. An. 16, p.
natural goods. 475.
2 Olc. Fin. ii. 11, 35 Ita :
" ac. Tusc. iii. 22, 54. Let
tres sunt fines expertes hones- it be observed that this view
tatis, unus Aristippi vel Epicuri of Carneades is specially placed
(pleasure), alter Hieronymi under the head of conviction
(freedom from pain), Cameadis on probabilities. It is said, he
tertius (the satisfaction of na- attacked the proposition, videri
tural instincts). Cont. Ibid. \. fore in Eegritudine sapientem
7, 20 ; 8, 22. patria capta. The other state-
CARNEADES. 559

Putting all these statements together, we obtain Chap.


xxiir.
a view not unworthy of Carneades, and certainly
quite in harmony with his position. That philo-
sopher could not, consistently with his sceptical
principles, allow scientific certainty to any of the
various opinions respecting the nature and aim of
moral action; and in this point he attacked the
Stoics with steady home-thrusts. Their inconsistency
in calling the choice of what is natural the highest
business of morality, and yet not allowing to what is

simply according to nature a place among goods,'


was so trenchantly exposed by him that Antipater is

said to have been brought to admit that not the


objects to which choice is directed, but the actual
choice itself, is a good.^ He even asserted that the
Stoic theory of Groods only differed in words from
that of the Peripatetics ; to which assertion he was
probably led by the fact that the Stoic morality
appeals to nature only, or perhaps by the theory
therewith connected of things to be desired and
things to be eschewed.^ If there were any difference

between the two. Stoicism, he thought, ignored


the real wants of nature. The Stoics, for instance,

ments of Caraeades on ethics, Carneades. . Carneades even


such as that in Phct. De Adulat. practically attributes it to the
Stoics.
16, p. 51, hare nothing charao-
teristic about them.
Cic. Fin. iii. 12, 41 : Car-
1
gee p. 279. neades tuus rem in sum-
. . .

' Plut. C. Not. 27, 14 ;Stob. mum discrimen adduxit, prop-


Eel, ii. 134. Plutarch, how- terea quod puguare non destitit,
ever, only quotes it as the in omni hac qusestioue, quae de
opinion of individuals. It ap- bonis et mails appelletur, non
esse rerum Stoicis cum Peripa-
pears more probable that it was
an opinion of Chrysippus which teticis coutroversiam, sed no-

Antipater defended against minum.


560 THE SCEPTICS.
Chap, called a good name a thing indifferent ; Carneades,
'_ however, drove them so much into a corner because
of this statement that they ever after (so Cicero
assures us) qualified their assertion, attributing to a
good name at least a secondary value among things
to be desired {'n-po'ny/j.svay Chrysippus, again, be-
lieved to find some consolation for the ills of life

in the thought that no man is free from them. Car-


neades was, however, of opinion that this thought
could only afford consolation to a lover of ill ; it

being rather a matter for sorrow that all should be


exposed to so hard a fate,' Believing, too, that
man's happiness does not depend on any theory of
ethics,' he could avow without hesitation that all

other views of morality do not go beyond pro-


bability ; and thus the statement of Clitomachus, as
far as it refers to a definite decision as to the highest

good, is without doubt correct. But just as the


denial of knowledge does not, according to the view
of Carneades, exclude conviction in general on
grounds of probability, no more does it in the pro-
vince of ethics. Here, then, is the intermediate
position which was attributed to him a position not
only suggested, by the traditions of the Academic
School, but remaining as a last residuum to the
sceptical destroyer of systems so opposite as Stoicism
and the theory of pleasure. The inconsistency of at

' Fin. iii. 1 7, 57. sophoTiun sententia sit de fini-


' do. Tuso. iii. 26, 59. biis,tamen virtus satis habeat
' Hid. V. 29, 83: Et quo- ad vitam beatam prEesidii, quod
Eiam videris hoc velle, ut, quae- quidem Carneadem disputare
cumque dissentientium philo- solitum accepimus, etc.
;

CARNEABES. 56]

one time identifying the satisfaction of natural in- Chap.


~^^^^'^-
stincts with virtue, and at another time making them
distinct from virtue, which is attributed to Carneades,
is an inconsistency for which probably Cicero is

alone responsible. The real meaning of Carneades can


only be that virtue consists in an activity directed
towards the possession of what is according to nature,
and hence that cannot be separated from this as
it '

the highest Grood. For the same reason, virtue, in


his opinion, supplies all that is requisite for hap-
piness.^ Hence, when it is stated that notwithstanding
his scepticism on moral subjects, Carneades was a
thoroughly upright man,' we have not only no reason
to doubt this statement as to his personal character,
but we can even discern that it was a practical and
legitimate consequence of his philosophy. It may
appear to us inconsistent to build on a foundation of
absolute doubt the certainty of practical conduct
nevertheless, it is an inconsistency deeply rooted in
all the scepticism of post-Aristotelian times. That
scepticism Carneades brought to completeness, and
in logically developing his theory, even its scientific

defects came to light.


For the same reason we may also give credit to

'
He
explicitly says, Fin. v. cording to nature, the prima
7, 18,that as each one defines secundum naturam are also ,

the highest good, so he deter- prima in animis quasi rirtutum


mines the honestum (the Kahhn, igniculi et semina.
virtue). The view of the Stoics, ^ See p. 560, 3, and Plut.
he says, places the honestum Tranq. An. 19, p. 477, where,
and bonum in an activity aim- however, the greater part seems
Ing at what is according to to belong to Plutarch,
nature adding that, according ^ Quintil. Instit. xii. 1, 35.
;

to the view which places it in See above 636, 1, end.


the possession of what is ao-
;

662 THE SCEPTICS.

Chap, the statement that Carneades, like the later Sceptics,


' notwithstanding his sharp criticisms on the popular
and philosophic theology of his age, never intended
to deny the existence of divine agencies.' On this
point he acted like a true Sceptic. He expressed
doubts as to whether anything could be known about
(xod, but for practical purposes he accepted the be-
lief in God as an opinion more or less probable and
useful.
Taking all things into account, the philosophic
importance of Carneades and the School of which he
was the head cannot be estimated at so low a value
as would be the case were the New Academy merely
credited with entertaining shallow doubts, and Car-
neades' theory of probabilities deduced from rheto-
rical rather than from philosophical considerations.*
For the last assertion there is no ground whatever
Carneades distinctly avowed that a conviction resting
on probabilities seemed indispensable for practical
needs and actions. On this point, too, he is wholly
in accord with all the forms of Scepticism, not only
with the New Academy, but also with Pyrrho and
the later Sceptics. He differs from them only in

the degree of accuracy with which he investigates


the varieties and conditions of probability ; but ,a

' Cic. N. D. 44 Hso


iii. 17, : God, but that he finds the ar-
Cameades aiebat, non ut Deos guments imsatisfaotory. Like-
toUeret. Quid enim philosopho wise Sextus, Pyrrh. iii. 2: t^

minus conveniens? sedutStoi- nlv $liji KaTaKoAoueoGfTes iSoJi-
cos nihil de Diis explicare con- aras ^a/iii/ elvai Seobs koI trepo-
vinoeret. In this sense the fiey fleous koI rpovosii/ airoiis (pa-
Academician in Cicero (i. 22, /xiv.
62) frequently asserts, that he ' Mtter, iii. 730, 694.
would not destroy belief in
SCHOOL OF CARNEADES. 563

question of degree can least of all be urged against , Chap.


a philosopher. Nor should doubts be called shallow _1^__L
which the ancients even in subsequent times could
only very inadequately dissipate, and which throw
light on several of the deepest problems of life by
the critical investigations they occasioned. No doubt,
in the despair of attaining to knowledge at all, and
in the attempt to reduce everything to opinion more
or less certain, indications may be seen of the ex-
haustion of the intellectual spirit, and of the extinc-
tion of philosophic originality. Nevertheless it must
never be forgotten that the Scepticism of the New
Academy was not only harmony with the course
in
naturally taken by Greek philosophy as a whole, but
that it was pursued with an acuteness and a scientific
vigour leaving no doubt that it was a really im-

portant link in the chain of philosophic develop-


ment.
In Carneades this Scepticism attained its highest c. School

growth. The successor of Carneades, Clitomachus,' ^/j"j"


' Clitomachus was a native he became esteemed as a philo-
of Carthage, hence called by sopher and productive as a
Max. Tyr. Diss. 10, 3, & Aifivs, virriter {JDiog. iv. 67). Treatises
and originally bore the name of his are mentioned by Cie.
of Hasdrubal. At home he Acad. ii. 31, 98 32, 102; J?io^.
;

devoted himself to study, and ii.92. He died (according to


wrote several treatises in his Stob. Floril. vii. 55) by suicide,
mother tongue (rp iSdj (pavf iv not before 110 B.C. (as Zwmpt
Tp TrarplSi 4^i\o(r6'<j>ei).' When remarks, Ueber d. philosoph.
40 years of age (according to Sohulen in Ath. Abh. d. Berl.
Steph. Byz. Be urbe Kapxi**": Akad., Jahrg.1842. Hist.Philol.
28), he came to Athens, was Kl. p. 67), since, according to
initiated by Carneades into do. De Orat. i. 11, 45, L. Cras-
Greek philosophy, -and devoted sus, during his qusstorship,
himself to it with such zeal and met him at Athens, which falls
success {Cic. Acad. ii. 6, 17; at the earliest in this year. He
31, 98 ; Athen. ix. 402, c) that must then have been very old.

o 2
564 THE SCEPTICS.

Chap. is known as the literary exponent of the views taught


XXIII.
by Carneades.' At the same time we hear of his
being accurately acquainted with the teaching of the
Peripatetics and Stoics ; and although it was no
doubt his first aim to refute the dogmatism of these
Schools, it would appear that Clitomachus entered
into the connection of their doctrines more fully
than is usually the case with opponents.' As to his
fellow-pupil, Charmidas (or Charmadas),' one wholly
unimportant utterance is our only guide for deter-

mining his views.'' For ascertaining the philosophy


of the other pupils of Carneades,^ nothing but the

' Mog. iv. 67 ; die. Acad, dicendi, nisi qui philosopho-


ii. 32, 102. rum inventa didicissent. Sext.
* As the peculiar observa- Math. ii. 20, also mentions the
tion in IHog. iv. proves av^p : hostile attitude of Clitomachus
iv rais rpifflv dlpeffefri SiairpE^as, and Charmadas towards rhe-
sv re ry 'AAaST^/iai'K^ Kal ireptira- toricians, at whom both he and
TTJTlKy Koi (TTaiK-p. the School to which he belongs
' According to Acad. ii.
Cio. tilt. His fellow-disciple Agnon
6, 17 ; De Orat. 45 Ora-
i. 11, ; drew up a treatise, according
tor, 16, 61, Charinadas was a to Quintil. ii. 17, 15, entitled
pupil of Oameades, whom he ' Charges against the rhetori-
followed not only in teaching cians.' Bitter's inferences,
but in method. He must have that Charmadas recommended
survived Clitomachus, since he philosophy as the only way to
taught at the same time with eloquence, and thus openly
Philo. See p. 566, 1. Philo, avowed the end of the philoso-
however, according to Clito- phical doctrine of probability,
machus, undertook the presi- iii. 695, make far too much of
dency of the School {JBus. Pr. a chance expression, which
Ev. xiv. 8, 9). According to really says nothing but what
Cio. De Oraf. ii. 88, 360, Tusc. the Stoics, and before them
i. he was remarkable
24, 59, Plato, had said.
for a good memory. ' In addition to Clitoma-
* ac. De Orat. i. 18, 84: chus and Charmadas, CHc. Acad,
Gharmadas asserted, eos qui 6, 16, mentions Hagnon and
ii.

rhetores nominabantur et qui Melauthius of Rhodes, the for-


dicendi prsecepta traderent ni- mer of whom is also mentioned
hil plane tenere, neque posse by Quintilian. (See AtJien.
quenquam facultatem assequi xiii. 602, d.) Cicero adds that
SCHOOL OF CARNEADES. 565

scantiest fragments have been preserved. The state- Chap.


ment of Polybius that the
Academic School degene- xxin.
rated into empty subtleties, and thereby became an
object of contempt,' may deserve no great amount
of belief but it does seem probable that the School
;

made no important advance on the path marked out

Metrodorus of Stratonioe passed &ITT dtaTTOpiLV, clS^ivut^v [1. fi Sv-


for a friend of Carneades ; he yardv] ia-ri,Tabs iv'PM\vai^ Suras
had joined him from among the 6(rippaiytr6ai rStv e^ofievuy uuy 4y
Epicureans (JDiog. x. 9). This "E<p4<Ta, Kol Stari^eiv, fiii na xaB'
Metrodorus must neither be h Kaiphv iv ^AKoSTjfiiq. SiaKfyovraL
confounded with Metrodorus of vepl Tointov oiix inrkp &\\uv &p' iv
Skepsis, the pupil of Charma- oiKip KaraKeifievoi ro^rovs 5iaT(-
das (see p. 566, 1), nor with BevTat Tohs \6yovs' i^&v Si' uTrcp-
the Metrodorus distinguished ^o\^v T^s 'irapado^o\oylas eh Sia-
as a painter, 168 B.C., whom 0o\ijv iJxatTtriiv '6\tjv a'lpetrtv, Sxrre
.Smilius Paulus brought to Ka} ra Ka\u/s aTropoifj.eva vapSt ToTs
Eome {Plin. H. N. xxxv. 11, ivOpciiTois eis ibmarlav fjx^'^'t f"'
135). The former must haTe Xwpls TTJs iSias atrroxias Kal 7o7s
been younger, the latter older, veois TotovTov ivreroKaiTi ^\ov,
than Metrodorus of Stratonice. Tuv fiev ijdtHuv Kal irpayfia'
c&ffre
A pupil of Melanthius (Diog. TiKuv \6yuv ^ijSk rijv rvxovirav
ii. 64), and also of Carneades iirivoiav Troie7(T6aty 8i' Siv Hujitris
in his later years {Phct. An. Tols tpt\o<Totpova't^ Trepi Seros avu-
Sen. S. Ger. Resp. 13, l,p. 791), <pf\eis Kal napaSo^ovs evpeai?ij)ylas
was .Xschines of Naples, ac- Kevodo^ovvres KaiaTpi^ovffi rois
cording to Cic. De Orat. i. 11, plovs. In the time of Carne-
45, a distinguished teacher in ades, whose cotemporary Poly-
the Academic School, likewise bius was, and to whom the re-
towards the close of the second mark of the enthusiasm of
century. Another pupil, Men- youth for Sceptical teaching
was by Carneades forbidden
tor, refers, such depreciatory Ian-
the School, because he was guage could not have been used
caught with his concubine of the Academy. The histori-
{Diog. iv. 63 ; Numen. in Mas. cal therefore, of the
value,
Pr. Ev. xiv. 8, 7). whole passage is suspicious. It
'
Exc. Vatic, xii. 26 koI yap: bears, besides, so entirely the
iKfiyay [ray iv 'AKaSrifiiif] Tivis maxk of exaggeration, that it
PouKiiitmi TTffi re tuv Trpocpavws is no more useful as giving a
KaraXijirruv fJvai ZoKoivrav koX view of the Academy than are
ircpl riiv iicaToA^irToiv eis hiroplav the caricatures of opponents
iyeiv Tohs Trpoaiiaxofifvovs Toi- for conveying any idea of mo-
a^rais XP^vrai irapaSo^oXoyiais Koi dern German philosophy.
TomtJras evvopovffi Tri6av6T7jTas,
;

56G THE SCEPTICS.

Chap. by himself and Arcesilaus, It did not even continue


XXIII.
true to that path for very long. Not a generation
after the death of its most celebrated teacher, and
even among his own pupils,' that eclecticism be-
gan to appear, the general and simultaneous spread
of which ushered in a new period in the history of
the post-Aristotelian philosophy.

' Among these pupils the tonice (see p. 564, 5), mentioned
tendency to lay stress on the by do. Acad. ii. 6, 16. Metro-
doctrine of probabilities in re- dorus of Skepsis might also be
lation to Scepticism was already suggested (Straio, xiii. 155, p.
strong. Proof may be found 609 ; xvi. 4, 16, p. 775 Flut. ;

not only in the accounts already Lucull. 22; Diog. v. 84; Go.
given us of Clitomachns and De Orat. ii. 88, 360 ; 90, 365
.^sohines, but also in the iii. 20, 75 ; Tuso. i. 24, 59 Pliu. ;

circumstance that many of the Hist. Nat. vii. 24, 89 ; Quintil.


older writers made the fourth X. 6, 1 ; xi. 2, 22 ; Miiller, Hist.
Academy date from Philo and Gr. iii. 203), who first learned
Charmidas, the fifth from An- rhetoric at Chalcedon, after-
tlochus (^Sext. Pyrrh. i. 220; wards entered the service of
Ihcs. Pr. Ev. xiv. 4, 16). At a Mithridates, and was put to
still earlier date, Metrodorusis death by his orders, B.C. 70, at
said to have departed from the an advanced age. Cic. De
platform of Carneades. Avgiis- Orat. iii. 20, 75, calls him an
tin. c. Acad. iii. 18, 41, after Academician and he is men-
;

speaking of Antiochus and his tioned, IMd. i. 11, 45, as a pupil


renunciation of Scepticism, of Charmadas. The language
says : Quamquam et Metro- quoted by Augustin may have
dorus id antea facere tenta- come from the treatise irepl
verat, qui primus dicitur esse awnBeias {Straho, p. 775). He
conf essus, non deoreto placuisse is otherwise only known as a
Aoademiois, nihil posse com- and politician. The
rhetorician
prehendi, sed necessario contra same remark applies to the
Stoicos hujus modi eos arma language in Cic. Acad. ii. 24,
sumsisse. Probably Augustin 78 (see p. 654, 3). We
do not
borrowed this passage from a know who is the Metrodorus
lost treatise of Cicero, and referred to. It may, however,
hence it may be relied upon. be inferred that it is the same
The Metrodorus referred to is Metrodorus who is mentioned
probably Metrodorus of Stra- by Augustin.
; ;

INDEX.
ACA APH
ACADEMIC, Scepticism, 537; Allegorical interpretations of
School, 560, 565 ; decline of, myths, 354.
565. Allegorising, the spirit of, among
Academician, 377 view of rea-
; the Stoics, 354.
son, 545 systems of morality,
; Amafinius, a promulgator of Epi-
399. cureanism at Kome, 411.
Academicians attacked by Stoics, view of, 265.
'AftipTTina, Stoic
233 ; objections to Chrysippus, Anaxagoras, sceptical arguments
545. of, 531.
Academy, 301 influence of, on
; Anaxarchus, a follower of Demo-
Stoics, 402 ; older, 399, 400, 558 ; critus, 518.
Middle, 46, 528, 535 New, 26, ; Animals, Stoic views on, 208
409, 517, 521, 523, 528 scepti- ;
Epicurean views on, 451.
cism of, 529, 545, 562, 563 con- ;
Antonies, the, 417.
nection witb Stoicism, 529 Antodinus'view of demons, 351.
Third, 537. Antigonus Gonatus, 39.
Achaean League, 13, Antipater of Tarsus, 336, 371 ;

Aohseans, 13, 14. a later Stoic and president of


Achaia, province of, 14. that School, 50 inference from
;

Achilles, shield of, explained, 360 a single premiss, 121 follows ;

staying the plague, 363. Zeno's example, 336 ; interpre-


'ASi((/)opa, 232, 283. tation of myths, 362 ; views on
.fflnesidemus, a later Sceptic, 523. divination, 371 ; views on
jEtolians, 13. moral choice, 559.
Affections permitted, 299. Antisthenes quoted as an exam-
Air, God as, 148. ple, 274, 292, 306 followed by
;

Air-currents, Stoic theory of, 127, Stoics, 357, 387, 388 by Zeno,;

129, 148, 152. 509 reflected by Aristo, 388


; ;

AKOTa\7)i('ia of Sceptics, 525. sophistical assertions of, 390.


Alexander of Macedon, 518. Anthropomorphic view of nature,
Alexander Aphrodisiensis, 117. 8.

Alexandria, 351 ; influence of, on Apathy, Stoio, modified, 292.


philosophy, 28; birthplace of 'Airaffa, 281.

Platonic School, 28. 'A</)0(r(o of Sceptics, 525.


Alexandrian period, 17. 'Aipopiiii, 242.
;;
; ;
;;
;

668 INDEX.
APH AEI
Aphrodite, Stoic interpretation of, Aristotle, merits and defects of,
361, 365, 366. 1 ; connection with Greek cha-
Apollo as the sun, 361 ; arrows of, racter, 6; idealism of, 2, 512 j
explained, 363. criticism of Plato, 2, 133 in- ;

ApoUodorus, an Epicurean, 411. consistencies of,133 3, 84,


'ATToirporiyufvov, 283. generic conceptions of, 19, 85
Applied moral science, 279. commentators on, 63 commen- ;

Aratus, a Stoic, and pupil of Zeno, dation of speculation, 57, 256,


43. 513 teaching of, 96 followed
; ;

Arcesilaus, a Sceptic, 29, 528 by Stoics, 97, 100, 194, 196, 202,
belonging to Middle Academy, 396, 397 categories of, 97, 98,
;

46 account
; of, 528 not con- ; 107 ; perfections of Greek philo-
nected with Zeno, 529 op- ; sophy in, 1, 11 ; mistakes in
ponent of Stoic theory, 531, natural science, 3; prominence
632 agreement with Stoics,
; given to dialectic method, 4
532 views on probability, 534
I
did not go far enough, 5 system ;

followers 535
of, compared ; of, connected with Greek cha-
with Carneades, 535, 565. racter, 7 ; failing to distinguish
Archedemus of Tarsus, a Stoic, 50 two sides of ideas, 8 the child of ;

view of the seat of the centre of his age, 10 ; speculations of, 18

force, 147. bridges over chasm between


Archipelago, Stoics In, 36. thought and its obj ect, 1 8 makes ;

Ares, story of, 361, 365. reason the essence of man, 19;
Aristarohus of Samos, 348. metaphysics of ,22 de velopes the
;

Aristippus considers bodily grati- doctrine of the syllogism, 65 ;

fication the highest pleasure, views on conceptions, 96 on ;

475 relation to Epicureanism,


; the modality of judgments, 115;
508 followed by Epicurus, 509
; the study of, 126 metaphysical ;

but not wholly, 510. notions of, 133; distinguishes


Aristo, the Stoic, 40 pupil of ;
matter and form, 104, 105 view ;

Zeno, 41 wins over the Cy-


; of two kinds of fire, 201 view ;

renaic Eratosthenes, 49 views ; of the world, 203 of the stars, ;

on logic and natural science, 59, 205; of the seat of life, 214 of ;

62 a native of Chios, 59, 255,


; the soul, 215 places knowledge
;

281 opposed to encyclical


; above action, 256 followed by ;

knowledge, 60 ethics of, 61 ; ; Zeno, 257 investigations into


;

peculiar views of, 62 differs ; individual virtue, 301 preju- ;

from Zeno, 63 objects to study


; dice against foreigners, 326;
of mind, 92, 298 divisions of ; relation of Epicureans to, 509,
emotions, 249 an enemy of
; 511; logic of, 123 followed by ;

speculation, 255 on the one- ; Chrysippus, 393 philosophy of,


;

ness of virtue, 261 not followed ; 126 theory on time and space,
;

by the Stoics, 281 follows ; 196 doctrine of the four ele-


;

Cynics, 297 followed by Clean-


; ments, 197, 199 on the regula-
;

thes, 298 view of the common


; tion of emotions, 252 under ;

source of virtue, 257, 261 denied ; the influence of Greek ideas,


s-msationto Deity, 347 relation j 301 view of Gods, 513 moral
; ;

of, to Stoics, 388. theory of, 398 many-sidednes^


;
; ;;

INDEX. 569
ARI CAT
of, 402 jdeveloped Socratio Basilides, an Epicurean and pre-
thought, ignored by Ar-
fill ; sident of the School, 410.
cesilaus, 531 formal and final
; Being, the Stoic category of, 98,
causes, lil; commentators on, 99, 126 primary, 161
; divine, ;

53. 217, 341, 349.


Aristotelian, logic, 124, 555 ori- ; Bithynia, birthplace of Asclepia-
ginal teaching, 3; categories, des, 415.
105; ethics, 804; spirit of, 555; Boethus, a Stoic, 49 inclining to ;

manner, 285 ; view of heaviness, the Peripatetics, 49 attacked ;

445 ;speculations, 516 ; philo- by Chrysippus, 76 ; dissents from


sophy, 396, 397. Stoic pantheism, 159 ; views on
Aristoxenus, 128, 133. divination, 371.
Artemis, explained as the moon, Bosporus, birthplace of Sphaems
361. the Stoic, 44.
Asclepiades, an Epicurean of Bi- Bryso, not instructor of Pyrrho,
thynia, 465. 518.
Asia, emigrants to, from Greece, Byzantine imperialism, 33.
14 ; the birthplace of Stoics,
36 ; Epicureans in, 406.
Assent, Stoic view of, 83. CALLIPHO'S view, 558.
Assos, birthplace of Cleanthes, 40. Canonic, the Epicurean, 425.
'Krapatjia, in the Epicurean system, Care, Stoic view of the causes of,
475 ; of Sceptics, 525. 249.
Atheism, 465. Cameades, a Sceptic, 535 his debt ;

Athene, Stoic interpretation of, to Chrysippus the Stoic, 56, 538 ;

358, 359, 361, 363. a thoroughly upright man, 561 -,

Athenian, 404. on formal knowledge, 539, 540 ;

Athens, 528 ; brilliant career of, scepticism of, 563, 538 ethics ;

9; seat of all Schools, 29 of, 558 negative views of, 538


;

foreign teachers at, 35 ; visited positive views of, 553 a century ;

by Zeno, 36, 528 appreciates; later than Arcesilaus, 536


him, 39; visited by Epicurus, founder of the Third Academy,
405, 406 ; Epicureanism at, 412, 537 ; denied tpainairla kotoXtj-
413, 417 ; visited by ApoUo- tttikJ), 541 common ground with
;

dorus, 412 ; rivalry with Sparta, Stoics, 542 strictures on Stoi-


;

11 ; the playball of rulers, 13. cism, 543 views of God, 546-


;

Atomists, system of, 501 ; view of 550 ; defends free will, 551
nature, 517. denies knowledge, 55"<;, 560
Atoms and empty space. Epicurean theory of probabilities, 553, 555;
view of, 439 ; deviation of, 444. views on morals, 556-559 im- ;

Angeas, 368. portance of, 562 pupils of, 564 ;

Authorities for Stoic philosophy, School of, 563.


53. Carthage, birthplace of Herillus,
'Mia, 227. 42, 256 ; destruction of, 558.
'A{(<^a, 110. Carus, T. Lucretius. See Lucre-
tius.

BAEGYLIUM, birthplace of Pro- Categories, the Stoic, 97, 99 ; re-


tarchus, 411. lation of, 109.
;
; ;;

570 INDEX.
CAT CLE
Cato quoted as an example, 274 ;
295 ;division of ethics, 298
death of the younger, 335, 337. shocks the feelings of cotem-
Cause, God the highest, according poraries, 307 moral character
:

to Stoics, 148. of, 309 his polity of the wise,


;

Centaur, 458. 322 view of demons, 352, 354


;

Cerberus, 364. view of divination, 370, 375;


Chffironea, results of battle of, 13. explains omens, 375 vagaries ;

Chain-inference, 119, 122. of, 380; follows Aristotle's


Charmidas, 564. logic, 393 completes Zeno's
;

Charybdis, Stoic explanation of, system, 401 developed Stoic


;

869. theory of knowledge, 525, 401


Chemical combination, 106, n. 2. 48, 55 on
; superhuman powers,
Chios, birthplace of Aristo, 41, 59, 545 definitions
; of sensations,
255. 546 on
; destiny, 180 on adip- ;

Chiron, 363. tation of means to ends, 184;


Christian ethics, 240 view of ; on punishment, 193 on faulty ;

demons, 354 modes of thought,


;
imagination, 246 on emotions ;

221. and virtue, 260 on the wise ;

Christianity, success of, 34 ; in- man, 284, 286, 322, 323 view of ;

fluence of, 9. the Gods, 346, 364, 545; ex-


Christians, early, 220 ; follow planation of myths, 365 regards ;

Zeno, 357 ethics of, 240 ; ex-


; knowledge as a means, 381 in- ;

ample of, 357. fluence of, 400; contemporary


Chrysippus, 54, 55, 57, 64, 65, 69 ; of, 48 unadorned style of, 63
; ;

first founder of later Stoicism, scholars of, 49, 375, 538, 541;
45 attended lectures of Aroe-
; time of, 64, 69, 70, 86, 257 sub- ;

silaus, 46 ; diilered from Clean- tlety of, 191 view of e^Sai/iovia,


;

thes, 47 ; a voluminous writer, 352.


47; 86; formal logic of the Cicero, 53 speaking as a Stoic,
;

StoicsfuUy developed by,92, 370 239, 346 follows Pansetius, 298,


;

contest between, and Diodorua, 315 ; account of Sceptics, 560


115; distinguishes five original treatise on duties, 298, 299, 302
forms of hypothetical sentences, on divination, 379 ; account of
119; exposes current fallacies, Epicureans, 414 ; responsible
122 ; narrows the field of logic, for Sceptic inconsistencies, 561
124; materialism of, 131; time of, 419.
teaches Kpams Si' iXeni, 138 his ; Cilioia, birthplace of Chrysippus
view of the world, 146 ; view of the Stoic, 45.
the resolution of the world, 153 Circe, house of, 369.
appeals to general conviction, Citium, birthplace of Zeno the
174 ; the theory of necessity, Stoic, 36.
178, 180; definition of time, Citizenship of the world, Stoic,
197 view of separate existence,
; 326.
21 9 places the essence of emo-
;
Civil Society, Epicurean view of,
tions in the imagination, 249 490.
theory of virtue, 299 defini-
; Cla,ss-conceptions of Stoics, 99.
tions of virtue, 260 ; on plea- Cleanthes the Stoic, 40 ; stem,
sure, 286 ;on virtue being lost, 237 a representative
; Stoic,
;; . ;

INDEX. 571
CLE CYE
400 instructor of Sphserus the
; Consensus gentium, appealed to
Stoic, 44; views of, 62; holds by Stoics, 543.
later theory to some extent, 76 Constantine, 32.
view of perceptions, 78 ; view Conversion, Stoic theory of, 275.
of life according to nature, 228 ;
Conviction or assent, 88.
sad view of life, 272 ; view of Cornutus, a Stoic, 53, 368.
the seat of efficient force, 147 ; Cosmopolitanism of Stoics, 35, 326.
view of the destruction of the Course of the world, 332.
world, 165 view of separate
; Crates the Cynic, 37 ; teacher of
existence, 218; holds that all Zeno, 40.
pleasure is contrary to nature, Criticism of popular faith by
237 determines the relations
; Stoics, 344.
of the virtues, 262 ; HeriUus a Cronos, 367.
fellow-student of, 281 teaches ; Cyclopes, 369.
indefectible virtue, 295 ; agrees Cynic, appeal to nature, 91 Kpi- ;

with Aristo, 298 ; moral cha- curean view of life, 488 j life,
racter of, 309 ; submission to 306 ; Zeno at one time, 322 ;
destiny, 333 ; death of, 336 ;
strength of will, 389 ; contempt
view of Stoicism, 342 ; seeks for theory, 390, 510; view of
for moral ideas, 355 explana- ; wise man, 488 ideas, 40 teach-
; ;

tion of myths, 361 ; distinguishes ing, 515 a precursor of Scepti-


;

two kinds of fire, 397 ; a coun- cism, 515 ; nominalism, 84 ;


teipart of Xenocrates, 400 ; al- School, precursor of Stoicism,
legorical interpretation of my- 17 onesidedness of, 306 philo-
;
;

thology, 361, 362, 364, 368 sophy, 28; followed by Aristo,


preparation for later teaching, 281, 297; virtue, 282; ethics,
370 ; teaching of, 44, 45, 46, 54, 386.
62 ; logical treatises of, 63 Cynicism, 43, 91, 92, 238 of the ;

view of the common source of Stoics, 305 instances of, 307


; ;

virtue,257 moral view of life,


; a, consequence of Stoic princi-

272 the successors of, 273


; ples, 308, 385, 387, 389, 390;
specially honours the sun, 146, attraction of, for Zeno, 401
165, 362 views on the soul,
; Cynics, 223, 239, 273, 277, 288,
217 view of divination, 370.
; 308 meagre teaching of, 37,
;

Cleomenes, Spartan reformer, 44. 255 appeal to nature, 92 con-


; ;

CUtomachus, 557, 558, 560, 563. nections of Stoics with, 291,


Colotes, an Epicurean, 409. 317, 323, 389, 390 followed by ;

Composite judgment of Stoics, Aristo, 297 precursors of Stoics,


;

113 inference, 119.


;
327.
Conceptions formed from percep- Cyprus, Citium in, 36.
tions, 79 truth of, 135 relation
; ;
Cyrenaio, 48; School, 44,511; a
to perceptions, 83 primary, a ;
precursor of Epicurean, 17, 511
standard of truth, 90 highest, of ; view of pleasure as the object
Stoics, 98 Socratio theory of, 9.
;
of life, 475, 510.
Condensation, a cause of being, Cyrenaios, theory of pleasure fol-
140. lowed by Epicurus, 509; con-
Connection, inner, of Stoic system, tent with feelings, 510 ; view
381. of language, 624.
;; ;;

5?2 INDEX.
DEI BNC
DEITY, the Stoic conception of, Dionysus, Stoic view of, 359, 364.
148; as original matter, 155. Divination, Stoic view of, 370
Demeter, Stoic view of, 358, 364. attacked by Sceptics, 550 a ;

Demetrius, an Epicurean, and proof of Providence, 175 causes ;

pupil of Protarohus, 411. of, 377.


Democritus, 518, 531 view of the ;
Divine Being, 216, 217, 341, 348.
world, 203 linown to Epicurus,
; Dogmatic, Schools of post-Aristo-
405, 433, 438 his pupil Anax- ; telian philosophy, 25 Scepti- ;

archus, 518 on being and not; cism, 26.


being, 440 view of atoms, 433,
; Dogmatists, struggle with Scep-
445, 447, 441, 443, 444 system ; tics, 524.
of, 405, 502 doctrine of atom- ; A(iia,the Epicurean, 430.
pictures, 457, 465 physics bor- ;
Duties, perfect and intermediate,
rowed by Epicureans, 510 sug- ; 287.
gests doubt to Pyrrho, 515 Dynamical theory of nature, held
sceptical argument of, 531 rela- ; by the Stoics, 126, 139.
tions of Epicureans to, 502, 510.
Demons, Stoic views on, 351.
Depravity of nature, 271. "PAST, the, 17, 28; nations of.
Desirable things, 278.
Desire, 249 a standard, 76.
; Eclecticism, 28 practical, 29
; ;

Destiny, God as, 150 nature of, ; involves doubt, 30.


170, as Providence, 170 as gene- ; Eclectics, 22 ; later, 399.
rative reason, 172 as fate, 170. ; Efficient cause with Stoics, 143
Dialectic, a branch of Stoic logic, nature of, 143.
70. 'HyeimviK6y, 158, 214, 216, 244,
^iavoitiiTM6v, 214. 455.
Dicaearchus, 133. 'Hyoiiifvav, 113,
Diocletian, 32. Egypt, Greek emigrants to, 14.
Diodorus, the logician, teacher of Egyptian customs, 28.
Zeno, 38 a Megarian, 115
; ElSos of Aristotle, 104.
captious, 38 School of, 385. ; El;Sa>\o, 457.
Diogenes, Laertius, 63, 261, 337. I.tiiapfi4vn of Stoics, 170.
Diogenes of Seleucia, a Stoic and Elean criticism, 518.
pupil of Chrysippus, 49 suc- ; Elements, the four, 197.
ceeded by Antipater, 50 defini- ; Elis, birthplace of Pyrrho, 517,
tion of virtue, 261 an example ; 528.
of wisdom, 274, 306 on for- ; Emotions, 290 ; varieties of, 249 ;
bidden gains, 285 division of ; and virtue, 243 nature of, 243.
;

ethics, 298 on suicide, 337


;
;
Empedocles, his view of Ares,
views on divination, 371. 366 ; on the origin of animals,
Diogenes the Cynic, 294, 306; 451 ; sceptical arguments of,
shamelessness of, 308. 581.
Diomedes, 366. Empire, attempt to revive the, 31;
Dionysius, a Stoic, and pupil of a loose congeries of nations, 32.
Zeno, 43 ;
joined Epicureans, Empty, the, 196, 439.
44 president of the Epicurean
;
'Ei'<4p7eio, 428.
School, 410. Encyclical knowledge, 60,
;;; ;;
;;;

INDEX. 673
EPI
Bnd-in-chief, of Stoics, 187. regard individual side in man,
'ZvidKTtKbv ffTiiielov, 115. 25 distinguished from Stoics,
;

'EvSLdeeros K6yos, 72, n. 2. 183, 372; points of agreement


'Ekkoiw Koica! of Stoics, 81. with, 507, 508, 515, 516 charged ;

Epaminondas, 11. with impropriety by opponents,


Ephesus, birthplace of Heraclitus, 407 view of divination, 372
;

393. aim of philosophy, 420 divide ;

Epictetus, 299 ; a, freedman, 325 philosophy into three parts, 424


native of Phrygia, 36 ; a Stoic, indiflferent to explaining pheno-
53, 92 ; of later times, 316 ; dis- mena, 434 refer them to natural
;

suades from matrimony, 324 ;


causes, 437 consider the earth
;

religions language of, 328 ; view the centre of the universe, 450
of demons, 351. on the relations of body and
Epicurean, 415, 419, 431, 437, 463, soul, 454, 479, 505 negative at- ;

489 ;view of Stoicism, 311 titude of, towards popular faith,


philosophy, 499 divisions of, ; 471 averse to public affairs,
;

424 antecedents of, 16 system,


1 ; 491 build a rational system on
;

character of, 418, 425, 432, 472, a base of the senses, 500 hold ;

474, 480, 481, 504, 516 outUved ; theory of atoms, 505 irreligious ;

others, 417 developed, 500


; ;
freethinkers, 505 practical phi- ;

historical relations of, 503 self- ; losophy of, 41 6 onesidedness ;

contentment, 17 imperturbabi- ; of, 424 explain man's origin


;

lity, 21; School, 29, 44, 415, naturally, 451 materialism of, ;

420 tone of, 498 appreciates


; ; 456 sincerity of, 465 view of
; ;

friendship, 502 doctrines, 411 ;


the Gods, 468 on bodily plea- ;

theory, 517 inner connection


;
sures, 478, 506 moral science ;

of, 499 ethics, 439, 456 friend-


; ; of, 485; friends of monarchy,
ship, 493, 495, 506 Gods, nature ; 492 view of friendship, 494.
;

of, 467 canonic, 415 views on


; ; Epicurus, school of, subordinate
nature, 434, 457 view of virtue, ; theory to practice, 19 view of ;

481, 482 moral science, 485


; ;
the world as unlimited, 203,
theory of pleasure, 505, 481. 409 ; of empty space, 445, 44
Epicureanism, 26, 400, 403 scien- ;
life of, 404 writings unread in
;

tific Value of, 418 intellectual ; Cicero's time, 419; despised


value, 420 grows out of Cyre-
;
learning, 421, 501 ; theory of
naic teaching,, 17 power of ;
knowledge, 423; on certainty
self-preservation, 418 estab- ; of the senses, 427 on st andard ;

lished in Rome, 411 historical ;


of truth, 431 a voluminous ;

position of, 503 relation to ; writer, 47 views on colour,


;

Stoicism, 400, 403, 503, 508, 514, 433 ;undervalues logic, 434,
515 ; relation to Aristippus, 425 undervalues natural science,
;

608; relation to Democritus, 436, 438, 511; and mind, 440,


610; to Aristotle and Plato, 513 relations to Democritus,
;

511 ; to older philosophy, 508; 439, 444, 502, 510 does not in- ;

aims at a practical science of vestigate psychologically, 459


life, 509 ; vindicated, 500, 513 does not give up belief in Gods,
Epicureans, 412, 414, 420, 458; 465, 466 position of, contrasted
;

of the Koman period, 411 with the Stoica, 481, 456, 484,
;; ;
;

574 INDEX.
EPO
504, 512 view on friendship,
; Family, Stoic view of, 320; Epi-
495, 496 system of, bears a de-
; curean view of, 490.
finite stamp, 503 dogmatism ; Fate or destiny, 170 fates, 365.;

of, 418 explains phenomena,


; Fear, 249.
435 and the origin of things,
; Fire, God as, 148, 154.
444 view of history, 453 of
; ; Fluvius explained by the Stoics,
the soul, 454 moral science of, ; 361.
472, 485 on the wise man, 483,
; Folly, 268.
506 connection with others,
; Force and matter, 139 ; nature of,
490; deprecated family life, 141.
492 his apotheosis of nature,
; Foreknowledge, an argument for
453 view of pleasure as the
; Providence, 175.
highest good, 235, 420, 473, 474, Form, Stoic category of, 102, 104;
475, 477, 478, 480, 488, 606, antithesis of, and matter, 6,
609; difficulties of, 499; view 173.
of philosophy, 500; objection Formal logic of Stoics, 92.
to predecessors, 508; personal' Freedom, Stoic views of, 219 ; of
vanity of, 509 labours of, 407 ; will defended by Carneades, 551.
writings of, 419 ; death of, 409 Friendship, Stoic view of, 317
garden of, 410 ; School of, 21, Epicurean view of, 493.
406, 501 ; scholars of, 408.
'ETToxh of Sceptics, 526.
Eratosthenes, a Cyrenaic, 48 GALENUS, 246.
gained for Stoicism, 49. Galilfeo, Aristarchus of Sa-
Esohewable things, 278. mos, the, of antiquity, 348.
Esprit de corps, of Greeks, 15. Generative reason, 172.
'ETepofuins, 78. Germanic character, 9.
Ethics, 67; Stoic views on, 213, G^d, conception of, 84, 343, 344,
382 ; Epicurean views on, 423. 347, 349; Stoic view of, 147;
Ether, God as the, 148, 154, 201. as original matter, 156 identi- ;

Eu/3ou\fa, 648. cal with the world, 156; Epi-


EuSai/uorfa, 352. curean view of, 465, 466 criti- ;

Euemerus, rationalism of, 350. cism of, 462 nature of, 466
;

Eiirrifleio,291. as Providence, 463; Sceptic


EiTux^r, 270. view of, 548.
Evil, existence of physical, 188 ;
Good, Stoic conception of, 84, 128;
of moral, 189 ; compared with Stoic view of highest, 225 and ;

good, 230. evil, 230 and pleasure, 235 as


; ;

'Efis, 208. law, 240 secondary, 250 Epi-


; ;

Expansion, cause of, 140. curean view of highest, 472


Expression of Stoics, 132 [see discussed by Carneades, 657,
Utterance] ; incomplete, 94 558, 561.
perfect, 94 ; 110. Graces, Chrysippus' view of, 365.
Grammar of words, 94.
Greece, state of, 13, 407; help-
FAITH, popular, and Stoicism, lessness of, 16; a Roman pro-
343. vince, 27; loss of nationality,
Fallacies, Stoic refutation of, 122. 34 intellect of, 10, 27, 29, 513
;
;;
;

INDEX. 675
GBE IND
Stoics in, 36 ; change in views Heraelitus, a Stoic philosopher,
of, 8 ; mental tone of, 9 ; bril- 53 ; explains the Odyssey, 369.
liant career of, 9 ;
political de- Herbart, 262.
gradation of, philosophic 10; Hercules, 292 ; Stoic view of, 359,
spirit of, 23 ; influence of Eome 367.
on, 27 ; common opinions of, Here, legend of, explained, 358,
286. 361, 368.
Greek, 327, 370, 402 ; culture, 34, Herillus the Stoic, 41 ; of Carthage,
842, 344 ; mind, 2 propriety of ; 42, 256 approximates to Peri-
;

conduct, 8 all brances of, family,


; patetic School, 43; declared
10 ; religion, 34 ; mythology, knowledge to be the chief good,
357, 370; philosophy, 568, 9, 58 and the end of life, 256 ;
;

the offspring of freedom, 15 fellow-student of Cleanthes,


lent itself to Eclecticism, 28, 281.
setting of, 34. Hermarchus, an Epicurean, suc-
Greeks, 15, 127 national exclu- ; ceeded Epicurus as president,
siTeness of, 8 and foreigners, ; 409.
14 the Bible of, 356.
; Hermes, Stoic view of, 359, 361,
863.
HADES, Stoic interpretation of, Hesiod, appealed to by the Stoics,
358, 368, 369. 356.
Happiness, connected with virtue, Hestia, Stoic view of, 358.
191 negative character of, 239
; Hippoclides, an Epicurean, 410.
intellectual, according to Epi- Homer, appealed to by the Stoics,
cureans, 476. 356 interpretation of, 357.
;

Hecato, 285. Homeric, Theomachy, 361 story ;

Helios, claim of, to be a God, 550. of Apollo's reconciliation, 363.


Hellas, seat of learning, 14 ; reli- Hypothetical judgment. 111, 113 ;

gion of, 8 the playball of


; inference, 119 sentences, five
;

changing rulers, 12 denuded ; original forms of, 119.


of her population, 14.
Hellenism, age of, 35.
Hephsestus, Stoic view of, 358, IADETOS, 367.
359, 361, 366. Mount, 360.
Ida,
Heraclea, birthplace of Dionysius Idealism of Plato, 130 ; and Aris-
the Stoic, 43. totle, 2, 9.
Heraelitus, of Ephesus, 393, 531 Ideas, 75.
relation of Stoics to, 133, 161, 'ISi'tos iroidv, 104.
197, 358, 392, 393, 402, 439, 602, Immortality, Stoic view of, 219.
510; views on cosmogony, 197, Imperfect expression of Stoics, 94.
204, 393, 394 ; not the cause of Imperialism, Byzantine, 33.
Stoic materialism, 1 34 scep- ; Imperturbability, mental, of Scep-
tical arguments of, 531 pan- ;
tics, 18, 525

theism of, 51 7 flux of things, ;


Impressions the basis of percep-
394 physics of, borrowed by
;
tions, 77.
Stoics, 510 view of Zeno, 358
; ;
Incorporeal, the, 132.
of Proteus, 360 ; of Apollo, 363 ;
Indefinite, the, the highest con-
of Cerberus, 364. j ception, 98, 99.
;; ;;;

576 INDEX.
IND MAT
India, 518. LACONIAN, 411.
Indicative sign of Stoics, 115. Lacydes, a philosopher of
Indifferent things, 281. Middle Academy, 46.
Individual, the, Epicurean views AdSe 0iiiiraf, Epicurean watchword,
of, 485 ; relation of, to Provi- 491.
dence, 177 ; importance of, 301. Latin, 411.
Inference, Stoic, 116 hypothetical,; Law, Universal, God as, 150, 170
117 ; composite forms of, 117 Highest Good as, 241.
,from a single premiss, 121. Leading clause, 113.
Jnnate ideas, 80. Leibnitz on the marvellous, 374.
Intelligence, 359 ; Epicurean, 476. AfKT6i>, the Stoic, 92, 132, 135.
Intermediate duties, 287. A^yoi', 113.
Intermingling, universal, Stoic Leto, Stoic view of, 361.
theory of, 136. Logic of Stoics, 70; formal, 75,
Irrational parts of nature, 204. 92, 119, 123 estimate of, 123
;

Irresistible perceptions, standard an outpost of their system, 124.


of truth with Stoics, 87 ; this Ao7i(rju(fs, 214.
theory attacked by Sceptics, AoyKrTm6v, 214.
530. Adyos ivdid0eTOSfX3;ffTrepfjLartK6Sfl72,
Italian allies of Greece, 13. 360, 397; <(>uffi(col \6yoi of the
Stoics, 365.
JEWISH notion of demons, 354. Lotoides, birth of, explained, 362.
Jews, ethics of, 240 ; follow Lotophagi explained, 369.
Zeno, 357. Lucretius, an Epicurean, 415
Judgment, Stoic, 110; simple, view of atoms, 447 ; view on the
111 ; composite, 113 ; modality origin of animals, 451 ; view of
of, 116; Sceptic, withholding religion, 462 ; view of the Gods,
of, 523. 467.
Jupiter, 202.
Justice, 315.
MACEDONIAN supremacy, 12,
KATAAHT12, 90, 531. 13, 332; conqueror, 327;
KaTO\i)n'TiK(iy, 91. empire, 401.
KoT<ip9Mfio, 265, 287. Macedonians, 13.
Knowledge, Stoic theory of, 75 Man,' Stoic views on, 210, 332;
general character of, 75 parti- ; and the course of the world, 332
cular points in, 77 artificially ; Epicurean views on, 451 origin ;

formed, 82 a standard, 77 im-


; ; of, 457.
possible with Sceptics, 521 de- ; Marcus Aurelius, a Stoic, 53, 184,
nied by Aicesilaus, 528 denied ; 299 the last of the Stoics, 314
;

by Carneades, 638, 541 Epi- ; a later Stoic, 816.


curean theory of, 426. Mars, 202.
KoiKol hvouu of Stoics, 81, 90. Material, 100, 172 reality belong-
;

Koivus iroidi/f 104. ing to, 126 causes of action,


;

KoToj, 367. 130 wide extension of, 131.


;

Kpo<rij, 106, n. 2 ; 5i' i\av, 137 Materialism, Stoic, 126, 210, 384,
defined, 137, u. 1. 385, 426 nature of, 126 ; causes
;

See also C. of, 132 ; consequences of, 135


;
;;;

INDEX. 57,7

MAT PAT
not an expansion of Peripatetic \TATUEAL SCIENCE, 67; of
views, 133. IN stoics, 125.
tfaterialisticnature of the soul, Nature, Stoic study of, 125 God ;

210. as, 150 Epicurean views of,


;

Matter, antithesis of, and form, 6, 434 object of study, 434 me-
; ;

101, 155 ; and force, 139 iden- ; chanical explanation of, 437 ;

tical with, God, 155; resolved general ideas on, 194 the same ;

into primary being, 164. asprimary being, ] 71 ; irra-


Mechanical combination, 106, n. 2. tional parts of, 204 ; submission
Megarian criticism, 518. to the course of, 332.
Megarians, fallacies fostered by, Necessity, a proof of Providence,
122 ; teaching of, 255 sophisms ; 174 ; meaning
of, 188 dif- ;

of, 533 logical accuracy of,


; theory of, 117.
ficulties of
38 subtleties of, 62, 533 rela-
; ; Negative character of happiness,
tion of Stoics to, 392 criticism, ; 239.
515. Neooles, father of Epicurus, 404
Mercury, 202. Neoplatonic School, 135 ; doctrine
Mercy, 315. of revelation, 380.
Meteoiology, Stoic, 206. Neoplalonism produced by a real
Metrodorus, an Epicurean, and interest in knowledge, 23 on ;

pupil of Epicurus, 408 writings ; the same platform as other post-


unread in Cicero's time, 419 Aristotelian philosophy, 24 ; of
favourite pupil of Epicurus, 478 ;
Alexandria, 28 ; transition to,
asserts that everything good 31 united previous elements,
;

has reference to the belly, 479 32 theintellectual reproduction


;

on the wise man, 483. of Byzantine Imperialism, 33.


Might, 332. Neopythagorean doctrine of reve-
Mind, God as, 148, 154. lation, 380.
Mijis, 106, n. 2 Stoic theory of,
; Neopythagoreans, 22, 23.
136 definition of, 137, n. 1.
;
Nominalism, Cynic, 84.
Mnaseas, the father of Zeno the Non-material, the, of the Stoics,
Stoic, 36. 132.
Modality, Stoic, of judgments, Notions, Epicurean, 428.
115.
Moon, 202.
Moral, responsibility, indicated,
ODYSSEY, explained by Stoic?,
369.
179 theory of the world, 186 ;
;
Olympians pull down Zeno, 359.
evil, 188 science applied, 297 ;
;
Opinion, Epicurean, 429.
connection of, and scientific ele-
Oriental modes of thought, 14,
ments in Stoicism, 385 ; view
28, 36; emperors of Rome, 31;
of Stoics attacked, 551 of ;
despotism, 33 mysticism, 33.
:

Sceptics, 556.
Original or primary being, 158.
Muses, 365.
"Opflbs K6yos, 76.
Musonius, a later Stoic, 92, 316. 242.
'Offiii,
Myths, interpretation of, 354
Stoic interpretation of, 356,
359, 362, 367. PAIN, freedom from, 474.
Pan, 366.

P P
;; ;
;;

ers INDEX.
PAN PLA
Pansetius, a later Stoic and scholar (pavTafflai, 77 ; KaToAnirTUCof, 89,
of Antipater, 51 ; not a severe 531, 541.
Stoic, 286; teacher of Posi- Phaedrus, an Epicurean, 413, 414,
donius, 298 treatise of, 302 ; ;
417.
followed by Cicero, 315 j trea- Philo, a pupil of Diodorus, 38.
tise on divination, 371 ; denies Philodemus, an Epicurean, 413,
omens, 374. 468 view of the Gods, 468.
;

Pantheism of Stoics, 126, 166, Philosophy, Stoic divisions of, 66


517 dissented from by BQethus,
;
Epicurean divisions of, 424.
159. Phlius, birthplace of Timon, 519.
napadeats, 106, n. 2 ; defined, 137, Phrygian, Epictetus, 36.
n. 1. iiffts, 228, 350, 209.
Parmenides, sceptical arguments UiBaiffi, 555.
of, 531. TIi9av6rTjs, 555.
Patro, an Epicurean, 414. Planets, Stoic view of, 208
Peloponnesian war, 10. Epicurean view of, 451.
Peloponnesus, 13. Plato, 55, 126, 305, 323, 509, 611,
Penelope, suitors of, 60. 513, 531 perfection of Greek
;

Verceptions derived by Stoics from philosophy in, 1 the study of, ;

impressions, 77; the basis of 126 example, 1 87 many-sided-


; ;

conceptions, 79, 83 a standard, ; ness of, 402 merits and defects


;

76 irresistible, the standard of


; of, 1 idealism of, 2, 9, 130 flaws
; ;

truth, 87 sole source of truth,


;
in teaching of, 3 dialectical ;

135 Epicurean view of, 425.


; exclusiveness of, 4 antagonistic ;

Perfect duties, 287. currents in, 45; general con-


Pericles, age of, 9. ceptions of, 18; denies virtue in
Peripatetic School, 29, 301 ap- ; great men, 274 view of demons, ;

proached by Herillus the Stoic, 351 theory of final causes,


;

43 on the human soul, 397


; 396 system of, connected with
;

materialism, 133 view of emo- ; Greek character, 7 ; doctrine of


tions, 253 goes back to earlier
;
the four elements, 197 view of ;

View, 301 philosophy, 133 ;


the stars, 205; of the seat of
debt of Stoics to, 402 notion, ; life, 214 view of the soul, 215
;
;

244 doctrine, 397 views, 398,


; ; on the regulation of emotions,
281 view of goods, 559.
; 262 permits a lie, 305 pre-
; ;

Peripatetics, opposed to the Stoics, judice against foreigners, 326


62, 66 the Sorites of the, 120
; ;
view of pleasure, 474 places ;

logic of, 124 ground occupied ;


knowledge above action, 256
by, 133 view of emotions, 253
; ;
advocates community of wives,
teaching of, 49, 398, 564 theory ; 310 distinguishes supreme and
;

of goods, 559 attacked by ; . popular gods, 348 known to ;

Stoics, 233 not the cause of ; Epicnrus, 405 sceptical argu- ;

Zeno's materialism, 134. ments ot, 531 pure speculation ;

Persseus, a Stoic and pupil of of, 57; metaphysical notions


Zeno, 43 fellow pupil of Aristo,
; of, 133 example of, 187, 268
; ;

298. time of, 178 teaching of, 252, ;

Persian war, 9 Greek dependence ; 399, 406; formal and final


on empire, 12. causes of, 141 relation of ;
;; ;

INDEX. 679
PLA PBO
Stoics to, 399 relation of Epi-
; 392, 484, 542, 566 ; causes pro-
cureans to, 511 ; Tiew of the ducing, 17, 35 character of, ] 9 ;
;

stars, 205 view of the soul,


; subordinates theory to practice,
213 School of, 528.
; 19 peculiar mode of dealing
;

Platonic, 55, 133, 221, 304, 516 with practical questions, 21 its ;

theory of conceptions, 5 sys- ; development, 25 unlike that of


;

tem, 31 ; speculations, 516 Socrates, 18 ; times, 392, 561


School at Alexandria, 328. systems, 402, 512 ; Scepticism,
Platonism, 3i2, 399, 531 Seneca's ; 514, 561; common characteristics
resemblance to, 222 a religious ; of, subordinates science to
19 ;

system, 342. ethics, 542 ; refers man back to


Platonists, 22, 30, 61 apologetical ; himself, 19 ; includes Stoicism
writings of, 25 School of, con-; andNeoplatonism, 24 variously ;

verted to Scepticism, 29 op- ; modified, 24 ; personal cha- '

posed to Stoics, 62. racter of, 33 ; reverses relations,


Pleasure^ 249 and the good, 235
;
;
301 ; practical tendency of, 392 ;

Epicureans, 472 freedom from ; aims at independence of man,


pain, 474. 484 common characteristics of,
;

Plotinus, 23. 511 materialism, 512.


;

Plutarch, 53, 261 ; treats virtues Predestination of the Stoics, 376.


as many, 261 ; treatise against Preferential things, 278, 289.
Colotes, 409. Pre-Socratic philosophy, influence
nvei/iaTa, the Stoic, 129, 148. of, on Stoicism, 133.
noirfv, 100, 104. npeVox, 303.
noioTTjs, 367. Primary conceptions a standard
Polemo, a teacher of Stoic Zeno, of truth, 90 ; being, 161, 170
32, 399 ; School of, 385. fire, 172, 198.
Political life, 318 ; Stoic aversion Probability, Arcesilaus' theory of,
to, 324. 534 ; Carneades' theory of, 553.
Polygenus, an Epicurean, pupil of Upimyiiivov, 283, 289, 290, 560.
Epicurus, 408. Progress, state of, 293.
Polybius, as an authority, 565. TlpoKo-ni], 294.

Polystratus, third president of the XlfioX^eis, Stoic, 80, 90; Epi-


Epicurean School, 410. curean, 428, 461.
Polytheism, truth in, 348; at- Property, Stoic category of, 102.
tacked by Sceptics, 549. Prophecy, Stoic explanation of,
Pontus, birthplace of Dionysius 374, 403.
the Stoic, 43. Prophetic powers. Stoic view of,
nSs ^xo", 100, 107. 369.
Poseidon, Stoic interpretation of, TlpoipopMhs \(!70s, 73.
358 claim of, to be a god dis-
;
Proposition, 110k
cussed, 550. np<is Ti vas ^X""; 100> 107.
Posidonius, the Stoic, 206, 208, Proserpine, rape of, 365.
293, 298; popular notion of Protagoras, language on truth,
demons, 357 views on divina-
;
431.
tion, 371, 373. Protarchus, of Bargyllium, an
Possible, 178. Epicurean, 411.
Post-Aristotelian philosophy, 301, Proteus, story of, explained, 360.

p p 2
;;; ;;;

580 INDEX.
PRO SCH
Providence, 156, 171, 359, 403 Rhodes, a centre of philosophy,
God as, 150 in the Stoic system.
; 35.
341 Zeus as, 359 Stoic argU'
; ; Roman, period, 17, 326; world,
ments in favour of, 173, 372 31 province, 27 ; jurisprudence,
;

argument from general con- 240 ; character, 32 ; dominion,


viction, 174 from God's per-
; 332 ; Empire, 401.
fection, 174 from necessity,
; Romans, 521 ; uphold traditional
174 from God'sforeknowledge,
; faith, 344.
175 from divination, 175 the
; ; Rome, 325, 413, 414, 415, 492,
idea of, 175 as necessity, 175
; 551 relations between Greece
;

relation to individuals, 176 and, 27 a centre of philosophy,


;

difficulties of, 177; rule of. 35 statesmanship in, 326


;

331 ;Stoic theory of, 388, Stoicism in, 492 influence of, ;

396, 403 Epicurean denial of,


; on philosophy, 27 arms of, 13 ; ;

435, 462, 463 denied by Car- ; decline of, 31 Gods of, 32 ;

neades, 544 criticism of, 542.


;
Epicureans in, 411, 413.
Ptolemy Soter, 28.
Ptolemsean dynasty, 28.
Pyrrho, the Sceptic, 517, 562 SAMIAN picture, 360.
teaching of, 518, 519, 520-525 ;
Samos, 348 ; birthplace of
agrees -with Arcesilaus, 533 Epicurus, 404.
and his followers, 517 receives ; Saturn, 202.
from Democritus an impulse to Sceptic, 525, 536, 562; imper-
doubt, 515 example of, 528
;
;
turbability, 17 ; suspension of
teaching of, 521 School of, ; judgment, 525 Schools deny ;

534, 526. every dogmatic position, 514.


Pytliagoras, 55. Sceptical theory, 516 Schools, ;

Pythagorean, 55, 399 School at ; 27. .

Alexandria, 28 system, 31 ; Scepticism, 26, 29, 514, 515, 528,


friendship, 496 influence on ; 651 ; influences producing, 27 ;
the older Academy, 399. involves eclecticism, 30 ; intel-
Pytho, defeat of, explained, 362. lectual objections to, 86 pure, ;

523 ; object of, 526 dogmatic, ;

26 ; historical position of,

EEASON, 133, 359, 368; ex- 514 relations to dogmatism,


;

<
ternal to man, 6 ; a standard, 514 ; of New Academy, 529,
76. 537, 563 School of, 517 ; posi-
;

Reason, right, 76 generative, ;


tive side of, 538 ; starts from
172; of the world, 170; iden- earlier philosophy, 515 causes ;

tical with God, 147. of, 515 ; relations to Epicu-


Reasoners, School of, 66. reanism and Stoicism, 515, 516.
Relation, category of, 108. Sceptics, 512, 517, 549 ; School of
Religion of Stoics, 341 of Epi- ; the, 19 opposed by Stoics, 21
;

cureans, 462 of Sceptics, 556.


; New School of, 22 ; happiness,
Republic, last days of, 32. the starting-point with, 521
Rhea, Stoic view of, 358. ethics of, 556 ; later, 562 ; more
Rhetoric, a branch of Stoic logic, ancient, 538, 553.
70. Schleiermaoher, 219.
;;;; ;;

INDEX. 581
SCI STO
Sciro, an Epicurean, 413. mitted a 305 sceptical
lie, ;

Soylla, Stoic explanation of, 369. arguments 531 on the deri-


of, ;

Secondary goods, 280. vation of the soul, 645; rela-


Seleucia, birthplace of Diogenes, tions of Stoics 'to, 387, 391, 396.
49. Socratic, old, teaching, 401 dic- ;

Seneca, 219, 239, 285, 299, 306, tum, 245, 247; introspection,
316, 319, 325, 326, 335, 337, 339, 511 ; views, 388 ; theory of con-
351 a Stoic, 53 ; in harmony
; ceptions, 9 teaching, 255
;

with the Stoics, 154 opinion ; philosophy, 392 ; School, 509.


on wickedness, 273 defends ; Soli, birthplace of Chrysippns,
external possessions, 285 views ; 45 of Aratus, 43.
;

on customs, 306 age of, 274 ; Something, the highest conception,


a later Stoic, 316 his views on; 98.
friendship, 318, 319; on the Sophists, practical philosophy of,
wise man's independence, 335 18 ; fallacies fostered by, 122.
on suicide, 337, 339 denies the ; Sorites, the, of the Peripatetics
use of prayer, 344 view of ; developed by the Stoics, 120.
demons, 351. Soul, of the parts, 213 nature of, ;

Sensation, Epicurean view of, 425, 210; the individual, 216; God
457. as, 148 Stoic views of, 210
;

Senses, Epicurean superiority to, Epiouream views of, 453 ; mate-


478. rialistic view of, 210.
Septimus Severos, Emperors after, Space, 196.
32. Sparta, rivalry of, with Athens,
Sextus Empiricus, a Stoic autho- 11, 13.
rity, 53. Spartan reformer, Cleomenes, 44.
Sidon, birthplace of Zeno the Spartans, 14.
Epicurean, 412. See \6yoi.
"Zirep^aTiKoi \6yoi.
Simple judgment, 110, 111. Sphferus, a Stoic and pupil of
Sirens explained, 369. Zeno, 44 from the Bosporus,
;

Social relations, Stoic view of, 44 logical researches of, 64


;
;

311. treatise on divination, 371.


Society, origin and use of, 311 Spinoza, 219.
Epicurean views on, 490. Standard of truth. See Knowledge.
Socrates, 274, 292, 305, 306, 501, Stoic, 86 need of, 86
; irre- ;

509, 511 definition of the good,


; sistible impressions, 87 pri- ;

229 ; of virtue, 59, 255 ; scep- mary conceptions, 90 Epi- ;

tical' arguments 531 view


of, ; curean, 431. See Canonic.
of natural science, 60 line of ; Stars, Stoic view of, 204.
thought presupposed by Epi- Stilpo, combined Cynic and Me-
cureanism, 511 philosophic
;
garian teaching, 37 School of, ;

ideas of, 2 practical philo-


;
385 connected with Zeno, 392.
;

sophy of, 17 differs from past


; 38, 327.
trait. voiKiK'ti,

Aristotelian philosophy, 18 Stobseus has preserved extracts


view of means and ends, 185 from writings of Teles, 48 ; and
time of, 225 defines the good
; definitions of virtues, 261.
as the useful, 229 an example ; Stoic, 49, 132, 251, 313, 324, 346,
of wisdom, 274, 292, 306 per- ; 374, 517, 531 ; apathy, 121 ; doc*
; ;

682 INDEX.
STO STO
trine fully expanded by Chry- 65 principles, logical result of,
;

sippus, 47, 48 appeal to the ; 311 principles, 153, 219, 225,


;

senses, 530 , assertion, 185 ; ;


256, 293; propositions, 310, 551
bias, 304 citizenship of the
; views on nature 194 ScJuiol. ; ;

world, 327 ; notions of Provi- 29, 62, 64, 69, 168, 274, 286, 297
dence, 177, 388 conception, ; 299, 300, 307, 336, 351, 388
397 theory of the good, 290,
;
founded by Zeno, 36 Chry- ;

559 wise man, 335 ; enquiries,


;
sippus presidentof, 45 a School ;

170 Ethies, 249, 278, 383 two


; ;
of reasoners, 66 (pairaa-la, 541 ;

currents of thought in, 382 severity, 286 skill, 363 specu


; ;

main features of, 383 ; explana- lation, 173 System, inner con
;

tion of myths, 367, 368 ; fata- nection of, 381 teaching, 55, ;

lism, 175, 551 influence of, ; 59, 67, 69, 4, 133, 221, 257, 316,
529 insensibility to pain, 477
; ;
456 ; theology, 545 ; treatment
KwraMi/is, 531 ; virtue, 398, 334, of science, 542.
58, apathy, 316^ pan-
505 ; Stoicism, 26, 69, 326, 339, 357,
theism, 176 morality, 229, 333, ; 380 ;
growing out of Cynicism,
390, 342 necessity, 176 ; philo-
; 17, 91, 392, 402 relation of, to;

sophers, 298, 322 ; citizenship previous system, 387 related to ;

of the world, 328, 506 material- ; Cynics, 387 ; to Socrates, 387 ;

ism, 384, 385 system, 91, 394 ; to Aristotle, 396 to Megarians, ;

68, 91, 125, 138, 152, 173, 223, 392; to Heraolitus, 392; to
249, 277, 301, 351, 354, 381, 394, Plato, 399 later, founded by
;

504, 516,543; PMlosojihy, 33i Chrysippus, 45 historical in-


;

authorities for, 53 divisions of, ; gredients of, 400 form fixed, ;

66 practical character of, 134


;
48 Eratosthenes won for, 48
; ;

scope of, 381 as a whole, 400 ; as traditionally known, 56


political antecedents of, 16 features of, 239 a religious ;

doctrine expanded, 47 problem ;


system, 342 essentially practi-
;

proposed to, 56 enquiries into ; cal, 380, 385 insists onself-sufii-


;

duties, 302 practical character, ;


cienoy of virtue, 389 preserved ;

56-; necessity for knowledge, original character of Socratic


58 ; position towards logic and philosophy, 391 stern tone of, ;

natural science, 59 relative ; 498 and the theory of pleasure,


;

importance of parts, 68 ; one- 560 entered the Roman world


;

sidedness of, 402 place in his- ;


under Panaetius, 51 declared ;

tory, 400 theory of interming-


; man independent of his fellows,
ling, 137 of irresistible impres-
; 311; makes a dogma of fatalism,
sions, 530; Zogic of, 70, 121; 332 connection with religion,
;

field of, 70 words and thoughts,; 341 with popular faith, 343
; :

73; formality of, 75, 92, 119; ethical side of, 382 scientific ;

estimate of, 123 ; categories, 97 ;


side of, 383 elements combined
;

theory of illation, 121 Know- ; in, 386 relation of Epicurean


;

ledge, theory of, 75, 525 pro- ;


system to, 503, 508, 509, 514,
minent points in, 77 prophecy, ; 517.
379 platform, 335, 353 point
; ;
Stoics [gee Table of Contents'], 276,
of view, 43, 90 polytheism, ;
814, 393, 398, 512 ; of the Roman
549 preference for argument.
; period, 36, 326, 492 School of ;
;;;;; ;; ;

INDEX. 683
STO STO
the, 19 feel the need of philo-
; 261 divide mankind into two
;

sophic speculation, 20 history ; classes, 269 the wise man of,


;

of, 35 sq. take their name from


; 270, 271, 291, 295, 304, 317, 383 ;

Htoa TtoMiKiij 38 highest con- ; influenced by Academy, 399 ;

ception of, 99 look at accuracy ; agrees with Arcesilaus, 532


of expression, 118 seek a stan- ; opponent of Cameades, 542,
dard of truth, 20 demand a ; 564 driven into admissions,
;

knowledge of conceptions, 479 ;


287 ; compelled to recognise
logic of, 96, 97, 123, 223 sorites, ; differences of degree, 293 ; con-
120 did little for natural
; nection with Cynics, 305, 307,
science, 20; opposed to Scep- 308, 327, 388, 402, 510 insist ;

tics, 21 teach original unity of


; on justice and mercy, 315 ;. pay
human family, 21, 490 apolo- ; great attention to domestic life,
getical writings of, 25 regard ; 321 view of suicide, 336, 338 ;
;

universal element, 25 belief ; of lying, 305 ; ethical principles


from idea, 36 develope the ; of, 385 aim at independence,
;

doctrine of the syllogism, 65 488 inexorable sternness of,


;

problem proposed to, 56 view ; 497 subordinate logic


; and
of 59, 128, 272, 300;
virtue, natural science to moral science,
unity of virtue, 266 ; differ 507 adhere to fatalism, 505
;
;

generally from Aristo, 62 ; their appeal to consensus gentium,


views expanded by Chrysippus, 543 theological views of, at-
;

64 ; make three divisions of tacked by Sceptics, 545 view ;

philosophy, 66 development of ; of the soul, 211, 214, 215,


teaching, 69 their view of
; 222 supposed connection with
;

thoughts and words, 74 had no ; Heraclitus, 135, 394 materalism ;

dis inct theory of knowledge of, 139, 210, 385, 425 hold one ;

before Chrysippus, 76 attach ; primary force, 143, 146 view of ;

importance to the senses, 77 Deity, 148, 152, 154 view of ;

make perceptions the source of popular Gods, 358, 362, 366, 368,
notions, 82, 91 XcktIiv of, 92 ; ;
369, 549 identify God and the
;

"consider material objects alone world, 156, 348, 349 theology ;

real, 84, 94 admit the existence


;
of, 341 pantheism of, 159 ;.
;

of immaterial attributes, 106 ;


view of nature, 194, 223, 361,
enumerate sentences, 110; dis- 373 view of the resolution of
;

cuss modality of judgments, the world, 165, 203 view of the ;

115 attached great value to


; seat of generative power, 173
the theory of illation, 116 view of divination, 175, 370,
strive to find firm ground, 123 ;
377, 550; prophecy, 373, 374,
their view of knowledge, 129 375, 378 view of relation of
;

ground occupied by, 134, 135 man to destiny, 182, 301 view ;

deny the freedom of the will, of the unity of the world, 183,
179, 217 distinguished from
; 231 ; of the perfections of the
Epicureans, 183, 470; agree- world, 187; of physical evil,
ment with, 454, 481, 484, 500, 188 ; view of moral evil, 189,
507, 508, 516 ; follow Aristotle, 191 ;inconsistencies of, 193 ;
194; do not explain irregular view of time and space, 197
impulses, 248; classify errors, hold two active elements, 179,
;;

584 INDEX.
STR UTT
201 consider the stars living,
; ivyriniifvov, 113.
206 ; meteorological investiga- [Sympathy of nature, 183.
tions of, 207 ; view of plants Syria, Stoics in, 36.
and animals, 208 ; view of man, Syro, an Epicurean, 413.
225, 490 ; view of good and
evil, 230, 233, 269, 293 view of ;

pleasure, 237 of emotions, 24i, ;


TARSUS, a philosophic centre,
35 ; birthplace of Zeno the
245, 248, 253, 473; theory of
pupil of Chrysippus, 49 birth- ;
necessity, 246 classification of ;
place of Antipater, 60.
errors, highest good, 557
261 ;

Teles, a Stoic., and cotemporary of


collisions with current views,
Chrysippus, 48.
278, 292, 296, 347, 352 on se- ;

Test-science of truth, 426.


condary goods, 280; on things
Thebes, 11.
indifEerent, 281, 338; things
Theophrastus, followed by Chry-
preferential, 283 views of ac- ;
sippus, 119.
tions, 290 casuistry of, 299,
;
Theory, modification of Stoic, 284.
552 moral science of, 302 on
; ;

Thoughts, Stoic view of, 73.


unchastity, 309 view of social ;

Time, 196.
relations, 311 ; relation of indi-
vidual to society, 312 friend-
Timon of Phlius, 519 ; a follower
of Pyrrho, 519 jealous of New
;

ship of the wise, 320 ; on the ;

rights of man, 329 ; citizenship


Academy, 521 ; Scepticism of,
621 places true happiness in
of the world, 326, 506 view of ;
;

aTapa|fa, 526.
demons, 353 ; allegorical inter-
Titans tear Dionysus to pieces,
pretation of 354 ; on predestina-
,

364, 367.
tion, 376 ; encouraged supersti-
Tdiros, 196.
tion, 379 ; neglect scientific
knowledge, 381, 391 Trendelenburg on Aristotle, 104.
philoso- ;
TpiToyevcm, 363.
phical pedigree of, 387 ; expand
Troad, the birthplace of Cleanthes,
Socratic philosophy, 392 ; know-
40.
ledge of conceptions, 479 ; spe-
the, of the Sceptics, 523.
Tp<(7roi,
culatively orthodox, 505 ; mental
Truth, Stoic standard of, 86.
repose of, 615 ; law of causality,
Tiiraxris, 78.
551.
Strato, 133.
Subject-matter, Stoic category of, "rtTAH Siroios, 100, n. 4 140, n. 1.
;

98. Ulysses, 292, 363, 368; a


Substance, Stoic category of, 98 pattern of all virtues, 369.
universal, 156. Universal depravity, 272.
Suggestive symbol, 116. Universe, course of, 163 nature ;

2u7KOT(4eeffis, 88, 532. of, 202 ; Epiotirean arrangement


Siyxyffis, 106, n. 2 ; 137, n. 1. of, 449.
Suicide, Stoic view of, 335, 489. 'riroKel/ieiiov, 100.
Su^3ci3T)KiiTa, of Epicureans, 439. 'tTr6\ri\\iis, Epicurean, 430.
2u/t7rT(^^aTa, of Epicureans, 439. TvonvniTTLKos, 115.
Sufafria, 142, n. 2. Uranos, 367.
SweKTiKol olfjiai, 142, n. 2. Utterance, the Stoic theory of, 73,
'iiyepya alfrio, 142, n. 2. 92 complete, 108.
;
;; ;;;;
:

INDEX. 585
VAR ZEU
VARIETY, Stoic category of, 40, 41 ; time of, 134 ; uncer-
107 of relation, 107.
; tainty as to motives of, 55 in- ;

Venus, 202. fluenced by Peripatetics, 133 ;


Virtue, connection of happiness polity of the wise, 322 ; views
and, 191 emotions and, 243
; on divination, 370; vindicates
Stoic idea of, 254 positive and ;
the supremacy of virtue, 385
negative aspects of, 254; vir- connected with Stilpo, 392
tues severally, 257 mutual re- ; strictures on Aristotle, 511 not ;

lations of, 261 unity of, 266 ;


;
connected with Arcesilaus, 529 ;
Epicurean, 478. estimate of rational things, 545
deification of seasons, 349 ; lead-
ing thought of, 385 debt to
WILL, Epicurean views on, 459. ;

Megarians, 392 debt to Polemo,


Wisdom and folly, 268. ;

Wise man, Epicurean, 399 ;views on causation, 86


Stoic, 268 ;

483.
view of the world, 146 view of;

Ether, 201 of life according to


Words, Stoic view of, 73 ;
gram- ;

nature, 228 distinguishes emo-


mar of, 94.
;

tions, 249; Herillus, his pupil,


World, identical with God, 156 ;
256 view of virtue, 257, 261
origin of, 161 ; end of, 163 ;

offends against propriety, 308


cycles in, 165 ; government of, ;

on unnatural vice, 309 advo-


170 nature of, 182 unity and
; ;
;

cates community of wives, 310


perfection of, 183 moral theory ;

Epi-
contempt for religion, 344, 347
of, 187 ; course of, 331 ;

seeks moral ideas, 355 draws ;


curean view of, 444 origin of, ;
on former systems, 386 distin-
447 ; arrangement of, 448. ;

guishes two kinds of fire, 397


aim of, 400 attracted by Cyni-
;

XEN0CEATES,41 influence on ; cism, 401 regards virtue as


;

Zeno, 399 Cleanthes, his ;


highest good, 401, 505.
counterpart, 400 known to Epi- ;
Zeno, of Sidon, an Epicurean, 412,
curus, 405 time of, 528; a ;
416.
teacher of the Stoic Zeno, 38. Zeno, of Tarsus, a Stoic and scholar
of Chrysippus, 49.
ZENO the Stoic, 36, 54, 58, 62, Zenonians, original name of Stoics,
246, 370, 400 of Cytium, 36 ; ;
38.
founder of Stoicism, 36 son of ; Zeus, 171, 271, 348, 364, 487, 550
Mnaseas, 36 ; only half a Greek, distinguished from nature, 153
327 death of, 336, 337 living
: ; the will of, 171 ; happiness of,
at Athens, 36 a pupil of Grates,
;
enjoyed by the wise man, 271
37 views on logic and natural
; distinguished from other Gods,
science, 62; relation to Hera- 357, 358; legends of, inter-
clitus, 134 ;
materalism of, 134 ;
preted, 358, 359 ; not envied
definition of time, 197 ; places by an Epicurean, 477, 487 cri- ;

force in heaven, 146 pupils of. ;


ticised by Sceptics, 550.

Upottiswoode d; Co., I'rinters, New-street Square, London.


The Authorised English Translation of


DR. E. ZELLER'S WORK ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE GREEKS.

SOCRATES and the SOCRATIO SCHOOLS. Translated


by O.J. Keichel, M.A. B.C.L. sometime Scholar of Queen's College, Oxford. Second
Edition, enlarged from Materials supplied by the Author, Crown 8vo. lO-i. 6d.
' This is a wholly new translation from all the flowing ease of a well-wTitten ori-
the third German edition, and the trans- ginal compositioa. , . , Taiken as a whole,
lator has done his work with such exceed- the book is one of profound value and
ing carefulness, and yet with snch success interest, and while specially so to tbe phi-
in rendering the sometimes crabbed and losophical student, may be commended to
often involved (Jerman into idiomatic all thoughtful readers.'
English, that his workmanship reads with British Quarterly Bevibw.
PLATO and the OLDER ACADEMY. Translated by
SARiH F. Alleyne, and At.pred Goodwin, B.A. Fellow and Lecturer, Balliol
College, Oxford. Crown 8vo. 18*.
* The compliment of translation is well 'The work must become indispensable
deserved by the patient erudition and to the student of Plato. It consists of
mastflfrly arrangement of. the original, sixteen chapters, in which Plato's life, the
which ia an indispensable aid to the readers order of his writings, the character of his
of Plato and Aristotle. Of this trans- Philosophy, his Physics, his Ethics, and his
lation it can be said that in all essential Eeliglon, are treated with great detail and
respects it may be relied on as an equivalent minuteness. It is, of course, impossible in
of Zeller's book.' Academy. these pages to do more with so vast a.
' This is a translation of Dr. Edtjard
work not vast, however, in bulk, being a
Zeller'S Plato und die altei'e Akademie, book of tiOO pagesthan to call attention
a work of great value to students of Plato, to it, and, if possible, to give some idea of
but hitherto only in part accessible to its style.' Educational Times. ,

English readers. The text has been admir- '


In all its departments Dr. Zellbr'S
ably translated by Miss Aj.leyne, who has bode is both comprehensive and trust-
proved herself fully competent to deal worthy. He seems to have said the last
with the philosopbieal terminology of the word on Greek philosophy and his volumes
;

German original, and to execute a transla- are among those monuments of nineteenth
tion which does not, like some translations, century German research which make one
proclaim itself as such by any un-English wonder what will remain for the scholars
structure of its phrases and sentence'5. of the twentieth century to do. He brings
Copioiis notes and references have besn to his task the two essential qualities
added by Mr, Goodwin, FeUow of Balliol vast learning, and the power of moving at
College, who shares with Mirb Alleyne pleasure in the ratified atmosphere of ab-
the responsibility of the work. The value stractions. ... It is evident that Mr.
of Dr. Zeller'S work has been amply Goi >DWIN, to whom this part of the under-
acknowledged by Professor Joweit in the taking fell, had no sinecure in his work of
Preface to the second edition of his Plato ; translation and verification. He has gone
and this translation of it wUl be a great bravely through with it, however, and
boon to many students of Plato who (as both his work and that of Miss Alleyne,
its Authors suggest in their Preface) are who translated the text, leave almost
less familiar with German than the Greek.' nothing to be desired.'
GUAHDLAJf. Saturday Review.
The STOICS, EPICUREANS, and SCEPTICS. Translated
by O. Beiohel, M.A. B.C.L. sometime Scholar of Queen's College, Oriord.
J. Second
Edition, thoroughly revised. Crown 8vo. 15^.

ARISTOTLE and the ELDER PERIPATETICS. Trans-


lated from the German of Dr. B. Zbller by B. P. 0. Costklloe, Balliol College,
Oxford. Crown 8to. U" preparation.
The PRAE-SOC RATIO SCHOOLS. Being a History of
Greek Philosophy from the Earliest Period to the Time of SOCEATBS. Translated
from the German of Dr. E. ZELIEB by Sarah F. Alleyne. Crown 8yo,
[In the press,
** The two volumes announced above will complete the English Translation of
Dr Zeller'S Work on the Philosophy of the Greeks.
.

London, LONGMANS & CO.


WORKS BY JOHN STUAET MILL
AUTOBIOGRAPHY. The Sixth Edition. 8vo. 7s. 6d.

THREE ESSAYS on ReWgion : Nature, the Utility of


Beligion and Theism. Fourth Edition. 8to. IOj. 6cl.

PRINCIPLES of POLITICAL ECONOMY, with some of


their Applications to Social Philosophy :^
Library Edition (the Seventh), 2 vols. 8vo. 30*.
People's Edition, crown 8vo. 5i.

A SYSTEM of LOGIC. Tenth Edition. 2 vols. 8vo. 25s.


STEBBING'S ANAIYSIS of MILL'S SYSTEM of LOGIC. 12mo. 3s. 6d.
KILLICK'S STUDENT'S HAUDBOOK of MILL'S LOGIC. Crown 8vo. 3. M.

EXAMINATION of HAMILTON'S PHILOSOPHY, and


of the Principal Philosophical Questions discussed in his Writings. The Fifth
Edition. 8vo. 16s.

DISSERTATIONS and DISCUSSIONS, POLITICAL,


PHILOSOPii lOAL and HISTOEICAL. i vols. 8vo. 47s.

On LIBERTY :
Library Edition (the Fifth), post 8to. 7s. 6d.
People's Edition, crown 8vo. Is. id.

On REPRESENTATIVE GOVERNMENT. The People's


Edition. Crown 8vo, 2j!.

UTILITARIANISM. The Seventh Edition. 8vo. 5s.

The SUBJECTION of WOMEN. The Fourth Edition.


Crown 8vo. 6.

ESSAYS on SOME UNSETTLED QUESTIONS of


POLITIOAi ECONOMY. Second Edition. 8vo. 6s. 6d.

ENGLAND and IRELAND. Fifth Edition. Svo. Is.


CHAPTERS and SPEECHES on the IRISH LAND
QUESTION. Crown Svo. 2s. Sd.

PARLIAMENTARY REFORM. Svo. Is. 6d.


INAUGURAL ADDRESS at the UNIVERSITY of ST.
ANDREWS. Second Edition. 8vo. bs. ; People's Edition, crown 8to. Is.

A FRAGMENT on MACKINTOSH: being Strictures on


some Passages in the D^ertation by Sir James Mackintosh prefixed to tlje
Encyclopaedia Britannica. By Jambs Mill. 8vo. 9*.

ANALYSIS of the PHENOMENA of the HUMAN MIND.


By James Mill. A New Edition, with Notes, IllUBtrative and Critical, by
AmxAHDER Bain, Andhew Findlater, and George Grote. Edited, with
additional Notes, by John Stdart Mill. 2 yols. 870. 28s.

London, LONGMANS & CO.


DVEJLieCDEaC 1887.

GENERAL LISTS OE WORKS


PUBLISHED BY
Messrs. LONGMANS, GREEN, & CO.
39 PATERNOSTER ROW. LONDON, E.G.

HISTORY, POLITICS, HISTORICAL MEMOIRS, Sec,


Abbey*s The Englisli Church and its Bishops, 1700-1800. 2 vols. 8vo. 24j.
Abbey and Overton's English Chnrch in the Eighteenth Century. Cr. Svo. Is, 6d.
Arnold's Lectures on Modem History, 8vo. 7i. 6d.
Bagwell'B Ireland under the Tudora. Vols. 1 and 2. 2 vols. 8vo. 32*.
Ball's The Reformed Chiu-ch of Ireland, 1537-1886. 8to. 7s. Gd.
Boultbee's History of the Church of England, Pre-Reformation Period. 8vo. 15*.
Buckle's History of Civilisation. 3 vols, crown Svo. 24j.
Cox's (Sir G. W.) General History of Greece. Crown Svo. Maps, 7s, 6d,
Creighton's History of the Papacy during the Reformation. Svo. Yols. 1 and 2,
32s. Yols. 3 and 4, 24j.
De Tooqueville's Democracy in America. 2 vols, crown Svo. IGs.
Doyle's English in America : Yirginia, Maryland, and the CaroUnas, Svo. IBs.
The Puritan Colonies, 2 vols. Svo. 36.
Epochs ol Ancient History. Edited by the Rev. Sir G. W. Cox, Bart, and C.
Sankey, M.A. With Slaps. Pep. Svo. price 2s, Qd, each.
Beesly *s Gracchi, Marius, and Sulla. lime's Rome to its Capture by the
Capes's Age of the Antonines. Gauls.
Early Roman Empire. Merivale's Roman Triumvirates.
Cox's Athenian Empire. Sankey's Spartan and Theban Supre-
Greeks and Persians. macies.
Curteis's Rise of the Macedonian Smith's Rome and Carthage, the
Empire. Punic Wars.
Epochs of Modem History. Edited by C. Colbeck, M.A. WiUi Maps. Fcp. Svo.
price 2s. Gd, each.
Church's Beginning of the Middle Longman's Frederick the Great and
Ages. the Seven Years* War.
Cox's Crusades. Ludlow's War of American Inde-
Creighton's Age of Elizabeth. pendence
Gairdner's Houses of Lancaster M'Carthy's Epoch of Reform, 1S30-
and York. 1S50.
Gardiner's Puritan Revolution. Moberly's The Early Tudors.
Thirty Tears' War. Morris's Age of Queen Anne.
(Mrs.) French Revolution, The Early Hanoverians.
1789-179C. Seebohm's Protestant Revolution.
Hale's Fall of the Stuarts. Stubbs's The Early Flantagenets.
Johnson's Normans in Europe. Warburton's Edward HI.

EDOChs of Edited by the Rer. Mandell Creighton, M.A.


Church History.
*^
Fcp. Svo. price 2s. 6d. each.
Brodrick's A
History of the tTni- Perry's The Reformationin England.
versity of Oxford. Plummer's The Church of the Early
Fathers.
Overton'B The Evangelical Revival
Eighteenth Century. Tucker's The English Church in
in the
other Lands.
*ft Other Volumes in preparation.

London : LONGMANS, GREEN, & CO.


General Lists of Works.

Freeman's Historical Geography of Bmope. 2 vols. 8vo. 31. 6d.


Fronde's English in Ireland in the 18th Century. S vols, crown 8vo. ISj.
I

! History of England. Popular Hdition. 12 vols, crown 8to. 3*. Bd. each.
Gardiner's History of England from the Accession of James I. to the Outbreak
of the Civil War. 10 vols, crown 8vo. 60j.
Historyof the Great Civil War, 1642-1649 (3 vols.) Vol. 1, 1642-1644,
8vo. 21*.
Greville's Journal of the Eeign of Queen Victoria, 1837-1852. 3 vols. 8vo. 36.
1852-1860, 2 vols. 8vo. 24j.
Historic Towns. Edited by B. A. Freeman, D.O.L. and Rev. William Hunt, M.A.
With Maps and Plans. Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d. each.
London. By W. B. Lottie. I Bristol. By Rev. W. Hunt.
Exeter. By E. A. Freeman. |

** Other volumes in preparation.

Leoky'B History of England in the Eighteenth Century. Vols. Hi 2, 1700-1760,


8to. 3e. Vols. 3 & 4, 1760-1784, 8vo. 36j.
History of European Morals. 2 vols, crown 8vo. 16*.

Eationahsm in Europe. 2 vols, crown 8vo, 16*.
Longman's Life and Times of Edward' ni. 2 vols. 8vo. 28*.
Maoaulay's Complete Works. Library Edition. 8 vols. 8vo. 5. 5*.
Cabinet Edition. 16 vols, crown 8vo. 4. 16*.
History of England :
Student's Edition. 2 vols. or. 8vo. K*. I Cabinet Edition. 8 vols, post 8vo. 48*.
People's Edition. 4 vols. or. 8vo. 16*. | Library Edition. S vols. 8vo. 4.
Macanlay's Critical and Historical Essays, with Lays of Ancient Bome In One
Volume :

Authorised Edition. Cr. 8to. 2*. 6d. I Popular Edition. Or. 8vo. 2*. 6d.
or 3*. id. gilt edges. |

Maoaulay's Critical and Historical Essays :


Student's Edition. 1 vol. cr. 8vo. 6*. |
Cabinet Edition. 4 vols, post 8vo. 24*.
People's Edition. 2 vols. or. 8vo. 8*. | Library Edition. 8 vols. Svo. 36*.
Maoaulay's Speeches corrected by Himself. Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d.
Malmcsbury's (Earl of) Memoirs of an Bx-Mlnister. Crown 8vo. 7*. 6iJ.
Maxwell's (Sir W. S.) Don John of Austria. Library Edition, with numerous
Illustrations. 2 vols, royal 8vo. 42*.
May's Constitutional History of England, 1760-1870. 3 vols, crown 8to. 18*.
Democracy in Europe. 2 vols. 8vo. 32*.
Merivale'sFall of the Roman Republic. 12mo. 7*. Sd.
General History of Rome, b.o. 763-a.d. 476. Crown 8vo. 7*. 6if.
History of the Romans under the Empire. 8 vols, post 8vo. 48*.
Nelson's (Lord) Letters and Despatches. Edited by J. K. Laughton. 8vo. 16*.
Outlines of Jewish History from b.o. 586 to o.E. 188B. By the author of ' About
the Jews since Bible Times.' Fcp. 8vo. 3*. M.
Pears' The Fall of Constantinople. 8vo. 16*.
Seebohm's Oxford Kefonnera Colet, Erasmus, & More. 8vo. 14*.
Short's History of the Church
of England. Crown 8vo. 7*. 64.
Smith's Carthage and the Carthaginians. Crown 8vo. 10*. 6d.
Taylor's Manual of the History of India. Crown 8vo. 7*. 6d.

London : LONGMANS, GREEN, & CO.


General Lists of Works.

Walpole'B Mt8tory of Bnglimd, from 1815. 5 vols. 8to. Vols. 1 & 2, 1815-1832, M>.
Vol. 3, 1832-1841, 18s. Vols. 4 & 5, 1841-1858, 365.
WyUe's History of England under Henry IV. Vol. 1, crown 8to, 10*. 6i.

BIOGRAPHICAL WORKS.
Amutrong's (E. J.) Life and Letters. Edited by Q-. F. Armstrong. Fop, 8vo, Ts.Qd.
Bacon's Life and Letters, by Sped(3ing. 7 vols. Svo. 4. 4.
Bagebot's Biographical Stadies. 1 toL Bto. 12j.
Carlyle's Life, by J. A. Froude. Vols. 1 & 2, 1796-1835, 8to. Z2a. Vols. 3 & 4,
1834-1881, 8to. 32s.
and Memorials. 3 vols. 8vo. 86s.
(Mrs.) Lettei^
Doyle (Sir F. H.) Keminiscences and Opinions. 8vo. 16j.
English Worthies. Edited by Andrew Lang. Crown 8vo. S. Gd. each.
Charles Darwin. By Grant Allen. Marlborough. By G-eorge Saintsbury.
Shaftesbury (The First Barl). By Steele. By Austin Dobson.
H. D. TraUl. Ben Jonson. By J. A. Symonds.
Admiral Blake. By David Hannay. G-eorge Canning. By Frank H. Hill.
*^* Other Volumes in preparation.
Pox (Charles James) The Early History of. By Sir Gt. 0. Treyelyan, Bart.
CrownSvo. 6s.
Fronde's Csesar : a Sketch. Crown 8to. 6j.
Hamilton's (Sir W. R.) Life, by Graves. Vols. 1 and 2, 8vo. 15*. each.
Havelock'B Life, by Marshman. Crown 8vo. 34. Bd.
Hobart Pacha's Sketches from my Life. Crown Svo. 7s, 6d.
Macanlay's (Lord) Life and Letters. By his Nephew, Sir G. 0. Trevelyan, Bart.
Popular Edition, 1 vol. crown Svo. 6s, Cabinet Edition, 2 vols, post
Svo. 12i. Libraiy Edition, 2 vols. Svo. 36*.
Mendelssohn's Letters. Translated by Lady Wallace. 2 vols. or. Svo. 5s, each.
Mill (James) Biography o^ by Prof. Bain. Crown Svo. 6s,
(John Stuart) Recollections of, by Prof. Bain. Crown Svo, 2*. 6d,
Autobiography, Svo. 7s. Gd.
,

Mtlller's (Max) Biographical Essays. Crown Svo. 7s. Qd.


Newman's Apologia pro Vita, Sua. Crown Svo. Qs,
Pasteur (Louis) His Life and Labours. Crown Svo. 7s. Gd,
Shakespeare's Life (Outlines of), by Halliwell-Phillipps. 2 vols, royal Svo. 10*. Gd,
Southey's Correspondence with Caroline Bowles. Svo. 14s,
Stephen's Essays in Ecclesiastical Biography. Crown Svo. 7s. Gd.
Wellington's Life, by Gleig. Crown Svo. 6s.

MENTAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY, FINANCE, &c.


Ames's View of the Science of Jurisprudence. Svo. 18*.
Primer of the English Constitution. Crown Svo. 6*.
Bacon's Essays, with Annotatioia by Whately. Svo. 10*. 6d.
Works, edited by Spedding. 7 vols. Svo. 73*. Gd.
Bagehot's Economic Studies, edited by Hutton. Svo. 10*. Gd,
The Postulates of English Political Economy. Crown Svo. 2*. Gd,
Bain's Logic, Deductive and Inductive. Crown Svo. 10*. Gd.
Part I. Deduction, 4*. | Part II. Induction, 6*, Gd.
Mental and Moral Science. Crown Svo.
'
10*. Gd.
The Senses and the Intellect. Svo. 15*.
The Emotions and the Will. Svo. 15*.
Practical Essays. Crown Svo. 4a. 6d,

London : LONGMAl^S, GREEN, & CO.


.

Oeneral Lists of Works.

Buckle's (E. T.) Miscellaneous and Posthumous Works. 2 vols, crown Sto. 31<,
Orozier's Civilization and Progress. 8to. 14i.
Crump's A Short Enquiry into the Formation of English Political Opinion.
8to. 7(. M.
DoTell's A. History of Taxation and Taxes in England. 4 vols. 8vo. 48f.
Green's (Thomas Hill) Works. (3 toIb.) Vols. 1 & 2, Philosophical Works. 8to.
16j. each.
Hume's Essays, edited by Green & Grose. 2 vols. 8vo. 28j.
Treatise of Human Nature, edited by Green & Grose, i vols. Svo. 38<.
Lang's Custom and Myth : Studies of Early Usage and Belief. Crown Svo. 7>. M.
Leslie's Essays in Political and Moral Philosophy. 8vo. 10. 6d.
Lewes's History of Philosophy. 2 vols, 8vo. 32j.
Lubbock's Origin of Civilisation. 8vo. lit.
Macleod's Principles of Economical Philosophy. In 2 vols. Tol. I, Svo. 1S>.
Vol. 2, Part 1. 13*.
The Elements of Economics. (2 vols.) Vol. 1, cr. Svo. It. M. Vol. 2,
Part I. cr. Svo. 7s. 6d.
The Elements of Banking. Crown Svo. Bi.
The Theory and Practice of Banking, Vol. 1, Svo. 12j. Vol. 2, 14j.
Economics for Beginners. Svo. 2s. 6(2.
. Lectures on Credit and Banking. Svo. 5s.
Mill's (James) Analysis of the Phenomena of the Human Mind. 2 vols. Svo. 2Sf.
Mill (John Stuart) on Hepresentative Government. Crown Svo. 2f.
on Liberty. Crown Svo. It. id.
Examination of Hamilton's Philosophy, Svo. ISj.
Logic. Crown Svo. 6t.
Principles of Political Economy. 2 vols. Svo. 30j, People's
Edition, 1 vol. crown Svo. St,
. Subjection of Women. Crown Svo. 6*.
Utilitarianism. Svo. is.
Three Essays on Beligion, &c. Svo. 6t.
Mulhall's History of Prices since 1860. Crown Svo. 6f
Sandars's Institutes of Justinian, with English Notes. Svo. 184.
Seebohm's English Village Community. Svo, 16<.
Sully's Outlines of Psychology. Svo. 12j. 6d.
Teacher's Handbook of Psychology. Crown Svo. Bs. fid.

Swinburne's Picture Logic. Post Svo. 5s.


Thompson's A
System of Psychology. 2 vols. Svo. 86.
Thomson's Outline of Necessary Laws of Thought. Crown Svo. Ss,
Twiss's Law of Nations in Time of War. Svo. 21<.
in Time of Peace. Svo. 15s.
Webb's The Veil of Isis. Svo. lOi. Sd.
Whately's Elements of Logic. Crown Svo. is. Gd.

Bhetoric. Crown Svo. 4f. Gd.
Wylie's Labour, Leisure, and Luxury. Crown Svo. 6<.
Zeller's History of Eclecticism in Greek Philosophy. Crown Svo. lOi. 6d. .

Plato and the Older Academy. Crown Svo. ISi.


Pre-Socratic Schools. 2 vols, crown Svo. 80 j.
-~ Boorates and the Sooratic Schools. Crown Svo. 10<. td.
Stoics, Epicureans, and Sceptics. Crown Svo. 15t.
Outlines of the History of Greek Philosophy. Crown Svo, lOi. 6(2.

London : LONG-MANS, GEEEN, & CO,


General Lists of Works.

MISCELLANEOUS WORKS.
A. K, H. B., The SssajB and Contributions of. Crown 870.
Autumn Holidays of a Country Parson. 3i. 6d,
Clianged Aspects of Unchanged Truths. 3j. Gd.
Conunon-Flace Philosopher In Town and Country. Zs. Gd.
Critical Essays of a Country Parson. 3^. Gd.
Counsel and Comfort spoken from a City Pulpit. Si. Gd.
Oraver Thoughts of a Country Parson. Three Series. Zs* Gd, each.
Landscapes, Churches, and Koralities. 3f. Gd.
Leisure Hours in Town. 3j. 6d. Lessons of Middle Age. 3i. 6(2.
Our Homely Comedy ; and Tragedy. Zs. Gd.
Our Little Life. Essays Consolatory and Domestic. Two Series. 3. Gd,
Present-day Thoughts. Zs, Gd. [^each.
Recreations of a Country Parson. Three Series. 3. Gd. each.
Seaside MusLngs on Sundays and Week-Days. Zs. 6d.
Sunday Afternoons in the Parish Church of a TJnlTersity City. 3f. Gd.
Armstrong's (Ed. J.) Essays and Sketches. Fcp. 870. 5s.
Arnold's (Dr. Thomas) Miscellaneous Works. 8to. Is. Gd.
Bagehot's Literary Studies, edited by Hutton. 2 vols. 8vo. 28a.
Beaconsfleld (Lord), The Wit and Wisdom of. Crown 8to. 1*. boards ; Is, Gd. cl.
Evanfl'a Bronze Implements of Great Britain. 8vo. 25s.
Farrar'a Language and Limguagesi. Crown 8to. 6.
Fronde's Short Studies on G-reat Subjects. 4 vols, crown Svo. 2is.
Lang's Letters to Dead Authors. Fcp. Svo. Gs. Gd.
Books and Bookmen. Grown 8to. 6s. Gd.
Macaulay's Miscellaneous Writings. 2 Svo.
vols. 1 vol. crown 8to.
21*. Gd. 4i.
Miscellaneous Writings and Speeches. Crown Svo. Gs.
Miscellaneous Writings, Speeches, Lays of Ancient Bome, &o.
Cabinet Edition. 4 crown Svo.
vols, 24<.
Writings, Selections from. Crown Svo. Gs.
MUller's (Max) Lectures on the Science of Langu^e. 2 crown 870. vols, I61,
Lectures on India. Svo. Gd, 12s.
Proctor's Chance and Luck. Crown Svo. 5*.
Smith (Sydney) The Wit and Wisdom of. Crown 8vo. Is. boards ; Is. Gd. cloth.

ASTRONOMY.
Herschel's Outlines of Astronomy. Square crown Svo. 12s.
Proctor's Larger Star Atlas. Folio, 15*. or Maps only, 12*. Gd.
New Btw: Atlas. Crown Svo. 5a.
Light Sctience for Leisure Hours. 3 Series. Crown Sro. 5*. each.
The Moon. Crown Svo. Gs.
Other Worlds than Ours. Crown Svo. 5s.
The Sun. Crown Svo. 14*.
Studiffl of Venus-Transits. Svo. 5*.
Orbs Around Us. Crown Svo. 5*.
Universe of Stars. Svo. 10*. Gd.
"Webb's Celestial Objects for Common Telescopes. Crown Svo. 9*.
THE 'KNOWLEDGE' LIBRARY.
Edited by Biohard A. Proctor.
How to Play Whist, Crown Svo. Si- Pleasant Ways in Science. Or. Svo. 6*.
Home Whist. 16mo. Is. Star Primer. Crown 4to. 2*. Gd.
The Borderland of Science. Cr, Svo. Gs. The Seasons Pictured. Demy 4to. 5s,
Nature Studies. Crown Svo. Gs. Strength and Happiness. Cr. Svo. 6s,
Leisure Headings. Crown Svo. Gs. BoughWays made Smooth. Cr.870.6.
The Stars in their Seasons. Imp. Svo. 6*. The Expanse of Heaven. Cr, Svo. 6*.
Myths and Marvels of Astronomy. Our Place among Infinities, Cr, Svo. 6*.
Crown Svo. 6a. [

London: LONGMANS, GKEEN, & CO.


General Lists of Works.

CLASSICAL LANGUAGES AND LITERATURE.


.Sschylus, The Eumenides of. Text, with Metrical English Translation, by
J. E. DaTies. 8yo. 7s.
Aristophanes' The Aohamians, translated by E. T. Tyrrell. Crown 8vo. 2j. M.
Aristotle's The Ethics, Text and Notes, by Sir Alex. Grant, Bart. 2 vols. 8vo. 32.
The Nicomacbean Ethics, translated by Williams, crown 8to. 7*. 6d.
The Politics, Books I. III. IV. (VII.) with Translation, &C. by
Bolland and Lang. Grown 8vo. Is. Bd.
Becker's Charicles and Oallus, by Metcalfe. Post 8vo. 7s. 6d. eaoh.
Cicero's Correspondence, Text and Notes, by B. Y. Tyrrell. Vols. 1 & 2, 8vo.
12s. each.
Homer's Iliad, Homometrically translated by Cayley. 8to. 12j. 6d.
Greek Text, with Verse Translation, by W. d. Green. Vol. 1,
Books I.-XII. Crown Svo. 6j.
Mahaffy's Classical Greek Literature. Crown Svo. Vol. 1, The Poets, 7s. 6d,
Vol. 2, The Prose Writers, 7s. M.
Plato's Pannenides, with Notes, &c. by J. Magnire. Svo. 7s. ed.
Virgil's Works, Latin Text, with Commentary, by Kennedy. Crown Svo. 10. Sd.
2Ejneid, translated into English Verse, by Conington. Crown Svo. 9s,
_ _ _ byW.J.ThoruhiU. Cr.8vo.rj.6ii.
Poems, Prose, by Conington. Crown Svo. 9.
Witt's Myths of Hellas, translated by P. M. Tounghusband. Crown Svo; Sd, 8>.
The Trojan War, Pep. Svo. S,
The Wanderings of Ulysses, Crown Svo. 3<, 6il

NATURAL HISTORY, BOTANY, & GARDENING.


Allen's Flowers and their Pedigrees. Crown Svo. Woodcuts, 6i.
Deoaisne and Le Maout'e General System of Botany. Imperial Svo. 31s. id.
Bixon's Bural Bird Life. Crown Svo. Illustrations, 5s.
Hartwig's Aerial World, Svo. 10. ed.
Polar World, Svo. 10s. 6d.
Sea and its Living Wonders. Svo. 10s, 6d,
Subterranean World, Svo. 10s. Gd.
Tropical World, Svo. 10. 6d.
Lindley's Treasury of Botany. 2 vols. fop. Svo. 12.
Loudon's Encyclopsedia of Gardening. Svo. 21s,
Plants. Svo. Us.
Rivers's Orchard House. Crown Svo. 5s.
Miniature Fruit Garden. Pep. Svo. is.
Stanley's Familiar History of British Birds. Crown Svo. 6*.
Wood's Bible Animals. With 112 Vignettes. Svo. 10. 6iJ.
Common British Insects. Crown Svo. 3s. 6d,
Homes Without Hands, Svo. 10s. 6d.
Insects Abroad, Svo. IDs. 6d.
Horse and Man. Svo. 14s.
Home. With 700 Illustrations. Svo. 10* Bd.
Insects at
Out of Doors. Crown Svo. 5 J.
Petland Bevisited. Crown Svo. 7. Sd.
Strange Dwellings. Crown Svo. 6s. Popular Edition, 4to. ed.

London: LONGMANS, GBEEN, & CO.


.

General Lists of Works.

THE FINE ARTS AND ILLUSTRATED EDITIONS.


Eastlake's Household Taste in Furniture, Sic. Square crown 8vo. 144.
Jameson's Sacred and Legendary Art. 6 toIb. square 8vo.
Legends of the Madonna. 1 vol. 21s.
Monastic Orders 1 toI. 21s.
Saints and Martyrs. 2 vols, Zls. Bd.
Saviour. Completed by Lady Bastlake. 2 vols. 42s.
Macaul^'s Lays of Ancient Rome, illustrated by Scharf. Fop. 4to. 10a. 6<2.
The same, with Ivrp and the Armada, illustrated by Weguelin. Crown 8vo. 3j. Sd.
New Testament (The) iUustrated with Woodcata after Paintings by the Early
Masters. 4to. 21s.

CHEMISTRY ENGINEERING, & GENERAL SCIENCE.


Amott's Elements of Physics or Natural Philosophy. Crown 8vo. 12*. 6d.
Barrett's English Glees and Part-Songs their Historical Development.
:

Crown 8vo. 7s. Qd.


Bourne's Catechism of the Steam Engine, Crown 8vo. 7a. 6d.
Examples of Steam, Air, and Gas Engines. 4to. 70s.
Handbook of the Steam Engine, Pop. 8vo. 9s.
Recent Improvements in the Steam Engme, Fop. 8vo. 6*.
Treatise on the Steam Engine. 4to. 42j.
Buckton's Our Dwellings, Healthy and Unhealthy. Crown 8vo. 3*. Qd.

Clerk's The Gas Engine. "With Illustrations, Crown 8vo. 7s. 6d.
Crookes's Select Methods in Chemical Analysis. 8vo. 24j.
Culley's Handbook of Practical Telegraphy. 8vo. 16s.
Fairbaim's Useful Information for Engineers. 3 vols. croWn 8vo. 31j. 6d.
Mills and MiUwork. 1 vol. 8vo. 25s.
Ganot's Elementary Treatise on Physics, by Atkinson. Large crown 8vo. 15*.

Natural Philosophy, by Atkinson. Crown Svo. 7s, 6d.


Grove's Correlation of Physical Forces. Svo. 16a
Haughton's Six Lectures on Physical Geography. Svo. Us.
Helmholtz on the Sensations of Tone. Royal Svo, 28s.
Helmholtz's Lectures on Scientific Subjects. 2 vols, crown Svo. 7s. 6d. each.
Hudson and Gosse's or ' Wheel Animalcules.' With 30 Coloured
The Botifera
Plates. 6 parts. 4to. 10s. 6d. each. Complete, 2 vols. 4to. 3. 10s.
Hullah's Lectures on the History of Modem Music. Svo. 8. Qd.
Transition Period of Musical History. Svo. lOa. Bd.
Jackson's Aid to Engineering Solution. Royal Svo. 21s,
Jago's Inorganic Chemistry, Theoretical and Practical. Fcp. Svo. 2s.
Jeans' Railway Problems. Svo. 12*. 6d.
Kolbe's Short Text-Book of Inorganic Chemistry. Crown Svo. 7s. Sd,
Lloyd's Treatise on Magnetism. Svo. 10s. Gd.
Macalister'B Zoology and Morphology of Vertebrate Animals. Svo. 10*. 6d.
Macfar^en's Lectures on Harmony. Svo. 12s.
Miller's Elements of Chemistry, Theoretical and
Practical. 3 vols. Svo. Part I,
Chemical Physics, 16*. Part II. Inorganic Chemistry, 24j. Part III. Organic
Chemistry, price 31*. 6d
Mitchell's Manual of Practical Assaying. Svo. 31*. 6d.

London: LONGMANS, GREEN, & 00.


Noble's Hours with, a Three-inch Telescope. Crown 8vo. 4, fid.

Northoott's Lathes and Turning. 870. 18^.


Owen's Comparative Anatomy and Physiology of the Vertebrate Animals.
3 vols. 8to. 73f. Gd.
Art of Perfumery. Square crown 8vo. 21s.
Piesse's
Reynold's Experimental Chemistry. Pep. Sto. Part I. U. Gd. Part II, Si. 6(2.
Part in. Bs. Gd,
Schellen's Spectrum Analysis. 8vo. 3l5. 6d.
Sennett's Treatise on the Marine Steam Engine. 870. 21s.
Smith's Air and Hain. 870. 245.
Stoney's The Theory of the Stresses on Girders, &c. Royal 870. 36*.
Tilden's Practical Chemistry. Fcp. Svo. Is, Gd.

Tyndall's Paraday as a Disco7erer. Crown 8to. Ss. Gd.


Pleating Matter of the Air. Crown 870. 78. Gd.
Fragments of Science. 2 7ols. post 870. 16.
Heat a Mode of Motion. Crown 870. 125.
Lectures on Light deli7ered in America. Crown Svo. 55.
Lessons on Electricity. Crown 870. 2*. Gd.
NotM on Electrical Phenomena. Crown 870. Is. sewed, 1*. Gd. cloth.
Notra of Lectures on Light. Crown 870. Is. sewed, Is. Gd. cloth.
Sound, with Frontispiece and 203 Woodcuts. Crown 870. IOj. 6d.
Watts's Dictionary of Chemistry. 9 70ls. medium 870. 15. 2s. Gd.
Wilson's Manual of Health-Science. Crown 8vo. 2*. Gd.

THEOLOGICAL AND RELIGIOUS WORKS.


Arnold's (Rev. Dr. Thomas) Sermons. 6 vols, crown 870. 5*. each.
Boultbee's Commentary on the 39 Article. Crown 8vo. 65.
Browne's (Bishop) Exposition of the 39 Articles. 870. 16s.
BuUinger's Critical Lexicon and Concordance to the English and Greek New
Testament. Royal 870. 15.
Colenso on the Pentateuch and Book of Joshua. Crown 870, Gs.
Conder's Handbook of the Bible. Post 870. 7s. Gd.
Conybeare 8i Howson's Life and Letters of St. Paul :

Library Edition, with Maps, Plates, and Woodcuts. 2 7ol8. square orown
870. 21s.
Student's Edition, revised and condensed, with 46 Illustrations and Maps.
1 7ol. crown 870. 78. Gd.
Cox's (Homersham) The First Century of Christianity. 870.' 123.
Da7idson's Introduction to the Study of the New Testament. 2 7ols. Svo. 30i,
Ederahetm's Life and Times of Jesus the Messiah. 2 vols. Svo. 24f.
Prophecy and History in relation to the Messiah. Svo. 12*.
Ellicott's ^Bishop) Commentary on St. Paul's Epistles. 870. Galatians, 8. Gd.
Sphesians, Bs. Gd. Pastors^ Epistles, lOs. Gd. Philipplaus, Colossians and
Philemon, 10s. 6d. Thessalonians, 7s. Gd.
Lectures on the Life of our Lord. 870, 12.
Bwald's Antiquities of Israel, translated by SoHy. 870. 12*. Gd.
History of Israel, translated by Carpenter & Smith, 8 vols. Svo. VoU
1 & 2, 24*. Vols. 3 & 4, 21s. Vol. 5, I8s. Vol. 6, 16*. Vol. 7.' 2ls,
Vol. 8, ISi.
Hobart's Medical Language of St. Luke, 870. IGs,
Hopkins's Christ the Consoler. Fcp. 870. 2^. Gd.

London: LONGMANS, GKEEN, & CO.


(General Lists of Works.

Jukea's New Uan and theEternal Life, Crown 8ro. Ss.


Second Death and the Bestitutiou ol all Thinga, Crown 8to. 3s. 6<2.
Types ot Genesis. Crown 8vo. 7i. 6<J.
The Mystery of the Kingdom. Crown 8to. 3*. 6d.
Lenormant's New Translation ot the Book of Genesis. Translated into English.
8yo. lOi. Bd.
Lyra Germanica : Hymns translated by Miss Winkworth. Fcp. 8vo. 5s,
Macdonald'a (G.) Unspoken Sermons. Two Series, Crown 8vo. 3f. Sd, each,
The Miracles of our Lord. Crown 8vo. 3a. ed.
Manning's Temporal Mission of the Holy Ghost. Crown Sto. St. Si.
Martinean's Endeavours after the Christian Life. Crown 8to. 7s. 6d.
Hymns of Praise and Frayer. Crown 8to. is. 6(2. 32mo. Is. 6(2.
Sermons, Hours of Thought on Sacred Things. 2 vols. 7s, 6(2, each,
Monsell's Spiritual Songs for Sundays and Holidays. Fcp. 8vo. 5s. 18mo. 2f,
MUller'a (Max) Origin and Growth of Religion. Crown 8vo. 7s. 6(2.

Science of Religion. Crown 8vo. 7s. 6(2.

Newman's Apologia pro Yitft Su&. Crown 8vo. 6s.


The Idea of a University Defined and Illustrated. Crown Bvo, 7s,
Historical Sketches. crown 8vo. 6s. each.
3 vols,
Discussions and Arguments on Various Subjects. Crown 8vo. 6s.
An Essay on the Development of Christian Doctrine. Crown 8vo. 6s,
Certain Difficulties Felt by Anglicans in Catholic Teaching Con-
sidered. Vol. 1, crown 8vo. 7s. 6(2. Vol. 2, crown 8vo. 5s. 6(2.
The Via Media of the Anglican Church, Illuatrated in Lectures, &c,
2 vols, ccovnx Bvo. 6s. each
Essays, Critical and HistoricaL 2 vols, crown 8vo. 12s.
Essays on Biblical and- on Ecclesiastical Miracles. Crown 8vo. 6s.
An Essay in Aid of a Grammar of Assent. 7s. 6i2.
Overton's Life in the English Church (1660-1714). 8vo. 14s.
Supernatural Religion. Complete Edition. 3 vols. 8vo. 36s.
Younghusband's The Story of Our Lord told in Simple Language for Children.
Illustrated. Crown 8vo. 2s. Sd. cloth plain ; 3s. 6(2. cloth extra, gilt edges.

TRAVELS, ADVENTURES, See.


Alpine Club (The) Map of Switzerland. In Fonr Sheets. 42s.

Baker's Eight Tears in Ceylon. Crown 8vo. 5s.


Rifle and Hound in Ceylon. Crown 8vo. Ss.

Ball's Alpine Guide. 3 vols, post 8vo. with Maps and Illustrations : I. Western
Alps, 6s. 6(2. n. Central Alps, 7s. 6(2. HI. Eastern Alps, 10s. 6(2.

Ball on Alpine Travelling, and on the Geology of the Alps, Is.


Braaaey's Sunshine and Storm in the East. Library Edition, 8vo. 21s, Cabinet
Edition, crown 8vo. 7s. 6(2. Popular Edition, 4to. 6(2.
Voyage in the Yacht ' Sunbeam.' Library Edition, 8vo. 21s. Cabinet
Edition, crown 8vo. 7s. 6(2. School Edition, fcp. 8vo. 2s. Popular
Edition, 4to. 6d.
In the Trades, the Tropics, and the ' Roaring Forties.' Library Edition,
8V0.21S. Cabinet Edition, crown 8vo. 17s. 6(2. Popular Edition,
4to. 6(2.

Fronde's Oceana ; or, England and her Colonies. Crown 8vo. 2i. boards ; 2s. 6(2.

cloth,
Howitt'a Visits to Remarkable Places. Crown 8vo. 7s. 6(2.
Three in Norway, By 1\"0 of Them, Crown 8vo, Illustrations, 6s,

London : LONGMANS, GEEEN, & CO,


:

10 General Lists of Works.

WORKS OF FICTION.
Beaconsfield'8 (The Earl of) Novels and Tales. Hi^henden Edition, with 2
Portraits on Steel and 11 Vignettes on ^Vood. 11 vols, crown 8vo. 2. 2s
Cheap Edition, 11 vols, crown 8to. Is. each, boards ; Is. 6d. each, doth.
liOthair. Contarini Fleming.
Sybil. Alroy, ladon, &c.
ConingBby. The Tonng Dnke, &c.
Tancied. Vivian &rey.
Venetia. Endymion.
Henrietta Temple.
Black Poodle (The) and other Tales. By the Author of * Vice Versfi.' Or. 8vo. 6*.
Braboume's (Lord) PriendH and Foes JErom Fairyland. Grown 8vo. Ss.
Caddy's (Mrs.) Through the Fields with linnseus : a Chapter in Swedish History.
2 vols, crown 8vo. 16a.
Haggard's (H. Bider) She: a History of Adventure. Crown 8vo. Gs.
Harte (Bret) On the Frontier. Three Stories. 16mo. Is.
By Shore and Sedge, Three Stories. 16mo. 1*.
In the Carquinez Woods. Crown 8vo. 2s, boards ; 2s. 6d. cloth.
Melville's (Whyte) Novels. 8 vols. fcp. 8vo. 1*. each, boards ; Is. 6d. each, cloth.
Digby Grand. Gk>od for Nothing.
General Bounce. Holmby House.
Kate Coventry. The Interpreter.
The Gladiators. The Queen's Maries.
Moiesworth's (Mrs.) Marrying and (xiving in Marriage. Crown 8vo. 7s. Gd.
Novels by the Author of * The Atelier du Lys '
The Atelier du Lya ; or, An Art Student in the Reign of Terror. Crown
8vo. 2s. Gd.
Mademoiselle Mori : a Tale of Modem Kome, Crown 8vo. 2s. Gd,
In the Olden Time a Tale of the Peasant War in Germany. Crown 8vo. 2s. Gd.
:

Hester's Venture. Crown 8to. 6*.


Oliphant's (Mrs.) Madam. Crown 8vo. Ss. 6(2.
In Trust the Story of a Lady and her Lover.
: Crown 8vo.
2s. boards ; 2s. Gd. cloth.
Payn's (James) The Luck of the Barrells. Crown 8vo. 3*. Gd.
Thicker than Water. Crown 8vo. 2s. boards ; 2s. Gd. cloth.
Reader's Fairy Prince FoUow-my-Lead. Crown 8vo. 5*.
The Ghost of Brankinshaw ; and other Tales. Fcp. 8to. 2s. Gd.
Ross's (Percy) A Comedy without Laughter. Crown 8vo. 6*.
Sewell'B (Miss) Stori^ and Tales. Crown 8vo. Is. each, boards ; Is. Gd. cloth ;

2s. Gd. cloth extra, gilt edges.


Amy Herbert. Cleve Hall. A Glimpse of the World.
The Earl's Daughter. Katharine Ashton.
Experience of Life* Laneton Parsonage.
Gertrude. Ivora. Margaret Percival. Ursula.
Stevenson's (R. L.) The Dynamiter. Fcp. 8vo. 1*. sewed ; 1*. Gd. cloth,
Strange Case of Dr. Jekyll and Mr. Hyde. Fcp. 8vo. 1*.
sewed ; Is. Gd. cloth.
Trollope's (Anthony) Novels. Fcp. 8vo. Is. each, boards ; Is. Gd. cloth.
The Warden I Barchester Towers.

London : LONaMANS, GEEEN, & CO.


General Lists of Works. 11

POETRY AND THE DRAMA,


Anrwtrong's (Bd. JO
Poetical Works. Fcp. 8vo.5*.
'(G. F.) Poetical Works ;
Poems, Lyrical and Dramatic. Ecp. King Saul. Fop. 8to. 5s.
8vo. Bs. King David. Fcp. 8to. 6s,
XTgone : a Tragedy. Pep. 8to. 6*. King Solomon Fcp. 8to. 6. .

AQ-arland from Greece. Fcp. 8vo.9. Stories of Wicklow. Fcp. 8vo. 9*.

Bowen's Harrow Songs and other Verses. Fcp. 8vo. 2s. 6d. ; or printed on
hand-made paper, 5a.
Bowdler*s Family Shakespeare. Medium 8to. 14s. 6 vols, fop^ Bro. 21.
Dante's Divine Ctmiedy, translated by James Innes Mjnohin. Crown Svo. 16s.
Goethe's Faust, translated by Birds. Large crown 8to. 12a, 6d.

translated by Webb. 8vo. 12j. Qd,

edited by Selss. Crown 8vo. 5s.
Ingelow'B Poems. Vols. 1 and 2, fcp. 8va. 12s. VoL 3 fcp, 8to. 6*.
Lyrical and other Poems. Fcp. 8to. 2i. 6d. doth, plain ; 3a, cloth,
gilt edges.
Macaulay's Lays of Ancient Borne, with Ivry and the Armada. DluBtrated by
Weguelin. Crown 8to. 3s. 6d. gilt edges.
The same, Popular Edition. Uluatrated by Scharf. Fcp. 4to. Gd, swd., Is, cloth.
Nesbit's Lays and Legends. Crown 8vo. 5*.
Header's Toices from Flowerland, a Birthday Book, 2s. 6tZ, cloth, 3s. Gd. roan.
Southey's Poetical Works. Medium 8vo. 14a.
Stevenson's A Child's Garden of Verses. Fcp. 8vo. 5s.

Virgil's .Slneid, translated by Conington. Crown 8vo. 9s.


Poems, translated into English Prose. Crown 8vo. 9a.

AGRICULTURE, HORSES, DOGS, AND CATTLE.


Dunster'sHow to Make the Land Pay. Crown 8vo. 5s.

Fitzwygram's Horses and Stables. 8vo. 5s.


Lloyd's The Science of Agriculture. 8vo. 13*.
Loudon's EncyclopsBdia of Agriculture. 21*.

Miles's Horse's Foot, and How to Keep it Sound. Imperial 8vo. 12s. 6(2.

Plain Treatise on Horse-Shoeing. Post 8vo. 2s. 6d.


Remarks on Horses' Teeth. Post 8vo. Is. 6(2.

Stables and Stable-Fittings. Imperial 8vo. 15s.

Nevile's Farms and Farming. Crown 8to. Qa.


Horses and Biding. Crown 8vo. Gs.

Steel's Diseases of a Manual of Bovine Pathology. 8vo.


the Ox., 15s,

Stonehenge'B Disease. Square crown 8vo. 7a.


Dog in Health and 6(2.
Greyhound. Square crown 8vo. 15*.
Taylor's Agricultural Note Book. Pep. 8vo. 2s. 6d.
Ville on Artificial Manures, by Crookes. 8vo. 21*.
Touatt's Work on the Dog. 8vo. 6s.
_ _ _ Horse. 8vo. 7s. Gd.

London : LONaMANS, GREEN, & CO.


12 General Lists of Works.

SPORTS AND PASTIMES.


The Badminton Library of Sports and Pastimes. Edited by tbe Duke of Beanfort
and A. E. T. Watson. With nnmerous Illnstrationa. Crown 8to. lOi. Sd.
each.
Hunting, by the Dnke of Beaufort, &c,
fishing, by H. Cholmondeley-Fennell, &c. 2 Tols.
Bacing, by the Earl of SufTelk, &c.
Shooting, by Lord Walsingham, &c. 2 vols.
Cycling. By Viscount Bury.
%* Other Volumes in preparation.
Campbell-Walker's Correct Card, or How to Play at Whist. Fop. 870. 2i. id.
Dead Shot (The) by Marksman. Crown 8vo. 10. Sd.
I^ancii'a Treatise on Fishing in all its Branches, Post 870, ISj.
Longman's Chess Openings, Fcp. 8vo. 2. &d.
Pease's The Cleveland Hounds as a Trencher-Fed Pack. Boyal 8to. 18j.
Pole'sTheory of the Modern Scientlflc Game of Whist, Fcp. Sto. 2>. id.
Proctor's How to Play Whist. Crown 8vo. 5s.
Bonalds's Fly-Fisher's Entomology. 8to. lis.
Vemey's Chess Eccentricities. Crown 8vo. 10. id.
WUcocks's Sea-Fisherman. PostSvo. 6.

ENCYCLOP/EDIAS, DICTIONARIES, AND BOOKS OF


REFERENCE.
Acton's Modem Cookery for Private Families. Fcp. 870. is. id.
Ayze'B Treasury of Bible Knowledge. Fop. 8vo. 6s.
Brando's Dictionary of Science, Literature, and Art. 3 vols, medium 8vo. 63s.
Cabinet Lawyer (The), a Popular Digest of the Laws of England. Fcp. 8vo. 9s.
Cates's Dictionary of G-eneral Biography. Medium 8vo. 28s,
Doyle's The Official Baronage of England. Vols. L-in. 3 vols. ito. 5. 5s.
Gwilt's Encyclopaedia of Architecture. 8vo. 62s. Gd.
Keith Johnston's Dictionary of Geography, or General Gazetteer. 8vo. 42s.
M'Culloch's Dictionary of Commerce and Commercial Navigation. 8vo. 63s.
Maunder's Biographical Treasury, Fcp. 8vo. 6s.
Historical Treasury. Fcp. 8vo. 6s.
Scientific and Literary Treasury. Fcp. 8vo. 6s.
Treasury of Bible Knowledge, edited by Ayre. Fop. 8vo. 6s.
Treasury of Botany, edited by liudley & Moore. Two Parts, ISs.
Treasury of Geography. Fop. 8vo. 6s.
Treasury of Knowledge and Library of Beference. Fcp. Svo. 6s.
Treasury of Natural History. Fcp. Svo. 6s.
Quoin's Dictionary of Medicine. Medium Svo. 31s. id., or in 2 vols. 34s.
Keeve's Cookery and Housekeeping. Crown Svo. 7s. id.
Bich's Dictionary of Roman and Greek Antiquities. Crown Svo. 7s. id,
Boget's Thesaurus of English Words and Phrases. Crown Svo. 10s. id.
lire's Dictionary of Arts, Manufactures, and Mines. 4 vols, medium Svo. AT, It,
WlUich's Popular Tables, by Marriott. Crown Svo. 10s. id.

London: LONGMANS, GEEEN, & CO.


.

A SELECTION
OF

EDUCATIONAL WOEKS.
TEXT-BOOKS OF SCIENCE
FULLY ILLUSTRATED.
Abney'B Treatise on Photography. Fcp. Svo. 3f. 6(2.
Anderson's Strength of Materials. Ss. 6d.
Armstrong's Organic Ohemistry. 2s. Gd.
Ball's Elements of Astronomy. 6t,
Barry's Bailway Appliances. 3. Gd.
Bauerman'B Systematic Mineralogy. Gf
Descriptive Mineralogy. 6i.
Blozam and Huntington's Metals. 5t,
G^lazebrook'g Physical Optics. &s.
Glazebrook and Shaw's Practical Physics. 6j.
Gore's Art of Electro-Metallurgy. 6.

Griffin'sAlgebra and Trigonometry, ds. 6d. Kotes and Solutions, 3t. 6d.
Holmes's The Steam Engine. Gs.
Jenkin's Electricity and Magnetism. 3s, Sd.
Maxwell's Theory of Heat. 3j. Gd.
Merrifield's Technical Arithmetic and Mensuration. 3^. 6d. Eey, 3^. Gd,
Miller's Inorganic Chemistry. 3s. 6d,
Preece and Sivewright's Telegraphy. 5*.
Butley's Study of Bocks, a Text-Book of Petrology. 4*. 6d.
Shelley's Workshop Appliances. 4s. Gd.
Thome's Structural and Physiological Botany. 6.
Thorpe's Quantitative Chemical Analysis. 4^. 6d, '

Thorpe and Muir's Qualitative Analysis. 3s. Gd,


Tilden's Chemical Philosophy. 3j. 6d. With Answers to Problems. 4j. Gd.

XJnwin's Elements of Machine Design, Gs.


Watson's Plane and Solid Geometry. 3s. Gd.

THE GREEK LANGUAGE.


Bloomfield's College and School Greek Testament. Fcp. Svo. 5s.

Bolland &
Lang's Politics of Aristotle. Post Svo. 7s. Gd.
CoUis'a Chief Tenses ot theGreek Irregular Verbs. Svo. 1*.
Pontes Gneci, Stepping-Stone to Greek Grammar. 12mo. 2s. Gd.
Praxis Gneca, Etymology. 12mo. 2s. Gd.
Greek Yerse-Book, Praxis lambica. 12mo. 4. 6d.
Fexrar's Brief Greek Syntax and Accidence. l2mo. is. Gd,
Greek Grammar Bules for Harrow School. 12mo. Is. Gd.
Geare's Notes on Thucydides. Book I. Fcp. Svo. 2*. Gd.
Hewitt's Greek Examination-papers. 12mo. 1*. Gd.
Isbister's Xenophon's Anabasis, Books I, to III. with Notes. 12mo. Ss. Gd.
Jerram's Graeo6 Beddenda, .Crown Svo. 1*. 6d.

London: LONGMANS, GEEEN, & CO.


14 A Selection of Educational Works.

Kennedy's Greek Grammar. 12mo. 4*. 6d.


Liddell& Scott's English-Greek Lexicon. 4to. 365, ; Square 12mo. 7. 6d.
Malmfly's Classical Greek Literature. Crown 8to. Poets, 7.ed. Prose "Writers,
7s. Bd,
Morris's Greek Lessons. Square 18mo. Part I. 3s. 6d. ; Part II. Is.
Parry's Elementary Greek Grammar. 12mo. Ss. Gd.
Plato's Republic, Book I. Greek Text, English Notes by Hardy. Crown 8vo. Ss.
Sheppard and Evans's Notes on Thucydides. Crown 8vo. 7s. 6d.
Thucydides, Book IV. with Notes by Barton and Chavasse. Crown 8to. 5s.
Valpy's Greek Delectus, improved by White. 12mo. 2s. Gd. Key, 2s. 6d,
White's Xenophon's Expedition of Cyrus, with English Notes. 12mo. 7s. Gd.
WilMns's Manual of Greek Prose Composition. Crown 8to. 5s. Key, 5s.
Exercises in Greek Prose Composition. Crown 8vo. 4j. Bd, Key, 2s. Gd.
New Greek Delectus. Crown 8vo. 3s. Gd. Key, 2s. Gd.
Progressive Greek Delectus. 12mo. 4. Key, 2s. Gd.
Progressive Greek Anthology. 12mo. 5s.
Scriptorea Attici, Excerpts with English Notes. Crown 8vo. 7s. Gd.
Speeches from Thucydides translated. Post 8vo. 6s.
Tonge'a English-Greek Lexicon, 4to. 21*. Square 12mo. 8*. Gd.
;

THE LATIN LANGUAGE.


Bradl^'s Latin Prose Exercises. 12mo. 3j. Gd. Key, 5s.
Continuous Lessons in Latin Prose. 12mo. 5*. Key, 5*. Gd.
Cornelius Nepos, improved by White. 12mo. 3*. Gd.
Eutropius, improved by White. 12mo. 2s. Gd.
Ovid's Metamorphoses, improved by White. 12mo. 4jt. Gd.
Select Fables of Phsedrue, improved by White. 12mo. 2s. Gd.
Colla's Chief Tenses of Latin Irregular Verbs. 8vo. la.
Pontes Latini, Stepping-Stone to Latin Grammar. 12mo. 3s. Gd.
Hewitt's Latin Examination-Papers. 12mo. 1*. Gd.
Isbister's Caesar, Books I.- VII, 12mo. 45. ; or with Reading Lessons, 4. 6dl.
Caesar's Commentaries, Books I.-V. 12mo. 3s. Gd.
First Book of Cseaar's GaUic War. 12mo. Is. Gd.
Jerram'a Latini Reddenda. Crown 8vo. \s. Gd.
Kennedy's Child's Latin Primer, or Pirst Latin Lessons. l2mo. 2s.
Child's Latin Accidence. 12mo. Is.
Elementary Latin Grammar. 12mo. 3s. Gd.
Elementary Latin Reading Book, or Tirocinium Latinum. ISmo. 2s.
Latin Prose, Paleestra Stili Latini. 12mo. Gs.
Latin Vocabulary. 12mo. 2s. Gd.
Subsidia Primaria, Exercise Books to the Public School Latin Primer,
I. Accidence and Simple Construction, 2s. Gd. II. Syntax, 3*. Gd.
Key to the Exercises in Subsidia Primaria, Parts I. and II. price 5*.
Subsidia Primaria, III. the Latin Compound Sentence. 12mo. 1*.
Oorrioulum Stili Latini. 12mo. 4*. Gd. Key, 7j. Gd.
Falaeatra Latina, or Secood Latin Reading Book. 12mo. 5s.

London: LONGMANS, GREEN, & CO.


A Selection of Educational Works. 15

Millington's Latin Prose Composition. Crown 8vo. 2s. 6d.


Selections from Latin Prose. Crown 8vo. 2s. 6(f.
Moody's Eton Latin Grammar. 12mo. 2*. 6d. The Accidence separately, 1*.
Morris's Elementa Latina. Fcp. 8vo. Is. 6d. Key, 2s. 6d.
Parry's Origines Eomanae, from Livy, witli English Notes. Crown 8vo. 43.
The Public School Latin Primer. 12mo. 2s. 6d.

Grammar, by Bev. Dr. Kennedy. Post 8vo. 7s. 6(i.
Prendexgast's Mastery Series, Manual of Latin. l2mo. 2s. 6(2.
Bapier's Introduction to Composition of Latin Verse. 12mo. Ss. Gd. Key, 2s. Gd,
Sheppard and Turner's Aids to Classical Study. 12mo, &s. Key, Gs.
Valpys Latin Delectus, improved by White. 12mo. 2s. Gd. Key, 3*. Gd.
Virgil's .^neid, translated into English Verse by Conington. Crown 8vo. 9s.
Works, edited by Kennedy. Crown 8vo. IOj. Gd.
translated into English Prose by Conington. Crown 8vo. 9s.
Walford's Progressive Exercises in Latin Elegiac Verse. 12mo. 2s. Gd. Key, 5*.
Wbite and Riddle's Large Latin-English Dictionary. 1 vol. 4to. 21^.
White's Concise Latin-Eng. Dictionary for University Students. Royal 8vo. 12j.
Junior Students* 'Eng.-'La.t. & Lat.-Eng. Dictionary. Square 12mo. 5s.
qotkh-o+^Itt i
"^^ Latin-English Dictionary, price 3s.
iseparareiy
^ ,j,^^
English-Latin Dictionary, price Zs.

Tonge's Latin Gradus, Post 8vo. 9*. ; or with Appendix, 12*.

WHITE'S GRAMMAR-SCHOOL GREEK TEXTS.


^sop (Fables) & Palsephatus (Myths). Xenophon, Book I. without Vocabu-
32mo. Is. lary. 3d.
Euilpldes, Hecuba. 2s. St. Matthew's and St. Luke's Gospels,
Homer, Iliad, Book I. Is. 25. Gd. each.
Odyssey, Book I. Is. St. Mark's and St. John's
Gospels,
Lucian, Select Dialogues. 1*. Is, Gd. each.
Xenophon, Anabasis, Books I. III. IV. The Acts of the Apostles. 2s. Gd.
V. & VI. 1*. Gd. each ; Book II. Is. ; St. Paul's Epistle to the Bomans. Is.Gd
Book VII. 2s.
The Four Gospels in Greek, with Greek-English Lexicon. Edited by John T,
White, D.D. Oxon. Square 32mo. price 6*.

WHITE'S GRAMMAR-SCHOOL LATIN TEXTS.


Cffisar.Gallic War, Books I. & II. V. Nepos, Miltiades, Simon, Pauaanias,
& VI. 1*. each. Book I. without Aristides. 9d.
Vocabulary, 3d. Ovid. Selections from Epistles and
Ctesax, Gallic War, Books III, & IV. Fasti. Is,
Ovid, Select Myths from Metamor-
Cffisar, Gallic War, Book VII. 1*. Gd. phoses. 9d.
Cicero, Cato Major (Old Age). 1*. Gd. Phaedrus, Select Easy Fables,
Cicero, Laslins (Friendship). Is. Gd. PhsBdms, Fables, Books I. U. U. &
Eutropins, Roman Histoiy, Books I. Sallust, Bellum Catilinarium. lA Gd.
& n. 1. Books m.
& IV. Is. Virgil, Georgics, Book IV. Is.
HDrace,Odes, Books I. II. & IV. 1*. each. Virgil, ^neid, Books I. to VI. is. each.
Horace, Odes, Book III. Is. Gd. Book I. without Vocabulary, Sd.
Horace, Epodes and Carmen Seculare. Virgil, ^neid, Books VTL VIII. X.
XLXn. U
6d. each.

London: LONGMANS, GREEN, & CO.


.

16 A Selection of Educational Works.

THE FRENCH LANGUAGE.


Albita*B How to Speak French. Fop. Sto. 5s. 6d.
Instantaneous Frencli Exercises. Fcp. 2s. Key, 2s.
Gassal's French Genders. Grown Sto. 3s. Sd.
Oassal &
Earcher's G-raduated French Translation Book. Fart I. Zs. Gd.
Part Key to Part I. by Professor Oassal, price 5s.
II. 5j,
Gontanseau*s Practical French and English Dictionary. Post Sto. 3. Bd.
Pocket French and English Dictionary. Square ISmo. If. 6(2.
, Premi&res Lectures. 12mo. 2s. 6d.
First Step in French. 12ino. 2a. Qd. Key, St.
French Accidence. 12mo. 2t. Gd.
Grammar. 12mo. 4*. Key, 3s,
Gontanseau's Middle-Olass French Course. Fcp. 8to. :
Accidence, 8d. French Translation-Book, 8(2.
Syntax, 8d. Easy French Delectus, 8d.
French GonTersation-Book, Bd. First French Header, 8(2,
First French Exercise-Book, Bd. Second French Beader, 8d.
Second French Exercise-Book, Bd. French and English Dialogues, 8
Contanseau's Guide to French Translation. 12mo. 3^. 6d. Key 3^. Gd,
Prosateurs et Fortes Fran^ais. 12mo. 5s.
Precis de la litt^rature Fran^aise. 12mo. 3s. 6(2.
Abr6g6 de rHlstoire de France. 12mo. 2s. Gd.
F^rars Chouans et Bleus, with Notes by C. Sankey, M.A, Fcp. 8to. 2s. Bd.
Jerxam's Sentences for Translation into French. Gr. Sto. Is. Key, 2s. Bd.
Prendergast's Mastei*y Series, French, 12mo. 2s. Bd.
Souvestre's Philosophe sous les Toita, by Sti&Tenard. Square ISmo. 1*. Bd.
Stepping-Stone to French Pronunciation. ISmo. Is.
Sti&Tenard's Lectures Franpaises from Modem Authors. 12mo. 4s. Bd
Rules and Exercises on the French Language. 12mo. 3s. Bd,
TarTer's Eton French Grammar. 12mo. Bs. Bd.

THE GERMAN LANGUAGE.


Blackley's Practical German and English
Dictionary. Post Sto. St. Bd.
Bnchheim's German Poetry, for Repetition. ISmo. li. Bd.
Collis's Card of German Irregular Verbs. Sto, 2t.
Fischer-Flschart's Elementary German Grammar. Fcp. Sto. 2*. Bd,
Just's German Grammar. 12mo. Is. Bd.
German Beading Book. 12mo. 3;. Bd.
Longman's Pocket G^e^man and English Dictionary. Square ISmo. 2*. Bd.
Naftel's Elementary German Course for Public Schools. Fcp. 8to.
German Accidence. 9d. German Prose Composition Book. 9d.
German Syntax. -Sd. First German Reader. 9d.
First German Exercise-Book. 9d. Second German Reader. 9<2.
Second German Exercise-Book. 9d.
Prendergast's Mastery Series, German. 12mo. 2s. Bd.
Quick's Essentials of German. Crown Sto. 3s, Bd.
Selss's School Edition of Goethe's Faust. Crown 8to. 5*.
Outline of German Literature. Crown Sto. 4*. Bd.
Wirth's German Ohit-Chat. Grown 8to. 2t. Bd.

London: LONGMANS, GREEN, & CO.

J^ottUwoode Js Co. PHnterSt New-street Square^ London.

Você também pode gostar