Você está na página 1de 17

Journal of Pragmatics 38 (2006) 321337

www.elsevier.com/locate/pragma

Contextualization in translator- and


interpreter-mediated events
Mona Baker
Centre for Translation and Intercultural Studies, University of Manchester,
Oxford Road, Manchester M13 9PL, UK
Received 10 February 2005; received in revised form 19 April 2005; accepted 19 April 2005

Abstract
The notion of context has been extensively invoked but rarely critiqued and elaborated in the study of
translation and interpreting. This paper first explores recent thinking on the notions of context and
contextualization in pragmatics and linguistic anthropology and examines the extent to which these notions
have explicitly or implicitly informed current thinking on translation and interpreting. It then argues that
closer attention to processes of contextualization in both the production and reception of translated texts and
interpreted utterances can tell us much more about the goals and ideological positioning of participants than
any static listing of contextual variables, however detailed and comprehensive. The discussion is supported
by various examples of the way in which translators and interpreters frame their interaction with others.
# 2005 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.

Keywords: Translation; Interpreting; Power; Contextualization

Most of the central notions in the study of translation at least the most illuminating have
always been rather elusive and difficult to pin down. This reflects the highly complex nature of
the translation act. Like the very material in which it mostly takes shape, namely language, the act
of translation is deeply embedded in wider social and cultural practices.
During periods and within scholarly traditions in which researchers focused on the internal
mechanisms of language, the analysis of translation and interpreting events seemed relatively
straightforward, if not particularly illuminating. The exclusive focus on internal mechanisms
could not continue for long, however, and as scholars of both language and translation
increasingly acknowledge the dynamic and negotiable aspects of both phenomena, they find that
they inevitably have to draw on more fluid notions such as context, culture, power and ideology.

E-mail address: mona.baker@manchester.ac.uk.

0378-2166/$ see front matter # 2005 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.
doi:10.1016/j.pragma.2005.04.010
322 M. Baker / Journal of Pragmatics 38 (2006) 321337

Many have attempted to address the question of what the concept of culture means and how it
impacts on translational behaviour; Katan (1999/2004) is the most recent and extensive
treatment of this issue. Others have tried to tackle the notion of ideology in similar ways; the
most recent treatment is by Calzada Perez (2003). Very few have addressed the notion of power,
among them Tymoczko (2000:3134) and Tymoczko and Gentzler (2002). Yet, although the
notion of context is routinely invoked in much of the literature on translation and interpreting, it
is hardly ever subjected to scrutiny in its own right. In fact, no scholarly publication within
linguistics or translation studies has yet attempted to explore the issue of context as it impacts
on translational behaviour in any depth.1 Even Hickey (1998), the only collection dedicated to
the interface between translation and pragmatics, fails to address the issue of context in any
detail or theorize it explicitly, except as part of the application of relevance theory in the article
by Gutt (1998).
Within the limited scope of this paper, I will first outline a range of perspectives on context as
elaborated in the recent literature in pragmatics and linguistic anthropology and offer examples
of the various ways in which these perspectives relate to translation research and practice. My
main interest ultimately lies in describing some of the active processes of contextualization in
which translators and interpreters engage or to which they have to respond, and such processes
are discussed and exemplified in the second part of the article. Rather than focusing on static
descriptions of various components of context, I will argue, it is far more productive to examine
contextualization as a dynamic process of negotiation and one that is constrained by the uneven
distribution of power which characterizes all exchanges in society, including those that are
mediated by translators and interpreters.
I start with the following broad distinctions in an attempt to explore the usefulness of
various conceptions of context to the study of translation and interpreting: (1) cognitive versus
social/interactive definitions of context; (2) static versus dynamic models and the shift from
context to contextualization; and finally (3) neutral versus power-sensitive definitions of
context.2

1. Cognitive versus social/interactive definitions of context

The notion of context has variously been conceptualized as an abstract, psychological


construct that exists within rather than outside, or independently of, the mind of the language
user, or as a concrete set of entities and parameters in the real world that allow us to make sense of
verbal exchanges in actual instances of interaction.
Proponents of a cognition-driven approach argue that contexts as such are not social
situations but mental constructs (Van Dijk, 2001a:582), that they are not out there, but in
here: They are mental constructs of participants (Van Dijk, 2001b:18).3 This is the approach

1
There have of course been some excellent attempts at exploring the notion of context in socio-pragmatics, linguistic
anthropology and applied linguistics; see, especially, Auer and di Luzio (1992), Duranti and Goodwin (1992), Malmkjr
and Williams (1998) and Dilley (1999). But none have addressed the issue in relation to translation and/or interpreting.
2
Needless to say, the literature abounds with other types of distinction. Akman and Bazzanella (2003), for example,
distinguish between local and global notions of context, the former relating to the immediate structural environment
(context of the ongoing interaction) and the latter to external components of context. This is similar to Schegloffs (1992)
distinction between proximate and distal variables of context. My first distinction between cognitive and social/
interactional definitions of context is closer to Linells (1998) distinction between cognitive and situational contexts.
3
Cf. the more anthropological and hermeneutic formulation by Holy (1999:50): the context of the phenomenon does
not exist out there for us to grasp but is itself, like the meaning, the result of our interpretation.
M. Baker / Journal of Pragmatics 38 (2006) 321337 323

adopted by the proponents of relevance theory, one of the few theories of pragmatics to have been
applied in detail to the study of translation. Sperber and Wilson (1986/1995:15) insist that [a]
context is a psychological construct, a subset of the hearers assumptions about the world. It is
these assumptions . . . rather than the actual state of the world, that affect the interpretation of
an utterance. When Gutt (1990, 1991, 1996, 1998, 2000) applies this conception of context in
his writing on translation, what he ultimately takes as a point of departure in his analysis is not
some readily identifiable and stable social reality but the assumptions of target readers. These
assumptions are not out there for translators to recover; they are a product of our own
cognitive processes, but they do guide us in making decisions about how to render a text from
one language and social context into another. Ultimately, the question is one of interpretation,
not of verifiable reality against which the truth or falsehood of a translation may be judged
(Gutt, 2000:233):
the focus of relevance-theory based translation is on the comparison of interpretations, not
on the reproduction of words, linguistic constructions or textual features.
A cognitive view of context, then, will tend to draw a relatively clear line between what is in
the world and what is in the mind of the language user or translator, stressing that it is the
language users assumptions about what is in the world, rather than what is actually in the world
(assuming we have a reliable way of establishing the latter), that influences the way language is
used and the kind of inferences that are drawn in a given situation. Thus, cognition-oriented
definitions of context encourage us to see translational behaviour as motivated by a series of
ultimately unverifiable assumptions on the part of the translator. And in this sense they are fairly
similar to postmodern literary approaches which describe translation as a process by which the
chain of signifiers that constitutes the source-language text is replaced by a chain of signifiers in
the target language which the translator provides on the strength of an interpretation (Venuti,
1995:17; emphasis added). The two approaches, however, differ markedly in terms of their resort
to the notion of intention. Gutts cognitive orientation does not preclude him from speaking of
the correct, that is, speaker-intended, interpretation of an utterance (1998:49). Venuti and
other scholars working within the postmodern literary tradition rarely, if ever, invoke the notion
of intention in their discussions of translation.
Approaches that focus exclusively on social/interactive parameters, on the other hand,
traditionally saw context in terms of a series of pre-existing entities and relations in the real
world. The best known and one of the most elaborate is Hymes SPEAKING model: Situation,
Participants, Ends (outcomes and goals), Act sequence (form and content), Key,
Instrumentalities (channels & forms of speech), Norms of interaction, and Genres. Hymes
purpose in elaborating the notion of context in these terms is to stress that the linguistic form on
its own supports a whole range of meanings, but in any given context (understood in terms of the
SPEAKING model) many of these meanings are eliminated or downplayed (Hymes, 1964). In
other words, the context restricts the range of relevant meanings of the form. On the other hand, a
given context may support a whole range of meanings, and these in turn are restricted by the form
used. Ultimately, Hymes was attempting to illuminate the process by which the actions of
participants, including their verbal behaviour, interact in a given situation with social structures
such as norms and genres to guide our interpretation of discourse.
This type of framework has been drawn on fairly extensively in translation studies, where
scholars have sometimes found it useful to draw up a map of the context of situation of the source
and target texts to anticipate potential problems in translation. Nord (1991) is a good example of
this trend, as is much of the extensive literature on bible translation. Houses (1981, 1997) well-
324 M. Baker / Journal of Pragmatics 38 (2006) 321337

Fig. 1. Sample header file from TEC corpus.

known dimensions of language user and language use, which are employed to assess the quality
of translation, offer another variant on this approach. Indeed, the application of systemic
functional linguistics with its specific take on the context of situation (in terms of field, tenor and
mode), which is ultimately a more elaborate instantiation of Hymes model, has informed much
work in translation studies, including Bell (1991) and House (1981, 1997). More recently, House
(2002 and this volume) specifically described her empirically derived modes of translation
covert translation and overt translation as two fundamentally different types of
contextualization (2002:97). In another relatively recent development in translation studies,
we can see the same general conception of context being applied in corpus-based research. For
example, the header files that document extra-linguistic information on individual texts in the
Translational English Corpus,4 as described in Laviosa (1997) and Baker (1999), are in some
respects instantiations of Hymes SPEAKING model or some variant of it, specifically giving
details of situation and participants (see Fig. 1).
To my mind, the two approaches cognitive and social/interactive are not mutually
exclusive but can be applied at the same time, with varying degrees of emphasis, quite
productively. For instance, we might want to explore how thinking of translation itself as a genre

4
TEC is the largest computerized collection of translated texts anywhere in the world, currently around 10 million
words in size. It consists of contemporary translations into English from a variety of source languages, and is divided into
four sub-corpora: fiction, biography, newspapers and inflight magazines. See http://ronaldo.cs.tcd.ie/tec/jnlp/.
M. Baker / Journal of Pragmatics 38 (2006) 321337 325

(the last component of Hymes SPEAKING model) and situating this conception within a
broader social framework may help explain the extent to which readers expect multiple cultural
environments and voices to be invoked in a translationand in turn how translators own
assumptions about such patterns of expectation may guide their decision-making process. Brief
references to this potential line of research can be found in the literature, albeit very occasionally
and largely only in passing, as in the following statement by Weizman and Blum-Kulka
(1987:72):
. . . it seems that the identification of a text as a translation, which is a meta-linguistic
process in essence, protects the reader, as it were, from misinterpreting the writers
intentions. As is well-known, when looking for the implicit or indirect meanings of a text,
the reader assumes that the writer indeed intended to convey them. The identification
of a text as a translation product implies that deviations from cultural norms are not
judged as intentional, and therefore are not assigned any hidden meanings. In this
respect, the perception of translationese plays a significant role in the process of text
interpretation.
There is also evidence in the literature (e.g. Shlesinger, 1989) that court interpreters tend to
correct witnesses who sound confused, most probably because they believe this confusion may
be interpreted by other participants as an indication of their own incompetence. This type of
behaviour, as well as Weizman and Blum-Kulkas argument above, further support the
cognitive view of context in that they suggest that we respond not to the context as it is in the
world but to what we perceive as other participants intentions as well as assumptions about the
world.

2. Static versus dynamic models of context

Thinking of context as a process of interaction between linguistic form and elements of the
situation as outlined in Hymes model can help account for creativity in language use. It is not
the newness of words and structures that make an utterance creative (almost all our utterances
are highly repetitive in this respect); creativity in language, and hence in translation, is more a
question of the ability of the language user or translator to produce new meanings by extending
the resources of language to new contexts of situation. However, defining context as a list of
components of the type outlined by Hymes in his SPEAKING model or Scollon and Scollon
(1995:2223) in their grammar of context suffers from serious limitations. The most serious
weakness is that the components and entities are often treated as static phenomena that exist in
a fairly stable environment which the analyst can simply document and use to generate an
analysis of events and behaviour. For example, a participant is traditionally assumed to have a
stable identity throughout the interaction, whereas more recent approaches in socio-pragmatics
and linguistic anthropology would prefer to treat all elements of context as at least having the
potential to shift and develop during the course of an event, to both shape and be shaped by the
ongoing interaction. Another obvious problem with this approach is that such open-ended
lists suggest that the components are coordinate and independent, and they leave us with the
nagging uncertainty of never knowing whether the list is complete or whether yet more
components are needed (Hanks, 1992:47). A third problem concerns the difficulty of deciding
which of the components on the list are relevant for the interpretation of a particular speech
event. This is partly a question of whether we treat the components as static, taking the analysts
classification of the event as a given, or follow the perspective of the participants and find ways
326 M. Baker / Journal of Pragmatics 38 (2006) 321337

of establishing what they see as relevant by paying attention to those features that they
themselves seem to attend to.
In terms of gender or profession for instance (if we were to consider either or both as aspects of
a participants profile), neither would be treated as purely a given within a dynamic conception
of context: we perform our gender, we step in and out of professional and other roles numerous
times during the course of a single conversation, and therefore, whether a participant behaves and
responds as a woman, as a gay person, as a doctor, or as a professional interpreter at any moment
depends on a variety of factors and can change during the course of a single interaction. Consider
how a community interpreter will often shift back and forth between playing out the role of
professional interpreter and other participant roles in a communication. In the following
example, a community interpreter clearly switches into a different role that of a caring adult as
she tries to comfort Clara, a 7-year-old child who is about to receive an injection (Wadensjo,
1992:159):

Interpreter: I can sit I can be here. (.) yes. Clara, you know how many children
I have seen already. whove had it done. and I havent seen a single
one that . . . you know what. there have been those who cried like you.
and afterwards they were so surprised that it was all over. this is what
they say. is that all:::?

The required norm in interpreting is for the pronoun I to be strictly reserved for the
speaker. But the interpreter here speaks in her own voice, not in her professional capacity as
interpreter. It is not at all unusual for community interpreters to alternate between their
professional and other roles in this way. Similar examples from a different domain can be
found in Katan and Straniero-Sergio (2001), who discuss the shifting alignments of media
interpreters in the context of talkshows on Italian television. Here are two particularly
interesting demonstrations of the way in which an interpreter in this context switches
participant roles in response to the unfolding dynamics of the show. English back-translations
are provided in square brackets.
In the first example, the interpreter (Olga Fernando) signals the switch in participant roles
clearly:

Guest: I must say one thing


Interpreter: posso dire una cosa? [May I say something?]
Guest: She is very shaken (pointing to Olga Fernando)
Interpreter: io s- . . . sta dicendo che (.) linterprete (.) io e un po sconvolta
adesso spieghera perche [I sh- . . . shes saying that (.) the interpreter
(.) me is a little shaken shell explain why now]
Guest: Before the show we were sitting here and I said to (.) Olga who is
that lady there?
Interpreter: prima dellinizio dello spettacolo eravamo seduti qui e Rose ha
chiesto a me parlo in prima persona adesso chi era quella signora
[before the beginning of the show we were sitting here and Rose
asked me Im speaking in the first person now who was that lady?]

(Maurizio Costanzo Show, Canale 5, 14.05.1998; adapted from Katan and Straniero-Sergio,
2001:232233)
M. Baker / Journal of Pragmatics 38 (2006) 321337 327

In the next example, it is not entirely clear whether the interpreter has switched roles or not,
and there is some confusion about the referent of the pronoun I. The guest in this case is Asha
Philips, the author of Saying No: Why Its Important for You and Your Child:

Guest: but I think culturally (.) because a lot of us I think were (.) young
teenagers in the sixties (.) we find it very difficult (.) to:: ehm agree
to and to find a structure and rules that we dont want to fight
against ourselves
Interpreter: poiche (.) noi eravamo==adolescenti (.) molti di noi erano adolescenti
negli anni sessanta (.) eh parlo anche per me per noi e difficile
immaginarci (.) di strutturare ehm il= [because (.) we were==
adolescents (.) many of us were adolescent in the sixties (.) eh Im
speaking also for myself here (.) for us its difficult to imagine
ourselves (.) structuring ehm the=]
Host: beati voi [Lucky you (pl.) referring to being adolescent in the
sixties; notice in particular the plural you]
Interpreter: =nostro atteggiamento (.) in modo tale da dire no senza sentirci poi
a nostra volta ribelli contro questa struttura [= our behaviour (.) in
such a way as to say no without becoming rebels against this
structure]

(Maurizio Costanzo Show, Canale 5, 30.3.2000; adapted from Katan and Straniero-Sergio,
2001:233)

There are many such examples in the literature and in real life, which highlight the dynamic
nature of every aspect of the interpreting event. Translation studies scholars would therefore do
well to adapt their methods of analysis to allow for the fact that participants in a translation event
can themselves define rather than simply respond to the context that is sometimes assumed to
surround them statically. And of course they can use language itself to do so.
Duranti and Goodwin (1992:5) stress that the dynamic mutability of context is complicated
further by the ability of participants to rapidly invoke within the talk of the moment alternative
contextual frames. Indeed this is one of the key insights provided by Gumperzs notion of
contextualization cues, which he uses to refer to speakers and listeners use of verbal and
non-verbal signs to relate what is said at any one time and in any one place to knowledge acquired
through past experience, in order to retrieve the presuppositions they must rely on to maintain
conversational involvement and assess what is intended (Gumperz, 1992:230). Contextualiza-
tion, within the Gumperzian framework, is achieved by means of cues at the levels of prosody,
paralinguistic signs, code choice, and choice of lexical forms or formulaic expressions
(1992:231). Other examples include code switching, the use of italics in writing, and discourse
markers such as lets be serious now. When Venuti describes how at various points in his
translation of Tarchettis Fosca he alternated between British and American spelling or made
the combination of various lexicons more jarring to remind the reader that he or she is reading a
translation in the present (1998:17), he offers us a good example of the use of code switching as
a contextualization cue in translation. According to Gumperz (1992:232), contextualization cues
serve to highlight, foreground or make salient certain interpretations or aspects of the
communicative situation. We can safely assume that translators and interpreters make as much
use of this dynamic aspect of interaction as everyone else.
328 M. Baker / Journal of Pragmatics 38 (2006) 321337

Other examples of the dynamic process of contextualization include the way in which
interpreters sometimes adopt linguistic strategies to redefine the context in which they are
delivering their services, to make it clear to other participants such as defendants and their
families in court that they are not to be held responsible for certain statements, i.e. that these
statements do not represent their own views or wishes, perhaps as a way of protecting themselves
from potential backlash when a harsh sentence is passed by the judge or an aggressive question
posed by an attorney. Thus, as Berk-Seligson (1990:116) points out, when the judge says
something like I am now remanding you to the authority of the federal marshalls, interpreters
will tend to render this either as Yo, el juez (I, the judge), to make it absolutely clear who the I
refers to, or alternatively, they will use the noun phrase El juez by itself, thereby referring to the
judge entirely in the third person. Another example, also from Berk-Seligson (1990:114115),
illustrates the use of different linguistic means to realize the same pragmatic strategy of
recontextualizing the utterance to avoid the I of the speaker being confused with the I of the
interpreter and hence holding the latter responsible for the utterance:

Attorney: As Ive indicated, the defendant has pleaded not guilty.


Interpreter: Como se ha indicado el defendientee se ha declarado no culpable
en esas acusaciones. [as has been indicated]

It is worth stressing again that none of the schematic approaches outlined here necessarily rules
out the other perspectives. It is ultimately a question of emphasis. Thus, for example, while Basco
et al. (2004) focus on elaborating categories of context and in that sense may be seen to approach the
issue from a static, taxonomic perspective, they nevertheless embed their description within the
dynamic notion of a behaviour game. Moreover, they clearly inject their description with a
dynamic view of context that acknowledges the agency of participants when they argue that
The recognition of the behavior game bid by the speaker does not bind the hearer to play a
particular role in the game. On the contrary, the hearer can decide to accept or reject the
proposed game, or to propose a different one, or to negotiate a specific one. (2004:471)
Similarly, an approach can be both cognitive and dynamic, as in the work of Van Dijk, who
stresses that context models are not static mental representations, but dynamic structures. They
are ongoingly constructed and reconstructed by each participant in an event (2001b:18). I would
therefore argue that adopting a dynamic approach to context in the study of translation and
interpreting does not mean that we do not need access to the type of ethnographic/extra-linguistic
information documented in the TEC header in Fig. 1, for instance, because in order for the
researcher to appreciate whether someone is doing or performing the role of interpreter or
friend or caring adult at any point, he or she first needs to know who the speaker is, in what
capacity they are engaged in the interaction, and so on. The idea, then, is not to throw lists of
apparently static situational components out altogether but to use them merely as a starting point
for analysis, to acknowledge that they are not all necessarily relevant in every context and, more
importantly, that every element is open to negotiation in the course of a given interaction.

3. Neutral versus power-sensitive definitions of context

With the exception of more nuanced positions such as Basco et al.s (2004), the various
conceptualizations of context that I have surveyed so far, including the dynamic notion of
contextualization cues, suggest a purely speaker-led form of communication as the norm,
M. Baker / Journal of Pragmatics 38 (2006) 321337 329

whereas it is of course not up to an individual participant alone to decide what is to count as


context at any moment. Hence, Goodwin and Duranti (1992:6), among others, stress that in so
far as the processes to which context is relevant are social and interactive, one partys proposals as
to what should constitute operative context might fail to achieve ratification by others since
context is a socially constituted, interactively sustained, time-bound phenomenon.
A related, and more important point, is that most treatments of context in the literature,
including Hymes and even Gumperz, imply that context is a neutral field or framework in which
we play out our social roles, and that in order to take control of it and shape it to our advantage all
we need to do is learn how to employ the appropriate contextualization cues.5 Lindstrom
(1992:103) explains that however plotted, these models of context often grant context an inert
neutrality: context is a neutral field for the play of speech events, or is the cumulation of cognitive
schemata that are cued to foreground past understanding. These models clearly fail to explain
much of what goes on in interaction. For example, as Shea (1994) points out, studies have shown
that the simple association of an Asian face with standard English speech can be enough to make
the speech of the Asian relatively incomprehensible to white US college students, which suggests
that, however well the Asian speaker might master the use of contextualization cues, he or she
remains seriously restricted in the way they are able to guide their interlocutors interpretations of
their behavior. In the specific context of translation and interpreting, I would argue that an
uncritical application of the notion of contextualization cues risks encouraging analysts and
participants in an interaction to use the translator or interpreter as a scapegoat, an easy source of
explanations for communication breakdown. The translator or interpreter can always be blamed
for failing to adjust contextualization cues to target norms of interaction, when more often than
not the failure or derailing of an interaction might lie in the cultural or political outlook of the
participants, or in the conflicting agendas they bring to the speech event.
Dilley (2003:453) asks [a]re the individuals captured in Afghanistan and now held at a US
base in Cuba to be identified as prisoners in the context of war or as criminals in the context of
criminal law?. His answer underlines the effect of power on determining what counts as context
at any moment: [t]he ability to define a context in a particular way or to initiate a set of
contextualizing moves in a particular direction can be constructed as a political act in the light of
other possible definitions or moves that could have been made (2003:453). Part of the power that
an interpreter can exert in certain situations derives from the fact that he or she is normally the only
participant with access to both languages and can therefore control the discourse to a large extent.
This power is eroded in situations where monitoring6 is possible and those doing the monitoring
are in a more powerful position than the interpreter (socially, professionally, ethnically, etc.). Here
is an example from court interpreting in the US, where many of the jurors and even the judge him- or
herself often have some command of Spanish (Berk-Seligson, 1990:213):

Juror: I understand the word La Vado I thought it meant restroom.


She translates it as bar.
Interpreter: In the first place, the jurors are not to listen to the Spanish but
to the English. I am a certified interpreter.
Juror: Youre an idiot.

5
See Shea (1994) for an excellent critique of Gumperz along these lines.
6
I refer specifically here to linguistic monitoring, i.e. situations where one or more of the participants in an event is not
linguistically handicapped and can therefore monitor the interpreters performance and potentially intervene to correct
him or her.
330 M. Baker / Journal of Pragmatics 38 (2006) 321337

Here, the interpreters attempt to shape the context in ways that suit her own understanding of
her role fails miserably, mainly because of the imbalance of power between her and other
participants in this interaction. Other examples of the power relations encoded in the context of
court interpreting concern the way in which court interpreters are prevented from seeing any
documents relating to a case prior to the hearings, and the fact that they are normally not allowed
to initiate turns or conversational sequences, except for the purpose of clarificationand very
sparingly in this case.
Turning to another domain of interpreting, a more sinister exercise of power in determining
the course of an interaction is evident at various points in Trevor McDonalds 1990 interview
with Saddam Hussein, analysed in Baker (1997). Here, the exercise of power is not as overtly
aggressive as in the example from Berk-Seligson above, but in real terms it is much more
stressful for the interpreter and restrictive of his ability to participate actively in shaping the
emerging context (adapted from Baker, 1997:121; back-translation from Arabic in square
brackets)7:

McDonald: Mr. President, these reports of atrocities you see are encouraged
by the fact that you have sealed Kuwait off from the rest of the
world. Why dont you let us go in and see for ourselves whether
these reports are true?
Saddam:
[You are right in part of what you say.]
Interpreter: Yes, youre right, youre partly right there.
Saddam (To Int.):
[In part of what you say.]
Interpreter: Partly right there.

In this excerpt, Saddam corrects the interpreter, making it clear that he expects a literal
rendering of what he says. He repeats to the interpreter in Arabic, emphasizing every word: In
part of what you say. The interpreter repeats (presumably to reassure him): Partly right there.
Saddams verbal instructions are accompanied by a stern look in the direction of the interpreter
(who is not shown on the screen at that point).
But power also shapes the context of interpretation in more subtle ways in translation and
interpreting, as in all instances of language use. One of its effects is to encourage the translator to
evoke narratives that have currency within the dominant target culture in order to give voice to
marginalized source-culture participants and enable a process of identification or empathy to
ensue. Some of the interventions by the subtitlers of Mohamed Bakris documentary Jenin Jenin,
released in 2002 following the Israeli incursions into the Jenin camp in the West Bank,8
demonstrate this quite clearly.
At one point in the documentary, an old Palestinian man expresses his shock at what happened
and the worlds apparent indifference and reluctance to intervene. He ends his contribution by

7
Saddam Hussein seems to have a good command of English and did not need Arabic translations of the questions
posed in English during that interview. But he answered in Arabic throughout, and the interpreter therefore only
interpreted his answers into English for the benefit of Trevor McDonald and the viewers.
8
And the ensuing international controversy over what happened and the extent of the damage and loss of life in
that area. Indeed, the term incursion itself was heavily contested in the media and by numerous pro-Palestinian
groups.
M. Baker / Journal of Pragmatics 38 (2006) 321337 331

saying, literally in Arabic, What can I say, by God, by God, our house/home9 is no longer a
house/home.

The subtitle for this frame is:


What can I say? Not even Vietnam was as bad as this.
In order to communicate the gravity of the situation to a world public whose conception of
gravity is conditioned by the political dominance of the US, the subtitlers recontextualize the
event by evoking a narrative which has moral resonances for those viewers. Indeed, the entire
documentary is subtitled in such a way as to improve the chances of American and world public
opinion, which is seen as holding the key to change in the area, empathizing with the Palestinian
population. The subtitlers, for example, largely avoid translating the Arabic word shaheed and all
its derivatives in the speech of Palestinian characters in the documentary into its standard
equivalent martyr, presumably to suppress the associations of Islamic fundamentalism, terrorism
and suicide bombing that this word readily evokes in the current political context, even though
many Arab speakers who use it, including Palestinians interviewed in this documentary, may be
totally opposed to any acts of violence on either side. Here is a typical example:
Original speech of Palestinian man:

[we have mentally retarded people who have been martyred; we have disabled people who
have been martyred; we have children who have been martyred; we have women who have
been martyred.]
English subtitles:
They killed some mentally disabled people, children and women in the camp.
In another shot, a Palestinian doctor describes how, as his area was being shelled by Israeli planes
during the first intifada, he tended to many injured people and managed to save many lives, only
to discover when the shelling stopped that his own son had been shot and was lying somewhere
nearby bleeding to death. In one frame, he explains that when the shelling stopped he heard some
of his neighbours shouting:

[Ameed [his son] has been martyred, Ameed has been martyred].
The subtitles read as follows:
After the cease-fire the neighbors
started shouting that Ameed
my son was dead

9
The Arabic word used (beitbeitna ma saar beit) can mean both house (in the physical sense) and home, with all
the connotations of the latter. It cannot, however, as in English, index a homeland or country.
332 M. Baker / Journal of Pragmatics 38 (2006) 321337

Thus, the effects of power and dominance are always inscribed within processes of
(re)contextualization. The dominant party generally dictates the terms of contextualization;
even when the marginalized participant decides to contest the context as it were, they
ultimately do so largely within the terms set by the dominant party. The tragedy of Jenin has to
be compared to Vietnam, rather than any of the other tragedies suffered by other parts of the
world in the recent past, in order to become meaningful in the context of American political
dominance. But participants in most types of interaction are not totally powerless, and
dominance is hardly ever absolute. In this context, the subtitlers could have evoked a more
recent event which has even more currency among the target viewers, namely 9/11, but in
opting for Vietnam they simultaneously identify the dominant political power as aggressor and
perpetrator of violence even as the Jenin tragedy is recontextualized in terms that are relevant
to that power.

4. Contextualizing translation

Holy (1999:48) states that [c]ontext is and always has been the key anthropological
concept. The same could be said of translation and interpreting, except that translation
scholars have so far largely ignored the obvious centrality of the notion of context to their own
discipline and failed to grant it sufficient scholarly attention. The question, of course, is what
form this scholarly attention might productively take. We could, for instance, spend
considerable time trying to enumerate all the possible elements that constitute context in any
type of translational event and the various ways in which these elements constrain the behavior
(linguistic and non-linguistic) of translators and interpreters. But this approach can only take
us so far. The problem is that the same complexity which makes context a powerful device
both in knowledge and cognition . . . make[s] context difficult to define and study formally
(Akman and Bazzanella, 2003:322). More importantly, as Holy (1999:50) explains, [t]he
difficulties of specifying precisely what constitutes the relevant context and of marking the
contexts boundary, arise from the fact that the specification of the context is itself the result of
interpretation.
Instead of treating context as a constraint, a set of restrictions on what we can or
cannot achieve in translation and other communicative events, and setting out to specify
the numerous facets of that constraint, it might ultimately be more productive to recog-
nize context as a resource, something that we selectively and strategically construct as we
engage in any act of communication, including the act of translation. This suggests both
an emphasis on the dynamic and ever changing nature of context and directing our attention
to the strategic processes of contextualization in which translators and interpreters
engage.
In terms of the dynamic nature of context, for example, a given source text will often have a
thicker and possibly very different context in the target culture, partly through the sheer
passing of time and the ensuing change in social and political environments. With the passage
of time, a literary or scholarly text will have accumulated critical response and resonances,
and both it and its translation(s) will be read and interpreted in a different contextpolitically,
culturally, socially, aesthetically. Jones (2004) raises a related and important ethical issue. In
deciding to translate the work of the Serbian author Vasko Popa during the war against Bosnia
in the 1990s, he was concerned that Popa drew on Serbian atavistic images . . . such as the
Kosovo myth or the figure of the wolf as tribal totem (2004:719). Jones explains that Popa
invoked these images positively in order to explore his cultural roots in an age (the 1970s)
M. Baker / Journal of Pragmatics 38 (2006) 321337 333

when such explorations were relatively untainted (2004:719). The question Jones poses as a
translator who has to take an ethical decision is whether a text can remain untainted by its
social context (2004:723), in this case the racially and ethnically torn Yugoslavia of the
1990s. The answer, I believe, is that it cannot, unless a serious effort is made to
recontextualize the text in question. The success or failure of any such attempt at
recontextualization will depend on many factors, most of which will be beyond the control of
the translator as a single and not particularly powerful participant. I would nevertheless argue
that such attempts at (re)contextualization are ultimately what we should be directing our
attention to, and that processes of contextualization are far more revealing than any set of
contextual constraints we might want to enumerate and describe in detail.
Holy (1999:53) argues that meanings are subject to manipulation. And so are contexts
because if meanings are intrinsically context-dependent, any manipulation of meaning
involves, perforce, manipulation of its contextualization. More specifically, Mey (2003:332)
draws our attention to the problem of an ambiguous utterance being wrongly interpreted
in contexts that are decisive for the life or death of the utterer and, I would add, that play
an important part in heightening political or racial tension. A productive engagement with
the notions of context and contextualization in the study of translation must be able to address
the politics of context definition (Dilley, 2003:440) and explain how and why different
parties to an interaction contextualize events and expressions in specific ways. A recent
example from the so-called war on terror demonstrates how such processes of
contextualization work in practice.
On 29 October 2004, in the thick of the US elections, Al-Jazeera aired a tape from Osama
Bin Laden in Arabic. Its translation into English has been widely contested, especially the
translation of a keyword used towards the end of the tape. The Arabic word wilaya can, in
principle, mean either state in the sense of nation/country or state in the modern day sense of
electoral region. Al-Jazeera translators opted broadly for the first sense, while the translators of
MEMRI, a neo-conservative media institute which specializes in translating selected Arabic
documents for Western consumption, opted for the second sense. Here are the two translations,
respectively:
Translation 1 (Al-Jazeera)10

In conclusion, I tell you in truth, that your security is not in the hands of Kerry, nor Bush,
nor al-Qaida. No.

Your security is in your own hands. And every state that doesnt play with our security has
automatically guaranteed its own security.
Translation 2 (MEMRI)11
Your security is not in the hands of Kerry or Bush or Al-Qaida. Your security is in your
own hands, and any [U.S.] state [wilaya]12 that does not toy with our security automatically
guarantees its own security.

10
http://english.aljazeera.net/NR/exeres/79C6AF22-98FB-4A1C-B21F-2BC36E87F61F.htm.
11
http://memri.org/bin/articles.cgi?Page=archives&Area=sd&ID=SP81104.
12
Square brackets and italics in original.
334 M. Baker / Journal of Pragmatics 38 (2006) 321337

Shortly after MEMRI posted and publicized its version of the speech, other web sites and news
agencies began to circulate this version, without the qualifying brackets and the original Arabic
term, as in the following version posted on WorldNetDaily13:
Your security is not in the hands of Kerry or Bush or Al-Qaida. Your security is in your
own hands, and any U.S. state that does not toy with our security automatically guarantees
its own security.
MEMRI and other like-minded media outlets insisted that Bin Laden threatened each U.S.
state, [and] . . . offered an election deal to the American votersa sort of amnesty for states that
dont vote for Bush, and that [t]he U.S. media have mistranslated the words ay wilaya
(which means each U.S. state) to mean a country or nation other than the U.S. . . . while
in reality bin Ladens threat was directed specifically at each individual U.S. state.14 Juan Cole,
Professor of History at the University of Michigan and owner of the activist web site Informed
Comment (http://www.juancole.com) contested this interpretation15:

MEMRI is claiming that the word used for state . . . means state as in Rhode Island and
New Jersey.

But while they are right to draw attention to the oddness of the diction, their conclusion is
impossible.

Bin Laden says that such a state should not trifle with Muslims security. He cannot
possibly mean that he thinks Rhode Island is in a position to do so. Nor can he be referring
to which way a state votes, since he begins by saying that the security of Americans is not in
the hands of Bush or Kerry. He has already dismissed them as equivalent and irrelevant, in
and of themselves.
In contextualizing their interpretation of the potentially ambiguous word wilaya, MEMRI
chose to appeal to the immediate political and temporal context (the elections and timing of Bin
Ladens speech). Juan Cole, whose political views are very different from MEMRIs, chose to
invoke a range of very different aspects of the context. He first posits that there is a logical
problem with MEMRIs interpretation, by appealing partly to the immediate co-text (Bin Laden
says that the security of Americans is not in the hands of Kerry or Bush) and partly to our
knowledge of the world (a state like Rhode Island cannot possibly influence the security of
Muslims, only nation states can). These aspects of the context are not sufficient to support his
interpretation, however, since he has already acknowledged that Bin Ladens use of the word
wilaya is unusual, and he goes on to admit that
It is true that in modern standard Arabic, wilayah means state or province and that al-
Wilayaat al-Muttahaddah is the phrase used to translate United States. A state in the sense
of government or international power would more likely nowadays be dawlah or hukumah.
So he goes on to suggest that there are two possible explanations for bin Ladens diction here.
The first explanation is that Bin Laden is simply using a fundamentalist archaism. This
explanation invokes religious culture, linguistic culture, and history:

13
http://www.worldnetdaily.com/news/article.asp?ARTICLE_ID=41211.
14
http://www.worldnetdaily.com/news/article.asp?ARTICLE_ID=41211.
15
http://www.juancole.com/2004/11/bin-ladens-audio-threat-to-states.html.
M. Baker / Journal of Pragmatics 38 (2006) 321337 335

[Bin Laden] regularly uses archaisms. He has steeped himself in ancient, Koranic Arabic
and the sayings of the Prophet, and he and his fellow cultists in Kandahar developed a
peculiar subculture that rejected much of modernity.
...

In classical Arabic, a ruler is a wali, who then rules over a wilayah or walayah. Wilayah
can have connotations even in modern Arabic . . . of sovereignty and it can mean
government. Bin Laden is attempting to revive ways of thinking he maintains were
common among the first generation of Muslims, and to slough off centuries of
accretions.

The second explanation Juan Cole offers relates to aspects of the personal history of the
speaker (Bin Laden) and features of language contact, and further appeals to the specific political
context of Pakistan to support the argument:

The other possibility is that bin Laden has lived most of the past 25 years in Persian, Pashto,
and Urdu-speaking environments and that he occasionally lapses into nonstandard usage.
In Hindi-Urdu, I noticed that one meaning of vilayat is the metropole. At least in past
generations, people going from British India to the UK said they were going to vilayat.
More important, there is some evidence for fundamentalist Muslims using the word
wilayah or walayah to mean country. The Pakistani radical group Hizb al-Tahrir locates
itself in Walayah Pakistan, i.e., the country of Pakistan.

As can be seen from this example, the same event can be strategically placed in a number of
different contexts by different participants, depending on their relevant agendas. No model of
contextual components, however detailed and comprehensive, can on its own explain what is
happening here nor predict which of the two interpretations will be favored by any given
participant in an interaction that involves this text. But paying attention to the process of
contextualization itself can tell us a great deal about the goals of each participant and what they
hope to achieve by appealing to any set of contextual variables, given that contextualizing is a
form of social action (Dilley, 2003:440). The way people construct contexts for the same
phenomenon differs because of the differences in roles, interests, purposes and power of those
who do the contextualizing (Holy, 1999:57).

5. Conclusion

The past decade or so has witnessed a general shift in scholarly discourse away from static
concepts such as that of context and towards active processes of engagement, implied in notions
such as contextualization, which underline the fluidity of interaction and the fact that it is socially
and jointly constructed, partly in advance but also to a great extent at the point of interaction itself.
Similar shifts have been taking place in translation studies, for example away from static concepts
of equivalence and norms and towards recognition of the fact that the process of translation does not
consist of passive responses to cultural, social and aesthetic conventions but of active negotiation
among participants with shifting agendas and unequal levels of control over the interaction.
As we move towards a more explicit elaboration of how we engage in contextualizing
discourses in and about translation, as well as our ethical and social responsibilities as
translators, we would do well to acknowledge, as does Lindstrom (1992:102103), that . . .
336 M. Baker / Journal of Pragmatics 38 (2006) 321337

context is a field of power relations. It is not, however, a frozen field. . . . People can
occasionally say the unsayable. They can contest the context, by evoking available alternative
or competing discourses. This fluid, dynamic conceptualization of context should prove
empowering for translators and scholars of translation, as well as more responsive to the
political and cultural realities of what is proving to be one of the most conflictual phases of
world history.

References

Akman, Varol, Bazzanella, Carla, 2003. The complexity of context: guest editors introduction. Journal of Pragmatics 35,
321329.
Auer, Peter, di Luzio, Aldo (Eds.), 1992. The Contextualization of Language. John Benjamins, Amsterdam.
Baker, Mona, 1997. Non-cognitive constraints and interpreter strategies in political interviews. In: Simms, Karl (Ed.),
Translating Sensitive Text: Linguistic Aspects. Rodopi, Amsterdam, pp. 113131.
Baker, Mona, 1999. The role of corpora in investigating the linguistic behaviour of professional translators. International
Journal of Corpus Linguistics 4, 281298.
Basco, Francesca M., Bucciarelli, Monica, Bara, Bruno G., 2004. The fundamental context categories in understanding
communicative intention. Journal of Pragmatics 36, 467488.
Bell, Roger, 1991. Translation and Translating: Theory and Practice. Longman, London and New York.
Berk-Seligson, Susan, 1990. The Bilingual Courtroom: Court Interpreters in the Judicial Process. The University of
Chicago Press, Chicago and London.
Calzada Perez, Maria (Ed.), 2003. Introduction. Apropos of Ideology: Translation Studies on IdeologyIdeologies in
Translation Studies. St. Jerome, Manchester, pp. 122.
Dilley, Roy (Ed.), 1999. The Problem of Context. Berghahn Books, New York and Oxford.
Dilley, Roy, 2003. The problem of context in social and cultural anthropology. Language & Communication 22, 437
456.
Duranti, Alessandro, Goodwin, Charles (Eds.), 1992. Rethinking Context: Language as an Interactive Phenomenon.
Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Gumperz, John, 1992. Contextualization and understanding. In: Duranti, Alessandro, Goodwin, Charles (Eds.),
Rethinking Context: Language as an Interactive Phenomenon. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp.
229253.
Gutt, Ernst-August, 1990. A theoretical account of translationwithout a translation theory. Target 2, 135164.
Gutt, Ernst-August, 1991/2000. Translation and Relevance: Cognition and Context. St. Jerome, Manchester.
Gutt, Ernst-August, 1996. Implicit information in literary translation: a relevance-theoretic perspective. Target 8, 239
256.
Gutt, Ernst-August, 1998. Pragmatic aspects of translation: some relevance-theory observations. In: Hickey, Leo (Ed.),
The Pragmatics of Translation. Multilingual Matters, Clevedon, pp. 4153.
Hanks, William, 1992. The indexical ground of deictic reference. In: Duranti, Alessandro, Goodwin, Charles (Eds.),
Rethinking Context: Language as an Interactive Phenomenon. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 4376.
Hickey, Leo (Ed.), 1998. The Pragmatics of Translation. Multilingual Matters, Clevedon.
Holy, Ladislav, 1999. Contextualisation and paradigm shifts. In: Dilley, Roy (Ed.), The Problem of Context. Berghahn
Books, New York and Oxford, pp. 4760.
House, Juliane, 1981. A Model for Translation Quality Assessment. Gunter Narr, Tubingen.
House, Juliane, 1997. Translation Quality Assessment: A Model Revisited. Gunter Narr, Tubingen.
House, Juliane, 2002. Universality versus culture specificity in translation. In: Riccardi, Alessandra (Ed.), Translation
Studies: Perspectives on an Emerging Discipline. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 92110.
Hymes, Dell H., 1964. Toward ethnographies of communicative events. Excerpts from introduction: toward ethnographies
of communication. American Anthropologist 66, 1225. In: Giglioli, Paolo (Ed.), 1972. Language and Social Context.
Penguin, Harmondsworth, pp. 2144.
Jones, Francis, 2004. Ethics, aesthetics and decision: literary translating in the wars of the Yugoslav succession. Meta
XLIX, 711728.
Katan, David, 1999/2004. Translating Cultures. St. Jerome, Manchester.
Katan, David, Straniero-Sergio, Francesco, 2001. Look whos talking: the ethics of entertainment and talkshow
interpreting. The Translator 7, 213237.
M. Baker / Journal of Pragmatics 38 (2006) 321337 337

Laviosa, Sara, 1997. How comparable can comparable corpora be? Target 9, 289319.
Lindstrom, Lamont, 1992. Context contests: debatable truth statements on Tanna (Vanuatu). In: Duranti, Alessandro,
Goodwin, Charles (Eds.), Rethinking Context: Language as an Interactive Phenomenon. Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge, pp. 101124.
Linell, Per, 1998. Approaching Dialogue: Talk, Interaction and Contexts in Dialogical Perspectives. John Benjamins,
Amsterdam.
Malmkjr, Kirsten, Williams, John (Eds.), 1998. Context in Language Learning and Language Understanding.
Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Mey, Jacob L., 2003. Context and (dis)ambiguity: a pragmatic view. Journal of Pragmatics 35, 331347.
Nord, Christiane, 1991. Text Analysis in Translation. Rodopi, Amsterdam.
Schegloff, Emanuel, 1992. In another context. In: Duranti, Alessandro, Goodwin, Charles (Eds.), Rethinking Context:
Language as an Interactive Phenomenon. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 191227.
Scollon, Ron, Scollon, Suzanne Wong, 1995. Intercultural Communication. Blackwell, Oxford.
Shea, David, 1994. Perspective and production: structuring conversational participation across cultural borders.
Pragmatics 4, 357389.
Shlesinger, Miriam, 1989. Monitoring the courtroom interpreter. Paralleles: Cahiers de lEcole de Traduction et
dInterpretation 11, 2936.
Sperber, Dan, Wilson, Deirdre, 1986/1995. Relevance. Communication and Cognition. Blackwell, Oxford.
Tymoczko, Maria, 2000. Translation and political engagement: activism, social change and the role of translation in
geopolitical shifts. The Translator 6, 2347.
Tymoczko, Maria, Gentzler, Edwin (Eds.), 2002. Translation and Power. University of Massachusetts Press, Amherst,
MA.
Van Dijk, Teun A., 2001a. Text and context revisited. In: Proceedings of the First Seoul International Conference on
Discourse and Cognitive Linguistics: Perspectives for the 21st Century, Seoul, Korea, June 910 2001.
Van Dijk, Teun A., 2001b. Discourse, ideology and context. Folia Linguistica XXXV, 1140.
Venuti, Lawrence, 1995. The Translators Invisibility. Routledge, London and New York.
Venuti, Lawrence, 1998. The Scandals of TranslationTowards an Ethics of Difference. Routledge, London and New
York.
Wadensjo, Cecilia, 1992. Interpreting as InteractionOn Dialogue Interpreting in Immigration Hearings and Medical
Encounters. Linkoping University, Linkoping.
Weizman, Elda, Blum-Kulka, Shoshana, 1987. Identifying and interpreting translated text: on the role of pragmatic
adjustment. In: Toury, Gideon (Ed.), Translation Across Cultures. Bahri Publications, New Delhi, pp. 6173.

Mona Baker is Professor of Translation Studies at the Centre for Translation and Intercultural Studies, University of
Manchester, UK. She is author of In Other Words: A Coursebook on Translation (Routledge, 1992) and Translation and
Conflict: A Narrative Account (Routledge, in press), Editor of the Routledge Encyclopedia of Translation Studies (1998,
2001), Founding Editor of The Translator: Studies in Intercultural Communication (St. Jerome Publishing, 1995 ),
Editor of the forthcoming Critical Concepts: Translation Studies (Routledge, 2006, four volumes) and Editorial
Director of St. Jerome Publishing. She is also Vice-President of IATIS (International Association of Translation &
Intercultural Studies).

Você também pode gostar