Você está na página 1de 6

Topoi (2006) 25:85–90

DOI 10.1007/s11245-006-0013-2

‘Philosophy is its own time comprehended in thought’


Robert B. Pippin

Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2006

Abstract So much philosophy is so unavoidably gui- I would be most often characterized by the profes-
ded by intuitions, and such intuitions are so formed by sion as ‘‘a historian of philosophy,’’ especially as a
examples, and such examples must of necessity present specialist in modern German philosophy from roughly
so cropped and abstract a picture of an instance or the end of the 18th century to the present. There are
event or decision, that, left to its traditional methods, some weighty, well-known names in this period—Kant,
philosophy might be ill-equipped on its own to answer Hegel, Nietzsche, and Heidegger—weighty enough
a question about the true content of an historical ideal and obscure enough to have inspired several hilarious
like ‘‘autonomy’’, or authenticity or ‘‘leading a free Monty Python bits. But it is a designation—‘‘histo-
life’’. One needs to bring so many factors into play at rian’’—that many in the profession consider the aca-
once that one non-traditional but more promising path demic equivalent of ‘‘librarian’’ of philosophy, or of
might be through reflection on the modern novel—or someone designated to take the notes at a meeting, or
modern drama or poetry or film or even modern at imagined past meetings, but not to participate. This
painting. is because much of contemporary philosophy aspires
not to have a history or at least not to have a history
Keywords intuitions Æ examples Æ novels Æ autonomy relevant in any philosophical sense. The aspiration is
that such a history should be as relevant as the history
of chemistry is to chemistry; perhaps of antiquarian
I interest but of no real importance to any working
chemist today. Literature and art may have living his-
I am not at all sure ‘‘what needs to be done’’ now in tories (no one would seriously claim that playwriting
contemporary philosophy, although the source of the has so ‘‘progressed’’ since Shakespeare that Ibsen
phrase itself in Lenin suggests a Hegelian theme I represents a better version of what Shakespeare was
would like briefly to discuss: the historical location of trying in his somewhat backward way to do), but many
philosophy. That is, I am not sure what needs to be claim there has been real, indeed decisive progress in
done, but I do think there is something missing in much philosophy,1 such that much of the past has been left
contemporary discussion (this historical dimension), behind or if not must be creatively re-interpreted so as
and I would like to address that lacuna. A grander to be made to address contemporary issues.
thesis, only hinted at here, would be a claim about the I don’t agree with the conventional view of what a
advantages of an essentially interdisciplinary concep- historian of philosophy is and want to raise here the
tion of philosophy, but that discussion would far question of the historical location of philosophical
exceed the bounds of this brief essay. activity, especially recently, in the modern West. But I

1
R. B. Pippin (&) Kant’s demonstration of the impossibility of traditional
University of Chicago, Chicago, IL, USA metaphysics and Frege’s innovations in philosophical logic (the
e-mail: r-pippin@uchicago.edu ‘‘invention of the quantifier’’) are often cited.

123
86 R. B. Pippin

note first that my daughter was headed in a good There is straight progressivism, especially for philos-
direction on this issue, when she was about eight and I ophers who link modern philosophy to the discoveries of
overheard her being asked by a friend, ‘‘What does modern natural science and regard past philosophy the
your father do for a living,’’ and she responded, ‘‘Oh, same way they regard past religion: as bad and now
he steals ideas from dead people.’’ The friend naturally superseded science. Indeed, many of the thinkers we
enough asked, ‘‘Why doesn’t he think up any of his take to be the ‘‘founders’’ of a distinctly modern
own?’’ and my daughter defended a version of my own philosophy (e.g., Hobbes, Descartes) clearly believed
answer: ‘‘He says all the best ones have already been that so much had changed that philosophy itself had to
thought up, but we don’t yet really understand what simply begin all over again, from scratch. (This kind of
they mean, and have to think about them some more.’’ view—that past philosophers are bad versions of us—is
Her friend did not note that this is a somewhat para- connected to a general philosophical temptation to-
doxical response, much like the apocryphal restaurant wards an imperialism of a sort, manifest especially when
complaint: ‘‘The food is terrible there, and they don’t philosophers show up at colloquia of other depart-
give you enough of it.’’ ments—to wit, that everything else in the humanities and
This characterization is not altogether false, and it much of the social sciences is simply a bad version of
does capture what I sometimes feel I am doing for a philosophy, not a good version of what it is.)
living, but many of the German philosophers I am There are also the perennialists, who think there is a
interested in would answer somewhat differently be- small, permanent core of philosophical problems—like
cause they believe that there is an essential relation ‘‘why should anyone care about justice if they can get
between philosophy and its historical time and that, to away with unjustly bettering their own lot?’’ or ‘‘what
understand that historical aspect of philosophy in our is a number?’’—and each generation has its own go at
own time, we need to say something about how that it, failing to make much progress, just like all other
relation manifested itself in the prior epochs out of generations, but captured by the problems nonetheless.
which ours developed. The idea is that, although there (This is of course the position, or perhaps one should
are any number of what seem like straightforward say, given its great success at the time, the marketing
philosophical issues in our contemporary world, we strategy of the Great Books program, associated with
can be led astray if we simply charge ahead and start Mortimer Adler and the Hutchins era at my own uni-
trying to ‘‘solve’’ the problems. (Indeed, as Ian versity, the University of Chicago.)
Hacking has pointed out, the whole idea that philos- And there are the various kinds of relativists, who
ophy consists of ‘‘problems’’ is itself a relatively new see philosophical problems as so bound up with their
one, has a history, ‘‘...was canonized in English age that they should be thought of as games and puz-
around 1910 with titles by G. E. Moore, William zles or anxieties or obsessions that arise for a while in a
James, and Bertrand Russell...’’ (Hacking 2002, p. 72).) certain period, like literary or painting or musical
Moreover, as opposed to many once standard prob- styles, and then change and fade away as times change.
lems that have pretty much died out—like proofs for Perhaps Wittgenstein’s phrase is apt here: philosophy
the existence of God or the immortality of the soul—, as conceptual music.
these current problems continue ‘‘to have a historical It is quite likely that all of these answers are correct,
life,’’ we might say, because of complex and often some for certain sorts of problems, some for others.
hidden links with non-philosophical issues, links that There are likely historically novel ‘‘problems’’ abstract
become apparent only by locating the philosophy of a enough that, however important and complicated, a
time in the right historical narrative, something that is historical genealogy does not contribute much. There
not possible by attention to academic philosophical are no doubt other sorts of issues that emerge and
issues alone. disappear as if mere fashions of the moment.2 But this
Or so goes the kind of claim I am interested in.
2
There are scores of controversies about everything I’ve But stated so broadly this sort of call to historical arms is
just said, the key issue being what one might mean by similar to one final position from which it should be distin-
guished. I mean the philosophical assumptions behind much
‘‘develop out of’’ the past and especially a distinction
creative, valuable work in recent history and sociology of sci-
that we all sometimes invoke but do not much explore: ence. The direction I am eventually going to take branches off
what distinguishing a ‘‘living’’ notion or practice from a from much of this work in a couple of respects. The main result
‘‘dead’’ or ‘‘dying’’ one amounts to. But, for the sake of of such recent historicizing philosophy has been to emphasize the
discreteness and uniqueness of new concepts and projects and
context, we should also note that there are numerous
even ‘‘new objects’’ (i.e., that science is full of wholesale, vast,
possible positions here about what it is for philosophy radical ‘‘paradigm shifts,’’ not really development), and thus
to have a history, and it is easy to get lost quickly. to demonstrate the contingency of such origins. The narratives

123
Philosophy is its own time 87

general outline doesn’t tell us much. Most everyone is capacity to obey the dictates of pure practical reason,
willing to concede that the concepts by which we do not look either like mere changes in fashion or
explain and evaluate our experience are ‘‘historically eternally accessible problems, ‘‘discovered’’ by chance
conditioned’’ in some sense. That ancient authors do at one time rather than another. It looks like such
not seem to recognize what Christian metaphysicians changes will all have to be explained in a way that is
call the will, or that British philosophy of the 18th profoundly ‘‘historical.’’ But, as noted, it is not con-
century ties normative distinctions so much to the troversial to concede something like this. As with
influence of the passions, or that Kantian moral psy- everything else, the devil is in the details.
chology describes agency as paradigmatically the

II
Footnote 2 continued
often aim to be de-stabilizing, de-familiarizing, even de-
legitimating. ‘‘Things could have easily been much different than Consider an example—the ideal of freedom, especially
they ended up being,’’ goes the story, and it should give us great an understanding of what it is to lead one’s own life in
pause to note how quickly deep transformations in a practice can
become canonical and how little ‘‘reason’’ or ‘‘discovery’’ ex-
such a way that it requires protection of basic entitle-
plain such transformations (the covering term for the absence of ments for individuals (like property rights) and
such reason or discovery is often simply ‘‘power’’). The way in understands human agency as resulting in actions by
which various concepts are linked up with others could have individuals for which they may be held individually
been quite different as well. So when Ian Hacking or Ruth Leys
responsible.
(2000) demonstrates the great historical novelty of concepts like
‘‘psychological trauma’’ (and the way in which the language of Even though these questions—what is the real con-
trauma and traumatology has quickly replaced the language of tent of this ideal (what would it be to lead a free life)
neurosis, and taken over a great deal of, almost all of, therapeutic and why has it become so important to us, what is its
psychology), or when Hacking documents the enormous, anxious
importance to us—are obviously pretty vague, it al-
importance to modern parents of the benchmarks drawn up by
new ‘‘childhood development specialists’’ (and so the great new ready does not look like a strictly philosophical answer
anxiety about measuring ‘‘normal’’ development—it wasn’t al- to those questions could get us very far, at least it
ways true that the first question parents would ask about a new doesn’t seem likely to me. It is after all only relatively
baby was its length and weight, the first mark of normalizing
worries), or when Lorraine Daston investigates the distinct ori-
recently in Western history that we began to think of
gins of concepts like fact or objectivity (Daston and Park 1998), human beings as something like individuals directing
or Foucault goes after the norms inherent in the treatment of the and guiding the course of their own lives, in some sense
mentally ill (the invention of mental illness) or norms of pun- independent and self-determining centers of a causal
ishment, their interest is not the normative status of these no-
agency; only relatively recently that one’s entitlement
tions themselves—whether they merit the hold they have on us,
whether a historical narrative can help illuminate and even to such a self-determining, self-directed life seemed not
solidify this hold—as it is to explain, in the manner of an just valuable but absolutely valuable, for the most part
empirical scientist, under what conditions people in fact com- more important even than any consideration of secu-
mitted themselves to such norms and practices. Said another
way, such work is relevant to the question of whether such norms
rity, well-being, and peace that would make the
merit their authority, but only by way of showing, in all these attainment of such an ideal more difficult, so important
cases, that they probably do not, or at least that they cannot be that it was even worth the risk of life in its defense. At
defended in the standard ways. The standard ways project a least, this moral, quasi-religious insistence on the value
myth; the reality is very different. The normative question itself
of individual liberty has attained this level of impor-
is regarded either as a separate one—leaving philosophical and
historical questions distinct—or, as just indicated, as a naı̈ve one, tance in the United States (as distinct from Continental
since the legitimating argument is, as we have seen, itself likely to Europe). Its legitimacy is not so much defended by
have a historical site and distinct origins, as well as to be subject appeals to self-interest but by appeals to a kind of
to the same demonstration of utter contingency. The ambitious
absolute moral entitlement. That is one of the reasons
ideas of a continuous or even self-correcting normative project
and so of a kind of holism, and of a kind of philosophical defense why the great American political philosopher, John
of some norm that appeals to history and historical development, Rawls, found such a large American audience for his
all sound anachronistic and dogmatic nowadays. In fact they Kantian defense of freedom, of an entitlement to
sound like the epitome of bourgeois self-satisfaction and smug-
ness, and so many intellectuals in our age accordingly prefer the
pursue one’s own life plan, as an essential element in
deflationary and critical. But, while there are many ungrounded justice. The claim for importance actually has a lot to
claims to normative worth that ought to be exposed by this do with a claim by Rousseau that has also found gen-
demonstration of contingency, something is just going haywire if erations of passionate American adherents: that there
that demonstration is totalized, and an inquiry into normative
is a condition necessary for a life to have any value for
authority as such is either re-quarantined off as in another
workshop, or unremittingly itself exposed as some historical me—that it be my life, that nothing can be a good for
accident or other, explicable but not thereby affirmable. me unless it is a good to me, recognized as such by me,

123
88 R. B. Pippin

under conditions that allow the recognition and eval- that it was because of the beauty of the arguments of
uation to be truly mine. It seems unlikely in the ex- Rousseau. And, one would grant immediately, how-
treme that this notion of freedom and its most ever much one might want to concede something like
important political implication—the idea of a human such a claim, one also has to be careful about turning
or natural right—should have been sitting in history any discussion of a philosophical issue into some ver-
unnoticed, waiting for Locke and Rousseau to discover sion of historical sociology or sociology of knowledge.
it. One still wants some way of assessing the normative
We can try to quarantine, as it were, the philo- status of what originated, even conceding the full his-
sophical issues—arguing that, however such an ideal torical texture of the ideal itself.
got on our agenda is of no importance to philosophy, This is just as true of the rapidly growing dissatis-
that we just investigate its rational credentials once faction with the ideal throughout the last half of the
history hands it to us. But that seems quite disingenu- 19th century. For by this point the view that modern
ous since the notion has a kind of historical and social Western civilization itself represents a kind of failure
authority and priority in normative discussions and a or is historically exhausted is much more widespread
dense, complex ‘‘lived’’ meaning to those committed to and goes much deeper than any assessment of the
it that philosophy also needs to understand if it is to philosophical credentials of the idea could account for.
understand what the ideal entails and what actual At just the moment in the 19th century when Western
authority it has merited. We could also try to argue European societies, for all of their visible flaws, seemed
that the contexts wherein a claim for the complete to start paying off the Enlightenment’s promissory
autonomy of philosophy looks prima facie implausible notes, reducing human misery by the application of their
are actually quite restricted, few in number, limited new science and technology, increasing the authority of
perhaps to a few very broad ethical issues, and that the appeals to reason in life, reducing the divisive public
claim is not relevant to more formal issues in episte- role of religion, extending the revolutionary claim of
mology or semantics or philosophy of mind. It would individual natural right to an ever wider class of sub-
admittedly be harder to show the relevance of this jects, accelerating the extension of natural scientific
‘‘historical location’’ issue for some such contexts, but explanation, and more and more actually gaining what
the point would be that any such discussion begins with Descartes so boldly promised, the mastery of nature, it
assumptions about the significance of the problem also seemed that many of the best, most creative minds
being addressed, the centrality or marginality of vari- produced within and as products of such societies rose
ous issues, and criteria for what counts as an explana- up in protest, even despair at the social organization
tion or solution where such a claim for relevance would and norms that also made all of this possible. In
look more natural. painting, literature, and music, as well as philosophy,
Moreover, if it is plausible to consider the origin and bourgeois modernity as a whole became not only a
even the authority of such normative commitments as great problem but also a very confusing, largely dis-
unintelligible apart from their place in a changing, tasteful fate. All this eventually came to be reflected in
historical social organization, it is also highly plausible what the profession classifies as continental philoso-
that any particular mode of ‘‘investigating the rational phy—the end of metaphysics, the end of philosophy,
credentials’’ of such commitments is itself necessarily the impotence of reason, failed signifiers, the death of
attached to the same historical story. Argument forms the subject, the end of man, negative dialectics, the
determining what counts as a legitimating case also impossibility of poetry, the end of the novel, absolute
come attached to complex and developing histories contingency, anti-humanism, and on and on.
and need the same sort of proper location in order to
be understood and properly assessed. For example, the
idea of appealing to what form of authority ‘‘pre-social III
rational individuals would hypothetically choose to
submit to’’ is not something that would have made What sort of a philosophical problem is all this? How
much sense, say, to Aristotle, just as refraining from adequate is a philosophical response that simply says:
appealing to the proper natural role of men and wo- these complainants were wrong? Or that we just need a
men, to natural law, would have greatly puzzled more extensive realization of the ideal? How are we to
Aquinas. begin a philosophical assessment of the ideal when it is
However such an ideal of autonomy or self- so hard to state clearly the conceptual content of this,
realization got a grip on the imagination of intellectuals the deepest and most important animating ideal of the
and then the whole culture of the West, it is not likely modern West? Here another extra-philosophical

123
Philosophy is its own time 89

dimension besides social and cultural history seems inevitable death, Kate and Merton can live happily
relevant. So much philosophy is so unavoidably guided ever after on Merton’s inheritance. One of the great
by intuitions, and such intuitions are so formed by achievements of the novel is how good Kate is in
examples, and such examples must of necessity present convincing Merton (and us) that what they are doing is
so cropped and abstract a picture of an instance or not ‘‘deceiving a dying heiress’’; they are actually
event or decision, that, left to its traditional methods, ‘‘allowing a friend, Milly, to experience romantic love
philosophy might be ill-equipped on its own to answer once before she dies.’’ I can do no justice here to just
a question like one about the true content of an how good Kate is at this, and how different it all would
historical ideal like ‘‘autonomy,’’ or authenticity or seem if they had been successful and Milly had died
‘‘leading a free life.’’ One needs to bring so many unknowing and blissfully happy. One might want to
factors into play at once that one non-traditional but attribute Kate’s eventual inability to somehow make
more promising path might be through reflection on this description stick to the social conventions, which in
the modern novel (or modern drama or poetry or film fact override her attempted re-description, or one
or even modern painting). might want to say somehow that both descriptions are
In the space available I hope that a few concluding true in their own way. But Kate is good enough at what
examples can help clarify what I am trying to get at, she does to make it profoundly unclear just how such
and bring together the relevance of historical and lit- an issue should be settled, how our dependence on the
erary elements to philosophy. The bearing of such way a putative description like this would enter and
extra-philosophical elements is particularly appropri- circulate in a real social world can be squared with our
ate with regard to the freedom issue, since the histor- sense of the relative independence we want to assert
ical problem emerging in much modern literature about what we sincerely intended to do and what role
concerns the very confusing experience of extensive that should play in some determination of what was
social dependencies within a kind of life guided by ever done.
more extreme demands for reflective and social inde- But James goes the other way too, does not just
pendence. throw doubt on the independence of agents’ descrip-
Consider how a particular unresolved complexity tions in favor of the more standard or socially
manifests itself, given that all the notions we have authoritative ones. In The Ambassadors, the conven-
discussed as relevant to a free life (justifiability, reason- tional or socially authoritative view of the relationship
giving, and identification) presuppose some way of between a young heir dawdling years too long in Paris
having already settled in common a number of the very and the married Parisian woman with whom he daw-
simplest preliminary issues—what it is that you are dles, is that it is not serious, a mere bagatelle, poten-
actually doing, something that can itself be quite con- tially corrupting, and that the boy should come home.
testable and that requires some way of understanding The ambassador sent there to bring him home,
such act descriptions as involving profound social Lambert Strether, ends up disputing this description,
dependencies. I know it sounds vague and too literary seeing instead a world of subtlety, great sensitivity and
to suggest that we find in these documents extended complexity that it is good for Chad, the heir, to expe-
attempts to ‘‘work through’’ in some way this unre- rience. This divergence from the norm ends up costing
solved legacy of the bourgeois turn in history, but Strether everything he has (the boy’s mother is Stre-
perhaps examples will help. ther’s employer and benefactor) and James here
In one of the novels of Henry James, The Wings of manages to persuade us that Strether’s independence is
the Dove, an extraordinarily intelligent woman, Kate correct, although it remains mysterious how we know
Croy, befriends an American heiress, Milly Theale, he is right. (This is especially so because we keep faith
who is dying. Kate sees that Milly has fallen in love with Strether and his independence even after we and
with Merton Densher, with whom Kate herself is se- he learn that the conventional view had been largely
cretly engaged. Kate and Merton have not married and right, that Chad is a thoughtless playboy and has not
kept everything secret because for them, given their been helped much by his so-called education.)
tastes and ambitions, a marriage with no money would Novels testify in many ways to the great limitations
be miserable and they have hopes a solution may come of any notion of freedom that exaggerates this claim of
along. Kate’s solution is to have Merton make love to independence—an exaggerated pretence of indepen-
Milly, the rich heiress, marry her, and then, after her dence that, I am suggesting, is the chief bourgeois

123
90 R. B. Pippin

temptation.3 Perhaps the most prominent and well this core liberal notion, the claims about dead ends,
known are the dilemmas about romantic love and false consciousness, historical exhaustion, ideological
marriage. Three of the greatest of the 19th century distortion, and so forth are quite premature. Surely
novels, Flaubert’s Emma Bovary, Tolstoy’s Anna we need to know first, in a great deal more detail, and
Karenina, and Fontane’s Effie Briest, are about adul- in a way not traditionally thought of as purely
tery and just thereby already raise a number of issues philosophical, what a kind of life organized around
about the perceived unfreedom of the institution of such a commitment actually amounts to, what con-
marriage and so what it might mean to re-establish that flicts and even social pathologies it is heir to, for the
connection between my sense of my own agency and real, historically situated participants in such a nor-
my own deeds, as when Emma Bovary can say to mative community. And the question of the adequacy
herself in what amounts to a triumph of pathos: ‘‘I am of such an ideal might then be discussed in a way
having an affair!’’ (This sympathy is even true of the informed as much by an appreciation of the sustain-
author (in spite of himself) who is clearly out to write ability of such an ideal as it is lived out and experi-
an anti-adultery novel, Tolstoy.)4 enced over time as by the ability of the ideal to
The claim that this sort of historical and literary withstand rational challenge and criticism in the tra-
evidence is essential for philosophy and that this sort ditional sense.
of appreciation of historical content is not available to
one simply qua philosopher requires a much longer
discussion than is possible here. (The claim that such References
an appreciation is essential, rather than merely
Adorno T (1974) Minima moralia: reflections from damaged life,
exemplary, usefully illustrative, is particularly con-
translated by Jephcott EFN. Verso, London
troversial and not supported by anything said here.) Daston L, Park K (1998) Wonders and the order of nature. MIT
But this sort of approach is important not just with Press, Cambridge (MA)
respect to methodological issues in philosophy. The Hacking I (2002) Historical ontology. Harvard University Press,
Cambridge MA
modest suggestion is that the sort of sweeping claims
Leys R (2000) Trauma. A genealogy. University of Chicago
discussed above concerning the loss of authority Press, Chicago
among some segments of European high culture of

3
An important question here is what difference it makes that
these examples are fictional, from a work of art; what would
change if they were real-life examples? A very long answer
would be necessary to answer this question but one essential
reason for having to rely on fiction is the possibility opened up of
knowing quite a bit more about the state of and changes in the
inner experience of characters than would ever be possible in
‘‘real life.’’ It is false that we could ever know what James claims
to be able to know, but within that false or ‘‘mind-reading’’
assumption, there is a also a restriction the observation of which
distinguishes great from mediocre fiction, all in a way that cannot
be formalized or thematized: the ‘‘ring of truth.’’
4
Cf. Adorno (1974), pp. 30–33.

123

Você também pode gostar