Você está na página 1de 20

Journal of the Operational Research Society (2009) 60, 441 --460 © 2009 Operational Research Society Ltd.

Ltd. All rights reserved. 0160-5682/09

www.palgrave-journals.com/jors/

The history and ideas of critical rationalism:


the philosophy of Karl Popper and its
implications for OR
RJ Ormerod∗
University of Warwick, Coventry, UK
Critical rationalism is the philosophy developed by Karl Popper during the middle of the 20th century. Popper’s
approach is based on the naturalistic idea that society has developed through a process of solving problems
using trial and error. The natural and social sciences have been born out of such problem solving and progressed
by subjecting potential theories to vigorous testing and criticism. Falsified theories are rejected. Popper calls
for a society which is conducive to such problem solving, a society which permits bold theorizing followed
by unfettered criticism, a society in which there is a genuine possibility of change in the light of criticism: an
open society. Popper’s ideas provide a doorway for accessing philosophical ideas and debates relevant to OR.
For some such as Boothroyd it has proved inspirational, for others such as Ulrich it has provided a critical
point of departure.
Journal of the Operational Research Society (2009) 60, 441 – 460. doi:10.1057/palgrave.jors.2602573
Published online 5 March 2008

Keywords: philosophy of OR; history of ideas; critical rationalism

Introduction demarcation problem, but it also provided a productive


perspective from which to view the activities of science
This is the third in a series of papers that describe the history
generally. His approach attracted both interest and criticism.
and ideas of major intellectual movements and explore
Do scientists in practice abandon their theories when faced
their relevance for OR today. The first paper took as its
with falsifying evidence? On what basis should the evidence
subject pragmatism (Ormerod, 2006), the second Marxism
of falsification be accepted? If the most we can do in science
(Ormerod, 2008). Critical rationalism is the philosophy of
is to disprove theories, how do we know which theories to
the Anglo-Austrian philosopher Karl Popper (1902–1994).
believe and act on? (O’Hear, 1995a, p 702).
Popper made major contributions in two distinct (but in
The themes of human ignorance and the need for critical
Popper’s mind linked) areas of philosophy, the philosophy of
scrutiny of ideas are also prominent in Popper’s social and
science and the philosophy of sociology and politics. In his
political philosophy. He advocated the development of an
early works he was associated with, but not a member of, the
‘open society’ the key feature of which was the freedom
Vienna Circle (see below) and shared their interest in distin-
of those affected by policies to voice their criticisms and
guishing between science and other activities (the demarca-
to be able peacefully and regularly to change their rulers.
tion problem). However, he did not think it was possible to
He attacked those who claimed the right to impose their
approach that (or any other philosophical problem) by an
blueprints on the rest of us by virtue of a supposed knowl-
analysis of language or meaning. This set him outside the
edge of the course of history (historicism). His analysis of
main stream of philosophy at that time, analytic philosophy,
the origins and ideas of ideological totalitarian regimes (both
which was in the thrall of the linguistic analysis of Ludwig
fascist and communist) were published at the end of World
Wittgenstein (1889–1951).
War II just as the two great power blocks, representing on
Popper, following a sceptical approach, took ‘falsifica-
the one side free-market liberal democracy and on the other
tion’ as the distinguishing characteristic of science: universal
centrally planned communism, began to enter the next great
theories are never verified or confirmed with any positive
struggle, the Cold War.
probability, they can only be falsified. Popper showed how
Popper’s major work on the philosophy of science, Logik
this perspective not only solved the ‘problem of induction’,
der Forschung (Popper, 1934), was published in English 25
originally identified by David Hume (1711–1776), and the
years later as The Logic of Scientific Discovery (Popper, 1959).
∗ Correspondence: RJ Ormerod, 26 Coulsdon Road, Sidmouth, Devon His books on political philosophy, The Poverty of Histori-
EX10 9JP, UK. cism (Popper, 1944/5) and The Open Society and its Enemies
E-mail: richard@rormerod.freeserve.co.uk (Popper, 1945a, b), were published at the end of the war.
442 Journal of the Operational Research Society Vol. 60, No. 4

Conjectures and Refutations (Popper, 1963) brings together and it made a great impression on him (Popper, 1976a, p 13).
various essays and lectures on the theme that we can learn As a young man he was a socialist and for a brief period, at
by our mistakes. In Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary the age of 17, he regarded himself as a communist. However,
Approach (Popper, 1972), Popper addresses the arguments a violent incident in Vienna instigated by Marxists led him
of his critics and outlines his overall philosophy. The three to turn against it. Nevertheless, as in all large European cities
volumes of the Postscript, originally intended to be appen- the sight of abject poverty could not be avoided even by
dices to The Logic of Scientific Discovery, were extended and the reasonably well off. Popper came to believe that nothing
finally published in the early 1980s (Popper, 1982a, b, 1983). was more important than the eradication of poverty (Popper,
Key extracts from his major works can be found in The Pocket 1976a, p 12).
Popper (Miller, 1983). A brief but authoritative summary At University Popper studied a wide range of subjects. He
of Popper’s ideas can be found in Popper (Magee, 1973). then qualified to teach in primary schools and later to teach
Unended Quest (Popper, 1976a) is what Popper describes as mathematics, physics and chemistry in secondary schools.
an intellectual autobiography; it includes an extensive bibli- Remarkably, at the same time he was apprenticed to be a
ography of his published works. This biography is included cabinet maker, completing his apprenticeship in 1924. As
in Schilpp (1974), which also contains 33 critical essays and there were no teaching posts available he became a social
Popper’s responses. Summaries and evaluations of Popper’s worker, working with neglected children (Popper, 1976a,
life and works can be found in O’Hear (1980), Magee (1985), pp 39–41). Popper’s PhD was initially meant to be about
Williams (1989), Shearmur (1996), Corvi (1997), Hacohen psychology, but he became disillusioned with it and placed
(2000), and Notturno (2003). In Popper’s final book, The the emphasis on method rather than psychology itself; he had
Myth of the Framework: In Defence of Science and Ratio- concluded that the study of logic should have priority over
nality (Popper, 1994), he says that his work has been aimed the study of subjective thought processes. (Popper, 1976a,
at defending rationality and rational criticism as a way of pp 77–78). He obtained his PhD in 1928 and, after a period of
thinking and even a way of living: a readiness to listen to researching and writing, in 1930 he married and settled down
critical arguments, to search for one’s own mistakes, and to to school teaching. Late in 1934 his Logik der Forschung was
learn from them. published. The main outline of the The Poverty of Histori-
After a biographical sketch in the next section, a brief cism was completed in 1935 and read as a paper in 1936.
historical context of Popper’s life and work is given. The Finally, in 1937 at the age of 35, he became a full time
cornerstone of Popper’s thinking, his logic of scientific philosopher.
discovery, is then summarized and the consequent controversy On publication, the Logik der Forschung was widely
initiated by Thomas Kuhn is described. The next section sets reviewed and debated. As war approached and the future of
outs Popper’s views on social and political science (including those of Jewish origin started to look threatened in Austria,
his attack on historicism and his advocacy of the open his reputation allowed him to obtain a lecturing post in New
society) and gives an account of the subsequent dispute with Zealand. While there he wrote The Open Society and its
Theodor Adorno. In the final section describing Popper’s Enemies. It was published in two volumes in 1945. In 1946
views, his evolutionary account of epistemology (how we Popper took up a post at the London School of Economics in
know things) is briefly described. The next section looks the school of social sciences where he continued to develop
at the absorption of Popper’s ideas by operational research and defend his ideas.
(OR). It considers the approaches of Boothroyd and Ulrich,
both of whom have made use of Popper’s philosophy in The historical context
their quest to describe, provide foundations for and improve
Europe between the wars
professional practice; Dando and Bennett’s suggestion that a
Kuhnian revolution was underway in OR is examined; and the After World War I the Austro-Hungarian Empire was broken
approach of Jackson is viewed from a Popperian perspective. up and Austria was created out of the main German-speaking
Finally some suggestions are made as to how a productive areas. The war left Austria economically and politically
relationship between Popper’s philosophy and OR can be unstable and after a brief respite factions from the right
achieved. and left fought for ascendancy. In 1934 the ruling Christian
Socialist Party was displaced by The Popular Front, which
established a one-party fascist regime. At the same time
Karl Raimund Popper
much of Europe was also succumbing to fascism. Mussolini
Karl Popper was born in Vienna in 1902. His father was a gradually turned the liberal democracy of Italy into a fascist
practising lawyer and a historian. His mother was musical and totalitarian state. Hitler in Germany and Franco in Spain were
at one point he considered a career in music. Both Popper’s heavily influenced by Italy’s example. Under the impact of
parents were born in the Jewish faith, but were baptized into worldwide economic depression and 6 million unemployed,
the Protestant (Lutheran) Church before their children were the electorate in Germany swung to the right. In 1933 Hitler
born. Popper read his first book on socialism at the age of 12, was appointed Chancellor. In a series of manoeuvres the
RJ Ormerod—History and ideas of critical rationalism 443

democratic Weimer republic was replaced by a one-party this, science continued to move forward confidently with ever
dictatorship. In 1935 the so-called Nuremberg race laws were more and deeper insights as well as technical and commer-
passed directed at Jewish citizens. In Spain civil war broke cial successes. This needed to be explained. Another major
out in 1936. Backed by Hitler’s Germany and Mussolini’s issue was the status of the psychological pursuits of Freud
Italy the Nationalists under Franco were victorious in 1939. (psychoanalysis), Adler (individual psychology) and others.
In Russia, after the successful Bolshevik revolution in Since the enlightenment, science had fought a long battle to
October 1917, the communist regime under Lenin, faced with separate the rational and empirical truths of scientific inquiry
an enormous country savaged by war and anarchy, struggled from the revealed truth of religion. Were these new subjects
to develop a system to bring about the socialism of Marx’s part of science or merely new dogmatisms?
vision. In 1922 Lenin began his ‘new economic policy’ of
limited free enterprise before entering the era of giant state The need for a framework for economics and sociology
planning. On Lenin’s death in 1924 Stalin introduced a series
During the latter half of the 19th century the British school
of five-year plans and brutally eliminated all potential oppo-
of economics of the late 18th century and early 19th century
sition. Across Europe between the wars different types of
was dominant. This British tradition (based on the objective-
government, various attitudes to those of Jewish origin, and
cost and labour-productivity theory of value) ultimately led
struggles between left and right were continuously on display
to the rise of the Marxist doctrine of capitalist exploita-
as each nation attempted to recover from World War I and
tion. This way of thinking received its first serious chal-
overcome the effects of the global depression. None of this
lenge when the Principles of Economics by Carl Menger
was lost on Popper.
(1840–1921) was published in 1871. Menger spelt out the
subjective basis of economic value, and explained for the
Vienna
first time the theory of marginal utility. The approach of
Up to the end of World War I, Vienna was the capital of the the Austrian School of economists, which developed from
Austro-Hungarian Empire. Popper grew up there at a time Menger’s ideas, was based on the decisions of individuals;
when it was not only a political centre of great power but this brought them into direct conflict (known as the Method-
was also a vibrant world centre for the arts and sciences, a enstreit or methodological dispute) with the German Histor-
cauldron of intellectual endeavour and creative activity. As an ical School, which attributed market development to histor-
imperial capital at its zenith Vienna ruled over Hungarians, ical social forces. FA Hayek (1899–1992), a collaborator and
Czechs, Slovaks, Poles, Italians, Galicians, Slovenes, Serbs friend of Popper, was the best-known advocate of the Austrian
and Croats, and Austrians. Of course, it was not just a closed School’s ideas in the English speaking world. The Austrian
community at the centre of the Austro-Hungarian Empire, School needed support for their methodological approach.
it was also part of the wider German-speaking culture. Nor They found it in Popper’s philosophy.
was this Germanic culture isolated within Europe. Interac- Another heated controversy was the Werturteilsstreit or
tion with the French and English-speaking worlds ensured an value-judgement dispute. The conflict started in earnest in
exchange of ideas and intellectuals. Vienna University was a 1909 at a meeting in Vienna (Max Weber was a key partici-
flourishing seat of independent learning with an international pant). The issue was whether sociology should concern itself
reputation. solely with ‘what is’ rather than ‘what should be’? What is
the role of values, can they be empirically determined? Can
The new uncertainties of science science itself be value free? (Frisby, 1976, pp xxiii–xxiv). In
the 1960s Popper became the focus in another round of this
Just as Kant felt he had to derive a philosophical framework
dispute, this time referred to (misleadingly) as the Positivis-
that accounted for the logic of Aristotle, Euclidian geom-
musstreit (positivist dispute) (Adorno, 1969, 1976).
etry and Newton’s physics of space and time, philosophers of
science in the first half of the 20th century had to wrestle with
The philosophical landscape
the revolution in physics. The work of James Clerk Maxwell,
Heisenberg, Max Planck, Niels Bohr and above all Albert Arguably Betrand Russell (1872–1970) dominated Western
Einstein overthrew the long standing deterministic equations philosophy in the early decades of the 20th century. From the
of Newtonian physics, replacing them by the probabilistic, time of Descartes in the 17th century, the central branch of
relativistic equations of quantum mechanics and relativity philosophy had been epistemology, the study of what we can
theory. Newton’s laws, which had for many years been the know. British empiricists (Locke, Berkeley and Hume) were
exemplar of science’s ability to provide a reliable foundation among those who followed this tradition. But after Russell
of scientific knowledge and had been verified in numerous epistemology was displaced by the philosophy of language
and varied experiments and technical applications, had been and the premise that our words are the lenses through which
overturned. The epistemology of science needed rethinking to we access our thoughts and the world (Edmonds and Eidinow,
account for the fact that theories, however well established, 2001, pp 174–175). Russell took his approach to language
may in turn be superseded. Nothing was now certain. Despite from his attempt (with Whitehead) to put mathematics on a
444 Journal of the Operational Research Society Vol. 60, No. 4

sound logical footing. He applied the same rigorous use of sources of religion.) But I had held in my hands for many years
logical techniques to philosophical problems which took the a better criterion of demarcation: testability or falsifiability.
form of linguistic statements (Sainsbury, 1995, p 782). (Popper, 1976a, p 79)
In time, Russell came to be overshadowed by his student
Wittgenstein who applied Russell’s approach in his Tractatus Meaning and truth
Logico-Philosophicus. This work influenced the Vienna Circle
Popper rejected the idea that philosophy should try to establish
and a group in Berlin led by Reichenbach (1891–1953); it
the meaning of language (essentialism). Such pursuits would
was the mainspring, sometimes through misunderstanding,
always lead to an infinite regress: the meaning of the words
of their ‘logical positivism’ (Hacker, 1995, p 912). Analytic
used to describe the meaning of the words under scrutiny
philosophy, derived from the work of Russell and the early
would have to be defined. Rather than having any essence, he
Wittgenstein, came to dominate British philosophy. Linguistic
saw words as simply convenient shorthand for some longer
philosophy, derived from the later Wittgenstein (given defini-
description of a phenomenon. Thus Popper felt that philoso-
tive expression in his masterpiece Philosophical Investiga-
phies of meaning and language were unimportant (Popper,
tions), increasingly prevailed in most of the English-speaking
1976a, pp 20–22). Rather he took the view that: ‘In matters of
world from 1945 until about 1960 (Quinton, 1995, p 29).
the intellect, the only things worth striving for are true theo-
Popper was on the edge of the Vienna Circle and interacted
ries, or theories which come near to the truth—at any rate
with members of it. He shared their interest in the nature
nearer than some other (competing) theory, for example an
of science. However, he was a critic and was never invited
older one’ (Popper, 1976a, p 22). Popper therefore determined
to join. He was partly instrumental in its eventual demise.
to address the traditional philosophical problem of what is it
Another group, the Frankfurt School led by Max Horkheimer
that we can know (epistemology), particularly in the light of
(1895–1973) and Theodor Adorno (1903–1969), played no
the upheavals in physics and his doubts about the status of
part in the formative years of the development of Popper’s
psychological theories such as those of Freud and Adler. This
thinking but did come into conflict with him in the Positivis-
line of thinking went against that of Wittgenstein; Wittgen-
musstreit referred to above. Jürgen Habermas played a promi-
stein taught that the task of philosophers was to untangle
nent role in this dispute.
linguistic puzzles. Surprisingly, the two Austrian Jews from
Vienna, who had both emigrated to Britain, only ever met
The logic of scientific discovery once; this was the famous poker incident in Cambridge in
1946 (Edmonds and Eidinow, 2001).
Popper first formed his key idea of falsification at the age
of 17. He was concerned about the problem of demarcation,
Falsification and demarcation
which he formulated as: how can science be separated from
pseudo-science? It was only later that he extended his ‘crite- The results of his investigation into epistemology were
rion of demarcation’ to metaphysics. He had been shocked by published in Logik der Forschung (Popper, 1934). The book
the fact that the Marxists (whose central claim was that they was devoted to two problems, the problem of induction and
were social scientists) and the psychoanalysts of all schools the problem of demarcation, and their interaction. It was
seemed able to interpret any conceivable event as a verifica- meant to provide a theory of knowledge and, at the same
tion of their theories. In Unended Quest he says: ‘My main time, to be a treatise on method, the method of science
idea in 1919 was this. If somebody proposed a scientific theory (Popper, 1976a, p 85). His approach was to replace induc-
he should answer, as Einstein did, the question: “Under what tion by falsification. It is important to recognize this was a
conditions would I admit that my theory is untenable?” In decision, a decision going beyond rational argument: ‘My
other words, what conceivable facts would I accept as refuta- criterion of demarcation will accordingly have to be regarded
tions or falsifications, of my theory?’ (Popper, 1976a, p 41). as a proposal for an agreement or convention’ (Popper, 1959,
But it was not until he qualified as a teacher at the age of 29 p 37, original emphasis). He concludes, ‘There is only one
that he realised the significance of his earlier ideas: way, as far as I can see, of arguing rationally in support
of my proposals. This is to analyse their logical conse-
. . . my earlier ideas fell into place. I understood why the quences: to point out their fertility—their power to elucidate
mistaken theory of science which had ruled since Bacon—that the problems of the theory of knowledge’ (Popper, 1959,
the natural sciences were the inductive sciences, and that p 38, original emphasis).
induction was a process of establishing or justifying theo-
On falsification, the key point is that universal theories
ries by repeated observations or experiments—was so deeply
cannot be induced from singular statements as induction
entrenched. The reason was that scientists had to demarcate
their activities from pseudoscience as well as from theology would have it (from many observations of white swans it
and metaphysics, and they had taken over from Bacon the cannot be concluded that ‘all swans are white’). However,
inductive method as their criterion of demarcation. (On the the situation is asymmetric: universal theories may be refuted
other hand, they were anxious to justify their theories by an by singular statements (the observation of a black swan)
appeal to sources of knowledge comparable in reliability to the (Popper, 1976a, p 86). It follows that hypotheses cannot be
RJ Ormerod—History and ideas of critical rationalism 445

verified as envisaged by the method of induction. (If to date be false (have failed a test according to accepted basic state-
only white swans have been observed, another observation ments). The sorting is, of course, undertaken by scientists and
of a white swan does not verify or increase the probability scientists are humans subject to prejudices, biases and errors
of the statement that ‘all swans are white’.) (to this extent idealism is right). It is through the involvement
On demarcation, the logical positivists held that any of a community of scientists exercising their critical facul-
statements, which could not be assessed either by appeal ties that objectivity can be sought. As Popper puts it: ‘But to
to empirical evidence (synthetically true or false) or by obtain objectivity we cannot rely on the empty mind: objec-
appeal to the meaning of words and the grammatical struc- tivity rests on criticism, on critical discussion, and on the crit-
ture that constitutes them (analytically true or false), were ical examination of experiments’ (Popper, 1983, p 84). Thus
meaningless; this included metaphysical, religious, aesthetic, prejudice, biases and errors are driven out (thus in the end
and ethical claims. (Fotion, 1995, p 507). Popper instead realism is right).
held that these claims were by his definition not scientific,
but they were far from meaningless. What is intellectually Defence against induction and psychologism
disreputable is pseudo-science, which arises when holders of
To defend his position Popper has to ensure that induction
an empirical theory refuse to be deflected by observational
does not creep back in and he attempts to identify and expose
disproof or where a supposed scientific theory never makes
the presence of induction in his opponents’ arguments (his
any predictions (O’Hear, 1995a, p 702). Popper held that non-
opponents similarly try to find evidence of induction in his
science was crucial to the pre-science process of developing
arguments). He also needs to keep out any argument that
hypotheses; for instance, the idea of all matter consisting of
involved ‘psychologism’, anything that results in speculation
atoms was hypothesised (by Leucippus and Democritus in the
about sensations or beliefs: he has built his castle from logic
fifth century BC) long before it could be empirically tested.
not psychological speculation. He argues that the then current
almost universal belief in inductive logic was largely due to
The problem of ad hoc hypotheses and basic statements a confusion of psychological problems with epistemological
ones (Popper, 1959, p 30). To avoid psychologism (individual
Popper observed that when faced with falsifying evidence, it
psychological judgements or beliefs) Popper suggests that the
was always possible that the purveyor of an incorrect theory
objectivity of scientific statements lies in the fact that they can
or a pseudo-science could react by adding ad hoc an auxiliary
be inter-subjectively tested (Popper, 1959, p 44). To be inter-
hypothesis or by changing ad hoc a definition to their ‘law’
subjectively testable they must always have the character of
rather than discarding it. For instance, the discovery of black
universal statements (Popper, 1959, p 45n).
swan-like birds in Australia could lead to the classification
One particularly difficult problem Popper faced was how
of a new type of bird or to a change in the theory to exclude
to deal with laws couched in terms of probabilities: could
swans in the Southern Hemisphere, leaving the original asser-
probabilities avoid psychologism? Almost half of Logic is
tion of whiteness intact. Of course, the addition of ad hoc
concerned with probabilities. There are two issues: (i) how
qualifiers might in practice be an improvement for predic-
can a hypothesis, which predicts an event will occur with a
tive purposes, but the aim of science is to discover universal
given probability, be falsified by empirical evidence, and (ii)
laws; every added ad hoc hypothesis weakens this prospect.
whether a more frequently tested hypothesis is more probable
The aim therefore, to be adopted as a convention, is to falsify
than one that has been little tested? The first issue Popper
hypotheses rather than to use ad hoc additions to bolster them
refers to as the probability of events; the second, the proba-
up (Popper, 1959, p 43).
bility of hypotheses, he considers under the heading of corrob-
The other reaction to falsifying evidence is to reject the
oration (Popper, 1959, p 146).
evidence, arguing perhaps that the conditions were wrong,
the experimenters were incompetent, or that some deliberate
The probability of events
attempt to deceive was involved. Perhaps repetitions of the
experiment by different researchers in different laboratories Probabilities were central to the new physics based on
could clear up the disagreement; but to conclude that falsi- quantum mechanics. Popper claimed that physicists used
fying observations had been verified is itself an inductive probability without providing a satisfactory consistent defi-
statement. Thus the soundness or otherwise of basic or what nition of it. He split the task into two: (i) to provide new
are sometimes called protocol statements (statements of the foundations for the calculus of probability and (ii) to eluci-
empirical evidence) needs to be established. Popper’s solu- date the relations between probability and experience, or the
tion was to accept that all basic statements are falsifiable but problem of decidability. To help clarify quantum mechanics
at any time it is necessary to take a decision as to whether he needed an interpretation that was physical and objective,
a basic statement is to be accepted or not; it is the job of yielded probability hypotheses which could be statistically
scientists to decide. These basic statements are then used to tested, could be applicable to single cases, and are relative to
sort hypotheses into those that for the time being are accepted the experimental setup (Popper, 1976a, p 95). All subjective
as true (have yet to be falsified), and those that are taken to interpretations of probability, those that treat the degree of
446 Journal of the Operational Research Society Vol. 60, No. 4

probability as a measure of the degree of certainty or uncer- of truth or falsity may at any time itself be falsified (Tarski,
tainty, must be resisted (the Bayesian approach was a partic- 1956; Popper, 1972, pp 44–60).
ular target of attack). These can be recognized by expressions
such as ‘expectation’, ‘error’ and ‘belief’. Initially Popper The conduct of science
preferred a frequency interpretation. However, in Logic he
says that he had subsequently decided to replace this with Popper was not the first philosopher to suggest that scien-
an objective interpretation in terms of propensity (Popper, tific knowledge was fallible, the pragmatists, for instance,
1959, p 147n). This change is explained and developed in the were equally adamant on this point (Popper points out the
Postscript (Popper, 1983, pp 394–401). The propensity inter- amoeba also proceeds by trial and error); but he was the
pretation is, he suggests, that of classical statistical mechanics first to suggest that fallibility could provide solutions to the
(Popper, 1983, p 398). In Volumes II and III of the Postscript problems of induction and demarcation. Having established
he again applies his approach to quantum mechanics (Popper, his new perspective he then turned to how science should be
1982a, b). A review of Popper’s contribution to the philos- conducted:
ophy of probability can be found in Gillies (1995).
The problem of decidability is more distinctively method- Science is not a system of certain, or well-established, state-
ments; nor is it a system which steadily advances towards a
ological: probability hypotheses do not rule out anything
state of finality. Our science is not knowledge (episteme): it
observable; logically therefore such statements cannot be
can never claim to have attained truth, or even a substitute for
falsified. However, Popper had to accept that a physicist is it, such as probability [episteme is the old scientific ideal of
usually quite able to decide whether he may for the time absolutely certain, demonstrable knowledge]. Yet science has
being accept some probability hypothesis as ‘empirically more than mere biological survival value. It is not only a useful
confirmed’, or whether he ought to reject it as ‘practically instrument. Although it can attain neither truth nor probability,
falsified’, that is, useless for the purposes of prediction the striving for knowledge and the search for truth are still the
(Popper, 1959, pp 189–190). strongest motivation of scientific discovery. We do not know:
we can only guess. And our guesses are guided by the unsci-
entific, the metaphysical (though biologically explicable) faith
Corroboration in laws, in regularities that we can uncover—discover. Like
Bacon, we might describe our own contemporary science—‘the
If the principle of induction is untenable and hypotheses
method of reasoning which men now ordinarily apply to nature’
cannot be verified, what can be said? If we cannot prove some-
as consisting of ‘anticipations, rash and premature’ and of
thing is true or false, can we say it is more or less probable? ‘prejudices’ (Bacon, 1620). But these marvellously and bold
Popper suggests that instead of assessing the ‘probability’ of conjectures or ‘anticipations’ of ours are carefully and soberly
a hypothesis we should try to assess what tests, what trials, it controlled by systematic tests. Once put forward, none of our
has withstood; that is, we should try to assess how far it has ‘anticipations’ are dogmatically upheld. Our method of research
been able to prove its fitness to survive by standing up to tests; is not to defend them, in order to prove how right we were.
how far has it been corroborated (Popper, 1959, p 251); how On the contrary, we try to overthrow them. (Popper, 1959,
far has it ‘proved its mettle’ under fire? Given a theory and pp 278–279, original emphasis).
some accepted basic statements (data), the theory is corrob-
orated if these basic statements do not contradict the theory, Popper’s ideas on the conduct of science contradicted the
and it does this with due regard to the degree of testability of then current belief of scientists that they were engaged in a
the theory, and the severity of the tests to which the theory cumulative exercise of establishing the truth about the nature
has been subjected up to a stated point in time. Corrobora- of the world. Nevertheless, in Popper’s new perspective they
tion should not be equated to truth as it is time dependent: found a compelling account of the logic of science in the
it depends on the basic statements that have been obtained light of the revolution they had been experiencing in physics.
up to a particular time. In contrast the pragmatists proposed Furthermore, Popper’s model of bold conjectures and discrim-
to define truth in terms of the success of a theory—thus of inating tests is one they found they could fruitfully bring to
its usefulness, or of its confirmation or of its corroboration bear on their research programmes. Eminent scientists in the
(Popper, 1959, pp 266–276). second half of the 20th century came to regard Popper as
Using aspects of the theory of the truth of sentences devel- the greatest living philosopher of science (Magee, 1973, p 9).
oped by the Polish mathematician Alfred Tarski (1902–1983), Popper’s emphasis on falsification seemed to come as some-
Popper developed his concept of verisimilitude. Verisimili- thing of a relief to scientists—they no longer had to hold on
tude reflects the degree to which the hypothesis corresponds to the scientific laws that they had come to believe or even
to the truth defined in terms of its content (which will contain perhaps had themselves established; as Einstein said: ‘No
both true and false consequences). A theory which has some fairer destiny could be allotted to any physical theory than
false consequences may thus be retained because it has greater itself point out the way to introducing a more comprehensive
verisimilitude than competing theories. Any judgement about theory in which it lives as a limited case’ (Albert Einstein
verisimilitude will, of course, be fallible and the evidence quoted in Popper, 1983, p 131).
RJ Ormerod—History and ideas of critical rationalism 447

Criticism of Popper’s approach to scientific discovery to be more precise, have to relinquish the notion, explicit
or implicit, that changes of paradigm carry scientists and
Despite the positive response of scientists, Popper’s theories those who learn from them closer and closer to the truth.’
on the logic of scientific inquiry came under attack from (Kuhn, 1962, p 170). Kuhn had produced an evolutionary
philosophers, sociologists and historians of science from the view of science, not so much an evolution-towards-what-we-
word go. Much of the philosophical criticism centred on the wish-to-know, rather an evolution-from-what-we-do-know
logical implications of his formulation. He rebutted these (Kuhn, 1962, p 171). He rejected any emphasis on falsifica-
vigorously. However, he ran into most difficulty on the soci- tion rather than verification. When confronted by anomalies
ological/historical question of how scientists actually went scientists do not renounce the paradigm that led them into
about their business. The debate, initiated by Kuhn, attracted the crisis: ‘No process yet disclosed by the historical study
Lakatos, Feyerabend and others. Published only three years of scientific development at all resembles the methodological
after Popper’s Logic, Thomas Kuhn’s The Structure of Scien- stereotype of falsification by direct comparison with nature’
tific Revolutions (Kuhn, 1962) is credited with being one (Kuhn, 1962, p 77).
of the most influential books of the 20th century. Fuller The only time that Popper and Kuhn met was at a collo-
explains why the book achieved rapid prominence, ‘Structure quium held in 1965 in London. A session, chaired by Popper,
received appreciatively critical reviews by those interested in was dedicated to discussing Kuhn’s ideas. The papers given
reviving the fortunes of the American national philosophy, (together with some that were not) and a response from Kuhn
pragmatism, which had been eclipsed by logical positivism. were published in Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge
. . . Kuhn’s focus on science as a mode of experience was (Lakatos and Musgrove, 1970). A recurrent theme was the
credited with having reintroduced a “human” dimension to existence, nature and role of what Kuhn had labelled normal
science that had been the hallmark of pragmatism . . . .’ (Fuller, science as opposed to revolutionary science. The critics
2003, p 30) tended to disparage Kuhn’s normal science as boring and
In Structure, Kuhn suggested that scientific endeavour can dull, conducted by hacks and in any case ill-defined, with
be characterized by periods of ‘normal’ science interspersed the transition to exploratory science based on some sort of
infrequently with revolutions. During the period of normal vague mystical intuition (ideology). Kuhn was able to show
science, work is carried out under a particular paradigm that that his perspective, based in the first instance on careful
determines how the domain is understood, what theoretical historical observation, was no less logical, nor more ideo-
and methodological beliefs are taken for granted, what types logical than Popper’s perspective, based in the first instance,
of problems are addressed, what types of experiments are on logic. He accepted that Popper’s approach (scientists
conducted, what types of measurements are made and so on. should try at all times to be a critic and a proliferator of
If an unexpected result is obtained it is treated as an anomaly, alternate theories) was appropriate for revolutionary periods
perhaps the experimenter did something wrong, perhaps some but he urged ‘the desirability of an alternative strategy which
adjustment to some aspect is required. It is very difficult for reserves such behaviour for special occasions’ (Kuhn, 1970,
scientists to shift paradigms in the middle of their career; p 243). He argues that once a new theory (a new frame-
as a consequence they may spend their whole career in one work or paradigm) is in hand ‘the time for steady criticism
paradigm. At some point a new way of looking at things is and theory proliferation has passed’ (p 246). In such a case
suggested and a period of extraordinary, exploratory research ‘practitioners of mature sciences are freed to explore nature
identifies and develops a new paradigm. Particularly younger to an esoteric depth and detail otherwise unimaginable’ (p
scientists and scientists new to the field, unencumbered with 247). It is these productive periods of normal science that
past commitments, start to adopt the new paradigm because it distinguish science from other intellectual activities (such
is thought to be productive in solving some of the problems of as philosophy which is continuously in critical mode) and
the existing paradigm. Symptoms of a transition from normal accounts for its very success. Ultimately anomalies will alert
to extraordinary research may include the proliferation of scientists that there is a crisis looming and it is time for
competing articulations, the willingness to try anything, the them to become Popperian critics. Thus the Kuhnian model
expression of explicit discontent, the recourse to philosophy is an extension to the Popper model rather than an outright
and debate over fundamentals. Once a transition is underway rejection of it. Kuhn’s paper in Lakatos and Musgrove
the older schools gradually disappear. ‘To be accepted as a (1970) cemented his reputation as an insightful and subtle
paradigm, a theory must seem better than its competitors, commentator on science. However, Kuhn is clear that his
but it need not, and in fact never does, explain all the facts observations and interpretation are not simply a contribution
with which it can be confronted’ (Kuhn, 1962, p 18). It is to the history of science; rather, he is providing normative
very difficult to compare two paradigms because of their guidance as to how science should be taught, conducted and
incommensurability: proponents of competing paradigms organized.
fail to make complete contact with each other’s viewpoints Imre Lakatos (1922–1974), an LSE colleague of Popper,
(Kuhn, 1962, p 148). Kuhn is explicit that the new paradigm is generally depicted as coming into the debate on Popper’s
is not necessarily closer to the truth than the old: ‘We may, side. The starting point of Lakatos’ work was not that
448 Journal of the Operational Research Society Vol. 60, No. 4

knowledge existed but that it grows. The growth of knowledge Social and political science
provides a demarcation between ‘rational’ activity and ‘irra-
Historicism
tionalism’. Whereas the logical positivist Carnap had argued
that a good reason for a hypothesis is high probability in the The question of what methods or methodological approach
light of evidence and Popper had offered his conjectures and to adopt in the social sciences is the subject of The Poverty
refutations, Lakatos suggested examining and sorting past of Historicism (Popper, 1944/5). Popper defines ‘historicism’
sequences of theories to see whether they are degenerating as ‘an approach to the social sciences which assumes that
or progressive. A degenerating programme is one that grad- historical prediction is the principal aim, and which assumes
ually becomes closed in on itself with auxiliary hypotheses that this aim is attainable by discovering the “rhythms” or the
continually being added to deal with counterexamples. “patterns”, the “laws” or the “trends” that underlie the evolu-
Progressive programmes respond to new examples with tion of history’ (Popper, 1944/5, p 3). The person Popper most
strong new predictions, some of which turn out to be right. closely associates with historicism is the German sociologist
Despite their differences Lakatos continued to keep Popper’s Karl Mannheim (1893–1947), one of the founders of the ‘soci-
hypothetico-deductive reasoning at the centre of his own ology of knowledge’. Historicism claims that the methods of
ideas (Lakatos, 1970, 1981; Hacking, 1981). physics cannot be applied to the social sciences. The laws of
Feyerabend, a student of Popper’s, attacked Lakatos for social life differ in different places and periods; they depend
following the pragmatist CS Peirce (1839–1914) in replacing on a particular historical situation. Apart from trivial truisms
truth by method. In Against Method (Feyerabend, 1975) he (for instance, human beings always live in groups) there are
based his arguments on both historical analysis of scien- no long-run uniformities in society on which long-term gener-
tific discovery and, very importantly, its cultural context. He alizations could be based. A method which ignores this limi-
concluded that ‘the events, procedures and results that consti- tation and attempts to generalise will implicitly assume regu-
tute the sciences have no common structure . . . Successful larities are everlasting (Popper, 1944/5, pp 5–8).
research does not obey general standards; it relies now on one Historicists argue that social science runs into all sorts
trick, now on another . . . there can be many different kinds of difficulties if it tries to use the experimental methods of
of science’ (Feyerabend, 1975, pp 1–2). The approaches of physics. Artificial controls and conditions, which allow the
Kuhn (based on paradigms) and Lakatos (based on research reproduction of similar conditions, eliminate precisely those
programmes) both take a historical approach. Larry Laudan factors in sociology which are most important. Large-scale
in his Progress and its Problems (1977) developed a third experiments are never experiments in the physical sense: they
such approach based on research traditions. Laudan argued are not made to advance knowledge as such, but to achieve
that scientists may accept or reject theories, but they may also political success. Moreover, their very performance changes
pursue them, entertain them and take a range of cognitive the conditions of society; they can never be repeated under
stances. He observed that there are always co-existent rivals precisely similar conditions. Even the observer is changed
and conceptual debates: it was difficult to find any lengthy by the experience of observing, habits are formed, learning
period of normal science in the history of any science in the occurs; an observer has a history. According to historicism,
last 300 years. society also experiences and learns and it too has a history;
Newton-Smith (1981) held that people are generally traditions and traditional loyalties and resentments, trust and
rational in their own terms, but scientists have a narrower distrust, could not otherwise play their important role in social
requirement to be scientifically rational. Sometimes scien- history. In the world of physics nothing can happen that is
tists will yield to different interests and act in a scientifically truly and intrinsically new; whatever is invented can always
non-rational way. However, the success of science suggests be analysed into the components parts. Social newness, like
that scientists generally act in a scientifically rational way biological newness, is an intrinsic sort of newness, a newness
because he or she believes that there is a general interest in irreducible to its component parts: real novelty is always
doing so. However, the way scientists form their beliefs and emerging. Historicism concludes that nothing is of greater
adopt (scientifically or personally rational) goals is something moment than the emergence of really new periods or stages
that can be the subject of research. This says Newton-Smith, in history, each of which differs intrinsically from any other
a philosopher, is the proper role of sociologists, a prospect (Popper, 1944/5, pp 8–11).
that earlier had not appealed to Popper (Popper, 1970, pp There are other methodological difficulties with social anal-
57–58). In fact, sociologists, psychologists, historians, and ysis. Social life is a natural phenomenon that presupposes
others (including those from the newer fields of cultural the mental life of individuals (psychology), which presup-
studies, literary theory and science studies) needed no second poses biology, which presupposes chemistry and physics. The
bidding: the stable door had already been opened by Kuhn in factors involved are therefore complex. Predictions may influ-
the 1960s. The open warfare between critics and defenders ence people’s behaviour; for instance, they may act to prevent
of science has raged to this day (Sardar, 2000). These attacks an unwelcome event. Most historicists believe that there is
draw their strength from the observation and interpretation an even deeper reason why the methods of physical science
of actual practice. cannot be applied to the social sciences, namely the holistic
RJ Ormerod—History and ideas of critical rationalism 449

character of social groups. They argue that the social group Historicists argue that attempts to use sociology to support
is more that the mere sum total of its members; a group can planned change (of the type OR might attempt) are doomed.
retain much of its original character even if all of its original Such micro-analysis, which is blind to the macro-analysis
members are replaced by others. If we wish to understand of the laws of development, could never form the basis for
and explain a group and perhaps foresee its future develop- realistic constructions. A plan based on social facts cannot
ment, we must study its history, its traditions, institutions and account for new features in any new period with its own
rites. In contrast, we do not need to know the history of the intrinsic novelty. Scientific reasoning in the social domain
solar system (the age of the planets, for instance) to project can only be used to tell us the direction activity must take
its behaviour (Popper, 1944/5, pp 11–19). if it is to coincide with the direction of impending changes.
A methodological doctrine, which is very closely related to Activists can help bring about the inevitable changes (the
historicism, is that the proper method of the social sciences is midwife theory of activism). The changes cannot be brought
based on an intimate understanding of social phenomena, an about by reason but only by harsh necessity. To this end the
intuitive understanding. According to this doctrine, physics most reasonable thing to do is to adjust one’s system of values
aims at causal explanation, whereas sociology aims at an so as to make it conform with the impending changes (Popper,
understanding of purpose and meaning. This is why physics 1944/5, pp 42–54). Table 1 summarizes Popper’s depiction of
operates with inductive generalizations whereas sociology can the historicists approach to natural and social science.
only operate with the help of sympathetic imagination; soci-
ology must be content with the intuitive understanding of Piecemeal engineering
unique events, and of the role they play in particular situ- In the preface to the Poverty of Historicism, Popper offers the
ations; events occur within particular struggles of interests, following refutation of historicism:
tendencies, and destinies. A sociological method must be
holistic in character: it must aim at determining the role played 1. The course of human history is strongly influenced by the
by the event within a complex structure—within a whole growth of human knowledge.
which comprises not only contemporaneous parts but also the 2. We cannot predict, by rational or scientific methods, the
successive stages of temporal development. This approach future growth of our scientific knowledge.
tends to rely on the analogy between an organism and a group, 3. We cannot, therefore, predict the future course of human
and it tends to operate with ideas such as that of a mind or history.
4. This means that we must reject the possibility of a theoretical
spirit of an age (Popper, 1944/5, pp 19–24).
history: that is to say, of a historical social science that would
Despite all the difficulties of making sociological predic-
correspond to theoretical physics. There can be no scientific
tions with any detail or precision, historicism argues that theory of historical prediction.
it is possible to make long-term, large-scale predictions 5. The fundamental aim of historicist methods is therefore
whose vagueness is balanced by their scope and signifi- misconceived (Popper, 1944/5, pp vi–vii, original emphasis).
cance. Although vague, the qualitative terms of social science
(‘culture clash’, ‘prosperity’, ‘solidarity’, ‘urbanization’, The decisive step in this argument is statement 2. It says that
‘utility’) provide a certain richness and comprehensiveness of if there is such a thing as growing human knowledge, then we
meaning. Large-scale forecasts are the only forecasts worth cannot anticipate today what we shall know only tomorrow.
attempting and the only observational source for such fore- In his Postscript Popper offers a logical proof; no society can
casts is history: in fact sociology is theoretical history. Histor- predict, scientifically, its own future state of knowledge.
ical forces, whether spiritual (eg ethical ideas) or material The main text of Poverty attacks historicism on prac-
(eg economic interests), are of fundamental importance. To tical rather than logical grounds: Popper chooses to call his
analyse, to disentangle this thicket of conflicting tendencies preferred approach ‘piecemeal engineering’. In doing so he
and forces and to penetrate to its roots, to the universal driving is trying to avoid the terms ‘social technology’ or ‘social
forces and laws of social change, this is the task of the social engineering’, which might be associated with the social blue
sciences as seen by historicism. To be generally valid, real prints of the collectivist planners. He suggests that ‘piecemeal
social laws would have to apply to the whole of human history engineering’, or ‘piecemeal tinkering’ combined with critical
covering all its periods. But for all the reasons noted above analysis, is the main way to achieve practical results in the
there can be no social uniformities that hold good beyond social as well as the natural sciences; the approach to both
a single period. Thus the only universally valid laws must should be based on trial and error. He is in effect advocating
be those that link up the successive periods. Sociology thus continuance of the classic approach to the social sciences,
becomes an attempt to solve the problem of foretelling the which had largely developed out of criticism of proposals for
future, not so much the future of the individual as that of the social improvement, or in other words whether or not some
group, and of the human race. Sociological study should help particular economic or political action is likely to produce
to reveal the political future, and it should become the fore- an expected or desired result. The emphasis on a practical
most instrument of far-sighted practical politics for politicians technological approach gives rise to theoretical questions
with a sense of social destiny (Popper, 1944/5, pp 35–41). which set the agenda for theoretical speculation and force
450 Journal of the Operational Research Society Vol. 60, No. 4

Table 1 Popper’s depiction of induction and historicism


Science Social Science
Focus of Interest Natural World Society as a whole
Objective of Analysis Universal laws Universal laws
(stages/changes)
Method of Analysis Induction Historicism
Experimental verification (historical analysis/holism/Utopianism)
Change Creation Physical engineering Midwife activism
Verified laws Utopian engineering of social
arrangements (laws, institutions etc)
Actors International community Intuitive social scientists
of scientists Leaders/Planners

us to submit our theories to definite standards of clarity and to Mannheim, the aim is to seize the key positions and to
practical testability (Popper, 1944/5, pp 58–59). Piecemeal extend the power of the state until the state becomes nearly
engineering can address such questions as, whether you can identical with society. Popper argues that the greater the
introduce agricultural tariffs and at the same time reduce the holistic changes attempted, the greater are their unintended
cost of living, or whether you can have a centrally planned and largely unexpected repercussions. In practice, the holists
society with a price system that fulfils the main functions of always fall back on a somewhat haphazard and clumsy appli-
competitive prices, or whether you can make a successful cation of what is essentially a piecemeal method, but without
revolution if the ruling class is not weakened by internal its cautious and self-critical character. While the piecemeal
dissension or defeat in war. Piecemeal social engineering engineers can attack their problem with an open mind as to
resembles physical engineering in regarding ends as beyond the scope of the reform, the holists cannot do this; they have
the province of technology. (All that technology may say decided beforehand that a complete reconstruction is possible
about ends is whether or not they are compatible with each and necessary. Any resistance to large scale change needs to
other or realizable.) In this it differs from historicism, which be suppressed, leaving little room for discussion, admission
regards the ends of human activities as dependent on histor- of errors and learning. On the other hand in the piecemeal
ical forces and so within its province. approach ‘a systematic fight against definite wrongs, against
The task of piecemeal social engineers is to design social concrete forms of injustice or exploitation, and avoidable
institutions (private and public, from corner shop to an educa- suffering such as poverty or unemployment, is a very different
tional system), and to reconstruct and run those already in thing from the attempt to realize a distant ideal blueprint of
existence. They recognize that only a minority of social insti- society. Success or failure is more easily appraised, and there
tutions are consciously designed while the vast majority have is no inherent reason why this method should lead to an
just ‘grown’ as the undesigned results of human actions. They accumulation of power, and to the suppression of criticism.
will look at institutions from a ‘functional’ or ‘instrumental’ Such a fight against concrete wrongs and concrete dangers
point of view, as machines to achieve certain ends rather is more likely to find the support of a great majority than a
than as organisms. Piecemeal engineers do not believe in fight for the establishment of a Utopia’ (Popper, 1944/5, pp
re-designing society as a whole. Whatever the ends, they try 91–92). Table 2 summarizes Popper’s position on natural and
to achieve them by small adjustments and re-adjustments. The social science.
ends may be of diverse kinds, for example, the accumulation
of wealth or of power by certain individuals, or by certain
Open and closed societies
groups; or the distribution of wealth and power; or the protec-
tion of certain ‘rights’ of individuals or groups. Thus public or In the Open Society and its Enemies (Popper, 1945a, b),
political social engineering may have the most diverse tenden- Popper ‘selects some events from the history of historicist
cies, totalitarian as well as liberal. The piecemeal engineer thought, in order to illustrate its persistent and pernicious
knows, like Socrates, how little he knows. He knows that we influence upon the philosophy of society and of politics, from
can learn only by our mistakes (Popper, 1944/5, pp 64–67). Heraclitus and Plato to Hegel and Marx’ (Popper, 1944/5,
Popper contrasts piecemeal engineering with Utopian engi- p viii). Popper argues that a fundamental choice confronting
neering. Holistic or Utopian social engineering is never of a humanity is whether to adopt a closed, tribal way of life
‘private’ but always of a ‘public’ character; it aims at remod- or an open society. The closed society has just one view of
elling the whole of society in accordance with a definite plan the world, one set of values, one way of life: it is a world
or blueprint. He associates historicism, holism and Utopi- dominated by dogma, taboos and magic, a world devoid of
anism with fascism and Marxism; all are dissatisfied with doubt and uncertainty. The open society, by contrast, toler-
piecemeal engineering and muddling through. According ates a diversity of views, values and ways of life. In the open
RJ Ormerod—History and ideas of critical rationalism 451

Table 2 Popper’s falsification and piecemeal engineering


Science Social Science
Focus of Interest Natural World Society as people and institutions
Objective of Analysis Severely tested Effect of policy changes
hypotheses (conditional, local models)
Method of Analysis Conjecture Conjecture
Experimental Refutation Experiment via piecemeal engineering
Change Creation Physical engineering Piecemeal engineering of social
Best corroborated laws arrangements (laws, institutions etc)
Actors International community Analytical social scientists
of scientists Citizens and their representatives

society learning through criticism is possible just because tenet of Marxism is the idea that the laws of dialectical mate-
diverse views and values are tolerated. For Popper, the open rialism determine the evolution of the means of production,
society is the civilized society, in which individual freedom and this in turn determines the evolution of everything else,
and responsibility, justice, democracy, humane values, reason from class struggle to culture, religion, the law and politics.
and science can flourish (Maxwell, 2007). In rejecting this view Popper argues that historical predictions
Moving from the closed to the open society imposes a great made by Marx, on the basis of his economic historicism, have
psychological burden on the individuals involved. Instead of been falsified by subsequent historical events. The Russian
the security of the tribe, organic, dogmatic and devoid of revolution is, for example, entirely at odds with Marx’s theory,
doubt, there is all the uncertainty and insecurity of an ‘abstract as is the way in which the unrestricted capitalism of Marx’s
society’ and the painful necessity of taking personal respon- time has subsequently become more just and humane as a
sibility for one’s life in a state of ignorance. Many cannot result of diverse political interventions. Popper prefers an open
bear the burden of freedom and doubt, and long for the false society with elected rulers. He accepts that this may some-
security and certainties of the closed society. Some of the times put in power a ruler who turns out to be tyrannical but
greatest thinkers of western civilization have given in to this he argues that so long as the mechanism is in place for the
temptation and have, in one way or another, urged a return ruler to be (democratically) removed then the error can be
to something like a closed society under the guise of Utopia. corrected.
The lure of totalitarianism is built deep into our history and
traditions (Maxwell, 2007).
Popper depicts Socrates as the advocate of the Athenian Criticism of Popper’s political and social views
open society: his passionate scepticism, his searching criti- Of particular interest is the so-called Positivismusstreit (or
cism of current beliefs and ideals, his conviction that first positivist conflict). Popper was invited to give an address on
one must acknowledge one’s own ignorance before one could the logic of the social sciences with Adorno responding as
hope to acquire knowledge and wisdom. Plato on the other discussant. The occasion was meant to help German social
hand is depicted as the advocate of the closed society (he scientific and philosophy circles understand and debate
was particularly enamoured by Sparta): the tribal arrange- the competing positions of critical rationalism and critical
ments of old were the ideal, historical change involves decay theory. To everyone’s disappointment the anticipated conflict
and degeneration, and all that enlightened philosopher-rulers did not happen as Adorno largely agreed with Popper’s
can do is arrest change somewhat. Popper traces a direct link position—they were both opposed to positivism. In a different
from Plato to Marx via Hegel. All three philosophers uphold way the ‘dispute’ was continued in a series of publications
versions of historicism. Plato and Hegel were both pessimistic by Jürgen Habermas and Hans Albert (a critical rationalist).
historicists. Marx, by contrast, was an optimistic historicist: The various papers were included in the 1969 book Der Posi-
historical development will eventually result in socialism and tivismusstreit in der deustchen Soziologie (Adorno, 1969)
freedom (Popper, 1945a, b). and in an expanded English version (Adorno, 1976). Adorno
Popper depicts Hegel as a complete intellectual fraud. In was against positivism because (according to critical theory)
contrast, he pays tribute to Marx’s sincerity, his humani- science along with other forms of arguing (dialectics) and
tarianism, his intellectual honesty, his hatred of moralizing knowing (including sociology and philosophy) should be
verbiage and hypocrisy, his sense of facts and his sincere understood as a manifestation of the way mankind and
quest for the truth, his important contributions to historical society has developed. Science cannot therefore be under-
studies and social science, and his burning desire to help the stood as foundational, free of assumptions. Both natural and
oppressed. But these good points are, for Popper, more than social science have to be seen in this light: primacy should
counterbalanced by the dreadful defects, most of which stem not therefore be afforded to science. Popper comes to the
from Marx’s historicism, inherited from Hegel. The central same conclusion for quite different reasons. The thrust of his
452 Journal of the Operational Research Society Vol. 60, No. 4

argument can be gleaned from the following: istry and physics: new properties arise at each level inexpli-
cable in terms of the level below. Humans are influenced by
It is a mistake to assume that the objectivity of a science depends abstract concepts such as theories, standards and values that
upon the objectivity of the scientist. And it is a mistake to cannot be reduced to physical objects. He sees these concepts
believe that the attitude of the natural scientist is more objective
as forming an abstract world of ideas which are not merely
than that of the social scientist. The natural scientist is just
as partisan as other people . . . .. What may be described as
instinctive but which can be chosen (and rationally criticized)
scientific objectivity is based solely upon a critical tradition in the light of ideas from ethics, aesthetics, science and so on
which, despite resistance, often makes it possible to criticize (O’Hear, 1980, p 175).
a dominant dogma. To put it another way, the objectivity of Popper captures these ideas in his three world model.
science is not a matter of the individual scientists but rather World 1 is the world of physical objects and states. World
the social result of their mutual criticism, of the friendly-hostile 2 is the world of states of consciousness, mental states and
division of labour amongst scientists, of their co-operation and behavioural disposition to act. World 3 is the world of the
also of their competition. For this reason, it depends, in part, objective contents of thought (including particular scientific
upon a number of social and political circumstances. (Popper, and artistic theories about worlds 1 and 2) and of institutions
1976b, p 95) and values, considered abstractly. It has much in common with
Plato’s Forms or Ideas, Hegel’s Objective Spirit, Bolzano’s
The social and political circumstances that Popper has
theory of a universe of truths in themselves, and Frege’s
in mind are, of course, exemplified by an open society. In
objective contents of thought. It stands in opposition to those
Popper’s final short piece added to the English translation of
such as Descartes, Locke, Berkley, Hume, Kant or Russell
Der Positivismusstreit he concludes that the main issue of the
who are interested in our subjective beliefs, and their basis or
book is the accusation that he is bound by his methodology,
origin (Popper, 1972, pp 106–107). World 3 is autonomous,
which his critics equate to ‘positivism’, to defend the status
totally independent of anybody’s claim to know. In world 3
quo. He responds by pointing out that he has often combated
spoken language allows the creation and mutation of explana-
such a position. His theory of method is a theory of scien-
tory myths, and this is further supported by written language.
tific and intellectual revolutions. However, he admits that his
Science replaces the elimination of error in the violent
social theory favours gradual reform, reform controlled by
struggle for life by non-violent rational criticism: this allows
critical comparison between expected and achieved results.
us to replace killing (world 1) and intimidation (world 2) by
This he says is the only alternative to violence so far discov-
the impersonal arguments of world 3 (Popper, 1972, p 84).
ered: ‘it is the obvious duty of all intellectuals to work for this
World 3, Popper says, includes theoretical systems, prob-
revolution—for the replacement of the eliminative function
lems and problem situations (Popper, 1972, p 254). The
of violence by the eliminative function of rational criticism’
nucleus of world 3, the world of problems, theories and
(Popper, 1976b, pp 291–292).
criticism, is dominated by values, the values of objective
truth and of its growth (Popper, 1976a, pp 194–195). The
Evolution and Popper’s three worlds
intellectual (epistemic) values such as truth, the search for
Popper, concerned to place human knowledge in an evolu- truth, the approximation to truth through the elimination of
tionary context, turned to Darwinism for a general frame- errors and clarity of expression, support this quest (Popper,
work. He saw Darwinism as an application of the ‘logic of 1994, p 70). Values such as kindness, justice and alleviation
the situation’: mutations are thrown up (tentative solutions) of suffering, also have a place in world 3. These values (rela-
and those unsuited to the environment do not survive (error tive to a certain problem) may be created or discovered, and
elimination). This is true of all organisms but humans have discussed in relation to other values and to other problems.
the ability to address the problem of survival linguistically, Discussion and criticism of Popper’s evolutionary views of
a form that can be criticized and tested before putting our knowledge can be found in O’Hear (1980, pp 171–204) and
lives at stake (Popper, 1972, p 261). In the process something Smithurst (1995).
new has emerged: as well as there being a radical disconti-
nuity between the living and the non-living, there is a discon-
Popper in Operational Research
tinuity between animal communication systems and human
language. Emergence and novelty can be understood in terms The origins of OR lie in the activities of scientists employed
of a rejection of determinism at the biological level, a stance to help make military operations more effective during World
supported by the rejection of determinism at the level of War II (Kirby, 2003). Popper describes the methods of
physics and chemistry (in other words acceptance of a belief science thus: ‘A scientist whether theorist or experimenter,
that real physical processes are probabilistic). This indeter- puts forward statements, or systems of statements and tests
minism underpins his philosophy of freedom and choice at them step by step. In the field of the empirical sciences,
the psychological, social and political levels. In addition, he more particularly, he constructs hypotheses or systems of
rejects the idea that sociology can be reduced to psychology, theories and tests them against experience of observation
which in turn can be reduced to biology, and so on to chem- and measurement’ (Popper, 1959, p 27). OR has from its
RJ Ormerod—History and ideas of critical rationalism 453

inception positioned itself within science: working within than has been noticed from other points of view. He suggests
the ethos of science the pioneers saw themselves applying ‘that the would-be-scientific intervener typically would like
the methods of science. Thus when Logic was published (in to work with the falsifiable category, practices mostly in the
English) it created much interest among OR scientists and criticizable category, and largely goes along with the non-
I think it is fair to say that, like other scientists, they took falsifiable category without discerning it as such’ (Boothroyd,
the lessons of falsification on board. Nevertheless, Popper’s 1978, p 78).
rather stark assertion that it was the role of scientists to over- Popper depicts both the natural and social sciences as
throw hypotheses did not fit the OR practitioners’ day-to-day problem solving activities driven forward by criticism:
activities particularly well. In reality, much time was spent
P1 → TT → EE → P2
in trying to establish facts and relationships from scarce and
poor data for clients used to managing ‘by the seat of their where P stands for problem, TT for tentative theory, EE
pants’: the challenge was often to demonstrate to managers, for (attempted) error-elimination especially by way of crit-
who valued action, that there was also merit in analysis. ical discussion (Popper, 1972, p 287). When it comes to
the social sciences, as we have seen, he places his faith in
piecemeal engineering: in other words he addresses prac-
Boothroyd and articulate intervention
tice directly. In The Myth of the Framework (Popper, 1994,
One practitioner who took Popper very seriously was Hylton pp 154–194) he describes how such an approach is applied in
Boothroyd. He placed Popper’s philosophy at the centre social science practice. From this it can be seen why Popper’s
of his approach, Articulate Intervention (Boothroyd, 1978). work resonates so strongly with OR. He first differentiates
When Boothroyd was forming his ideas the debate was raging between the problem of explaining or predicting ‘singular
about the nature of science. Boothroyd’s conception of OR is events’ (an example from the natural sciences would be, when
that of consultants intervening in the action programmes of will the next lunar eclipse occur, or from the social sciences,
clients. The activities of the consultants themselves can also when will there be the next rise in unemployment in the
be thought of as an action programme. Thus an intervention Midlands or Western Ontario?) and predicting or explaining
involves two action programmes that together can be thought a certain ‘kind or type’ of event (why do lunar eclipses occur
of as a joint client–consultant action programme. Boothroyd again and again and only when there is a full moon, or
took his concept of ‘action programmes’ from Lakatos’ why is there a seasonal increase and decrease in the building
research programmes. He was not so much interested in the industry?). The first problem can be addressed using universal
progressive or degenerative nature of programmes as the idea laws together with initial conditions without constructing a
that an OR intervention could be seen in terms of the creative model. The second problem is most easily solved by means of
possibilities of combining the programme of the interveners constructing a model. Popper refers to these as ‘rough’ models
(the consultants) with that of the entered organization (the because they do not pretend to represent either the actual situ-
client). Following Lakatos, action programmes are charac- ation or the actual mechanism involved. In science, the model
terized by the (core) theories and proposals they embody. (eg a physical model or a drawing) replaces the need to specify
Boothroyd’s concept of ‘theories’ is a fairly straightforward initial conditions but does require ‘animating’ universal laws.
application of the ideas of Popper (Boothroyd, 1978, p 22). In the social sciences, prediction of singular events from initial
As we have seen Popper divides statements between those conditions is hardly ever applicable; the social sciences almost
that are falsifiable (science) and those which are not (non- always proceeds by constructing models. Popper says, ‘The
science, metaphysics and so on). However, Boothroyd notes fundamental problem of both the theoretical and the histor-
that Popper later ‘felt the need for a more general category ical social sciences is to explain and understand events in
than falsifiability, or perhaps for a middle ground: the criticiz- terms of human action and social situations. The key term
able.’ Boothroyd characterizes the three categories as follows. here is ‘social situation’ (Popper, 1994, p 166). The ‘models’
The falsifiable category contains hard-edged findings of ideas of the theoretical social sciences are essentially descriptions
left standing after imaginative observation which leaves no or reconstructions of typical social situations.
room for serious doubt according to the standing proposals In the construction of relevant models, Popper introduces
of the scientific community of the day. The non-falsifiable the idea of the ‘situational logic’ of typical social situations.
carries with it both the untestable ground theories of being When addressing a particular problem, analysis of the situ-
and thinking that we use and many of the notions by which ational logic enables the relevant factors to be brought to the
we organise ourselves: theories of long-term consequences fore while bracketing the infinity of situational details that
of various ethical principles and of various forms of social might be relevant on some other occasion. This allows the
organizations. The criticizable carries with it the notion that model to be built. However, the model needs to be ‘animated’
theories can be appraised against observation provided that by an assumption that the various persons act adequately or
one can start from a declared point of view which is one of appropriately according to the situation (known in the liter-
many, but from which it is possible to declare that, from that ature as the ‘rationality principle’). Popper states, ‘that this
point of view one can discern coherence over a wider range has little or nothing to do with the empirical or psychological
454 Journal of the Operational Research Society Vol. 60, No. 4

.
T
. T . .
T T . .
T T C C
T . C C
T . . . .
T A . .
. T A . C
. A C C
T C C
A
. C C
.
. . .
. C
P C
. A C
P C .
P
P A . .
P . . . .
P .
. C
P
C C
.
P C .
.
P

T indicates theories, P proposals, A actions, C consequences


Boxing indicates those which are active at a particular point in an intervention

Figure 1 Articulate intervention (Boothroyd, 1978, p 141).

assertion that man always, or in the main, or in most cases, of Boothroyd’s articulate intervention is given in Figure 1
acts rationally’. He agrees that the animating assumption of (Boothroyd, 1978, p 141). He suggests that the diagram acts
the rationality principle can clearly be seen to be false by as a direct reminder that in an episode of articulate reflection:
observing people’s behaviour. He further concedes that if the
rationality principle is false, then the model incorporating it 1. active theories [the boxed set of Ts in Figure 1] are drawn
must also be false. But he asks, can any model be true? His from an indefinitely large set of latent theories [Ts],
answer is no, any model in physics or social science, must be 2. active proposals [the boxed set of Ps] are drawn from an
an over-simplification: it must omit much and over-emphasize indefinitely large set of latent proposals [Ps], including
much. Situational models are not unusual in this respect and proposals about conditional action in various circum-
Popper believes they are the proper method of social science stances by all the relevant action programmes and
(he cites economics, social anthropology, sociology of power including proposals about measures of achievement,
politics, and social or political history) (Popper, 1994, 3. both active and latent proposals presume an indefinitely
pp 169–172). large cascade of supporting proposals, indefinitely large
Boothroyd places modelling at the centre of his conception behind each sector of the supporting cascade, and reaching
of articulate intervention referring to it as reflection before back indefinitely into the traditions of society and into
action: ‘At one extreme there is reflection which has no hint conflicting views about them,
of theoretical content however ill-founded; and at the other 4. actively considered actions [the boxed set of As] are drawn
extreme there is reflection whose entire content has been from an indefinitely large repertoire of imagined actions
exhaustively tested to the limits of human critical ingenuity’. [As],
In other words, the completely mindless and the known-to-be- 5. articulate reflection includes the combining of theories
almost-certainly-correct. ‘In between lies our actual reflection and proposals to imagine the consequences [Cs] of imag-
on . . . the imperfectly imagined futures we wish to happen ined actions, including the consequences conditional on
or we wish to avoid: futures about which . . . our delibera- future circumstances and including estimates of proposed
tions with ourselves and our persuasive arguments with others measures of achievement, and
take place in far less completely articulated ways than the 6. articulate reflection includes the acts of including and
published argumentative output from research programmes in excluding conceptualizable consequences from the actively
mathematics or the natural sciences’ (Boothroyd, 1978, p 47). considered set of consequences. (Boothroyd, 1978, pp
In Popper’s terms OR is very clearly engaged in piecemeal 141–142)
engineering. Perhaps the difference is that in the practice of
OR initial conditions are required to make specific predic- Boothroyd observes that in considering Figure 1 ‘an engi-
tions of the consequences of actions. A simplified diagram neer is concerned with being aware of the latent content of
RJ Ormerod—History and ideas of critical rationalism 455

four sets [theories, proposals, actions, consequences] and with correspondence with the facts as elucidated by Tarski]. For the
selecting and using four active sets under the proposal that he difference is that, in the search for knowledge, we are out to find
plans to achieve some consequences, whether it be something true theories, or at least theories which are nearer than others
as simple as the design of a small component or as complex to the truth—which correspond better to the facts; whereas in
as the construction of a highly automated factory. In contrast, the search for theories that are merely powerful instruments for
certain purposes, we are, in many cases, quite well served by
a pure scientist would seem to be more concerned with the
theories which are known to be false. (Popper, 1963, p 226)
proposal that he critically investigate the standing of a partic-
ular theory and its supporting cascade, or that he undertake
As OR’s primary aim is not to establish scientific knowl-
action heuristically to suggest relevant new theory. That is, it
edge but rather is to assist decision making and action, it is
would seem that the role of scientist does not include respon-
consistent with Popper to treat all theories in OR as (epis-
sibility for the assembly of active sets. This supports (in antic-
temologically) instrumental. In other words, the question of
ipation) the position of Keys who has argued that OR should
whether we are trying to find true or nearly true theories
be viewed as technology rather than science’ (Keys, 1989).
about reality (the realist position) or merely seeking theories
Boothroyd’s articulation provides a way of thinking about
of instrumental value (the pragmatist position), an important
situational logic and it is easy to see how it can accommodate
debate in the philosophy of science, can be bracketed for our
both problem structuring and model building. However, he
purposes (this bracketing does not include the separate issue
does not build into his approach any immunization against
of whether means can be separated from ends). Popper also
historicism and the closed society, though his own personal
says that in the world of action beliefs may be important
credo might well lead him to reject such a position. If a
(Popper, 1959, p 282). Thus the psychologism that Popper
would-be intervener wants to build in some assumptions
fights so hard to exclude from the quest for scientific knowl-
about the nature and future direction of society they can do
edge enters the picture when considering action.
so. Nor does Boothroyd drive out psychologism, another
of Popper’s bugbears as we have seen. In fact, he specifi-
Ulrich and critical system heuristics
cally builds into the notion of action programmes the idea
that theories and proposals will be viewed differently from Whereas for Boothroyd Popper proved inspirational, for
different action programmes. Thus the interpretive stance Ulrich he represented the scientific status quo to be criticized.
of, for instance, soft systems methodology can be accom- The distinction between theoretical and practical reasoning
modated: different combinations of theories, proposals, provides a focus for Ulrich’s seminal work Critical Heuris-
actions and consequences can be brought into focus to reflect tics of Social Planning (Ulrich, 1983). Ulrich concedes that
different points of view. However, rather than the lens of a Popper was ‘the first epistemologist who has systematically
systems perspective Boothroyd prefers his own perspective (though not entirely) replaced the idea of justification by
of articulating the dynamically changing actions, theories the idea of criticism’ (Ulrich, 1983, p 51). However, he
and proposals of actors engaged in action programmes at attacks Popper’s formulation of practical reasoning (or lack
different levels of aggregation. thereof) from a Habermasian perspective saying that Popper’s
Both Popper and Boothroyd mention the question of (epis- emphasis on theory (which Popper claims can be analysed
temological) instrumentalism. It is difficult to see how either objectively) ignores the all pervasive role of values: practice
piecemeal engineering or its OR application, articulate inter- (and indeed theory) is not only theory-laden but it is value-
vention, are at odds with it. Popper explains that the creed of laden as well. However, as we have seen above, Popper in his
the pragmatists or instrumentalists is that we should not, or evolutionary approach sees values deriving from problem-
cannot aim at ‘pure’ knowledge, or at truth, with our scien- solving trial and error behaviour in exactly the same way
tific theories: scientific theories are nothing but instruments as theory. Whenever he talks about criticism he is bringing
for prediction or practical application. Popper, as a realist, values into play. It is nevertheless true that he sees science
argues that there is more to it than that, we may learn from as a struggle to achieve value-free, objective knowledge.
science something about the structure of our world (Popper, It can hardly be said that Popper’s work lacks an ethical
1994, pp 171–177). However, he agrees that in the practical dimension. According to Keisewetter, ‘Popper believed that
sphere theories are used as instruments. Indeed, he concedes our Western civilization owes its rationalism, its faith in the
that most physicists of his day interpret the models of physics possibility of rational discourse, its basis of an open society,
as instruments of prediction rather than (possibly true) models and its scientific outlook, to two traditions: the ancient
of reality. In Conjectures and Refutations Popper follows the Socratic tradition and the Christian belief of the brotherhood
line adopted by the pragmatists: of man’ (Kiesewetter, 1995). As Popper himself says in The
Open Society, ‘Man has created new worlds—of language, of
And if we wish to elucidate the difference between pure and music, of poetry, of science; and the most important of these
applied science, between the search for knowledge and the is the world of moral demands, for equality, for freedom,
search for power or for powerful instruments, then we cannot and for helping the weak’ (Popper, 1945a, p 65). Popper
do without it [the objectivist theory of truth—that is truth as suggests that the most important principles of humanitarian
456 Journal of the Operational Research Society Vol. 60, No. 4

and egalitarian ethics are tolerance towards all those who claim that the reformist approach fails to tackle these issues
are not intolerant, the least amount of avoidable suffering adequately. However, they concluded that, in the current
for all (minimise suffering), and the fight against tyranny debate, proponents of the reformist stance would probably
(Popper, 1945a, p 235). What Ulrich is criticizing is not win for the time being (Dando and Bennett, 1981, p 101).
Popper’s ethical stance but his failure to embed consider- Dando and Bennett were applying Kuhn’s model in a way
ation of such matters in his methodological recommenda- that had become the norm in social science but had never
tions: even when addressing an issue of practical reason been intended or envisaged by Kuhn himself. Kuhn had been
Popper tends to separate out and address the theoretical talking about small groups of scientists (up to 50) dedicated
questions. to some narrow field of endeavour. He emphasized that a new
Ulrich’s attack would seem to be a continuation of the paradigm was not necessarily better than the existing one
Positivismusstreit (see above) taking the side of the Frankfurt and that it was periods of normal science rather than revo-
School. In the end his critical systems heuristics approach lution that were productive. His argument could therefore
takes little from Popper; instead it builds an approach to be used to support the proposition that the way to win the
professional practice based on pragmatism and Habermas in Cold War was to pursue normal science vigorously to outper-
a Kantian framework. What Popper and Ulrich do have in form the Soviet Union in both the military and industrial
common is that they have both adapted Kant’s framework. spheres: normal science (the status quo) should therefore be
Kant’s transcendental a priori concepts of human under- funded on a lavish scale (Fuller, 2003). In contrast, the social
standing are replaced by Popper with his concept of trial and science Kuhnian model (SSKM) that Dando and Bennett
error and by Ulrich with his concept of critical heuristics. adopted uses the language of Kuhn to quite different ends.
The SSKM considers whole subject areas, such as social
OR paradigms and Kuhnian revolutions science itself, involving thousands of researchers engaged in
a great diversity of activities. Movement from one paradigm
In 1981 Dando and Bennett suggested that a Kuhnian revo-
to another is seen as progression and the rolling back of
lution was underway in OR:
the frontiers of understanding and knowledge is achieved
More specifically it seems possible in OR and related fields to through revolution. There is no reason to reject SSKM on
identify three sets of rival proposals, which may be labelled offi- the grounds that it does not follow the original intent, but it
cial, reformist (eg Ackoffian) and revolutionary. However, the is as well to recognize that a conservative Kuhnian model
debate in OR differs from that in the Natural Sciences because has been replaced by a sort of neo-Hegelian/Marxist stages
it is not just about the best means of understanding the empir- model. The Hegelian/Marxist connection is reinforced by the
ical world. It is also about the type of world to be constructed fact that it seems to be assumed that the positivist paradigm
through the framework of assumptions adopted. (Dando and (in which they mistakenly include Popper) will in time be
Bennett, 1981, p 91, emphasis in original) replaced by a Marxist/Frankfurt/Habermas paradigm. Ironi-
cally Kuhn’s philosophy resurrects the position of Carnap,
. . . it is just possible that OR will achieve its professed aim of the leading logical positivist, while Popper was the anti-
being a reflective activity in which practitioners make informed
institutional advocate of permanent revolution (Notturno,
choices about their work—and help others to do so. It can be
convincingly argued that this in itself presupposes the possession
2003, pp 225–248).
of some form of ‘critical’ paradigm. Naturally, there will be Advocates of revolution have to whip up a sense of crisis, to
some situations in which a positivist or systems approach would create the feeling that change is inevitable, and OR academics
be found appropriate (or impossible to avoid). The important in the 1970s attempted to achieve this dynamic. They had
point is that the analyst would make conscious choice to proceed plenty of anecdotal evidence to feed on and as an exercise in
in this way, with some understanding of what the consequences bridging between OR and social science Dando and Bennett’s
of this choice will be both for him (or her)-self and for those analysis has a lot to commend it. Their distinction between
he wishes to serve (one of the hallmarks of this approach being official, reformist and revolutionary paradigms is helpful in
the possession of a very clear view of exactly who one is trying that we can use it as a basis to track progress some quarter of
to help). As against this possibility, however, we must make a century later. If the contents of JORS are examined over the
an important reservation. Although Ackoff has pronounced the
past 5 years (2002–2006) about 200 case-orientated papers
death of traditional OR, there are many practitioners who are
rather unconcerned about the whole debate. . . . It may well be
can be identified. Of these over 90% of cases are conducted
that most people in OR are still happily doing ‘Normal Science’ within the official paradigm, about 8% can be classified as
within the old positivist paradigm. From this, our conclusion is being within the reformist paradigm and only one case could
that, as yet, the crisis is still in a fairly early stage’. (Dando and arguably be described as revolutionary (I would argue it is
Bennett, 1981, pp 101–102, emphasis in original). not). Munro and Mingers (2004) in a survey of OR practi-
tioners found that of 22 respondents, 21 reported use of statis-
In conclusion Dando and Bennett agreed with the ‘revolu- tics, 17 of simulation, 16 of forecasting and 13 of mathemat-
tionaries’ that society is riven by conflict, domination, power ical modelling; in other words, a high proportion were still
and exploitation, and had considerable sympathy with the working in the official paradigm. Only two uses each of soft
RJ Ormerod—History and ideas of critical rationalism 457

systems methodology, strategic choice and cognitive mapping tists) are similarly motivated. Undoubtedly the great appeal
were reported, indicative of a little reformist activity (but even of Popper is that he makes the world of philosophy accessible
these uses may well be by practitioners still working in the (not without some struggle, of course). His range and depth
official paradigm). No usages were reported of total system is remarkable: he demonstrates in-depth knowledge of logic,
intervention or critical systems heuristics, which might be mathematics, physics, Greek and philosophy; he engages with
considered for inclusion in the revolutionary paradigm. The politics, economics, biology, music and art. All this has come
envisaged paradigm shifts have clearly not happened. There under detailed and critical scrutiny. For instance, Ronald B.
are a number of possible explanations for this including the Levinson wrote In Defense of Plato, a book of 645 closely
possibility that those opting for the new paradigms find some printed pages, attacking Popper’s depiction of Plato. Popper
grouping other than OR (such as the systems movement) more writes in remarkably clear English. He helpfully clarifies the
convivial. position of those with whom he chooses to disagree and points
out the assumptions and potential weaknesses of his own argu-
Jackson and total systems intervention (TSI) ments. He is thus one of the easiest of the great philosophers
While Boothroyd embraces Popper and Ulrich criticises to understand (Marx was another) and, by the same token, one
him, Jackson ignores him (Jackson, 2000). However, we of the most open to criticism. Popper’s accessibility and his
can examine Jackson’s approach through the lens of Popper. emphasis on epistemology and science make him an obvious
Jackson has long been an advocate of taking a sociological starting point for any member of the OR community wishing
approach to intervention. In effect, Popper divides sociology to explore what philosophy has to offer. We have seen that his
into two perspectives, historicism and piecemeal engineering. thinking gave rise to major disputes; this gives us an opportu-
Jackson combines the two: he envisages piecemeal type inter- nity to see how different perspectives are developed, promoted
ventions overseen by a debate about the approach to adopt and defended. It is as much in the developments that followed,
based on a sociological overview. In criticizing Ulrich’s CSH the arguments, debates, defences and improvements, as in the
he says that CSH ‘. . . is not critical in terms of the historical original Popper philosophy that the value lies for OR. Popper
materialism of Marx and the Frankfurt School sociologists’ (p offers some simple models that provide the basis for debate.
319). This is the gap that Jackson sees his TSI debate filling.
For Jackson, critical awareness is recognizing that there Models of scientific logic and discovery
are problem situations where there is fundamental conflict
between interest groups that have access to unequal power Popper’s great innovations in the epistemology of science (his
resources, and that there are organizational and societal pres- demarcation and falsification models) have been absorbed by
sures that lead to certain systems theories and methodologies the scientific and statistical communities (in which many of
being popular for guiding interventions at particular times the OR community were schooled). However, in the world of
(pp 356–357). OR practice it is extremely difficult to rid oneself of the habit
Jackson’s desire to sit above the fray and take an overview of thinking and arguing in an inductive way. For instance, to
based on sociology would be recognized by Popper as an take the swan example a step further, it is perfectly possible
application of the sociology of knowledge. Popper claims this to prove inductively the hypothesis ‘some swans are black’;
stems from a Marxist development of Hegel (Popper, 1945b, it is only necessary to observe one black swan in Australia
p 202). He says, ‘Thus the sociology of knowledge believes (or London Zoo) to conclude the hypothesis is true. So why
that the highest objectivity can be reached by the freely poised does Popper want to banish inductive arguments? The answer
intelligence analysing the various hidden ideologies and their is simply that Popper is only concerned with establishing
anchorage in the unconscious. The way to true knowledge universal scientific laws (or more accurately yet-to-be-refuted
appears to be the unveiling of unconscious assumptions . . . ’ hypotheses). ‘All swans are white’ is such a universal state-
(p 203). Sociologists of knowledge explain the disagreement ment. However, falsification of the universal statement is logi-
of an opponent by his social ideology. Popper continues, ‘Such cally exactly the same as inductively confirming the state-
methods are both easy to handle and good fun for those who ment ‘some swans are black’. Popper might want to stick to
handle them. But they clearly destroy the basis of rational the universal nomological (law-like) form but in OR this can
discussion, and they must lead, ultimately, to anti-rationalism seem awkward. For instance, one could suggest to a client in
and mysticism’ (p 204). the nuclear industry either that (i) they should try to falsify the
hypothesis that there are no stable geological formations suit-
able for waste disposal, or alternatively that (ii) they should
The implications for OR
try to identify at least one suitable site to establish that suitable
As an engineer I confess to a bias towards simplicity, clarity sites do in fact exist. The first formulation sounds academic,
and transparency in all matters related to theory. I look to the second practical. The point is they are logically the same.
theory to provide some simplifying insights into the infi- The whole subject area is a sort of logicians’ playground.
nite complexities of the real world. I have found that most For instance, Popper suggests that anything and everything
operational researchers (mainly mathematicians and scien- can be a source of new hypotheses: the scientist has to care-
458 Journal of the Operational Research Society Vol. 60, No. 4

fully use experimental falsification to sort the (potential) Models of the role of social science
wheat from the chaff. However, this is an impossible task
Popper’s model of social science contrasts historicism with
as there are an infinite number of true and false statements
piecemeal engineering. Although attempts to achieve major
that can be made about the world. Obviously, it is part of the
societal change to bring in some new Utopia or other have an
scientist’s craft skill to narrow the field down drastically in a
appalling record, we are not free of such attempts today. For
heuristic and inevitably inductive way. This is also the case
instance, Gray in Black Mass suggests that the American neo-
in OR practice. Hilary Putman emphasizes the importance of
conservative agenda to bring freedom and democracy to the
practice. He criticizes Popper for failing to see that practice
world can be seen in these terms ‘despite the fact that it was
is primary: ideas are not just an end in themselves; they
presented in the trappings of social science’ (Gray, 2007, p 1).
guide practice and structure whole forms of life. We obtain
Rather more optimistically Winter argues that it is important to
our ideas (both correct and incorrect ones) by close study of
recognize the enduring character of the Utopian tradition. He
the world. Accumulated experience does not lead to theories
suggests that the history of the 20th century should not only be
in an algorithmic or mechanical sense but (1) lack of expe-
written as a story of a series of catastrophes; the historical role
rience with phenomena markedly decreases the probability
of ‘minor Utopias’ and the visionary temperament should also
of correct ideas and (2) extensive experience increases the
be recognized. He describes six minor 20th century Utopias:
probability of correct or partially correct ideas in a marked
three are projects of social transformation centred on nation
fashion. The correctness of an idea is not certified by the fact
and social class; three are focused more on civil society and
that it came from close and concrete study of the relevant
human rights. Winter does not hesitate to point out the failings
aspect of the world (Popper is right in that respect); rather
in these minor Utopian projects, but he suggests that nonethe-
we judge the correctness of our ideas by applying them and
less a world without them is a barren one (Winter, 2006).
seeing whether they succeed. In general, and in the long run,
Popper’s description of piecemeal engineering sounds very
true ideas succeed. How do we know? Our experience tells
like certain classes of OR models, namely those that are, or
us it does. Thus induction cannot be ignored in the quest to
are very like, economic models; energy models are a good
understand the world. Induction cannot be ‘justified’ but nor,
example (Ormerod, 1980; Ormerod and McLeod, 1983). Of
Putman believes, can anything else including mathematics
course, Popper had economic models very much in mind
and logic (Putman, 1974, p 238).
when he developed his idea of piecemeal social engineering;
economics was the one area of social science where he
Models of the nature of the scientific research process believed progress was being made. Thus Popper comes to
practice from two different directions. We have from his
The debate about the nature of science has thrown up a
work on science the conclusion that we should use the best
number of models from Popper’s concept of discovery and
corroborated hypotheses and that an instrumental view of
Kuhn’s normal science to Lakatos’ research programmes
theories can be taken in practice. He also accepted that ad
and Laudan’s research traditions. Many other possible ways
hoc hypotheses may be useful for forecasting purposes, and
of combining logic and observations of practice have been
that questions of belief enter into practical decision-making.
suggested. It is clear that logic on its own is not sufficient
From his work on social science we have his conclusion
to explain scientific behaviour and observation of practice is
that we should engage in piecemeal engineering on prac-
not sufficient to explain the success of science. These models
tical grounds. However, he does not linger on the subject of
can only be suggestive of the line of attack to take when
practice long enough to reconcile these positions and make
attempting to understand the nature OR. As has been argued
the area his own. The practice domain would seem to be
by Keys (1989), OR is not a science, it is a technology: its
left open to the adoption of a pragmatist (or neo-pragmatist
focus is on practice rather than knowledge accumulation.
Habermasian) position. Thus from an OR perspective the
The problem for OR is that while there are some descrip-
epistemological disagreements between critical rationalists
tions of OR in practice written by practitioners and plenty
and instrumental pragmatists as to the nature of truth and its
of speculation from academics, there is very little in the
scientific determination can be bracketed and effort concen-
way of careful observation for sociological research purposes.
trated on the world of practice.
Despite these difficulties it would seem that there is no substi-
tute for examining practice directly. No doubt some major
Models of open and closed societies
shifts have occurred, for instance, from manual to computer-
based modelling and from in-house OR groups to external Popper’s models of open and closed societies still resonate
consultancy. But these can hardly be described as paradigm today and are often quoted in political debate. The terms open
shifts in the sense of grand epoch-making change. Perhaps and closed societies have entered the language. In Western
other changes can be described as paradigm shifts in the orig- democracies it is almost universally taken for granted that
inal Kuhnian (small scale) sense. Thus we may be seeing a openness is to be preferred and defended. Closed societies
shift from private informal methods to more formal public continue to be alluring to many; for instance, scientology with
methods in the area of problem structuring. its foundational myths, confident certainties and tight-knit
RJ Ormerod—History and ideas of critical rationalism 459

community is apparently the fastest growing religion in the was his original epistemological work on science (theoretical
UK today (The Sunday Times, 7 January 2007, p 7). Nations reason); he did not in my view provide a coherent account of
across the world still struggle with openness; migration, glob- how decisions should be taken in practice (practical reason).
alization and international environmental issues are high on Popper’s philosophy on its own is therefore insufficient to
the agenda. From an OR perspective, any widely cast scenario provide a basis for OR; a Boothroyd, an Ulrich or indeed a
exercise will have to address the direction these issues might Habermas is required to complete the task.
take and their far-reaching consequences. One of the themes running through Conjectures and Refu-
tations (Popper, 1963) and through much of Popper’s subse-
quent writings is that the proper task of philosophy is to
Conclusions
tackle, in an imaginative and critical way, real fundamental
Popper is one of the greatest philosophers of the 20th century. problems having their roots outside philosophy in science,
At the same time he is often threatened with being overshad- politics, art, and life. This conception of philosophy stands
owed by those with whom he profoundly disagreed or who in sharp contrast both to the pomposities and obscurities of
profoundly disagreed with him. These include as we have much so-called ‘continental’ philosophy, and to the poverty
seen Wittgenstein, Kuhn and Habermas. At the end of their and aridity of philosophy in the so-called ‘analytic’ tradi-
account of the famous poker incident, Edmonds and Eidenow tion, restricted to ordinary language analysis, the analysis
say, ‘Of the great figures in twentieth-century philosophy, of meaning. Popper has fought against both rival concep-
only a very few have given names to those who follow in tions of philosophy, and has sought to put into practice his
their path. Popper and Wittgenstein are two. . . . That one own critical rationalist, problem-solving conception. From
can be identified as a Popperian or a Wittgensteinian is a an OR perspective Popper provides an excellent entrée into
testament to the originality of these philosophers’ ideas and the debate about the nature, logic and practice of our own
the power of their personalities’ (Edmonds and Eidinow, subject area but does not provide the answer.
2001, p 232). Popper’s critics today still see themselves as
knocking him off his pedestal; his followers (including the Acknowledgements — The author would like to thank Gerald Midgley and
American William Bartley III, the German Hans Albert, an anonymous referee for their helpful comments and criticisms.
the Israeli Joseph Agassi and the British David Miller)
despair at his treatment. For instance Miller says ‘Sixty References
years after the publication of Logik der Forschung Popper’s
daring innovation continues to be widely misrepresented Adorno TW (ed) (1969). Der Positivismusstreit in der deutschen
Soziologie. Neuwied: Berlin.
and misunderstood—if not deprecated as a barren form of Adorno TW (ed) (1976). The Positivist Dispute in German Sociology
scepticism, or even irrationalism, then deprecated for itself (translated by Adey G and Frisby D). Heinemann: London.
incorporating some principle or rule of induction’ (Miller, Bacon F (1620). Novum Organum: True Directions Concerning the
1994, p x). Others, such as Raphael Sassower, have sought to Interpretation of Nature. Billium: London, (References are to Book
relate Popper’s thinking to modern themes such as feminism and numbered aphorisms).
Boothroyd H (1978). Articulate Intervention. Taylor and Francis:
and postmodernism (Sassower, 2006). London.
Popper’s reputation among practising scientists, politicians Corvi R (1997). An Introduction to the Thought of Karl Popper
and journalists is on much firmer ground: his notions of falsi- (translated by Patrick Camiller). Routledge: London.
fication and of the open society have become imbedded in the Dando MR and Bennett PG (1981). A Kuhnian crisis in management
science. J Opl Res Soc 32: 91–103.
conventional wisdom in Western democracies and a source Edmonds D and Eidinow J (2001). Wittgenstein’s Poker. Faber and
of inspiration for post-communist societies. However, in the Faber: London.
social sciences Kuhn is seen as a radical theorist of science, Feyerabend P (1975). Against Method. New Left Books: London,
whereas Popper is remembered as a grumpy autocrat (Fuller, (Page numbers refer to the Third Edition (1993). Verso: London).
2003, p 2). According to Fuller this is a travesty of the truth. Fotion NG (1995). Logical positivism. In: Honderich T (ed).
The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press:
Fuller, who has had privileged access to Kuhn’s private papers, Oxford, pp 507–508.
concludes that Kuhn was a servant of US Cold War interests Frisby D (1976). Introduction to the English translation. In: Adorno
whereas Popper, despite his championing of freedom and his TW (ed). The Positivist Dispute in German Sociology (translated
association with the Hayek, retained his socialist sympathies by Adey G and Frisby D). Heinemann: London.
Fuller S (2003). Kuhn vs Popper: The Struggle for the Soul of Science.
throughout (Fuller, 2003).
Icon: Duxford.
Popper’s ideas on the logic of scientific discovery, on the Gillies D (1995). Popper’s contribution to the philosophy of
propensity interpretation of probability and on the piecemeal probability. In: O’Hear A (ed). Karl Popper: Philosophy and
approach to a better society have undoubtedly had a profound Problems. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, pp 103–120.
effect on the thinking of OR practitioners. He also stimu- Gray J (2007). Black Mass: Apocalyptic Religion and the Death of
Utopia. Penguin: London.
lated ideas, disagreements and arguments, which have found Hacker PMS (1995). Wittgenstein, Ludwig. In: Honderich T (ed).
their way into debates about the nature and direction of OR. The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press:
However, the cornerstone of Popper’s philosophical edifice Oxford, pp 912–916.
460 Journal of the Operational Research Society Vol. 60, No. 4

Hacking I (1981). Lakatos’s philosophy of science. In: Hacking I Popper KR (1945a). The Open Society and its Enemies, volume I, The
(ed). Scientific Revolutions. Oxford University Press: Oxford, Spell of Plato. Routledge & Kegan Paul: London (page numbers
pp 128–143. refer to the 1962 fourth edition).
Hacohen MH (2000). Karl Popper: The Formative Years 1902–1945. Popper KR (1945b). The Open Society and its Enemies, volume II, The
Cambridge University Press: Cambridge. High Tide of Prophesy: Hegel, Marx and the Aftermath. Routledge
Jackson MC (2000). Systems Approaches to Management. & Kegan Paul: London.
Kluwer/Plenum: New York. Popper KR (1959). The Logic of Scientific Discovery. Hutchinson:
Keys P (1989). OR as technology: Some issues and implications. London (page numbers refer to the 1995 Routledge: London edition).
J Opl Res Soc 40: 753–759. Popper KR (1963). Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of
Kiesewetter H (1995). Ethical foundations of Popper’s philosophy. In: Scientific Knowledge. Routledge & Kegan Paul: London.
O’Hear A (ed). Karl Popper: Philosophy and Problems. Cambridge Popper KR (1970). Normal science and its dangers. In: Lakatos I
University Press: Cambridge, pp 275–288. and Musgrove A (eds). Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge.
Kirby MW (2003). Operational Research in War and Peace: The Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, pp 51–58.
British Expereince from the 1930s to 1970. Imperial College Press: Popper KR (1972). Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach.
London. Oxford University Press: London.
Kuhn TS (1962). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. University Popper KR (1976a). Unended Quest: An Intellectual Autobiography.
of Chicago Press: Chicago IL, (Page numbers refer to the 1996 Fontana: London. Originally published in 1974 as an
third edition). ‘Autobiography of Karl Popper’ in Schlipp PA (ed). The Philosophy
Kuhn TS (1970). Reflections on my critics. In: Lakatos I and Musgrove of Karl Popper in The Library of Living Philosophers. Open Court:
A (eds). Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. Cambridge Illinois, pp 3–181.
University Press: Cambridge, pp 231–278. Popper K (1976b). The logic of the social sciences. In: Adorno TW
Lakatos I (1970). Falsification and the methodology of scientific (ed). The Positivist Dispute in German Sociology. (translated by
research programmes. In: Lakatos I and Musgrove A (eds). Adey G and Frisby D). Heinemann: London. The paper in German
Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. Cambridge University was originally written in 1961 and published in Adorno TW
Press: Cambridge, pp 91–196. (ed). (1969). Der Positivistmusstreit in der deutchen Sociologie.
Lakatos I (1981). History of science and its rational reconstructions. Neuwied: Berlin.
In: Hacking I (ed). Scientific Revolutions. Oxford University Press: Popper KR (1982a). The Open Universe, volume II of the Postscript.
Oxford, pp 107–127. Hutchinson: London.
Lakatos I and Musgrove A (eds) (1970). Criticism and the Growth of Popper KR (1982b). Quantum Theory and the Schism in Physics,
Knowledge. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge. volume III of the Postscript. Hutchinson: London.
Laudan L (1977). Progress and its Problems. Routledge and Kegan Popper KR (1983). Realism and the Aims of Science, volume I of the
Paul: London. Postscript. Hutchinson: London.
Magee B (1973). Popper. Fontana: London. Popper KR (1994). The Myth of the Framework: In Defence of Science
Magee B (1985). Philosophy and the Real World: An Introduction to and Rationality. Routledge: London.
Karl Popper. Open Court: LaSalle, IL. Putman H (1974). The ‘corroboration’ of theories. In: Schilpp PA (ed).
Maxwell N (2007). Karl Raimund Popper. Available at http://philsci- The Library of Living Philosophers Volume XIV: The Philosophy
archive.pitt.edu/archive/00001686/01/Karl Raimund Popper.doc. of Karl Popper. Open Court: La Salle, IL, pp 221–240.
Miller D (1983). A Pocket Popper. Fontana: London. Quinton A (1995). Analytic philosophy. In: Honderich T (ed).
Miller D (1994). Critical Rationalism: A Restatement and Defence. The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press:
Open Court: Peru, IL. Oxford, pp 28–30.
Munro I and Mingers J (2004). Response to Richard Ormerod. J Opl Sainsbury RM (1995). Russell, Bertrand. In: Honderich T (ed).
Res Soc 55: 90–93. The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press:
Newton-Smith WH (1981). The Rationality of Science. Routledge and Oxford, pp 781–785.
Kegan Paul: London. Sardar Z (2000). Thomas Kuhn and the Science Wars. Icon Books:
Notturno MA (2003). On Popper. Wadsworth: Belmont, CA. Duxford.
O’Hear A (1980). Karl Popper. Routledge and Kegan Paul: London. Sassower R (2006). Popper’s Legacy. Acumen: Stocksfield.
O’Hear A (1995a). Popper, Karl. In: Honderich T (ed). The Oxford Schilpp PA (1974). The Library of Living Philosophers Volume XIV:
Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press: Oxford, pp The Philosophy of Karl Popper. Open Court: La Salle, IL.
702–703. Shearmur J (1996). The Political Thought of Karl Popper. Routledge:
O’Hear A (1995b). Hypothetico-deductive method. In: Honderich T London.
(ed). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Smithurst M (1995). Popper and the scepticism of evolutionary
Press: Oxford, p 385. epistemology, or, what were human beings made for? In: O’Hear T
Ormerod RJ (1980). Energy models for decision making. Eur J Opl (ed). Karl Popper: Philosophy and Problems. Cambridge University
Res 5: 366–377. Press: Cambridge, pp 207–324.
Tarski A (1956). Logic, Semantics, Mathematics (translated by
Ormerod RJ (2006). The history and ideas of pragmatism. J Opl Res
Woodger JH). Oxford University Press: London.
Soc 57: 892–909.
Ulrich W (1983). Critical Heuristics of Social Planning: A New
Ormerod RJ (2008). The history and ideas of Marxism: The relevance
Approach to Practical Philosophy. Haupt: Bern (the 1994 edition,
for OR. J Opl Res Soc, published online October 3, 2007; doi:
published by Wiley, Chichester, is referred to here).
10.1057/palgrave.jors.2602495.
Williams DE (1989). Truth, Hope and Power: The Thought of Karl
Ormerod RJ and McLeod J (1983). The development and use of the
Popper. University of Toronto Press: Toronto.
NCB Strategic Model. The Statist 33: 35–49.
Winter J (2006). Dreams of Peace and Freedom: Utopian Moments
Popper KR (1934). Logik der Forschung. Springer: Vienna.
in the 20th Century. Yale University Press: New Haven CT.
Popper KR (1944/5). The poverty of historicism. Economica 11: 86
–103 (part I); 11: 119-137 (part II); 12: 69-89 (part III) (page
numbers refer to the 1957 book published by Routledge & Kegan Received July 2007;
Paul: London). accepted January 2008 after two revisions

Você também pode gostar