Você está na página 1de 11

02 Stam (jr/d) 26/7/00 11:00 am Page 273

Theorizing Health and Journal of Health Psychology


Copyright © 2000 SAGE Publications
London, Thousand Oaks and New Delhi,
Illness: Functionalism, [1359–1053(200007)5:3]
Vol 5(3) 273–283; 013539

Subjectivity and
Reflexivity Abstract
Health and illness in
contemporary psychology are
remarkably undertheorized, with
the consequence that implicit
definitions of these topics are
unquestionably imported into
health psychology. Largely
inspired and oriented to the
medical system, health
HENDERIKUS J. STAM psychology is often subservient to
University of Calgary, Canada biomedically inspired theory or
directed to solving the problems
of the health care system, not
those of its patients or those who
H E N D E R I K U S J . S TA M
is a professor of psychology at might ultimately benefit from
the University of Calgary and a fellow of Division 38 health knowledge. Qualitative
(Health Psychology) of the American Psychological approaches have attempted to
reintroduce the voice of the
Association. He is the founding and current editor of
patient/sufferer/individual back
Theory & Psychology and writes on foundational and into health psychology but
historical problems in psychology. without adequate theoretical
integration this work has been
marginalized and ignored by
mainstream health psychology in
the service of medical modelling.
The point is not to develop a
health psychology as an exclusive
disciplinary enclave but rather to
open up the possibilities of a
responsible knowing. Using
Kathryn Addelson’s work on
professional knowing I argue that
the collective activity that
constitutes health psychology can
be made more explicit not only by
devising reflexive theories and
AC K N OW L E D G E M E N T S .
An earlier version of this article was practices but by focusing on what
presented at the First International Conference on Critical and
the outcomes of that activity
Qualitative Approaches to Health Psychology conference held in St
John’s, Newfoundland, July 1999. I am grateful to Michael Murray for
might be. Functional theories of
inviting me to take part in this meeting and to him and the many health and illness, on the other
participants who commented on this article. In addition I thank Elly hand, obscure our
Singer, Ruth Miltenburg, Wendy Stainton Rogers, John Spicer and epistemological and moral
Kerry Chamberlain for their helpful comments on a later draft. commitments.

COMPETING INTERESTS: None declared.


Keywords
ADDRESS. Correspondence should be directed to:
H . J . S TA M , Department of Psychology,University of Calgary,Calgary, epistemology, health and illness,
Alberta, Canada T2N 1N4. [email: stam@ucalgary.ca] moral commitment, theory

273
02 Stam (jr/d) 26/7/00 11:00 am Page 274

JOURNAL OF HEALTH PSYCHOLOGY 5(3)

T H I S A RT I C L E I S , simply put, a plea for theory. contested and configured in the activities of
One of the reasons for propagating the work of those who make up, provide and use biomedi-
theorizing came out of my own practice as a cine. These activities are constituted discursively
psychologist, now a decade ago, of working in a and an exploration of care-talk necessarily leads
cancer treatment setting as both a clinical and a to a deconstruction of traditional categories of
research psychologist. It is, I think, not necessary health care as well as an invocation of under-
to enumerate the kinds of personal, institutional standing such categories in terms of subjectivi-
and political problems one is confronted with in ties, power and knowledge (see Fox, 1994). In
such settings to say that there was a wide gulf addition, these activities are constituted collec-
between practice and the literature on health tively and an exclusive focus on individual actors
psychology or behavioural medicine (cf. Stam, usually obfuscates the complex moral/power
1988, 1992). Although I eventually decided that relations involved.
my contributions to a ‘politics of care’ could be These concerns seem a long way from the
more effectively made outside rather than inside ‘worlds’ created or constructed by contempor-
biomedicine, I have continued to remain ary health psychology around a set of limited
involved in health care institutions and research professional topics, but the connection between
in peripheral ways. I should note here that a politics of care and these topics I wish to draw
Health Psychology is (and can be) far more than here is precisely by way of the problem of
what is covered by the clinical focus of what is theory. In short, I want to make the case that
sometimes referred to as Clinical Health Psy- theory is not a luxury or what one does in one’s
chology. Although heavily involved in and influ- armchair after a hard day of collecting data. On
enced by clinical issues for reasons having to do the contrary, it is one of the most crucial steps of
with the social and economic organization of our entry into the world of health, disease and
clinical psychology, health psychology includes illness precisely because it establishes nothing
studies and problems that range from com- less than our political, epistemological and
munity research and studies that have impli- moral grounding. It also establishes our
cations for health policy to considerations of responsibility as professionals who intervene in
individual problems of adjustment to illness. the lives of others even if done at the level of
What I have to say about theory is generally rel- research. At the same time, it announces our
evant to all of these dimensions even though I commitments in advance, locating us as pro-
chose examples that come predominantly from fessionals among other professions and clients.
the latter domain (see also Marks, 1996; Spicer As such we had best try to get clear the grounds
& Chamberlain, 1996; Stainton Rogers, 1996). of our interventions. In addition, we do not, and
As will become clear below, by theory I do not I would argue we cannot, do this alone.
have in mind a conception based on the tra- I am now not only making claims that are rel-
ditional notions of reductionism, instrumental- evant to health psychology; disciplinary bound-
ism or realism in the philosophy of science. ary maintenance is particularly troublesome for
Indeed, neither do most psychologists for that any critical project that seeks to open for investi-
matter, who treat theory as mere variants of gation the grounds of its own practice. More-
functionalist claims that resemble hypotheses over, other social scientific disciplines similarly
but whose actual foundations are left some- involved in the health care system have engaged
where floating in mid-air (see Stam, 1996, in in serious theoretical work for many years. Cer-
press, for a discussion). My conception of theory tainly sociologists, anthropologists and some
is primarily governed by its reflexive properties psychologists are a case in point; it is difficult to
or the claim that the researcher shares in a non- imagine, for example, a Bryan Turner, an Emily
trivial way the practices of the community that Martin or an Alan Radley seriously proposing
he or she investigates, practices that are the kind of claim that one author in Health Psy-
premised on shared linguistic and cultural chology made recently. He said at the conclusion
customs. I will draw out several implications of of a long and complex empirical study on a
this for theory and practice below. chronic illness that the theoretical significance of
By referring to a politics of care, above, I his study was that stress and coping variables are
mean just those aspects of health care which are related in different ways to various dimensions
274
02 Stam (jr/d) 26/7/00 11:00 am Page 275

STAM: THEORIZING HEALTH AND ILLNESS

ofadjustment.1 Since such ‘findings’ are entirely is presented in terms of its adherence to a
obvious, and indeed, may not require empirical methodologically fixed set of principles that
research at all (cf. Smedslund, 2000 and com- suppress the discursive, social constitution of
mentaries), the practice of research has more to health care and its hierarchical allocation of
do with institutional and career progress than resources, as well as the negotiated and col-
the generation of new knowledge. lective constitution of ‘health’ and ‘illness’.
I do not wish to argue that mainstream health
psychology has no theory, but instead that it is
The discipline of health theory of a particular kind. Although health
psychology psychologists claim to rely on several models,
The hegemonic position of clinical psychology including systems theory, biopsychosocial
and the vast extension of biomedicine following theory and self-regulatory theories, among
the Second World War in the North-Atlantic others, these are all variants of functionalism.
world, and especially the English-speaking part For example, systems theory has been espoused
of that world, has led to an unprecedented domi- as providing a foundation for understanding
nation of health topics in the social sciences by adaptive mechanisms (e.g. Stone, 1980, Taylor,
psychologists. The emergence of Managed Care 1999). However, systems theory, especially the
in the USA and the related move to provide version that circulates in health psychology,
empirically validated treatments, supported by adheres in practice to the three necessary con-
the American Psychological Association among ditions for a functionalist model (Evans-
others, means that the dominance of what I will Pritchard, 1951): first, systems are natural
call ‘mainstream health psychology’ will con- phenomena with interdependent levels that
tinue. In addition, health psychology remains a serve to maintain the system; second, within
growing area of academic and applied psychol- systems theory social events are reduced to
ogy in North America as well as one of the more empirical relationships that are predictable; and
common areas where many psychologists find third, systems theory is ahistorical about the
employment (Stone et al., 1987; Taylor, 1999). makeup of systems. In this sense systems theory
The mission statement of Division 38 (Health is neutral about the nature of biomedical
Psychology) of the American Psychological systems. Within the context of health and health
Association (1996) contains the following: ‘Psy- care, such a functional view espouses a concept
chologists are in increasing demand in health of persons as well-tuned machines (rather than
and medical settings. The single largest area of sentient beings) whose actions are intelligible in
placement of psychologists in recent years has larger control systems. Self-regulatory models
been in medical centers’. Through the use of are likewise driven by functional considerations;
licensing, continuing education and the like, the the ‘self’, however conceived, is entirely absent
dominance of a mainstream perspective is insti- in these formulations.
tutionally defined and maintained. There are
two obvious consequences of this:
The biopsychosocial model
1. For health psychology, biomedical authority The ‘biopsychosocial’ position and related con-
and all its related social, financial and insti- cepts have a unique role in health psychology.
tutional supports remains a benign provider Engel’s original publication in Science in 1977,
of health care and a duly constituted auth- where the term originated, was primarily a cri-
ority on health and illness. The contested and tique of biomedicine. Only the latter half of his
shifting political, social and economic forces article concerned itself with the biopsychosocial
engaged in and by the health care system and model proper and most of this is by way of
their profound consequences for the clients example rather than the development of a
of that system are, to health psychology, model, theory or position. In fact he does not
psychologically uninteresting and unimpor- even define the term but argues that the ‘model
tant. must . . . take into account the patient, the social
2. A singular form of research is treated as the context in which he [or she] lives, and the com-
ultimate tool of knowledge, and this research plimentary system devised by society to deal
275
02 Stam (jr/d) 26/7/00 11:00 am Page 276

JOURNAL OF HEALTH PSYCHOLOGY 5(3)

with the disruptive effects of illness, that is, the a useful rhetorical device for the appropriation
physician’s role and health care system’ (p. 132). of a set of topics in health and illness into
Furthermore, argues Engel, the dichotomy psychological practice and research.
between ‘disease’ and certain ‘problems of From the perspective of professionalization,
living’ is clear neither for patient nor for phys- this is an exercise of ‘social closure’ (Turner,
ician. As an example he describes the case of 1986) wherein a profession’s knowledge base
grief. It exemplifies a phenomenon in which serves as a strategy of market regulation.
psychological factors are primary yet it consti- Although such a view might be construed as
tutes a discrete syndrome with a relatively pre- strictly concerned with the political and social
dictable symptomatology which includes bodily role played by health psychology, it is not
and psychological disturbances. A biopsycho- entirely surprising given that psychology is con-
social model would merely take all of these tinually in competition with neighbouring disci-
factors into account, and Engel alludes in his plines for the same territory. Family medicine,
conclusion to the relationship between the community medicine, nursing, social work, epi-
biopsychosocial model and systems theories. demiology, sociology of health and other health-
It is an interesting phenomenon in its own related disciplines have marked as their domain
right that such a loose formulation has become certain problems and topics in health care that
the rhetorical mainstay of theory in health psy- are also part of the practice and research reper-
chology (see Stam, 1988). I surveyed five recent toire of health psychologists. These include
health psychology textbooks and found that the topics such as the family, living with chronic
term ‘biopsychosocial’ is now thoroughly illness, prevention of diseases, and so on. In that
embedded in the discipline. Indeed it appeared sense, part of health psychology’s success is
almost obligatory to mention the model derived from its capacity to innovate and to
although none of the texts cite papers beyond secure new markets, clients and rewards.
the original formulations by Engel (e.g. 1977) or In a related sense it is strange, if not sus-
the revision published by Schwartz in 1982. The picious, that discussions of the deeply contested,
‘model’ has simply been taken for granted and, political and social issues that make up health
remarkably, there is absolutely no discussion of care today are absent from health psychology.
what this term could mean other than the ‘inter- One of the major expenses of western govern-
play’ or ‘interaction’ of biological, psychological ments, individuals and families is health and
and social factors. Taylor (1999) is even less health care. Dominated by mixed models of
committed by noting that these three factors are physicians as private entrepreneurs/public ser-
merely ‘involved’ in the model. No author notes vants who work within both private and public
that this is neither a theory nor a model.2 Indeed, medical facilities, health care has been (in the
I think it is sufficient to say that it is a clever neol- post-war period) and still is, in a constant state
ogism masquerading as a model and its naive of crisis and restructuring. The biomedical
distribution to undergraduates ought to lead us model has been challenged on many fronts and
to urge publishers to place a warning label on a steady growth and proliferation in health pro-
textbooks indicating that they are a danger to fessions and specialties (within medicine but
the health of one’s theoretical education.3 On also in dentistry, pharmacy, and so on) and com-
the other hand, the absence of theory and the plementary occupations (nursing, physiother-
vagueness of the model can be construed as a apy, laboratory specialists) have transformed
useful ploy because anything can be covered by the health labour force. As other groups have
it: anything remotely relevant counts as a topic joined this labour force through a strategy of
under ‘health’. As Shelley Taylor pronounces in professionalization (among others, psycholo-
the last sentence of her textbook on health psy- gists, chiropractors and nurses), and administra-
chology ‘the opportunities for the fledgling tive and support services have proliferated, the
health psychologist are boundless’ (1999, p. medical domain has become a contested and
489). Opportunities indeed, so long as they don’t fragmented one (see Aries & Kennedy, 1990;
interfere with institutional privileges. In short, Burke & Stevenson, 1993). As if this is occurring
the functionalist prescriptiveness and lofty inclu- in another world, psychologists ignore and sup-
siveness of the biopsychosocial ‘model’ make it press these events and their impact on their own
276
02 Stam (jr/d) 26/7/00 11:00 am Page 277

STAM: THEORIZING HEALTH AND ILLNESS

research and practices, their conceptions of ‘deductive-nomonological’ in nature. Theories


health and illness and, perhaps fatally, the in this context came to mean statements that had
importance of these considerations for their a specific relationship to the events to be
intended end-users, the research participants explained, a deductive-nomonological relation-
and the ill.4 ship. In the ideal case the theory was a universal
However, despite the crucial importance of law that could act as a ‘covering law’ that
the structural background to health psychology, explains the events under consideration.
this appears to me to be an incomplete picture. For all its elegance, the model can be seen in
It paints psychologists as ignorant of the world very little research after that of Clark Hull. Prac-
they inhabit or as ruthless entrepreneurs in the tically, the development of inferential statistics
same way that some critiques of medicine paint and the demise of behaviourism as an all-encom-
physicians as heartless technocrats. Such one- passing theory for psychology led to a much
dimensional caricatures may make sense of the more liberal approach in understanding theor-
background activities that make a profession etical claims. Although the emphases on obser-
possible; what is at stake, however, is not the vation and quantification persisted and were
individual motivation of psychologists but the strengthened by post-war generations of psy-
constitution of health psychology as a collective chologists, inferential statistics encouraged the
practice. What functionalist theory allows is the wider use of theoretical models or ‘hypotheses’
discursive construction of health and illness as a in psychology and discouraged formal theoriza-
set of variables whose identification is obvious tion (with the exception of some areas such as
and whose analysis requires no more than the mathematical psychology). It has only been the
use of aggregate statistics that allow one to make advent of cognitivism in the last 40 years that has
simple yes/no judgments. I wish to say a few gradually reintroduced theory in a more formal
words about this which I hope will clarify my manner by way of (cognitive) functional analy-
understanding of theory when I return to the ses, analyses that have come to rely on and
question of theory as a moral project. require the kind of statistical averaging used in
tests of statistical inference.
Among the many consequences of the wide-
Methodology and the
spread adoption of statistical inference tech-
constraints on theory
niques in psychology, the most deleterious was
Like theory in psychology generally, what passes their restriction of theoretical developments in
for theory in health psychology is loosely related the discipline (Gigerenzer, 1993; Stam & Pasay,
to a version of positivism (modelled on the 1998). Kurt Danziger (1990) gives an account of
philosophical version of logical positivism) that how, in response to the demand for an applied
has dominated psychology since mid-century. knowledge, research came to be conducted on
According to the philosophical version of logical groups that were constituted so that they could
positivism, a theory is no more than an axioma- be contrasted on an abstract variable. For
tized collection of sentences that has a specified example, research in intelligence demanded
relationship to a set of observables. This some conception of normative levels for the
relationship (dependent on a theory of veri- development of intelligence tests. Individual
fication) was much in dispute for the life of scores came to be reported in the aggregate and
logical positivism. Psychology generally by- deviations were construed as ‘error’. Aggregate
passed this view (and the concomitant debate). scores, however, make it difficult to develop
Instead, it has relied on the 19th-century posi- concepts about intra-individual processes and
tivism of Ernst Mach that was gradually these were the most important to the develop-
modified and introduced into psychological ment of the discipline. The introduction of infer-
research through behaviourism with an explicit ential statistics solved this problem for
emphasis on observation as the key element of psychologists, namely, it allowed the identifi-
scientific research (Danziger, 1990; Mills, 1998; cation of psychological properties with the hypo-
O’Neil, 1995). On this view observations were thetical distributions of statistical analyses. In
separate from theory, and gradually came to rely other words, individual scores no longer mat-
on models, such as Hull’s, which were tered but rather the distribution of scores came
277
02 Stam (jr/d) 26/7/00 11:00 am Page 278

JOURNAL OF HEALTH PSYCHOLOGY 5(3)

to represent the theoretical processes at hand. There are obviously occasions and questions
For example, such processes as memory could associated with health that demand an empirical
be captured not by studying individual acts of descriptive strategy. For example, we might
remembering but by comparing how different want to know the motives for condom use
groups (‘experimental conditions’) of indi- among young adults (e.g. Cooper, Agocha, &
viduals performed on some restricted task such Powers, 1999) or the relations among ethnicity,
as learning and recalling a list of nonsense sylla- wealth and health (e.g. Ostrove, Feldman, &
bles. The resulting, functional theoretical notion Adler, 1999). Note, however, that many such
was one that no longer referred to any single questions are broadly epidemiological or social
participant in the experiment but instead to an and not just psychological. That is, they concern
abstract property of ‘memory’. social and community health questions, pre-
Methodological prescriptions, including the cisely the kinds of questions to which one wants
requirement of confirmation through obser- to have descriptive data so that policy and prac-
vations analysed using statistical inference tech- tice issues can be brought to the fore. They do
niques, severely constricted the possibilities of not even begin to address what is psychological
theory development. However sophisticated about such issues.
one’s psychological notions, the indiscriminate What remains as theorizing in the mainstream
use of tests of statistical inference led to a of health psychology hides the professional and
mechanical and routine use of the technique that authorial source of knowledge, makes reci-
by its very nature foreclosed rather than procity between the source and the production
advanced theory (Gigerenzer, 1993). Psycho- of knowledge impossible, and treats the produc-
logical theory remains relatively simple because ers of that knowledge as professionals carrying
the techniques of adjudication between theories out a job in the name of science. It is unreflexive
require uncomplicated, elementary and simpli- about its knowledge production, namely that of
fied models and hypotheses.5 constituent players engaged in the construction
More important yet for health psychology, the of health and illness. Behind its universalism lies
restriction of theory and the absence of a strong an individualism that characterizes much of psy-
theoretical foundation allows the practices of chology; what the scientific knower knows is
psychologists to coincide with those of biomedi- independent of who the knower happens to be,
cine. I do not claim that this is necessarily or the knower’s social position, and the use to
always intentional; institutional prerogatives which such knowledge is put.
and agendas rarely are in any case. With its focus I will not rehearse the multiple antidotes to
on prevention, adjustment and coping, health this form of knowledge production that have
psychology considers ‘healthy’ the patient who been prescribed over the last four decades by
has regained the ability to perform. Health in theorists and methodologists in the name of
this sense is a functional entity, not one negoti- various emancipatory or post-positivist projects.
ated in a shifting discourse of health and illness Feminism, critical theory, postmodernisms of
encompassing the activities of falling ill or various kinds as well as the wide prevalence of
becoming well (see also Spicer & Chamberlain’s qualitative methods have sought to reclaim terri-
notion of ‘flowcharting’, 1996). I would argue, tory from the wider fields of health sciences just
however, that any substantial theorization of the as these have pervaded other domains of psy-
psychology of health and illness and its subjec- chology (e.g. Stainton Rogers, 1996). Neverthe-
tivization must begin by taking a critical distance less, qualitative research does not, in itself,
from the discourse of biomedicine. This distanc- guarantee an escape from more traditional
ing is almost impossible to do in mainstream mainstream forms of knowledge production. It
health psychology. Discursively and method- is an easy step to reformulate qualitative
ologically it is tied to a single simplified model, research so that it is yet another neutral method
the very maintenance of which is also a strategic of inquiry that captures better, and implicitly,
discursive act even as it masquerades as scien- more faithful and true characterizations of
tifically pure. health and illness.6

278
02 Stam (jr/d) 26/7/00 11:00 am Page 279

STAM: THEORIZING HEALTH AND ILLNESS

Responsible health more manageable. If, on the other hand, we


professionals negotiate these needs in the terms that the ill
give us, in terms of their own life histories and in
What multiple critical perspectives have fore- terms of their needs to negotiate a complex
grounded, however, is the place from which we health system, then we also create more respons-
do research or from which we practise. Feminist ible but less comfortable service positions for
philosopher Kathryn Addelson has argued that ourselves.
as professionals, ‘being morally responsible However, it is not only needs and practices
requires foresight in acting from one’s place, that we establish; we also have a hand in defin-
foresight on the outcomes of collective activity ing outcomes. When these are to be constituted
in which one takes part’ (Addelson, 1994, p. 18, as empirically verifiable constructs such as
original emphasis). This means that we devise adjustment, ‘quality of life’ objectively defined
‘theories and practices that can make explicit or compliance with a medical regime, we deny
what the collective activity is’ and what the out- that we are collectively, as a profession, defining
comes of that activity might be (p. 18). In other a set of outcomes for others. The process of
words, our interventions in health do not arise objectification denies the historical constitution
de novo from rational objective theories but of those outcomes. Historical constitution here
always first and foremost from a discursive pos- means simply that outcomes always take place in
ition within such seemingly objective theories collectives whether these range from the con-
that have as their ends the production of certain versation between two people to the discussions
‘goods’, be they function, adaptation, under- that take place in a conference on health psy-
standing, insight, and so on. chology (cf. Addelson, 1994). Professional
In addition, what the new epistemologies have accounts of outcomes are special kinds of out-
taken from us is the possibility of a fixed, certain comes, produced in the context of and support-
or rational standpoint from which to engage in ing existing social, political and economic
professional activities. Instead, our activities are orders.
always politically engaged because of our pos- To return for a moment to Kathryn Addel-
itions as professionals in the social order. Reflex- son’s work, I would like to pursue her general
ivity then means recognizing not only the proposal that ‘truth’ is always enacted in collec-
inevitability of being so positioned but deciding tive action. Our claims as professionals, even as
what moral goods we will pursue in our activi- critical or qualitative researchers, make sense so
ties. long as others recognize the talk. As collectives
Our cognitive authority as professionals is (such as at a conference or writing for, and
granted to us by the institutions that employ reading, specialized journals) we then elaborate
us. Indeed, Addelson argues that all pro- on, seek out further clarification of, and redefine
fessions, and this certainly includes the service our professional talk. But in our interactions
professions, are obliged to have knowledge with the ill or with other health care pro-
makers providing that ‘difficult body of know- fessionals we also come prepared and sensitized
ledge’ that legitimates their professional status. to the setting. Working on a defined terrain, we
And it is this body of knowledge that distin- know how, from within our professional activi-
guishes professionals, such as health psycholo- ties. Addelson argues that we are socially
gists, from workers in other occupations. As embodied actors who not only do professional
health psychologists we use this knowledge to work but in doing so are also significant moral
define more clearly the need that we in turn and political actors. We are taken to be ‘trust-
service.7 Hence there is an intimate relationship worthy instruments of governance’ (p. 208).
between our knowledge base and our practical
endeavours. If we define needs in terms of
What can be done
abstract functional variables such as coping and
adjustment, or in terms of DSM criteria, our At this juncture it is not an unreasonable
research priorities will reflect the objective and obligation on the critic that he or she should
abstract definitions of those needs. That makes proffer some alternative to the problems here
the service and research context simpler and enumerated. I have two objections to this
279
02 Stam (jr/d) 26/7/00 11:00 am Page 280

JOURNAL OF HEALTH PSYCHOLOGY 5(3)

request: first, there is already sufficient critical, how we read the outcomes of those activities. At
theoretical, morally informed research and each stage we are engaged in the negotiation of
writing in various literatures related to health. health, disease and illness through a complex
Large numbers of studies have been conducted moral and social process. Our theories are, if you
inspired by a host of approaches that cover a will, not only ‘observation-laden’ but also
wide range of phenomena and problems, albeit dependent on the place from which we theorize
largely outside psychology (but see, for example, and generate knowledge.
articles in this journal, the journal Health, To bring this into some kind of perspective,
or such examples—among many others—as allow me to give two case studies that focus on
Blair, 1993; Kleinman, 1996; Kugelmann, 1992; the subtle relationship that exists between insti-
Mathieson & Stam, 1995; Radley, 1994; Toombs, tutional commitments and knowledge claims. I
1992; Wennemo, 1993; Williams, 1993). Such ex- am not giving examples of either research or
amples typically begin by conceptualizing the how one ought to proceed. I want simply to
problems of health/illness outside the domains locate the problem of the relationship between
of biomedicine, locating it in lives as they are the professional, institutional context of our
understood by the ill, in class consciousness, in activities and our rational considerations of
culture and talk, and so on. What marks this health and illness. The first case comes from
literature is the separation of the institutional Ruth Miltenburg, a Dutch health care activist
agenda from the experiential, the social and the and organizational consultant who has a debili-
access issues governing health care. tating chronic illness herself. Her understanding
There seems to me a second, more compelling of being ill has been shaped by her conception of
reason not to provide lists of problems and the illness as a ‘job’ or ‘profession’. Just like other
manner in which I wish to see them addressed jobs, one must learn it well in order to carry it
with appropriate methods/attitudes and the like. off. But it is a difficult profession because it
My concerns about the nature of functional covers so many terrains that we normally do not
theory, aggregate statistics and the need for have to deal with when we are not ill, including
moral reflexivity is to open up and create new doctors and hospitals but also relationships,
possibilities for understanding health and illness death, and so on (Miltenburg, 1998). At a recent
that are not constrained by the turgid strictures conference on nursing care she said that ‘nursing
of methodocentric preoccupations whose care . . . is occupied with tasks that are better
purpose appears sometimes limited to helping known at the United Nations as torture, namely,
its authors become published and promote the systematic and organized deprivation of
careers but do not fundamentally involve our sleep and proper feeding . . . [the] disturbance of
understanding of the problems at hand. Or, as biorhythms, deprivation of freedoms, dehuman-
Daniel Robinson recently argued so elegantly, ization and so on’ (Miltenburg, 1997). By
‘progress in science is won by the application of juxtaposing the UN definition of torture with
an informed imagination to a problem of normal nursing care she brought the problem of
genuine consequence; not by the habitual appli- ‘care’ into the moral, everyday domain and
cation of some formulaic mode of inquiry to a set demanded that care at the very least requires the
of quasi-problems chosen chiefly because of skill to think from two perspectives, not only
their compatibility with the adopted method’ from that of one’s own profession but also from
(2000, p. 41). However we conceive of science the perspective of the ill. Or, more precisely, the
and its relation to health psychology, it is not professional orientation so common to nursing
going to progress in any sense of that word by frequently equates care with efficiency, time
following lists of prescribed formulations, even spent in hospital, physiological healing and the
if those formulations come from well-meaning like. Such simple matters as obtaining sufficient
critical theorists. sleep and a reasonable meal, which may be para-
Theorizing health and illness in psychology is mount to the patient, are not part of the nursing
not an abstract activity but one permanently definition of ‘care’ and hence simply don’t come
embedded in how we approach our research and to matter to institutional agendas.
practice settings, participants and colleagues, Finally, I recently had the opportunity to sit on
how we conduct ourselves in those settings, and the medical admissions committee of my home
280
02 Stam (jr/d) 26/7/00 11:00 am Page 281

STAM: THEORIZING HEALTH AND ILLNESS

university and witness more clearly how pro- classroom. Furthermore, we negotiate them in
fessional sensitivities operate. I initially thought practice so I am not advocating that we merely
that my early experience in the hospital would meditate on their implications. Instead, as we
prime me for seeking out particularly good are doing in print, here, we work them out in
candidates for the medical profession. Con- action. It is for these reasons that our theoretical
fronted by the applications, however, I quickly commitments are so crucial to our consider-
realized that the lore and lure of professional ations of health and illness, for I see them as
medicine is such that it draws a relatively hom- nothing less than an articulation of our political,
ogenous set of applicants. Virtually all of them epistemological and moral grounding.
are high achievers, many have had experiences
with illness and death, have extensive volunteer
Notes
experience and most are idealistic and express
altruistic motives, at least their applications are 1. This author is not alone or unique and I do not wish
rhetorically structured in such a way that they to single him out except that he was in a recent
give the appearance of a relatively unique group issue of the journal in question. This strategy of
of similar young adults. Once certain obvious (to theorizing is ubiquitous, inside health psychology
and out, and its historical and institutional foun-
the committee) candidates were excluded, one
dations are sufficiently complex that I can only
might think that the remainder were virtually note this here (cf. Stam, 1996).
chosen by lottery (as is the case in some coun- 2. Models in science are normally taken to be partial
tries). What I recognized among my own choices simulations derived from a theory and hence a
and those of my colleagues on the committee, limited test of a more advanced and developed
however, was that these were far from random theoretical formulation (Suppe, 1989). In the social
but gradually revealed a set of professional and sciences, however, the term ‘model’ is often used
personal concerns never articulated by the com- loosely to describe a guiding formulation that is not
mittee and not present in the admission criteria. related to a particular theory but is associated
instead with functional properties. My argument
We were sensitized by insiders’ and professional
here is that the ‘biopsychosocial model’ doesn’t
concerns, capable of making judgments in the
even approximate this looser use of the term
abstract about individuals we had never met, on ‘model’.
the basis of fine details in their biographical 3. An adaptation of an idea from Ian Lubek (1993)
reports or their application information. And who has argued that social psychology textbooks
although my own sensitivity was different from should, like cigarettes, carry a warning about their
the physicians’, it was there nonetheless, recog- potential hazards.
nizable by the criteria that gradually came to 4. In health psychology there is almost no discussion
make a difference to my judgments of ‘yes’ or of the ethical and economic limits of biomedicine
‘no’. that have become so apparent in the past decade
The point of this story is not that the medical and no recognition that the struggle to change life-
styles is at its worst a ‘hypochondriacal narcissism
admissions committee should change its criteria
of a privileged class shutting its eyes to the deterio-
or make its application process more effective or ration of the rest of the world’ (Renaud, 1993).
transparent. This would be merely to assume 5. In less official publications, health psychologists
that fully rational and objective decisions about acknowledge this problem. For example, using his
who can or cannot become a doctor are avail- presidential column in the APA Division 38 news-
able. Indeed, medical schools present just such a letter, Howard Leventhal remarked that ‘many of
face to the world, complete with discussions of our theories are little more than broad themes that
criteria and their evaluation via research pub- guide but do not constrain our thinking; they are
lished in medical journals. Hence the process frames of reference rather than theories’ (1996,
appears justifiably rational. My point, however, p. 1). Unfortunately, Leventhal had no solution to
this problem.
is only that such professional sensitivities are
6. See the special issue of this journal edited by
inevitable and ever-present in all our activities Murray and Chamberlain (1998) for a discussion of
inside institutions, including medical ones. We these problems.
never leave our moral commitments behind at 7. By ‘need’ I do not mean just clinical need. I also
the breakfast table, they follow us into the mean the ‘need’ for more research that is opened
consulting room, the meeting room and the up by any extant ‘finding.’

281
02 Stam (jr/d) 26/7/00 11:00 am Page 282

JOURNAL OF HEALTH PSYCHOLOGY 5(3)

References Mathieson, C. M., & Stam, H. J. (1995). Renegotiating


identity: Cancer narratives. Sociology of Health &
Addelson, K. P. (1994). Moral passages: Toward a col- Illness, 17, 283–306.
lectivist moral theory. New York: Routledge. Mills, J. A. (1998). Control: A history of behavioral
American Psychological Association, Division 38. psychology. New York: New York University Press.
(1996). Mission statement [On-line]. Available: Miltenburg, R. (1997). De verpleegkundige praktijk in
[http: //freud.apa.org/divisions/div38/mission.html]. Nederland: Een geval van neglect voor ‘zorg’.
Aries, N., & Kennedy, L. (1990). The health labor [Nursing practice in the Netherlands: A case of the
force: The effects of change. In P. Conrad & R. Kern neglect of ‘care’.] Paper presented at Netwerk IPB
(Eds.), The sociology of health and illness: Critical Verpleegkundige Kwaliteitszorg, November.
perspectives (3rd ed.) (pp. 195–206). New York: St Miltenburg, R. (1998). Over ziek zijn [On being ill].
Martin’s. Utrecht/Antwerp: Kosmos-Z&K.
Blair, A. (1993). Social class and the contextualization Murray, M., & Chamberlain, K. (1998). Qualitative
of illness experience. In A. Radley (Ed.), Worlds of research in health psychology: Developments and
illness (pp. 27–48). London: Routledge. directions. Journal of Health Psychology, 3, 291–295.
Burke, M., & Stevenson, H. M. (1993). Fiscal crisis and O’Neil, W. M. (1995). American behaviorism: A his-
restructuring in Medicare: The politics and political torical and critical analysis. Theory & Psychology, 5,
science of health in Canada. Health and Canadian 285–306.
Society, 1, 51–80. Ostrove, J. M., Feldman, P., & Adler, N. E. (1999).
Cooper, M. L., Agocha, V. B., & Powers, A. M. (1999). Relations among socioeconomic status indicators
Motivations for condom use: Do pregnancy preven- and health for African-Americans and whites.
tion goals undermine disease prevention among Journal of Health Psychology, 4, 451–463.
heterosexual young adults? Health Psychology, 18, Radley, A. (1994). Making sense of illness: The social
464–474. psychology of health and illness. London: Sage.
Danziger, K. (1990). Constructing the subject: His- Renaud, M. (1993). Social sciences and medicine:
torical origins of psychological research. New York: Hygeia versus Panakeia? Health and Canadian
Cambridge University Press. Society, 1, 229–247.
Engel, G. L. (1977). The need for a new medical Robinson, D. N. (2000). Paradigms and ‘the myth of
model: A challenge for biomedicine. Science, 196, framework’: How science progresses. Theory & Psy-
129–136. chology, 10, 39–47.
Evans-Pritchard, E. E. (1951). Social anthropology. Schwartz, G. E. (1982). Testing the biopsychosocial
London: Cohen & West. model: The ultimate challenge facing behavioral
Fox, N. J. (1994). Postmodernism, sociology and health. medicine. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psy-
Toronto: University of Toronto Press. chology, 50, 1040–1053.
Gigerenzer, G. (1993). The superego, the ego, and the Smedslund, G. (2000). A pragmatic basis for judging
id in statistical reasoning. In G. Keren & C. Lewis models and theories in health psychology: The
(Eds.), A handbook for data analysis in the axiomatic method. Jouranl of Health Psychology, 5,
behavioral sciences: Methodological issues. Hills- 133–149.
dale, NJ: Erlbaum. Spicer, J., & Chamberlain, K. (1996). Developing
Kleinman, A. (1996). Suffering, ethics, and the politics psychosocial theory in health psychology. Journal of
of moral life. Culture, Medicine and Psychiatry, 20, Health Psychology, 1, 161–171.
287–290. Stainton Rogers, W. (1996). Critical approaches to
Kugelmann, R. (1992). Stress: The nature and history health psychology. Journal of Health Psychology, 1,
of engineered grief. Westport, CT: Praeger. 65–77.
Leventhal, H. (1996) President’s column. The Health Stam, H. J. (1988). The practice of health psychology
Psychologist, 18(4), 1, 22. and behavioral medicine: Whither theory? In W. J.
Lubek, I. (1993). Social psychology textbooks: An Baker, L. P. Mos, H. V. Rappard, & H. J. Stam
historical and social psychological analysis of con- (Eds.), Recent trends in theoretical psychology
ceptual filtering, consensus formation, career gate- (pp. 313–325). New York: Springer Verlag.
keeping and conservatism in science. In H. J. Stam, Stam, H. J. (1992). Troublesome bodies. Disability
L. P. Mos, W. Thorngate, & B. Kaplan (Eds.), Recent Studies Quarterly, 12(2), 31–36.
trends in theoretical psychology (Vol. III) (pp. Stam, H. J. (1996). Theory & practice. In C. Tolman, F.
359–378). New York: Springer Verlag. Cherry, R. V. Hezewijk, & I. Lubek (Eds.), Prob-
Marks, D. F. (1996). Health psychology in context. lems of theoretical psychology (pp. 24–32). Toronto:
Journal of Health Psychology, 1, 7–21. Captus Press.

282
02 Stam (jr/d) 26/7/00 11:00 am Page 283

STAM: THEORIZING HEALTH AND ILLNESS


Stam, H. J. (in press). Theoretical psychology. In Taylor, S. E. (1999). Health psychology. Boston:
K. Pawlik & M. Rosenzweig (Eds.), International McGraw Hill.
handbook of psychology. London: Sage. Toombs, S. K. (1992). The meaning of illness. Dor-
Stam, H. J., & Pasay, G. A. (1998). The historical case drecht: Kluwer.
against null-hypothesis significance testing. Behav- Turner, B. S. (1986). Sociology as an academic trade:
ioral and Brain Sciences, 21, 219–220. Some reflections on centre and periphery in the
Stone, G. C. (1980). Psychology and the health system. sociology market. Australian and New Zealand
In G. C. Stone, F. Cohen, & N. E. Adler (Eds.), Journal of Sociology, 22, 272–282.
Health psychology—A handbook (pp. 47–75). San Wennemo, I. (1993). Infant mortality, public policy,
Francisco: Jossey-Bass. and inequality—A comparison of 18 industrialized
Stone, G. C., Weiss, S. M., Matarazzo, J. D., Miller, countries, 1950–85. Sociology of Health and Illness,
N. E., Rodin, J., Belar, C. D., Follick, M. J., & Singer, 15, 429–446.
J. E. (1987). Health psychology: A discipline and a Williams, G. (1993). Chronic illness and the pursuit of
profession. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. virtue in everyday life. In A. Radley (Ed.), Worlds
Suppe, F. (1989). The semantic conception of theories of illness (pp. 92–108). London: Routledge.
and scientific realism. Urbana, IL: University of
Illinois Press.

283

Você também pode gostar