Você está na página 1de 68

R a d i c a l     P h i l o s o p h y

a journal of socialist and feminist philosophy

152 CONTENTS november/decemBER 2008

Editorial collective COMMENTARY


Claudia Aradau, David Cunningham,
Howard Feather, Peter Hallward, Between Imperial Client and Useful Enemy: Pakistan’s Permanent
Esther Leslie, Stewart Martin, Kaye Mitchell, Crisis
Mark Neocleous, Peter Osborne,
Stella Sandford Justin Podur..................................................................................................... 2

Contributors
Justin Podur is Assistant Professor of articles
Environmental Studies at York University,
Canada. In July 2008 he was a Fellow of
the Iqbal International Institute for Research
Entsetzen: Walter Benjamin and the Red Army Faction, Part One
and Dialogue at the International Islamic Irving Wohlfarth............................................................................................... 7
University, Islamabad.
Irving Wohlfarth studied with Adorno and Flux and Flurry: Stillness and Hypermovement in Animated Worlds
the student movement in the 1960s and has Esther Leslie................................................................................................... 21
worked on Benjamin ever since. Recent
publications include ‘On Benjamin’s Death’,
Naharaim, autumn 2008 (with Nathalie Non-traduttore, Traditore? Notes on Postwar European Marxisms
Raoux) – a refutation of an article by Jeremy in Translation
Harding in the London Review of Books – and
‘Anachrony: Interferences between Benjamin Gregory Elliott............................................................................................... 31
and Sebald’, Internationales Archiv für die
Sozialgeschichte der Literatur. He is currently Introduction to Rozitchner
assembling an essay collection on Benjamin
entitled No Man’s Land and writing a book on Philip Derbyshire and John Kraniauskas.................................................... 40
Benjamin’s politics.
Esther Leslie teaches in the School of English Exile, War and Democracy: An Exemplary Sequence
and Humanities at Birkbeck, University León Rozitchner............................................................................................. 41
of London. She has recently published a
biography of Walter Benjamin in Reaktion
Books’ Critical Lives series (2007).
Gregory Elliott is a Visiting Fellow at reviews
Newcastle University. His Ends in Sight:
Marx/Fukuyama/Hobsbawm/Anderson was Quentin Meillassoux, After Finitude: An Essay on the Necessity of Contingency
published by Pluto earlier this year. Peter Hallward............................................................................................... 51
León Rozitchner is an Argentine intellectual.
Christopher Kelty, Two Bits: The Cultural Significance of Free Software
James Tobias.................................................................................................. 57

Nicos Poulantzas, The Poulantzas Reader: Marxism, Law and the State
Copyedited and typeset by illuminati Bob Jessop..................................................................................................... 61
www.illuminatibooks.co.uk
Layout by Peter Osborne and David Peg Rawes, Space, Geometry and Aesthetics: Through Kant and towards Deleuze
Cunningham
Printed by Russell Press, Russell House,
Garin Dowd.................................................................................................... 63
Bulwell Lane, Basford, Nottingham NG6 0BT
Bookshop distribution Alastair Morgan, Adorno’s Concept of Life
UK: Central Books, Josh Robinson............................................................................................... 64
115 Wallis Road, London E9 5LN
Tel: 020 8986 4854
Nick Hewlett, Badiou, Balibar, Rancière: Re-thinking Emancipation
USA: Ubiquity Distributors Inc., Todd May, The Political Thought of Jacques Rancière: Creating Equality
607 Degraw Street, Brooklyn, New York 11217
Tel: 718 875 5491 Pablo Lafuente............................................................................................... 65
Cover Snow Globe, 2008

Letters
Published by Radical Philosophy Ltd.
www.radicalphilosophy.com Critical Views of South Africa

© Radical Philosophy Ltd Patrick Bond and Ronald Suresh Roberts.................................................. 67


Commentary

Between imperial client


and useful enemy
Pakistan’s permanent crisis
Justin Podur

P
akistani scholar–activist Eqbal Ahmed, who died in 1999, had a canny ability to
predict events. In a 1974 article for the Journal of Contemporary Asia, he sug-
gested that Pakistan was headed towards a police state structure because of the
class and ideological composition of the military and its supremacy over civil society.1
Other sectors, such as the bureaucracy, feudal landlords and the small entrepreneurial
class, were weak and subordinate. Opposition parties, meanwhile, were ‘given more
to hyperbole and public meetings than to organizing and resisting. A large part of the
opposition is either ideologically reactionary or indistinguishable from the party in
power.’ A police state would use either a kind of developmental-fascist ideology (as
happened in Chile, Brazil and Greece) or it would rely on religious fundamentalism,
and would find an eager sponsor in the United States. ‘Unfortunately,’ the article
concludes, ‘the democratic and revolutionary groups in Pakistan to whom falls the
responsibility of halting this trend are as yet only weakly developed.’
The main elements of Eqbal Ahmed’s analysis remain valid today. The military
has become even stronger relative to civil society, opposing social forces weaker and
divided, with democratic and revolutionary groups only weakly developed. At the epi-
centre of the War on Terror, Pakistan’s current predicament brings together the inability
of the state to deliver development or justice to its people, an ambiguous imperial
sponsor, all the economic woes of neoliberal capitalism, and the cooptation mechanisms
of ‘democracy promotion’. Despite an absence of legitimacy, organizational inefficacy,
and shrinking capacity to respond to challenges from the USA or India, Pakistan’s
military dictatorship survives because it is stronger than civil society and political alter-
natives to it have been destroyed. The strength of the regime is based on the absence of
feasible alternatives.

Ousting Musharraf: back to civilian power?


President Musharraf resigned in August 2008, but, as Tariq Ali commented, ‘Over the
last 50 years the USA has worked mainly with the Pakistan army. This has been its
preferred instrument. Nothing has changed. The question being asked now is how long
it will be before the military is back at the helm.’2
In Pakistan the reins of government are the prize of a three-way contest between
civilian authority, a weak civil society and the military, with the military by far the
strongest player. Musharraf came to power in a coup back in 1999. When his legitimacy
was eventually challenged by the Supreme Court last year, he sacked the Supreme
Court judges. The judges responded and large numbers mobilized alongside them

 Radical Philosophy 152 (November/December 20 08)


in the ‘lawyers’ movement’ that began when Supreme Court Chief Justice Iftikhar
Muhammad Chaudhry was suspended in March 2007. That movement also found
support and strength from commercial media that had paradoxically acquired some new
freedom under Musharraf’s dictatorship, and continue tentatively to test that freedom.
The next phase of the contest was fought in the arena of the parliamentary elections,
which Benazir Bhutto, after negotiations with Washington and Musharraf, returned to
Pakistan to contest – only to be assassinated in December 2007. The elections took
place anyway, in February 2008; Bhutto’s Pakistan People’s Party (PPP) as well as the
Pakistan Muslim League–Nawaz (PML–N) of Nawaz Sharif, who had been prime min-
ister until ousted by Musharraf’s coup in 1999, came to dominate the post-coup govern-
ment. The Pakistan Muslim League-Quaid-e-Azam (PML–Q), Musharraf’s party, made
a poor showing, as did those Islamist parties that had enjoyed state sponsorship under
Musharraf. When the PPP and PML–N reached power with help from popular support
and the prestige of the lawyer’s struggle, they did not reinstate the Supreme Court.
Both Nawaz Sharif and the PPP head and new President Asif Ali Zardari, Benazir
Bhutto’s widower, have reasons to fear an independent judiciary. Zardari and Sharif
had both been up for corruption charges for their behaviour under previous govern-
ments. The post-election brokering involved various mutual amnesties. Moreover, if the
judiciary didn’t give in to the military government, it might not give in to the civilian
government either.
In August 2008, Zardari and Sharif finally made their move, taking action to
impeach President Musharraf and stating that the reinstatement of the judges would
follow. After months in power, during which they neither restored the judges nor made
any headway with the country’s growing number of political or economic problems,
the fractious coalition of the PPP and PML–N agreed on a plan: to move against
Musharraf, using the prestige the elected government still retains, and to reinstate the
judges. It was a risky strategy for leaders who are dogged by charges of corruption
and illegality dating from previous turns in government (or, in Zardari’s case, behind
the scenes in government). There is still no plan for dealing with the US occupation of
Afghanistan or the resistance against it, or with other forces operating from the Afghan
border area of Pakistan. Nor do they have a plan for the economic problems. No doubt
the strategy is to blame Musharraf for the inherited problems, to buy some time.

The USA in Afghanistan and Pakistan’s intractable insurgency


Now that the plan has succeeded, the coalition has already begun to unravel as US
military pressure continues on the Afghan border, and the Supreme Court judges
remain out of office. As the USA tries to decide whether Pakistan would be of greater
benefit as an ally or an enemy, Pakistan’s rulers have a delicate balance to strike if they
want to stay in power. Musharraf’s claim to competence was based on the fact that he
managed the country and kept a relationship with the USA through an impossible situa-
tion. Pakistan’s military strategy since its independence in 1947 has always been based
primarily on the Indian threat and Kashmir. Pakistan’s alliances with the United States
and China were motivated by this consideration.
Pakistan’s Northwest Frontier Province (NWFP) and the Federally Administered
Tribal Areas (FATA) are ethnically Pashtun, which is also the ethnicity of the largest
number of Afghans. The border is porous and not really recognized by the people
who live there. The state’s relationship to NWFP has also been complex. The FATA
area does not have provincial status and administration occurs through patron–client
and negotiated relationships with local leaders. Throughout its history, Pakistan faced
resentment from each subnational minority, all of whom resented domination by the
Punjabi majority, whose elite is overrepresented in the military. One of the reasons that
the military operations in the NWFP have been so unsuccessful is that Pashtuns in the


military do not see the logic of firing on their fellow Pashtuns, Pakistanis, Muslims, for
the sake of a US war.
When the USSR invaded Afghanistan in 1979, these areas of Pakistan became the
bases for a US-, Saudi- and Pakistani-sponsored war against the Soviets. This moment
saw three important changes in Pakistan. First, control passed to Zia ul-Haq, Pakistan’s
worst military dictator, who ‘Islamized’ the military and attempted to ‘Islamize’ the
other institutions of the country.3 Second, the USSR presence in Afghanistan changed
the US attitude towards Pakistan, including its nuclear programme, which the USA
began to support covertly. Third, the most ‘hands-on’ role in organizing this war was
taken on by Pakistan’s Inter-Services Intelligence (ISI). After the USSR left in 1988,
Pakistan maintained a very strong influence in Afghanistan, and was profoundly
influenced in turn – by the small arms, narcotics economy, and militarism that are
inevitably associated with covert operations, and by the Islamist ideology that was used
to mobilize fighters from all over the world to come through Pakistan to join battle with
the USSR. When veterans of these movements, angry with America’s bases in Saudi
Arabia, the destruction of Iraq and support for Israel, turned their guns on the USA and
attacked New York in 2001, Pakistan was in a bind. Clients that it had once supported
along with the USA were now in the gunsights of its ally. By providing the USA with
help in the invasion of Afghanistan, Pakistan was able to save its clients and its own
personnel from destruction, as much of the Taliban and al-Qaeda crossed the border to
Pakistan or went to ground and Afghanistan was taken over by US-friendly warlords.
Musharraf paid a price for this, however, in assassination attempts and accusations of
treason for supporting the USA against fellow Muslims in Pakistan and Afghanistan.
That tension has escalated continuously since 2001. Today, the USA and NATO
demand that Pakistan take action against insurgents operating in NWFP and FATA.
When Pakistan does so, its forces take casualties and it loses legitimacy in the region.
When it provides passive or active support for the insurgents, as it has in the past, it is
exposed to US threats (and its soldiers, sometimes, to US bombs). As the motives of the
USA/NATO themselves seem increasingly confused or contradictory – is their aim to
establish a long-term presence in the region? To watch and threaten Pakistan? To fight
al-Qaeda and the Taliban? – parts of the countryside of Afghanistan and the NWFP and
FATA have come under the control of the Taliban. While Pakistan’s authorities promise
to use their military to extend the ‘writ of the state’ in those areas, insurgency in both
countries is growing in opposition to the extension of the writ of the wrong kind of
state. The global and local balance of forces makes it virtually impossible for a state
like Pakistan to deal with this kind of insurgency.

Counterinsurgency and the absence of the state


As mentioned above, the FATA have no representative provincial administration: the
central government rules through deals with local leaders. This hangover from the
British Raj is a symptom of a colonial state, the operation of which has generated resis-
tance in FATA, Baluchistan and Sindh over decades. The Taliban have flourished not
just because of the NATO occupation of Afghanistan but also because of the absence
of the state in the NWFP and FATA. People rely on the insurgency’s sharia courts for
justice, as even brutal justice fills a vacuum.
In other parts of Pakistan, the vacuum is filled in different ways. In Karachi, for
example, there are reports of mob violence and lynching. The idea that the Taliban
could take all of Pakistan is exaggerated. Despite its strength in NWFP and FATA,
there are very different structures, elites, and power bases in Punjab, Sindh and
Baluchistan. If NATO leaves and Afghanistan falls to the Taliban, the maximal scenario
for Pakistan is probably a de facto Taliban-controlled NWFP and FATA. Deterioration
of the state could also be blamed for the region’s opium problem. Since 2001, there


have been periodic waves of stories about opium and its role in fuelling the insurgency
in the West. But the idea of an ‘opium-fuelled insurgency’ can be deceptive. Today, the
Afghan economy is dependent on poppy, which, according to the UN sociologist David
Macdonald, supplies 60 per cent of Afghanistan’s GDP and employs 10 per cent of its
people.4 Everyone in the economy, from farmers to local warlords, from foreign intel-
ligence agents to government officials, from the Taliban to probably NATO soldiers as
well, are taking a piece. It is not just the insurgency that’s opium-fuelled, but the entire
economy.
The narcotics trade provides resources for the
insurgency to challenge the state. Meanwhile, the
state, and specifically the military, is present in
areas that are normally the preserve of the private
sector. As Ayesha Siddiqa documents in her book
Military Inc., the military owns cornflakes, banks,
real estate, cement, insurance, and many other
industries. 5 This is far from the public ownership of
socialist economics, as there is no national develop-
ment project behind it. Indeed, transnational capital
is encouraged to take its share as well, especially
in resource-rich Baluchistan, where companies such
as Canada’s Barrick Gold are signing contracts for
exploration and mining. Military spending has also
drawn resources away from development and invest-
ment in the national economy.

Government failures, ecological dangers


Although Pakistan’s military business, or ‘Milbus’,
structure is sometimes blamed for poor economic
performance, the country has deeper structural
economic and ecological problems exacerbated
by the rise in energy prices and climate change.
Pakistan’s breadbasket is the Punjab, also the keystone site of the ‘Green Revolution’,
in which modern chemical agriculture was adopted at the urging of Western planners
and financiers. The Green Revolution is often presented as a tremendous advance, but
some students of South Asian agriculture, like Vandana Shiva, Devinder Sharma and P.
Sainath, have shown a less bright side to it – exhausted soil, people without work and
no way to feed themselves, rural-to-urban migration, increased vulnerability to global
commodity prices, and dependence on expensive inputs.
In 2008 Pakistan missed its cotton production target and had to import cotton to
run its textile industry, significantly reducing its earnings of foreign exchange Without
much energy of its own (except for gas in Baluchistan), Pakistan needs this foreign
exchange in order to buy ever-more-expensive energy. It is also importing food – milk,
meat, vegetables, wheat, dry fruits, tea, spices, edible oil, sugar and pulses. Combined
with global problems in the food system (see Raj Patel, ‘The Hungry of the Earth’
RP 151) and the supply of food to NATO in Afghanistan, Pakistan’s food security is in
peril. The way in which the energy price shocks of the 1970s hurt the development of
Third World countries that didn’t have their own oil resources is repeating itself today,
combined this time with the perils of climate change. The Punjab’s water comes mainly
from glacier-fed rivers, which, according to most scenarios, will dry up when the
glaciers melt. These economic and ecological problems are a potent source of regional
catastrophe, to which must be added the threat of nuclear destruction, derived from the
rivalry with India.


The weakness of the Left
Such converging crises ought to provide an opening for left politics. But secular left
forces in Pakistan are isolated and precarious, and have to contend with forces of
cooption that have become far stronger since the 1970s, especially NGOs. Critics of
neoliberalism, privatization and militarism are present, but cannot find a foothold in the
clientelistic structures of the main political parties. Some leftists work through the NGO
sector, but the NGO structure has its own serious limitations, based as it is on foreign
funding, often providing clientelistic services itself.
Some NGOs, like Roots for Equity, which works in villages in Sindh and NWFP,
are aware of these limitations and use the structure anyway, as a basis for organizing
and educating peasants about agrarian policy and problems. ‘The only alternative would
be to form a political party’, argued Azra Talat Syed of Roots for Equity, ‘and there
are dozens of tiny left political parties with no following. When movements are strong
enough, parties will emerge.’
Other grassroots groups such as the Rawalpindi-based People’s Rights Movement
(PRM) agitate and demonstrate on political issues, including support for the lawyers’
movement and opposition to military operations in the NWFP and FATA. Aasim
Sajjad Akhtar suggested that capacity was a problem for radical politics: ‘the objective
conditions for progressive politics are tremendous: all parties are not trusted and have
fallen off the pedestal. We are growing but not fast enough. There is potential but
we don’t have the people to do the work.’ Partly, PRM argued, the NGO sector was
diverting people who would otherwise join movements. Partly, there has been a break in
historical continuity, with missing generations of leftists and hence no one to work with
younger people interested in radical politics due to decades of dictatorship. Socialism
is often associated with atheism and, at worst, with the USSR and its invasion of
Afghanistan.
Secular opposition groups do not take an anti-religious stand, but instead focus on
economic and political issues without attacking the connection between religion and
politics directly. To date, there has not been a movement that articulated opposition to
the regime in religious terms. In Pakistan and India (as well as in Israel and the USA),
religious symbols in politics are associated with the Right, although there are hints of
attempts to challenge and contest right-wing politics and religion in Pakistan.
Despite its inability to offer development or democracy to most of its citizens,
Pakistan’s regime survives with help from the USA and through the absence of chal-
lengers in civil society strong enough to replace it. In relative terms, the military is still
the supreme institution in the country. In the coming years the regime could easily find
itself facing a hostile United States, and it might not survive such a contest. Many of
the possible future scenarios are disastrous, but not all of them. Forces in play include
those who mobilized to reinstate the judges, media that have had a taste of freedom,
fledgling anti-imperialist movements for social justice, and activists working for
dialogue and detente with India. When I was in the country in July, university students
invited me to return in twenty years, when, they promised, democracy in Pakistan
would be flourishing.

Notes
1. Eqbal Ahmed, ‘Pakistan – Signposts to a Police State’, Journal of Contemporary Asia, vol. IV, no.
4, 1974, republished in E. Ahmed, Between Past and Future, Oxford University Press, Oxford,
2004.
2. Tariq Ali, ‘Musharraf Will Be Gone in Days’, Guardian, 14 August 2008, www.guardian.co.uk/
commentisfree/2008/aug/14/pakistan.usa?gusrc=rss&feed=networkfront.
3. An entertaining and well-informed version of Zia ul-Haq’s last days is presented in Mohammed
Hanif’s 2008 novel A Case of Exploding Mangoes, Jonathan Cape, London.
4. David Mansfield, ‘Drugs in Afghanistan’, 2007, www.davidmansfield.org.
5. Ayesha Siddiqa, Military Inc.: Inside Pakistan’s Military Economy, Pluto Press, London, 2007.


Entsetzen
Walter Benjamin and the Red Army Faction,
Part One

Irving Wohlfarth

The true politician reckons only in dates. And if existence, conflagrations and celebrations are both
the abolition of the bourgeoisie is not effected by only so much play, preparation for its coming of
an almost calculable moment in economic and age, the hour when panic and celebration, now
technical development (one signalled by inflation recognizing the other as a long-separated brother,
and poison-gas warfare), then all is lost. Before the embrace one another in the revolutionary uprising.
spark reaches the dynamite, the lighted fuse must be (‘Schönes Entsetzen’ [‘Fine Terror’], 1929–34)3
severed. (‘Fire Alarm’, 1928)1
The course of history as represented in the concept
Between 1865 and 1875 a number of great of catastrophe has no more claim on the thinking
anarchists each worked, without knowing of one man’s attention than the kaleidoscope in the hands
another, on their infernal machine. And the astonish- of a child. With each new twist, everything collaps-
ing thing is that they independently set its clock at es into a new order. The image is thoroughly well-
exactly the same hour – and forty years later the grounded [hat sein gutes, gründliches Recht]. The
writings of Dostoevsky, Rimbaud, and Lautréamont concepts of the rulers have always been the mirrors
all simultaneously blew up in Western Europe. One by which the image of an ‘order’ was established.
might, to be more exact, single out one episode – The kaleidoscope must be smashed. (‘Central
from Dostoevsky’s entire work …: ‘Stavrogin’s Park’, 1938)4
Confession’ in The Possessed. This chapter …
contains a justification of evil. … ‘Hatred, to you Strength of hatred in Marx. Fighting spirit of the
I have entrusted my treasure,’ [Rimbaud] writes in working class. Interlay revolutionary destruction and
Une saison en enfer. … Since Bakunin, Europe has the idea of redemption. (Netschajev. The Possessed.)
lacked a radical concept of freedom. (‘Surrealism’, (Notes for ‘On the Concept of History’, 1939)5
1929)2

Is this dull multitude not waiting for a disaster great ‘Dangerous relations’?
enough to strike a spark from its own inner tension: Benjamin and the Red Army Faction – is the subject
a conflagration or world-end, something that could
even worth discussing?* Its background, or under-
suddenly convert this velvet thousand-voiced mur-
muring into a single cry, as a gust of wind sud- ground, has, it is true, hardly been broached in the sec-
denly exposes the scarlet lining of a cloak? For the ondary literature. Yet both sides claimed that violence
piercing cry of terror [des Entsetzens], panic dread, was needed to avert disaster; and Benjamin underwrote
is the other side of all authentic mass celebration an ethics which did not shrink from the ‘revolutionary
[Massenfeste]. In the unconscious depths of mass killing of the oppressor’.6

*
The present essay, to be published in three instalments, is a slightly revised version of one that appeared in the first of two
collective volumes (Der RAF und der linke Terrorismus, Hamburg, 2006) edited by Wolfgang Kraushaar under the auspices of
the Hamburger Institut für Sozialforschung. These are a sequel to an invaluable three-volume study under the same editorship
and auspices: Frankfurter Schule und Studentenbewegung. Von der Flaschenpost zum Molotow-Cocktail 1946–1995 (Hamburg,
1998). The volumes on the Red Army Faction and present-day German ‘reception’ of the latter thirty years after the events
constitute in large measure a case of what the Germans call ‘historicization’; a case too, on occasion, of ‘pathologization’.
It is as if there existed an unspoken consensus to put the ‘leaden years’ in their place – that is, safely behind us. (There was
considerably less agreement across the political spectrum about whether to release long-incarcerated terrorists one or two years
early.) Some former members of the extreme or dogmatic Left have, it is true, given self-critical accounts of their past aberra-
tions; but here too the purpose has been to settle accounts and lay ghosts. There is little doubt that the RAF was indeed a case
of historico-political pathology. But from where – from what normality – do we call it that? The same one that the student
movement originally rebelled against? Or one yet to be born? (And wouldn’t the latter require a certain madness – though not
that of the RAF?) Was the decade around 1968 merely the proverbial sowing of wild oats – the ‘wild years’, as a recent film
called them, of Uschi Obermaier, who lived in a Berlin commune (Kommune I) before becoming a fashion model? Why does

Radical Philosophy 152 (November/December 20 08) 


But a difficult question remains. Does any kind of pseudo-religious vow but a sober, provisional move of
fuse or trail lead from his words to their deeds? If a productively false kind. Under false circumstances,
so, it would mark a striking instance of the general thought and action certainly did not have to be false
problem: how responsible is a thinker for the fate of through and through, but they could not be completely
his/her ideas? Such questions were hardly foreign to dans le vrai. In Benjamin’s case, they were often
Benjamin. He had, he wrote only a year before Hitler spatially and temporally on the verge.
seized power, not yet considered what meaning might ‘There is no right life in a false world’: Adorno’s
be extracted from Nietzsche’s writings ‘in an extreme dictum in Minima Moralia has been much quoted.
case’ (im Ernstfall).7 But who, or what, determines, Arguing from very different premisses, Jacques
precisely when such a case obtains? Does the trajectory Derrida claims that there is no entirely innocent text.11
of the Red Army Faction (which will here henceforth All writing, seen from this ‘deconstructive’ angle,
be termed the RAF) raise in retrospect the question supervenes on, and intervenes in, a dense network of
of the political meaning that might be wrested, in an idioms that criss-cross one another and ‘themselves’.
extreme case, from Benjamin’s writings – especially If, as Benjamin claims, philosophy is confronted ‘at
since such states of emergency were their common every turn’ by the problem of exposition (Darstellung),
concern? then, according to Derrida, each turn marks a decision
Marx, Nietzsche, Heidegger, Benjamin… Each within a specific discursive situation – a decision for
‘case’ requires its own elaborate assessment. But by which the writer is accountable. The ‘critical’ activ-
whom, for whom, in the name of whose justice? In ity is – as Benjamin recalls in the very context at
one of the texts to be discussed below, Benjamin issue here – at once ‘discriminating’ (scheidend) and
claims that while ‘justice’ (Gerechtigkeit), in contrast ‘decisive’ (entscheidend).12 Doing justice to textual
to ‘right’ or ‘law’ (Recht), is ‘generally valid’, it is not complications/implications and reaching a judgement
‘susceptible to generalization’. It can only be done to on them is, for both Benjamin and Derrida, as difficult
a specific ‘situation’, never, as in the case of law, to as it is necessary, notably in the face of important,
a ‘case’ – unless each case be one unto itself. 8 This controversial and ‘dangerous’ writings. A philosophi-
claim could equally hold for Benjamin’s situations, cal philology of this kind represents an immense, still
those of the RAF, and relations, real or potential, largely neglected programme, not merely in the case
between them. of Benjamin’s texts and contexts.
Another of Benjamin’s key concepts should To live and think with and against danger: this was
be introduced here: the ‘guilt nexus of the living’ as critical to Nietzsche, who called himself ‘dyna-
(Schuld­zusammenhang des Lebendigen).9 At the time mite’,13 as to Benjamin, who often gravitated to images
he was considering joining the German Communist of ‘detonation’ (sprengen).14 Nor were their explosives
Party, he noted, in response to Gershom Scholem’s safe. ‘Danger’, Benjamin observed, ‘threatens both
(mis)apprehensions, that he had never been able to the stuff of tradition and its recipients’. Nietzsche was
‘respond rightly (richtig) to false circumstances – that a case in point. Over his dead body, his work was
is, with something “right”’ (mit “Richtigem”), but – or allowed itself to be – truncated and annexed to
only by way of a ‘necessary, symptomatic, productive the cause of National Socialism, whose ‘inner great-
falseness’.10 His decision to join the Party, had he ever ness’ his heir Heidegger briefly affirmed. Benjamin,
made it, would have been of this nature: no quasi- or who made certain ‘dangerous’ elements of right-wing

the erstwhile Left need to throw out the baby with the bath water? Doesn’t ‘historicization’ fall back behind Benjamin’s critique
of historicism? These are some of the questions behind the following essay. It is far from ‘soft’ on the RAF, if only because that
episode has had the long-term effect of further demobilizing radical energies. But it also wants to see in the RAF the symptom
of a collective pathology – a false, unconscionable answer to a true, massive, ongoing, urgent catastrophe of systemic, global
injustice. Meanwhile, the Left has still further declined and its place has been partly taken by terrorisms beside which the RAF
seems parochial. All this has created a new world disorder and complicated any contemporary discussion of terrorist violence.
Under existing conditions, and given the all too foreseeable consequences, no one in his right mind would still want to justify it,
at least in the Western context. But what mind is right without the demon which, unchecked, would lead us in that direction?
Such is perhaps the most intimate reason for our Entsetzen. This verbal noun, which is as untranslatable as das Un­heimliche
(or indeed the latter’s English counterpart: ‘the uncanny’), means, on the one hand, horror and dread to the point of de-rangement
(Ent-setzen); it thus marks, or so one of the opening epigraphs would have it, the reverse side of ec-stasy. On the other hand,
it signifies the displacing or deposing (ent-) of what has been legally instituted (setzen, gesetzt, Gesetz). If Benjamin argued in
1921 for the Entsetzung of Law and State, this was because the prospects for a new world-historical epoch which would break
the cycle of myth did not then seem so ‘inconceivably remote’ as to reduce such talk to insignificance [daß ein Wort gegen das
Recht sich von selbst erledigte]. Today this prospect does seem that remote: how remote the RAF’s attempt to force it involun-
tarily proved. Benjamin, however, held the prospect out even and precisely in the darkest hour – 1940 – as the only real chance
for survival. This claim has not been disproved and, for better or for worse, perhaps cannot be disproved.


thought his own, opted for, and for many years strug- do not have to be wrong because the right defends
gled with, Soviet Communism.15 Much ‘remains to them, even when it falsifies them in the same breath
be deciphered’16 on both left and right. The question by its tone and intent.
posed in the present essay is part of this wider ‘context In historical retrospect, the events that took place
of guilt’. between 1965 and 1969 look to this particular eye-
This context affords no immunity, no place safe witness more or less as follows. Relations between
from guilt, violence or danger, no situation devoid of the Frankfurt School and the emerging student move-
complexities and perplexities.17 ‘We are all embarked’ ment were marked by a Hegelian ‘cunning of reason’
(Pascal), all variously and differently implicated. which, whatever their theoretical familiarity with the
Today’s common wisdom has it that such implication concept, operated as usual behind everyone’s back. It
can be avoided by identifying right- and left-wing fell to Adorno, the author of a programmatic essay,
extremism as two sides of the one and the same totali- ‘Education after Auschwitz’, to play a public role
tarian coin.18 The allegedly neutral ground from which which Benjamin, in some respects his educator, had
this claim is usually made is, however, the radical never known – a thankless and barely dischargeable
middle out of – and against – which the extremes grew task for which he was barely equipped. That no life,
in the first place. thought or teaching can be right in a false world
If danger was Benjamin’s element, this was not would be painfully confirmed in his own case by a
because he wanted to ‘live dangerously’ in some neo- sequence of events which may well have shortened his
romantic way, but because he found himself caught up life. Every attempt to break out of the ‘administered
in shifting ‘constellations of danger’.19 In the general world’ of late capitalism was, so his pedagogy implied,
economy of his thought (he wrote in response to well- almost inevitably doomed; yet – and here something
meaning warnings concerning his allegedly dangerous quasi-religious came to the rescue – this could not
closeness to Brecht), a select number of relationships be all there was. A whole generation of students was
had always allowed him to ‘affirm a pole utterly unable to accept this conclusion – one of unresigned
opposed to that of my original being’. His life, like resignation – and the meagre recommendations that
his thought, moved in extremes: accrued from it: reformist politics, retreat to sublime
The breadth it thereby stakes out, its freedom to areas of resistance, notably art, hibernation in the
juxtapose things and thoughts usually considered iron cage in hopes of a better day. Under the impact
incompatible, gains its complexion only from of the Vietnam War, the sense of powerlessness and
danger – a danger that in general also appears frustration fostered by Adorno’s philosophy of history
to my friends in the guise of such ‘dangerous’ erupted into a political activism that was at once
relationships.20
theoretically top-heavy, short-sighted and false – yet
Only through exposure to danger can thinking perform productively so in many respects. The unproductively
its task. The positions this involves can even be reclin- false aspects of this situation included both the viru-
ing ones, as in the case of Proust, whose achievement lent denunciations of the student movement mounted
has its place ‘in the heart of the impossible, at the notably by the Springer press conglomerate and its
centre – and also at the point of indifference – of all own skewed ‘anti-authoritarianism’, fixated as it was
dangers’.21 on its father figures.
To return to the original question: is there really As long as right-wing demagogues made the teach-
some kind of relation between Benjamin and the ers’ theory directly responsible for their students’
RAF? The question is full of pitfalls. To answer in acts, it was clear that this was not the time to reflect
the affirmative was at the time to risk playing into in public on the real but easily misunderstood and
the hands of the hardened right-wing ideologues who misappropriated connections between the Frankfurt
tried to incriminate the Frankfurt School for the real School and the German student movement. Important
and alleged excesses of the 1968 student movement though it still may be to make up for that missed
and the terrorism of the 1970s. From such smear chance, which raises still-relevant questions about the
campaigns it is only a short step to Sippenhaft: the relation between theory and praxis in the context of
Nazi incarceration of an entire family for the misdeeds political protest, the moment for this may meanwhile
of a single member. But this danger harbours another, have passed – for in matters of timing there may
contrary one to which the Left has in the past, when indeed be, as one of the opening epigraphs to the
it still existed, been particularly vulnerable: that of present essay claims, ‘rightness in the false’. Much of
claiming a doctrinal monopoly on the truth. Positions the ’68 generation seems, with age, to have yielded to


the resignation, and accepted the analyses, for which it Carlos Marigella and others) had little to offer them in
once indicted Adorno; and today’s ‘fragile’ generation, the way of revolutionary strategy, there was nothing to
confronted as it is with problems of survival to which prevent them from wrenching a whole series of motifs
their predecessors were far less exposed, has no need from the body of his thinking and casting themselves
or time for rebellion. It struggles instead for a place in as its political executor. Nothing, that is, except its
the system that its elders had once dreamt of overturn- complexity.
ing. Between these generations lies the RAF episode In so doing, they did it violence. The RAF freely
– a desperate lunge at ‘direct action’ (the name, this, incorporated quotations from Benjamin into their own
of its French counterpart) whose excesses help explain delusional system. But they could thereby claim – or
the ‘dull thousand-voiced’ inertia that rules today: the might have claimed – to be doing far greater justice
reverse, this, of what Benjamin dreamt of in one of the to the driving impulse of his work than anything that
epigraphs to this essay. The RAF episode is a disaster the sophisticated exegeses of Benjamin philology had
from which the German Left has failed to recover. to offer. Did not his own method of citation enact a
Let us return to the narrower focus of our initial theory and practice of violence?
question. The reasons why the RAF was eager to
enlist Benjamin into its cause are not hard to find.
Even and especially parricides need father figures.
Once the other mentors of the German student
protest movement (Habermas, Marcuse and Negt
in particular) had refuted the RAF’s analysis and
methods and had been denounced as traitors to the
cause, there remained, apart from Marx himself,
only one German ‘authority figure’ with whom the
RAF could identify – one who, being dead, could
not object to what they did with him. The way they
not merely used but instrumentalized his thought
was, moreover, in complete contradiction to its
fundamental impulse. Instrumental rationality is
the defining feature of bourgeois thought and action: Only one who despairs discovers in citation the
power not to preserve but to purify, tear out of
this was as clear to Benjamin as it was to Max Weber.
context, destroy: the only power in which hope
Hence the uncompromising rejection of all means–end still lies that something might survive this time and
relations at the heart both of his theory of language place – because that hope has been hewn out of it.22
and his critique of violence – a nexus to which we
will shortly return. The RAF were themselves despairers, indeed des-
Benjamin was all the more valuable a prize for the perados, who tore Benjamin’s writings out of context
RAF, because their intellectual (ex-)fathers, notably (and in so doing, like Brecht, dropped his ‘Judaisms’).
Adorno and Marcuse, themselves appealed to his They could, moreover, have made further interesting
authority. In claiming to be his only legitimate political finds, such as his praise for the Surrealists’ ‘frenetic
heir, the RAF drove a wedge between the living and will’ to ‘escape the stage of endless discussion and
the dead. Benjamin thus represented symbolic capital come, at any price, to a decision’. 23 On the strength
and pedigree. But there were also other reasons for of their claim to be no longer discussing but doing,
their preference. However slender the RAF’s actual they practised ideological blackmail on their more
acquaintance with his thought, it cannot have escaped vulnerable sympathizers. For a variety of reasons,
them that he had staked out a bolder position vis-à-vis Benjamin could hardly have endorsed the reckless
the question of violence than their teachers had done. decisions to which they ‘at any price’ came. That he
Already the student movement had played off Benja- had felt compelled to do a certain calculated ‘violence’
min’s ‘historical materialism’ against their Frankfurt to his original way of thinking was not, in his eyes,
teachers out of frustration with their political timidity a matter of internalized blackmail but, as he put it,
and the withdrawal of ‘the critical theory’ (as it called of solidarity with the experiences of his generation.
itself) from its original positions. The RAF polarized The task was ‘not to decide once and for all, but to
the fronts still further. While Benjamin (compared decide every moment. But indeed to decide.’24 And to
with Marx, Che Guavara, Gramsci, Frantz Fanon, do so, in his own case, without reducing ‘the entire

10
contra­dictory fund’ of his thinking to a mere ‘credo’. 25 activism or right-wing realpolitik, both of which are,
‘Always radical, never consistent’, especially in the face from his standpoint, based on the debased, instrumen-
of a party line whose motto was practically the reverse tal language of everyday communication. (Benjamin’s
– this would remain Benjamin’s circuitous, tortuous, universe is equally remote from that of George Orwell,
but by no means alogical or equivocal strategy, one who, in his essay ‘Politics and the English Language’,
that had, as in chess, to be worked out anew with each holds out clean plain English prose as the antidote to
new move.26 To be of the Left also meant improvising corrupted political language.)
‘with the left hand’. By contrast, the line taken by 2.  Benjamin’s ‘very particular stance’ on the phil-
the RAF, while no less improvised, was radical in a osophy of language32 thus raises at least two questions
compulsively, suicidally consistent way. in the present context. First, whether the actions of the
In short, the RAF fatally parodied Benjamin’s deci- RAF weren’t, contrary to appearances, closer to the
sions and positions. ‘Hear me! For this precisely is who ‘bourgeois’ politics of impure, instrumental means than
I am. Do not, above all, confuse me with another!’27 to the other, communist politics of ‘pure means’;33 but,
Thus spoke the author of Ecce Homo, whose alter ego, second, what, besides the model of the pure general
Zarathustra, warns in turn against being ‘confused and strike, such a politics might conceivably look like.
confounded’ with the socialists.28 It is true that Ben- 3.  The question remains whether a not-so-magic
jamin could on occasion champion ‘falsification’ and spark might have ‘overleapt’ another gulf – the one
‘being misunderstood’.29 But such ‘new barbarism’ had between Benjamin’s words (or Word) and the RAF’s
to be done ‘the right way’.30 Which meant among other actions. Would he have seen in their leap into action
things: without falsification or misunderstanding. his own theory of the ‘leap’ (Sprung)?34 Or rather its
In a dense letter to Martin Buber written in 1916, parody?
Benjamin anticipates the move from his essay of the This brings us back to the original problem: under
same year ‘On Language in General and the Language the pressure of a ‘critical’ situation (im Ernstfall),
of Man’ (1916) to his ‘Critique of Violence’ (1920–21), did the RAF, by its actions, do justice to, or pass
to both of which he will remain faithful throughout. un­witting judgement on, Benjamin’s politics? Or was
The letter rejects all political language that aims it a mockery of such justice?
to motivate, influence and activate others; the essay
likewise rejects the prevailing (‘bourgeois’) reduction Clues to a possible encounter
of language to a debased, powerless, merely external
These questions do not in principle depend on there
‘means’ of communication directed towards equally
having been an actual relation between the RAF and
debased activities (Mittel, Mittelbarkeit). What Benja-
Benjamin. It would be enough to establish a virtual
min invokes in their place is the intensive, ‘im-mediate’
dialogue. Did, however, the elements of a real dialogue
(un-mittel-bare) action of a ‘poetic prophetic objective’
exist? In lieu of the circumstantial investigation that
language; the notion of a ‘matter-of-fact (sachlich) yet
would have been needed to decide this question, here
highly political’ style; and a ‘sphere of the wordless’
are a few shreds of documentary evidence concern-
that yet marks the ‘crystal-pure elimination of the
ing the RAF’s intermittent contact with Benjamin’s
unsayable’, one where ‘the magic spark’ is generated
thought.35
that ‘overleaps’ the distance between word and deed. 31
In the ‘Critique of Violence’ this sphere will be called 1. On 13 September 1985, Karl Dietrich Wolff, the
that of ‘pure means’ and exemplified by the ‘general then chairman of the Association of German Socialist
strike’. At this point, however, the politics implicit Students (SDS), published an ‘Open Letter’ in the
in this quasi-mystical conception of language can Tageszeitung entitled ‘Anything would be better than
barely be made out. Two aspects nevertheless begin to go on murdering this way’, written in response to
to emerge. This other politics somehow emerges from two attacks committed by the RAF the month before
the depths of language; and it is worlds apart from the which had resulted in the death of three American
– interrelated – spheres of individual psychology and soldiers. He here recalls having discussed Benjamin’s
instrumental rationality. ‘Critique of Violence’ in 1969 with Gudrun Enslin
What relevance did this seemingly esoteric train of in the Preungsheim Women’s Prison, where she had
thought have to the issue at hand? just been incarcerated following her conviction for
1.  It points to the immense gulf between Benjamin’s participation in arson attacks on two department stores
politics (‘“my” politics’, he once called them) and in Frankfurt; and adds that he has recently reread
everything we normally consider such, be it left-wing Benjamin’s essay. He then goes on:

11
With your murder of Edward Pimenthal, and the wrestle with it in solitude and, in awful cases [in
cynical bad faith of your public statement [of 25 ungeheuren Fällen], to take upon themselves the
August 1985], you have betrayed whatever once responsibility of disregarding it. This is how it was
motivated the West German terrorist movement. understood in Jewish tradition, which expressly re-
Your ‘war’ contains no image of liberation. Your jected the condemnation of killing in self-defence.37
violence has become ‘part of the problem’, not its
solution. Is it nevertheless possible even now – after The RAF was embroiled in a political logic of
this murder and this statement – to call on you to means and ends that Benjamin’s essay unequivocally
turn back? Yes, nevertheless. rejects. Its members also laid claim, however, to a
certain expanded notion of self-defence and convinced
The final paragraph of the letter reads:
themselves that they were standing at a world-historical
Betrayal of terrorism? War without an image of lib- turning point. Now according to the ‘Critique of Vio-
eration? Violence as part of the solution? Questions lence’ the imminent prospect of a ‘new world-historical
upon questions. era’ may indeed, as in antinomian messianism, allow
or require the transgression of legal rights and holy
Wolff draws the line here between arson and murder
commandments. Nor is it always possible to identify
– more precisely, the premeditated abduction and
in what ‘awful’ cases such ‘expiatory’ violence has
killing of an American soldier for the purpose of
actually taken place:
It is less possible and also less urgent
… to decide when pure violence
[reine Gewalt] became real in par-
ticular cases. For only mythic, not
divine, violence will be recognizable
with certainty as such, unless it be
in incomparable effects, because the
expiatory power of violence is not ap-
parent to men.38

If men cannot know when ‘pure’


violence has taken place, it follows
that they cannot appeal to it to justify
their actions. It is, on the other hand,
difficult to avoid the conclusion that
the violence championed by the RAF
was and is ‘recognizable with cer-
tainty’ as being not of the ‘expiatory’
but of the ‘guilt-incurring’ (verschul-
dende) kind which, far from breaking
the ancient mythic cycle, perpetuates
obtaining his uniform and ID card. it. How to break this Schuldzusammenhang through a
Violence against things, yes; violence against pure violence that, as Benjamin variously presents it, is
human beings, no. On the strength of this or similar
as powerful as it is powerless: this is the enigma with
distinctions, many former sympathizers sooner or later which the ‘Critique of Violence’ leaves us.
severed all links with the RAF. The issue to which
Benjamin’s ‘Critique of Violence’ had addressed itself 2.  In a ‘Letter to the Prisoners’ (1978), the RAF’s
was, however, a quite different one. 36 Neither side leader Andreas Baader repeatedly cites Benjamin’s
could here plausibly appeal to the precise wording Theses ‘On the Concept of History’ (hereafter the
of this very difficult text. Wolff’s sense of its spirit Theses) on
did not, however, deceive him. It could not have been the question of how we may achieve the particular,
used – or only have been used – to justify the murder historically possible form of revolutionary violence
in question. that matches the institutional use of power, this
Benjamin had there written: through the notion of a revolutionary break and
a definition of the reactionary forces at work in
[The commandment ‘Thou shalt not kill’] stands not Europe, in relation to which mass action can be
as a standard of judgement, but as a guideline for meaningful only if it absorbs the experience of the
the actions of persons or communities who have to front lines of armed struggle worldwide.39

12
In conclusion he cites Thesis XII: were honoured, if also misread and disregarded, on all
sides. It thus represented a coup – a putsch – to claim
The subject of historical knowledge is the strug-
them as one’s own. Among their quotable revolution-
gling, oppressed class itself. In Marx’s writings
it appears as the last enslaved, the avenging class ary phrases was the one about ‘blasting’ texts out of
that completes the work of liberation in the name their original context and saving certain splinters as
of generations of the beaten [Geschlagener]. This citations ‘à l’ordre du jour’.43 This clearly was, or could
consciousness, which briefly came back into its own have been, how the RAF thought it was reading them.
in the Spartacus League, was offensive to Social
But was the Communist Manifesto still, as it had been
Democracy from the outset. Within three decades it
for Benjamin from 1929 until the day of his death, the
managed to extinguish almost completely the name
of Blanqui, whose iron ring had caused the previous ‘order of the day’?44 If so, how, exactly?
century to quake. It found it congenial to cast the
3.  This letter of Baader’s, along with its quotations
working class as a redeemer of future generations.
Thereby it severed the sinews of its best strength. It from Benjamin, forms part of a rambling, more than
taught the working class to unlearn both its hatred 300-page declaration entitled Erklärung zur Sache,
and its spirit of sacrifice. For both are nourished by which Baader, Ensslin, Meinhof and Raspe read at the
the image of enslaved ancestors rather than by the court in Stuttgart–Stammheim on 13 and 14 January
ideal of liberated grandchildren.40 1976.45 This declaration of war against the world
capitalist system itself had something of a paranoid
Baader’s comments here are not merely wooden but
world-system about it.46 In the second Exposé (of
somewhat garbled:
1939) to his Arcades Project, Benjamin had noted
this point is essential, for the project of a utopia something seemingly similar, but ultimately antitheti-
held out as socialist can only be the attempt to cal, in Blanqui’s last text.47
make the revolution look as if it were attractive and
The Stammheim trial was, on both sides, a con-
thus to await its conjuncture. The revolution is real
only as the negation of the existing state of things, tinuation of the struggle by other means. As such, it
as its destruction.41 provided confirmation for Benjamin’s analysis in the
‘Critique of Violence’ of the violence exerted by the
In lingua veritas, said Victor Klemperer. It is Baader’s law (Rechtgewalt). The court refused to recognize the
language that gives his politics away. Its critique is accused as political prisoners; they in turn tried to
partly contained in a passage from Benjamin’s Sur- transform the occasion into the ‘tribunal of history’.48
realism essay (which Baader is unlikely to have read) In so doing, they cited three of Benjamin’s Theses as
which rejects the ‘as-if’ rhetoric typical of social- witnesses for the defence.
democratic party programmes, predicated as they are
on an attitude of vague, indefinite waiting for a utopian (a) Thesis XII. The phrases already cited from Baader’s
never-never land. The optimism they profess is in letter are amplified here by a few partially incomplete
fact defeatism: the despairing capitulation of socialist sentences:
thought to bourgeois modes of thought. Benjamin’s the more capital organizes itself and coordinates
analysis of social-democratic phraseology could be (its cycle) in the state, the experience that power
partly adapted to that of the RAF. What both dia- only comes from the barrel of a gun brings with it
metrical opposites have in common is a programmatic, the problem: how to develop forms of action which
self-alienated rhetoric that strenuously masks an inner accelerate this development … and political-military
action on the part of the revolutionary avant-garde,
despair. Both are equally remote from Benjamin’s
which directly intervenes in the crisis and deter-
alternative: the ‘organisation of pessimism’.42 mines its course and resolution for the offensive.49
Since Baader had no wish to be thought an intel-
lectual, one might hardly have expected him to pay The ‘political-military action’ of an urban guer-
much attention to Benjamin’s Theses, especially since, rilla force – the ‘revolutionary avant-garde’ – is here
even on a less than careful reading, they lend little conceived as the alarm or fuse which will set off
credence to his attempt to cast the RAF as the only revolution throughout Europe.
legitimate heir of a revolutionary tradition, notably that According to one of the preparatory notes for the
of Blanqui and the Spartacists, that social democracy Theses, the defining trait of the materialist historian
had repeatedly betrayed. But the idea of carrying off is a sharpened consciousness of the crisis in which
such booty must have been very tempting. The Theses, the ‘subject of history’ – namely, the ‘struggling and
Benjamin’s political testament, had meanwhile been oppressed class in its most exposed situation’ – finds
practically canonized by the German student Left and himself. 50 Already here the notion of a collective

13
subject is on the verge of becoming a wishful, exhorta- calculated to take the entire ‘inactive’ left hostage. In
tory belief, a ‘consummation devoutly to be wished’, the ‘Critique of Violence’, on the other hand, blackmail
even if the Proletarian International still existed at is opposed to ‘pure’ violence and said to perpetuate
the time. Forty years later, the RAF will believe, the existing order.
against all the evidence, that they now represent the
(b) Thesis IV:
most exposed European vanguard of this universal
subject. They derive their political-military strategy The class struggle, which a historian schooled in
from their allegedly sharpened consciousness of a Marx always has before him, is a struggle for the
situation which pits the international proletariat against crude and material things without which there are
no refined and spiritual ones. The latter are never-
global capital. The connection with the above-quoted
theless differently present in the class struggle than
note and with Benjamin’s Theses is as compelling as as a vision of the spoils that fall to the victor. They
it is deluded. Thesis XII still invoked, in Marxian, are alive in this struggle as confidence, courage,
biblical and already somewhat apocryphal fashion, the humour, cunning and perseverance and have effects
‘struggling and oppressed class’ as the ‘last enslaved, that reach far back into the past. They will forever
the avenging’ one. Meanwhile, however, the Arcades call into question each victory that fell to the rulers.
As flowers turn their heads to the sun, so, by virtue
Project had increasingly focused on a ‘dream collec-
of a secret heliotropism, the past turns toward the
tive’51 intent on not waking up. In the RAF’s court sun that is rising in the sky of history. The histori-
declaration, the class which, in Marx’s scheme of cal materialist must know about these, the most
things, had represented a theoretical but still plausible inconspicuous of changes.54
and substantive construction has become an object of
Baader introduces this quotation with the remark:
rhetorical, emptily self-fulfilling belief. Amidst the
‘Benjamin says of bourgeois values in the proletarian
endlessly abstract and inflexible phraseology of the
revolution’ and follows it with the comment: ‘Gramsci
Erklärung, one unclear turn of phrase casts a sudden
said the same thing in a few words: the proletariat
shaft of light: ‘class is merely strategy’. 52 It is thus still
represents the heritage of classical German philoso-
to be constituted. Already in George Lukács’s History
phy.’55 But it is precisely not the ‘heritage’ or ‘spoils’
and Class Consciousness (1923), class was the empiri-
of bourgeois ‘values’ that interest Benjamin here, but
cal bearer of a non-empirical, ‘imputed’ (zugerechnet)
rather a bundle of revolutionary virtues which might
consciousness. Fifty years later, such imputation cannot
have rescued the RAF from its demons – notably, his
withstand the facts without arming itself against them
equation of revolutionary consciousness with attention
– without, that is, wanting to exchange the people for
to imperceptible changes. Baader, on the other hand,
another one (as Brecht said of the rulers). According
parades the Theses as a trophy – that, perhaps, of
to another late note of Benjamin’s, every moment
‘rising’ would-be rulers.
brings with it ‘its own revolutionary opportunity’. 53
The task was, and is, to find out what the remaining (c) Thesis VIII. The court declaration cites this Thesis
post-revolutionary opportunity is. Measuring it against – to which we will return – in full and adds the fol-
reality would have meant, at least in the West European lowing garbled commentary:
context, abandoning a desperate, dogmatic belief in
to be the protagonist of the class struggle in the
armed struggle. But that, as the RAF would have been
major urban centres, from the history and defeats
the first to object, leaves us back where we are and can of the proletariat, here from its subjection to the
only be a – very unpromising – beginning. imperialist state through social democracy which is
Baader’s observations on Thesis XII in his ‘Letter in the hands of US capital and the CIA-controlled
to the Prisoners’ are pursued in the Erklärung: trade unions [sic] – the motor of the revolutionary
proletarianization of society.56
the destruction, the shattering of the capitalist
relations of production – in economic, military, cul- Of all the Theses, the eighth seems to lend itself
tural, and ideological terms. Experience tells us that most easily to a ‘terrorist’ reading. In the ninth, history
the function of utopia is a kind of arrangement with
contracts – before the terrified eyes of the Angel of
the badness of the present, a way of enduring the
History as he is borne away from Paradise by Progress
bad conscience that arises from our own inactivity.
– into a ‘single catastrophe’. In the eighth, it is polar-
This gesture, which recalls Lukács’s low remark that ized between an immemorial state of emergency and
the Frankfurt School had taken up quarters in the the unprecedented one needed to end it. The only
‘Grand Hotel Abyss’ – Adorno would in turn entitle remedy against Self-Sameness is the wholly Other:
his article on Lukács ‘Extorted Reconcilation’ – is one Entsetzen is pitted against the other.

14
The Angel and the RAF hardly constitute a well- Between the message in the bottle
matched pair. But they have at least one thing in and the Molotov cocktail: Benjamin,
common: the will to arrest the continuum of history. 57 Marcuse, Negt
‘Since he is himself exposed to fright’ (Schrecken), Herbert Marcuse’s ‘Afterword’ to a collection of essays
Benjamin writes, ‘it is not unusual for Baudelaire to published in 1965 by Suhrkamp under the title The
occasion it.’58 To quell terror by terror – to derange Critique of Violence and Other Essays constitutes
derangement: this is the classic, apotropaic answer to a plausible link between Benjamin and the RAF.
the gaze of the Medusa. The petrified stare of Ben- This small volume marked an important moment both
jamin’s Angel is of that order. It petrifies a Medusa- in the initial reception of Benjamin’s work and the
like History into an arresting wide-angled image – a emergence of the student movement. Here for the first
violent act of non-violence that, in turning the world’s time the inner connection between the early ‘Critique
violence against itself, transforms it beyond recogni- of Violence’ and the late Theses – and thereby the
tion. The RAF too wanted, in Hegelian fashion, to latter’s politically explosive character – was brought
‘enter the enemy’s strength’. Against the great infer- to the fore.
nal machine of the world they built some of their But the ‘Afterword’ also contains tacitly cautionary
own. They took the language of exploding (sprengen) words from its mentor-to-be for the emerging move-
history literally. It was no longer a matter of quotation ment – potentially the most serious addressees of these
but of bombs. texts. He writes:
To sum up, there indeed exists, over their dead
bodies, a whole complex of conflicted connections The writings of Walter Benjamin collected here
between all four elements: the Frankfurt School, Ben- originated in the historical period that began with
the outbreak and end of the German revolution
jamin, the German student movement and the RAF.
(the two dates almost coincide) and ended with the
The hard evidence for the Benjamin–RAF connection Second World War. They belong to that ‘image of
is scanty; the soft evidence – the social and intellectual the past which threatens to disappear with every
climate (Umfeld), the web of intervening figures, real present that fails to recognize itself as intended in
and rhetorical – is considerable. There is no longer it’. Words appear here, perhaps for the last time,
any need, if there ever was, to deny it. But the links which can no longer be seriously uttered without
taking on a false content or resonance: words such
are difficult, often tenuous, always delicate and easily
as ‘culture of the heart’, ‘love of peace’, ‘redemp-
misstated, misunderstood and misappropriated. The tion’, ‘happiness’, ‘spiritual things’, ‘revolutionary’.
Angel of History could, after all, hardly figure on a Their interrelations and the form their truth takes in
wanted list. This whole field of tensions, as Benjamin the present are the stuff of Benjamin’s work.61
might have called it, is not the night in which all
differences lose their contours, but that of an epoch Marcuse reads Benjamin’s texts the way they want
in which everything depended upon making critical to be read: in the ‘Now’ of their ‘recognizability’
distinctions and decisions. (Erkennbarkeit).62 The present can, they both claim,
A preceding volume documenting the historical recognize itself even, and perhaps above all, in texts
reception of Dialectic of Enlightenment was subtitled that belong to an irretrievable past. It can do so,
From the Message in the Bottle to the Molotov Cock- however, only from a – by no means safe – distance
tail: 1944–1975. This formula neatly summarizes the which leaves none of their content unchanged. In the
problematic relation of word and deed at issue here. present case, that content is the common cause; and
Published in Amsterdam in 1947 and widely circu- Marcuse, who had decades before taken sides with the
lated in ‘auratic’ pirate editions during the 1960s, short-lived German Revolution, here ventures to ask
Dialectic of Enlightenment59 has been described as a whether that cause can still be called the ‘revolution-
‘time bomb’ that lay dormant for twenty years.60 By ary’ one. Benjamin’s critique of social democracy is,
casting their ‘philosophical fragments’ as a ‘message he writes, not primarily that of a party that has come
in a bottle’, Adorno and Horkheimer had, however, to be an underpinning of the status quo, but ‘the (not
effectively defused the other ‘bomb’ wrapped up in yet despairing) memory of the truth and actuality of
theirs: Benjamin’s Theses. Both the SDS and the RAF revolution as a historical necessity’.63 From the further
aimed, in very different ways, to reactivate the bomb distance of our present, Marcuse’s parenthesis – ‘(not
that had been consigned to the philosophers’ bottle. yet despairing)’ – prompts the question whether the
It was here that the crucial distinctions/decisions had RAF wasn’t desperately clinging to a version of the
to be made. common cause whose hollowness it was both putting

15
to the test and unwilling or unable to concede.64 ‘The plausibly be suggested that on the question of violence
angry man’, Benjamin said of Baudelaire, ‘“will not he would have been close to the eminently militant and
listen”.’65 What Benjamin had called the ‘revolutionary eminently reasonable line argued by such elder states-
chance’ inherent in every moment might, in short, men of the student movement as Marcuse and Negt in
now best survive in a certain abandonment of ‘the’ a series of fraught dialogues with Horkheimer, Adorno,
revolution. Habermas, Dutschke, Krahl and others.72 There were
Benjamin’s Theses, Marcuse goes on, other ways of reading Benjamin’s Theses ‘in earnest’
were written at the outbreak of the Second World than by appealing to the ‘language of the gun barrel’73.
War, at a time when Fascism was triumphing. The That a ‘certain circumspection and caution’ is called
present no longer belongs to the same historical for, especially in matters of ‘destruction’, if historical
period: it has put an end to the age when the open materialism is to prove a ‘match for all comers’,74 was
or covert struggle against Fascism still seemed
not something that the RAF was capable of hearing.
capable of exploding the continuum of history.
Its ultra-radicalism stood ‘to the left of the possible’.75
This continuum has once again closed over. Real
developments thus stand as a bloody testament to Our present stands far to its right.
Benjamin’s truths.66 Translated by Nick Walker and Irving Wolhfarth
Weitermachen (Keep on): so reads the inscription
Notes
on Marcuse’s Berlin grave. The struggle goes on (as
1. Walter Benjamin, Gesammelte Schriften (henceforth
Rudi Dutschke, a student leader opposed to the RAF, GS), ed. Rolf Tiedemann and Hermann Schweppen-
called out at the graveside of Holger Meins, an RAF häuser, Suhrkamp Verlag, Frankfurt am Main, 1972–89,
member who died in prison after a hunger strike). But IV, 1, p. 122; ‘Fire Alarm’, in One Way Street, in Wal-
ter Benjamin, Selected Writings (henceforth SW), ed.
it cannot do so, according to Marcuse, in its past guise.
Michael W. Jennings, Harvard University Press, Cam-
The terms which rang false in his ear already in 1965 bridge MA, 1999, vol. 1, p. 470. In what follows, extant
included not merely ‘redemption’ and ‘culture of the English translations are often amended.
heart’, but also ‘Fascism’, ‘the class struggle’, and so 2. GS, II, 1, pp. 305–6; ‘Surrealism: The Last Snapshot
of the European Intelligentsia’, in SW, vol. 2, pp.
on – in short, the typical later phraseology of large 214–15.
sections of the SDS and of the entire RAF.67 And yet, 3. GS, IV, 1, pp. 434–5.
Marcuse argues, the struggle for which Benjamin’s 4. GS I, 2, p. 660; ‘Central Park’, trans. Lloyd Spencer
name stands draws its ‘strength’ and ‘weakness’ from with Mark Harrington, New German Critique 34, Winter
1985, p. 34.
the fact that he was unable to ‘compromise the concept 5. GS, 1, p. 1241.
of revolution – even at a time when compromises still 6. GS, II, 1, p. 201; ‘Critique of Violence’, in SW, vol. 1,
seemed to further its cause’.68 pp. 250–51.
7. Walter Benjamin, Gesammelte Briefe (henceforth GB),
Marcuse expounds the uncompromising argument
ed. Christoph Gödde and Henri Lonitz, Suhrkamp Ver-
of the ‘Critique of Violence’ in a few broad strokes,69 lag, Frankfurt am Main, 1995–2000, IV, p. 100, letter to
sides with it, raises the unavoidable question of how Gershom Scholem of 1 June 1932; English translation:
an interruption of the existing order can be effected The Correspondence of Walter Benjamin 1910–1940,
trans. R. and E.M. Jacobson, University of Chicago
when the class struggle is ‘not acute’70 and concludes, Press, Chicago, 1994, p. 394. The materials of the Ar-
in suddenly Adorno-like fashion, by appealing to great cades Project contain the following jotting: ‘There is a
art as the repository of homeless radical impulses. In draft where Caesar, rather than Zarathustra, appears as
contrast to his long-standing Frankfurt associates, the bearer of Nietzsche’s doctrine. … This is of some
importance. It underscores the fact that Nietzsche sensed
however, Marcuse was ready and willing to become something of the complicity of his own doctrine with
publicly involved in the ensuing turbulence.71 Combin- imperialism’ (GS, V, 1, p. 175).
ing political radicality, youthful anger, sane judgement 8. ‘For ends that for one situation are just, universally
recognisable and universally valid, are so for no other
and long experience, he openly supported the ‘Extra-
situation, no matter how similar it may be in other re-
parliamentary Opposition’ (APO), clearly distinguish- spects’ (GS, II, 1, p. 196; ‘Critique of Violence’, in SW,
ing its theory and praxis of counter-violence from that vol. 1, pp. 247–8).
of the RAF and remaining faithful to the revolutionary 9. GS, II, 1, p. 175; ‘Fate and Character’, in SW, vol. 1, p.
204.
idea without overestimating its existing chances of 10. GB, IV, pp. 24–5, letter to Gershom Scholem of 17
realization. April 1931; The Correspondence of Walter Benjamin,
It is pointless to speculate about the political posi- p. 385.
tions that Benjamin might have taken if he had lived 11. Cf. Derrida’s contribution to the controversy provoked
by certain disturbing remarks in the wartime writings of
to see the 1960s and 1970s and could have intervened the young Paul de Man, Mémoires: For Paul de Man,
in, among other things, his own reception. But it may trans. C. Lindsay, J. Culler and E. Cadava, Columbia

16
University Press, New York, 1986. 24. Benjamin’s letter to Adorno of 10 November 1938,
12. GS, II, 1, p. 202; ‘Critique of Violence’, in SW, vol. 1, Adorno–Benjamin Briefwechsel 1928–1940, ed. Henri
p. 251. Lonitz, Suhrkamp Verlag, Frankfurt am Main; Walter
13. Friedrich Nietzsche, Kritische Gesamtausgabe (hence- Benjamin, Theodor W. Adorno, The Complete Corre-
forth KG), ed. Giorgio Colli and Mazzino Montinari, De spondence 1928–1940, trans. Nicholas Walker, Har-
Gruyter, Berlin, 1969, VI, 3, p. 363; Ecce Homo, trans. vard University Press, Cambridge MA, 1999, p. 284.
A.M. Ludovici, Dover, New York, 2004, ‘Why I Am a Cf. Benjamin’s response in his letter of 9 December
Fatality’, p. 131. 1938 (Briefwechsel, p. 379; The Complete Correspond-
14. George Orwell’s dismissal of intellectuals who, for lack ence, pp. 291f.). This exchange epitomizes their different
of any other outlet, indulge in violent thought and lan- relations to the question of violence.
guage may be countered by Georges Bataille’s claim 25. GB, IV, p. 408, letter to Gershom Scholem of 6 May
(on behalf of the Marquis de Sade) that the worst vio- 1934; The Correspondence of Walter Benjamin, p.
lence usually shelters behind a facade of bureaucratic 439.
euphemism. 26. GB, III, p. 159, letter to Marcel Brion of 2 September
15. The differences are nonetheless decisive. Can one le- 1935. If, as Jürgen Habermas claims, Benjamin’s thought
gitimately play off Brecht’s and Benjamin’s relations to should not be confronted with ‘facile demands for con-
communism against Heidegger’s to Nazism by claiming, sistency’, this is because, in and through all its leaps and
as Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe does, that they were all tangents, it has, contrary to that claim, another, more
‘taken in’ (floués)? Cf. La fiction du politique, Bour- radical consistency. Cf. Zur Aktualität Walter Benjamins,
geois, Paris, 1987, p. 43; Heidegger, Art and Politics, ed. Siegfried Unseld, Suhrkamp Verlag, Frankfurt am
trans. Chris Turner, Blackwell, Oxford 1990, pp. 61f. Main 1972, p. 176; J. Habermas, ‘Consciousness-Raising
16. Cf. the title, taken from Benjamin, of the collection of or Rescuing Critique’, in On Walter Benjamin, ed. Gary
critical essays edited by Burkhardt Lindner, ‘Links hatte Smith, MIT Press, Cambridge MA, 1988, p. 92.
noch alles sich zu enträtseln’ … Walter Benjamin im 27. Friedrich Nietzsche, Ecce Homo, ‘Foreword’ I, KG, VI,
Kontext, Syndikat, Frankfurt am Main, 1978. 3, p. 255, also pp. 363–4; Ecce Homo, trans. Duncan
17. ’Have not all railings and bridges fallen into the water?’, Large, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2007, pp. 3f.
asks Zarathustra. Friedrich Nietzsche, Also sprach and 88f.
Zarathustra, III, ‘Von alten und neuen Tafeln’, KG, VI, 28. ‘There are those who preach my doctrine of life, and
1, p. 248; Thus Spake Zarathustra, Part III, ‘On Old are at the same time preachers of equality, and tarantu-
and New Tablets’, section 8, trans. Walter Kaufmann, las’. KG, VI, 1, p. 125; Thus Spake Zarathustra, trans.
Penguin, New York, 1966. Hannah Arendt – the first to Thomas Common, New York 1999, Part II, ch. XXIX,
dare, rightly or wrongly, to link Heidegger and Benjamin p. 66.
– similarly called for a ‘thinking without railings’, H. 29. Cf. GS, II, 1, p. 297 (‘Surrealism’, in SW, vol. 2, p. 208);
Arendt, Denken ohne Geländer, Piper, Stuttgart, 2005. GS, II, 2, p. 621 (‘Dream Kitsch’, in SW, vol. 2, p. 4);
18. Cf. Norbert Bolz, Auszug aus der entzauberten Welt. GS, IV, 1, p. 397 (‘The Destructive Character’, in SW,
Philosophischer Extremismus zwischen den Weltkriegen, vol. 1, p. 542).
Wilhelm Fink Verlag, Munich, 1989. 30. GS, II, 1, pp. 217–19; ‘Experience and Poverty’, in SW,
19. Cf. GS, I, 3, p. 1242 (notes and materials for ‘On the vol. 2, pp. 732 and 735.
Concept of History’). 31. GB I, 325–7, letter to Martin Buber of 17 July 1916;
20. Walter Benjamin, Gretel Adorno. Briefwechsel 1930– The Correspondence of Walter Benjamin, p. 80.
1940, ed. Christoph Gödde and Henri Lonitz, Suhrkamp 32. A certain form of ‘mediation, however fraught and prob-
Verlag, Frankfurt am Main, 2005, p. 156. lematic’, he claims, links his philosophy of language ‘to
21. GS, II, 1, p. 311; ‘On the Image of Proust’, in SW, vol. dialectical materialism …, but none whatsoever to the
2, p. 237. bloated character of bourgeois knowledge’ (GB, IV, p.
22. GS, II, 1, p. 365; ‘Karl Kraus’, in SW, vol. 2, p. 455. 18, letter to Max Rychner of 7 March 1931).
23. GS II, 1, p. 295; ‘Surrealism’, in SW, vol. 1, p. 207. 33. Given its situation as a would-be urban guerrilla move-
Benjamin is thinking here – in 1929 – of the surrealists’ ment bereft of any support from the general population,
‘highly exposed position’ between ‘anarchistic Fronde including its left-leaning segments, the RAF was reduced
and revolutionary discipline’. André Breton aimed to to endless strategies of self-preservation and bogged
break with ‘a praxis that presents the public with the down in what Benjamin’s early essay on language had
literary precipitate of a certain form of existence while termed Mittelbarkeit – an endless means–ends nexus that
withholding that existence itself. To put it in a nutshell: was the fallen antithesis of all divinely inspired language
The realm of literature was exploded (gesprengt) from and revolutionary action. For a discussion of its mem-
within’ (GS, II, 1, 295–96; ‘Surrealism’, in SW, vol. 1, bers’ ‘autistic’ fixation on their own activities and the
pp. 207–8). Like Nietzsche’s ‘dynamite’, such explosive logic of exchange underlying the release of prisoners,
is clearly metaphorical; yet it partakes, in however sub- see Wolfgang Kraushaar, ‘Die Schleyer-Entführung: 44
limated a way, of the non-metaphorical kind; otherwise Tage ohne Opposition’, in Revolte und Reflexion. Poli-
it would be a merely metaphorical ‘as-if’. The leap from tische Aufsätze 1976–87, Frankfurt am Main, 1990, pp.
literature to life here remains a literary act this side 81–3. ‘Entering into the adversary’s strength’ – Hegel’s
of the border; but what this act invokes is, precisely, postulate for effective combat – thus meant – or resulted
the leap beyond that border – the drawing of practical in – assuming the features of the ‘monster’ (p. 83) that
consequences from a verbal commitment to the revolu- the would-be liberators were fighting. But how avoid this
tion. True, the anarchists’ machines infernales referred dilemma under modern conditions and in such unequal
to above are all literary texts. But they are not merely combat? Beyond the particular case of the RAF, this vast
literary, inasmuch as the ‘real’ ones are all mediated problem remains. It confronts apologists of the status
through and through by language. quo with the question whether even legitimate violence

17
may not be monstrous (in which case, distinctions be- 50. GS, I, 3, p. 1243 (notes and materials for ‘On the Con-
tween forms of monstrosity become unavoidable). And cept of History’).
it asks Benjamin how ‘pure’ violence can exist (or from 51. GS, V, I, pp. 493ff. In the second 1939 outline of the
where it can intervene) in the enveloping ‘guilt nexus’ Arcades Project, Benjamin no longer refers, as he had in
he describes. Doctrines of racial, ideological and other the first 1935 one, to a ‘historical awakening’ (GS, V, I,
purity have spawned the impurest violence (genocide, p. 59; Paris, Capital of the 19th Century, 1935 Exposé,
ethnic cleansing etc.). Purity is a much-contaminated, p. 13).
reactive notion. This is, however, no reason to lump all 52. Typescript: ‘with reference to I (2), 2.’
doctrines of purity together. The motives for doing so 53. GS, I, 3, p. 1231 (notes and materials for ‘On the Con-
are themselves ‘impure’. cept of History’).
34. Cf., among other relevant places, GS, I, 2, p. 701; ‘On 54. GS, I, 2, p. 694–5; ‘On the Concept of History’, Thesis
the Concept of History’, Thesis XIV, in SW, vol. 4, p. IV, in SW, vol. 4, p. 390.
395. 55. Typescript 4.
35. The following material was made available to the author 56. Typescript 2, day 7.
by Wolfgang Kraushaar. 57. GS, I, 2, p. 667 (‘Central Park’, in New German Cri-
36. Between private individuals, Benjamin observes, count- tique 34, 1985, p. 39); GS, I, 2, pp. 702 and 703 (‘On
less cases exist in which conflicts find non-violent solu- the Concept of History’, Theses XVI and XVII, in SW,
tions. These are, however, usually of a ‘mediate’, objec- vol. 4, pp. 396–7).
tive nature ‘by way of things’ (GS, II, 1, p. 191; ‘Critique 58. GS, I, 2, p. 616; ‘On Some Motifs in Baudelaire’, in
of Violence’, in SW, vol. 1, p. 244). Walter Benjamin, Charles Baudelaire, trans. H. Zohn,
37. GS, II, 1, pp. 200–201; ‘Critique of Violence’, in SW, Verso, London, 1997, p. 117.
vol. 1, p. 250. 59. ‘If [this message] can be addressed to anyone today, it
38. GS, II, 1, p. 202–3; ‘Critique of Violence’, in SW, vol. is neither the so-called masses nor the individual, who
1, p. 252. is powerless, but rather an imaginary witness to whom
39. Cited from Texte der raf, Stockholm 1977, pp. 177– we bequeath it so that it does not entirely go under with
207; partially reproduced in ‘Dokumente zur Rezeptions­ us’. Max Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno, Dialektik
geschichte Andreas Baaders’, Schattenlinien 6–7, Berlin der Aufklärung, Suhrkamp Verlag, Frankfurt am Main
1993, pp. 83ff.; and Reinhard Markner, ‘Walter Benjamin 1969, p. 273; Dialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical
nach der Moderne. Etwas zur Frage der Aktualität an- Fragments, trans. E. Jephcott, Stanford University Press,
gesichts der Rezeption seit 1983’, Schattenlinien 8–9, Stanford, 2002, p. 213. At the time, Marcuse had ob-
Berlin 1994. The text of the ‘Declaration to the Court’ jected to the image of a ‘message in the bottle’ (in a
(Erklärung zur Sache), which has never been published letter to Horkheimer of 11 November 1941; cited in
in its entirety, is housed in the archives of the Hamburg Willem van Reijen and Gunzelin Schmitt Noerr, eds,
Institute for Social Research. In the following discussion Vierzig Jahre Flaschenpost: ‘Dialektik der Aufklärung’
it is cited as ‘Typescript’. 1947–87, Fischer Verlag, Frankfurt am Main, 1987, pp.
40. GS, I, 2, p. 700; ‘On the Concept of History’, Thesis 8–9).
XII, in SW, vol. 4, p. 394. The last sentence tells us 60. Ibid., p. 7.
precisely where the ‘image of liberation’ mentioned in 61. Walter Benjamin, Zur Kritik der Gewalt und andere
Wolff’s letter is to be looked for. Aufsätze, Suhrkamp Verlag, Frankfurt am Main 1965,
41. Typescript, p. 14. p. 99 (henceforth Zur Kritik). Benjamin suspects even
42. GS, II, 1, pp. 308–9; ‘Surrealism’, in SW, vol. 2, pp. the ‘recent German revolution‘ of having amounted to
216–17. Benjamin proceeds to contrast (dialectical) a ‘political’ general strike – the type in which, accord-
‘image’ with (social-democratic) ‘metaphor’, to insist ing to Georges Sorel, ‘the masses change their masters’
on the necessity of ‘expelling moral metaphor from – rather than a ‘proletarian’ one directed against the
politics’, and to equate the revolution with a process of masters (GS, II, 1, p. 194; ‘Critique of Violence’, in SW,
‘dialectical destruction’. vol. 1, p. 246). The latter exercises ‘pure’, the former
43. GS, I, 2, pp. 694 and 703; ‘On the Concept of History’, ‘impure’ violence. According to the Theses, such pure
Theses III and XVII, in SW, vol. 4, pp. 390 and 396. revolutionary consciousness briefly re-emerged with the
44. In this connection, cf. the concluding remarks of the Spartacus League (GS, I, 2, p. 700; ‘On the Concept of
essay on ‘Surrealism’ (GS, II, 1, p. 310; SW, vol. 2, pp. History’, Thesis XII, in SW, vol. 4, p. 394). The latter
217–18). would thus have represented the ‘struggling, oppressed
45. See note 39 above. class in its most exposed situation’ (GS, I, 3, p. 1243,
46. Freud pointed to the affinity between paranoid and philo- notes and materials for ‘On the Concept of History’).
sophical systems. How both might be disentangled is a 62. GS, I, 3, p. 1237 (notes and materials for ‘On the Con-
question also raised by a text of a quite different calibre cept of History’).
that belonged to the theoretical underpinnings of the 63. Zur Kritik, p. 101.
German student Left, namely Dialectic of Enlighten- 64. In two late essays Adorno explicitly links student ‘ac-
ment. Anti-systematic though they are, these ‘philo- tionism’ to ‘desperation’. ‘Where experience is blocked,
sophical fragments’ constitute a closed system of their or altogether absent, praxis is damaged and therefore
own. longed for, distorted, desperately overvalued’ (T.W.
47. GS, V, 1, pp. 75–7; Paris, Capital of the 19th Century, Adorno, Gesammelte Schriften, ed. Rolf Tiedemann,
1939 Exposé, in The Arcades Project, trans, H. Eiland Suhrkamp Verlag, Frankfurt am Main, 1977, vol. 10.2,
and K. McLaughlin, Harvard University Press, Cam- p. 760; Marginalia to Theory and Praxis, in Critical
bridge MA, 2002, pp. 25–6. Models, trans. H. Pickford, p. 260). ‘Desperation which,
48. Cf. GS, V, I, p. 459 (notes and materials on Baudelaire). finding the exits blocked, blindly leaps into praxis joins
49. Typescript, day I, p. 14. forces with catastrophe – with the purest of intentions’

18
(Gesammelte Schriften, vol. 10.2, p. 766; Critical Mod- reservations about Benjamin’s political sympathies. But
els, p. 265). ‘People who are locked in desperately want he never comes to grips with the ‘Critique of Violence’,
to get out’ (Gesammelte Schriften, vol. 10.2, p. 796; even though it belongs to the early theological phase of
‘Resignation’, in Critical Models, p. 291). Adorno, who Benjamin’s thinking, in which, in their discussion of the
himself once said with a smile ‘Open Sesame: I want to Arcades Project, Adorno holds out against what he takes
get out’, did not reflect, at least in print, on the possibil- to be Benjamin’s dangerously Brechtian, insufficiently
ity that what he called the ‘actionism’ of the students dialectical turn to Marxism.
might in some measure be an unintended consequence 72. In this connection, cf. the following letters by Marcuse:
of his own teaching and thus a bitter instance of his ‘Letter to Max Horkheimer’ (17 June 1967); ‘The prob-
dictum: ‘However one does it, one does it wrong.’ lem of violence in the context of political opposition’
65. GS, I, 2, p. 642; ‘Some Motifs in Baudelaire’ Section (13 July 1967), and its continuation in ‘This terror is
X, p. 143. In the penultimate strophe of the fourth counter-revolutionary’ (11 June 1972); ‘The predica-
‘Spleen’ poem in Baudelaire’s Les Fleurs du mal, howl- ment of the revolutionary spirit’ (15 June 1972); ‘Murder
ing church bells furiously leap at the sky, followed in cannot be a weapon of politics’ (16 September 1977);
the final strophe by a slow, silent funeral procession in ‘I have never preached terrorism’ (19 July 1978). Cf.
which the ‘sable banner’ of ‘terrifying, despotic Fear’ also the following letters by Oskar Negt: ‘Politics and
– which thus has the same colour as the flag of anarchy protest’ (28 October 1967); ‘Politics and violence. On
– is planted on the defeated subject’s skull. Charles the assassination of Rudi Dutschke’ (18 April 1967);
Baudelaire, Œuvres Complètes (henceforth OC), ed. Y.- Negt’s ‘Introduction’ to ‘The Left Responds to Jürgen
G. le Dantec, Gallimard, Paris, 1968, p. 71. Benjamin Habermas’ (1968); ‘The strategy of answering violence
links the poem to the coup d’état of Napoleon III and with violence’ (26 April 1968); ‘Student protest – liber-
Blanqui’s surrender to the stellar system in L’Eternité alism – “Left Fascism”’ (June 1968); ‘On the Baader–
par les astres (GS I, 3, p. 1139 [notes and materials Meinhof case’ (October 1971); ‘Socialist politics and
for Charles Baudelaire]). terrorism’. All reprinted in: Frankfurter Schule II, pp.
66. Zur Kritik, pp. 106–7. 261–3, 272–8, 297–303, 356–63, 366–7, 406–7, 417–25,
67. See, by contrast, Marcuse’s letter to Horkheimer of 17 745–7, 752–7, 758–61, 806–7, 828–31. If these careful
June 1967: ‘Allow me to express my view in the most demarcations of the problem have lost much of their
extreme manner possible: I see today’s America as the relevance for today, this is also because today has lost
historical heir of Fascism.’ Frankfurter Schule und much of its relevance for them. It is in part because the
Studenten­bewegung (henceforth Frankfurter Schule), ed. Left has meanwhile lost so much ground that present-day
Wolfgang Kraushaar, Rogner and Bernhard, Hamburg discussion of the problem of violence has fallen behind
1998, II, p. 262. the level reached in the 1960s and 1970s.
68. Zur Kritik, p. 101. 73. GB, V, 248, letter to Adorno of 27 February 1936; The
69. ‘The violence which is the object of Benjamin’s critique Complete Correspondence, p. 126.
is not the one generally criticized, especially when those 74. GS, I, p. 693; ‘On the Concept of History’, Thesis I,
below use (or attempt to use) it against those above. This in SW, vol. 4, p. 389. Some sympathizers of the RAF,
latter violence is precisely the one that …Benjamin calls however, voiced doubts about its theoretical position. In
“pure” violence. … The violence criticised by Benjamin 1967 there appeared a pirate edition of Benjamin’s The-
is that of the existing order, which has acquired a mo- ses, along with two essays by Adorno, never officially
nopoly of legality, truth and law, whose violent character published in his lifetime, which argued the current im-
has disappeared, only to reappear all more terrifyingly possibility of revolutionary praxis (‘Reflections on the
in so-called ‘states of emergency’ (which de facto are Theory of Class’ and ‘Theses on the Concept of Need’,
no such thing). For the oppressed, such a state of emer- in T.W. Adorno and W. Benjamin, Integration und Des-
gency is the rule; the task, however, is to bring about that integration, Kritik Verlag, Hanover, 1976; reprinted in:
“actual state of emergency” which can explode the his- A. Götz von Olenhausen, ‘Der Weg vom Manuskript
torical continuum of violence’ (Zur Kritik, pp. 99–100). zum gedruckten Text ist länger, als er bisher je gewesen
Roughly accurate though this summary of Benjamin’s ist’. Walter Benjamin im Raubdruck 1969 bis 1996,
argument is, it ignores its theological underpinnings and Lengwil am Bodensee 1997, pp. 96ff. There is no refer-
transforms his critique of violence into a militant ver- ence here to Adorno’s two published responses to the
sion of Frankfurt ‘critical theory’: ‘The truth of critical student movement: Marginalia to Theory and Praxis
theory has seldom been expressed in such exemplary and Resignation). The editor’s ‘Foreword’, signed by
form.’ Ibid., p. 104. ‘J. Peachum’, explains the purpose of this unauthor-
70. Marcuse responds to this problem at the end of One- ized edition. The West German Left is, it claims, cur-
Dimensional Man (Beacon Press, Boston MA, 1964, p. rently retreating into a ‘re-privatization’ of politics’,
257), where he interprets the ‘Great Refusal’ of unarmed is considering whether to establish a new party and is
marginal groups as a possible ‘chance’ for radical change thereby acting ‘as if nothing at all had happened’. Its
– this in the spirit of Benjamin’s claim: ‘It is only for fear of contact with the RAF and other armed groups
the sake of those without hope that hope is given to us’ has led to ‘political impotence and intellectual sterility’.
(cited in Zur Kritik, p. 257). Theoretical clarification of the situation is needed. It is
71. For his concrete differences with Adorno on the question provided by the theoretical contributions of the student
of violence, cf. Marcuse’s letter to Adorno of 5 April leader Hans Jürgen Krahl, Benjamin’s ‘indispensable’
1969 and Adorno’s reply of 5 May 1969 (Frankfurter reflections on the philosophy of history, and Adorno’s
Schule, II, pp. 601–2 and 624–5). The correspondence ‘uninhibited’ adoption of key concepts of Marxist
between Marcuse, Adorno and Horkheimer in the 1960s theory.
takes up, in certain respects, Adorno’s exchange of let- 75. GS, III, p. 281; ‘Left-wing Melancholy’, in SW, vol. 2,
ters with Benjamin in the 1930s. There Adorno voices p. 425.

19
 centre for research in modern european philosophyi

LONDON’S CENTRE FOR POSTGRADUATE


STUDY IN CONTINENTAL PHILOSOPHY

MA Modern European Philosophy


Study the great texts of nineteenth- and twentieth-century European philosophy:
Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit, Nietzsche’s Will to Power,
Heidegger’s Being and Time, Sartre’s Critique of Dialectical Reason

MA Philosophy and Contemporary


Critical Theory
Combine study of the two main traditions
of Critical Theory – the Frankfurt School and
French anti-humanism – with a focus on more
recent work: Agamben, Badiou, Deleuze &
Guattari, and Negri

MA Aesthetics and Art Theory


Combine study of philosophical
aesthetics in the European tradition
with an orientation towards
contemporary art theory: Kant Autumn/Winter 2008/9
and the Aesthetic Tradition, Post-
Kantian Aesthetics, Modernism Mansion, Trent Park Campus
and Contemporary Art Theory, 30 October Animal Presence
Commodification and Subjectivation Andrew Benjamin (Monash
University)
APPLY NOW FOR 2009–10 20 November From the State as ‘Metaphysical
Event’ to Hegemony as
Research Degrees ‘Philosophical Fact’
MA by research 30,000-word thesis Peter Thomas (University of
MPhil 40,000-word thesis Amsterdam/Jan van Eyck
PhD 80,000-word thesis Academie)
11 December What is the Speculative Subject?
Staff Dider Debaise (Max Planck
Professor Éric Alliez Institute, Berlin)
Professor Peter Hallward Conference Undoing the Aesthetic Image
Dr Mark Kelly
Tate Britain, London SW1P 4RG
Dr Christian Kerslake
Professor Peter Osborne 24 January Éric Alliez (CRMEP)
Dr Stella Sandford Patricia Falguières (History,
EHESS, Paris)
Georges Didi-Huberman
(Art History, EHESS, Paris)
Jacques Rancière
(Emeritus, Philosophy, University
of Paris–VIII)

www.mdx.ac.uk/www/crmep

20
Flux and flurry
Stillness and hypermovement in animated
worlds

Esther Leslie

Animation, as any Wikipedia reader knows, is ‘the time is stretched out, presenting us not so much with
optical illusion of movement’, whether achieved an example of the optical illusion of movement of an
through photographing drawings, moving clay models object but rather with the perception of movement
and recording the tweaks frame by frame, drawing itself in motion.
directly on film or devising models digitally. But the A definition of animation, found in the relays
definition is a weak one, or only a starting point. Not between movement and stillness, is outlined here, per-
only animation but all film/video proceeds by generat- versely perhaps, by exploring some scenes or sites that
ing an ‘optical illusion of movement’. A recording are more or even much less conventionally conceivable
device samples fragments of the world, repeatedly as animation. At first glance these are motionless sites,
biting a moment of time from its flow. Later the result- but, on closer examination, they prove to be sites of
ing still frames of a film or video strip are cranked movement, in various ways. The characterization of
or streamed into motion, generating a second-order animation pursued is different to the commonsensical.
re-creation of the motion of which they had once been It is best described as an insistence that animation’s
part. Furthermore, to define animation as ‘the optical special contribution to cinematic culture is not the illu-
illusion of movement’ makes it impossible to think of sion of movement but rather, chiastically, and at least
animated stillness – perhaps rightly so. But, in one way potentially, the movement of illusion, a displacement
or another, there is much stillness in animation: from that brings to light or focuses the given illusion even to
the aforementioned individual cels or frames at ani- the point of dispelling it. It does this through the con-
mation’s root to the static backgrounds that accompany densation, within and between animated elements, of
a scene’s main action; from production storyboards to a number of movements, a series of passages between
those moments, occasioned by the narrative or gag, different states and forces, conditions and temporali-
when everything has to stop. This must be qualified: ties. A shorthand version of my definition is animation
it is true only inasmuch as stillness can ever be said is ‘different nature’ or animation is ‘non-indifferent
to exist and is not itself something of an illusion. It nature’. Animation is ‘different nature’ (Benjamin1)
is, after all, a question of scale whether the movement because it is different to ours, but not distinct from
that inhabits all things is perceived and, in addition, the it. Animation reflects on nature, but shatters its laws
perceiving eye itself is always in movement. Moreover, in its physics-defying recombinations of space, time
what animation or any cinematic production presents and matter. Animation proposes ‘small worlds’, each
is not simply an illusion of movement. It is move- one bound by the newly and specifically devised laws
ment itself: movement of the image data through the of the animator. Animation is ‘non-indifferent nature’
projecting mechanism, which produces movement on (Eisenstein2), because it appeals to us, invites us into
the screen. There is, indeed, an animation technique its particular small world. Its appeal is mediated via
that explores vision’s contingency and the relativity of technology and is a shuttle between the image world of
stillness and movement through the extreme extension a new or second nature and us, addressed too as nature.
of time. Bullet time or time slice or view morphing We are invited in for the duration of the show. This
stills the scene or object within the flow of the film image world or microcosm is, in turn, appropriated
or moves it only at extreme slowness, while our view – or, better, inhabited – by its viewers. Animation’s
of it changes constantly, as the visions of multiple small and dialectical image worlds propose certain
cameras are sequenced. Thereby a frozen moment of stances on the part of viewers, encouraging them to

Radical Philosophy 152 (November/December 20 08) 21


be at least minimally alert to the ways of the image ment, life and lifelessness, identity and non-identity,
world unrolling before them, especially as it compares singularity and universality, fetishism and its criticism
to the world in which they sit. They are aware too, at and a basic repetition or replication that paradoxically
some level, of the differences within the image world yields heterogeneity. These forces are at work vari-
– that is to say, the gaps between the cels or poses. ously: perhaps in the image or between images or in
These gaps, key to animation’s structure, enable the the storyline or the technology or at the moment of
excessive or implausible movements that characterize projection and being seen.
animation and mark it as seemingly unlimited and To explore this further the present enquiry takes in
infinitely potential. This animated nature might assume some frozen sites – ostensibly the least animated thing
any form and usually does in its presentation of hybrids imaginable, for that which is frozen is precisely immo-
of human and animal, coagulations of machineries and bilized, though this no more so than the still image
bodies, scenarios in which natural law is overturned that is the cell of animation. After a spell among the
or maliciously asserted. Animation presents a dynamic frozen, some melting into air follows. First the focus
image world in which – in much the same way as is on a stilled figure, allowing us to arrest our attentive
Sergei Eisenstein, Disney fan, describes the dialecti- eye on an entity that quite literally crystallizes numer-
cal cinema he hoped to develop as his contribution ous dialectical tensions, such as might also be found
to post-revolutionary culture – there is manifested a lurking in the obviously mobile animated image.
condensation of tensions that appeals, or may appeal,
in a particular, cognitive way to its viewers. This Microphotography of snow crystals
is because, in propelling the viewer from image to On 15 January 1885 Wilson Bentley of Vermont,
thought, from percept to concept, it models the motion USA, became the first person to photograph a single
of thinking itself – such that viewers are invited to snow crystal. Having built and adapted a bellows
complete the film through an act of appropriation of camera and a microscope and taking advantage of
its new nature. the icy winters in North America, Bentley captured
To specify, animation is, characteristically, whatever snowflakes, whisked them inside a cold hut, isolated
its form, genre, technique, enlivened, which is not to several beautiful crystals on a microscope slide and
say that it is lively only because it displays movement. quickly photographed each one singly. The procedure
Rather, more specifically, it is made lively by the was impelled by a scientific desire to understand, by
inherent movement of the dynamic contradictions that bringing into view, the snow crystal. That it produced
inhabit it and that are projected in its small image something of aesthetic beauty was a happy side effect
worlds. Animation’s small image worlds are generated that Bentley noted and exploited in publications. He
– structurally, formally, content-wise – through the went on to produce and reproduce many hundreds of
work of oppositional and interconnected, or, better, images.
dialectical, forces, these being stillness and move- Walter Benjamin points out in his ‘Little History
of Photography’ (1931) how in its initial period pho-
tography enjoyed a particular affinity with science. 3
In those early days, some of its first uses explored
how the whole cosmos could be projected into port-
able form, for contemplation in the interior. This
was, Benjamin decreed, part of photography’s original
utopian compass. In a speech to the French Chamber
of Deputies in 1839, when he sought to gain state funds
for Daguerreotypy, François Arago reveals something
of this utopianism of scientific enquiry. Arago was an
astronomer and a politician, and had requested that
Daguerre make a photographic image of the moon,
which Daguerre did on 2 January 1839. Arago imag-
ined the uses to come for photography. He planned
Olaus Magnus, 1555

wondrous maps of the planets, too far away for the


human eye to perceive, but brought into vision through
chemistry. He imagined photographs of infinite numbers
of stars, in a mapping of the heavens. He also conceived

22
R. Hooke, 1665

a comprehensive record of the only recently poten- off-worlds brought down to earth, in this case, but rather
tially legible Egyptian hieroglyphics. Mysterious and the tiniest portions of our universe projected larger. The
extraterrestrial worlds are visualized. Furthermore, as smallest particle is amplified and makes thereby, in
Benjamin notes of an epoch that, with its widespread representation, a small image world in itself, particular,
promulgation of possession, is turning away from unique, complex and intricate. Microphotography – and
the optical towards the ‘tactile’,4 these largest worlds never more so than in the case of snow crystals – is a
– offworlds – are made graspable, quite literally, as replicational, repetitive technology that evinces hetero­
they are taken into the viewer’s hand in image form. geneity, the disparateness of nature displayed to the eye
When Bentley devised a way to capture snowflakes, he as curiosity.
was performing likewise a seemingly impossible task. Snow forms in the atmosphere, perhaps around a
He was capturing accurately the image of something microscopic dust particle or on a frozen droplet. The
tiny and ephemeral, enlarging it vastly and making six branches of the crystal grow from bombardment
a permanent record of it for hands-on leisurely and by water molecules present in air’s vapour. Each snow
scientific contemplation. crystal self-organizes its hexagonal lattice, a complex
However, by Bentley’s time, some forty-odd years result of repetition, under a particular and peculiar
into its life, photography comes to be better known set of circumstances: the specific temperatures in the
as a mediator of more everyday visions. It is increas- air at various points, the particular supersaturation
ingly associated with multiplication, reproduction and at the time of formation, might favour the formation
a recording of the mundane. The relationship to, on the of snow needles, or, instead, plates, stars or columns.
one hand, the outlandish and mysterious and, on the Blown through clouds, every crystal is subjected to
other, the scientific and exploratory, slips behind more random shifts of temperature. Each forms in response
prosaic and superficial uses of the medium. Bentley’s to these fluctuating conditions, which are unrepeatable.
practice, though (like other examples of nature photog- Some journey down from the sky intact, their intricate
raphy), holds on to the twin aspects of photography as designs preserved. Some fuse with cloud droplets or
magical and scientific, in the context of normalization conglomerate into flakes. Each life history is recorded
of the photograph. His work presents another image of in the crystal and made visible in microphotography.
contradictory nature. Photography, a mechanical form What the viewer receives, in the microphotograph,
of image production, bore important implications for is static, an arrest of a process of falling, floating,
the shaping of concepts such as originality and unique- melting. Yet still, it might be said, these photographs
ness, key concepts of traditional art understanding. constitute a type of animation, for they provide, in
Photography and film possessed no original. Each print a flash, evidence of diachronic processes, of indi-
from the negative was only as ‘original’ as the next or vidual and heterogeneous ‘biographies’, ‘physiognomic
the one before it, which is to say not original at all. In aspects’5 – that is to say, indications of deep structures,
this context it is of some fascination that Bentley’s first processes and character – legible through the surface
photographs of snow crystals in 1885 and then the thou- of the finished form.
sands that follow, despite their endlessly reproducible In 1893, a little while after Bentley’s first photo-
nature, despite their multiple, series-like appearance, graphs, the German meteorologist Gustav Hellmann
provide evidence for quite the opposite – a proof of published his scientific reflections on snow crystals.
the cliché that largely still holds as scientifically true: These were accompanied by heliogravures from micro-
that no two snow crystals are the same. A technique of photographs by Richard Neuhaus. Originally, Hell-
multiplicity garners proof of uniqueness. It is not giant mann confesses, each winter, gleeful at the appearance

23
of snow, he tried to sketch individual snow crystals, known. Just as Hellmann deems photographed nature
but melting and evaporation meant he had to fill in the livelier than drawn, schematized nature, Benjamin
missing parts and so he relied on symmetry. Comparing too endows the photographed image of nature, or the
these drawings with crystals glimpsed for a moment nature that comes into being photographically, with a
under a microscope, they appeared ‘too schematic and liveliness or vividness that results from a more intense
too stiff’.6 Hellmann observes how drawings, as, for knowing.
example, in the sketches of Mrs Glaisher, carried out at Close-ups are a key vehicle of this knowing and
her meteorologist husband James’s behest, idealize the they are attuned to the requirements of a photography
crystal’s form. The drawings of snow crystals produce of the everyday, which differs in terms of its scale from
symmetrical, geometric figures that do not exist in
actuality. They do this as a way of finishing off an
image whose original model was long melted away. Or
perhaps drawing captured a geometry that existed only
for a moment long ago at the snow crystal’s formation,
never to be visible to a human eye.7 In contrast to the
drawing, the microphotographs reveal imperfections,
asymmetries, deformations, deviations from the laws,
which is to say that the photographs detail the ‘reality’
of the snow crystal. Through the microphotographs,
Hellmann commented:
Now we no longer have ideal shapes and schematic

R. Neuhaus, 1893
figures in front of us, but real images, as offered to
us by nature. Indeed, one could say that, in spite of
the icy congealment of the object what we see here
are images of nature as warm as life.8

The human eye perceives – after the intervention


the earlier epoch’s bringing of vast stars and the moon
of the mechanical eye with its enlarging lens – a ‘real
and the sun miniaturized down to earth. In Benjamin’s
image’, an image of reality. The microphotography of
view, the knowledge that photography as close-up
snow crystals mediates, via the camera, what Walter
uncovers is also a curious one. The different nature
Benjamin characterizes as a different nature, one that
that the camera imports discovers the ‘mysterious’ in
is accessible to machine-enhanced perception. This
the everyday, according to Benjamin in his description
different nature visaged by the machine is now deemed
of the close-ups of plants by Karl Blossfeldt. These
more real, more lively.
reveal strange analogies, ones that intermingle natural
Benjamin’s essay ‘Little History of Photography’
and artefactual forms and dramatize the action of the
details the other nature available to machine-enhanced
camera on nature. That is to say, these are images
perception.
of ‘different nature’ or second nature, of a nature
For it is another nature which speaks to the camera confronted by creative human labour self-constituting
rather than to the eye: ‘other’ above all in the sense and expressing a world-view, kinship and protection,
that a space informed by human consciousness gives
in short human civilization: ancient columns in horse
way to a space informed by the unconscious.9
willow, a bishop’s crosier in the ostrich fern, totem
For Benjamin the camera reveals aspects, indeed poles in tenfold enlargements of chestnut and maple
whole worlds of images, ‘physiognomic aspects, image shoots, and gothic tracery in the fuller’s thistle. As
worlds, which dwell in the smallest things’,10 that have such the images are evidence that nature too can be a
previously never been seen before – except perhaps in realm of human transformation in coordination with
dreams. The camera discloses these through its barrage technology and thought. Hellmann discovers analogies
of effects that assault the unquestioned coherence of through the magnifying lens too, though his do not
actuality: slow motion and enlargement, for example. invoke the philosophical conundrums of second nature.
It routes vision through the machine and so detaches That the snow crystal resembles other natural forms,
humans from their conscious, or habitual, modes of botanical forms in particular, is the revealed secret
seeing. It ‘reveals the secret’ and so, paradoxically, of the magnifying lens, the exposed filmstrip and the
dredges the world up from unconsciousness into being time-defying coated papers. It is the magical trick or

24
technologically acquired fact which makes tangible differently perceived. For Adorno, the glass globes
what was not tangible before – for example, that snow house Nature morte, still life, dead life. Their appeal to
crystal columns are hollow tubes. Walter Benjamin, who collected them, like that of other
What the machine brings back for vision is not ‘petrified, frozen or obsolete components of culture’,11
deadly, not ahuman or inanimate, even if the mecha- such as fossils or plants in herbariums, signals, for
nism that recovers it is. Rather, as Hellmann phrases Adorno, Benjamin’s attraction to everything that has
it, it makes images that are ‘warm as life’. And while alienated from itself any ‘homely aliveness’. The snow
the photographed ice crystals never move before the globe is an emblem of de-animation, of the passage to
eye, the image that appears on the filmstrip and gets a reified death or non-life as characterizes experience in
printed on photographic papers is the end-result of a industrial and bureaucratic capitalism. For the literary
process that takes place over time – or through history. theorist Paul Szondi, the emphasis, on the contrary,
It betrays the marks of such process in its imperfec- was on the snow globe’s freeze-framing of a scene of
tions, thus compounding time or history in a single life, not death. He called the snow globes ‘reliquaries’,
image that is as ‘warm as life’ because it is so real. which provide shelter, the preservation of something
That is to say, animation – the apparent ‘breath’ of – a scene, an event – as image to bequeath to the future
life (a meaning suggested by its root anima, a cognate in the shape of hope.12 A cruder, crueller description
of animus, or mind) – might be found in what seems might argue that the globe replicates a standardized
like stillness. The microphotograph of the snow crystal moment of happiness ad infinitum. The snow globe
brings into vision a small image world imbued with fixates the mind on a special moment stilled forever,
life interrupted, cancelled, preserved, and like ours it except for the intermittently falling snow.
is one in which historical process has produced the The snow globe is always an ideal scene, a com-
present state of things. The frozen mobile nature of posite or fantasy, a small image or imagined world
ice is frozen again, through the camera, into a stilled
image, a ‘different nature’, but that image of ‘different
nature’ pulsates with life. Indeed its ‘different nature’
is, it could be said, just such enhanced liveliness.
Animation may be the very state of the different nature
that inhabits a small image world.
Perhaps microphotography distils something intrin-
sic to animation: its achievement is, it seems, to conjure
a world that pulsates with physicality, analogy and
potential, even where life appears to be arrested.
Through processes of replication – the replication of
nature in image, the replication of the image from the
filmstrip – a unique and heterogeneous image world that existed only in dreams and that comes to life in
is discovered. its being moved, in displacement. Is the snow globe
animated? Unlike the microphotograph of the snow
Another scene: snow globes crystal, it is unreal, in Hellmann’s terms – that is to
The snow globe protects a little world housed under say, not photographic or indexical. It is an image of
glass or, later, transparent plastic. The scene is perfection, a plastic mould loosely based on reality
un­touchable, but the globe itself exists precisely to – reinvented, with blue backing, in Germany, in the
be grasped in the hand, which neatly fits around its 1950s, as a vehicle for an excess production of flat
rounded or oval contours, in order every so often plastic brooches. It is the image of an ideal or idea.
to shake up the artificial snowflakes or flitter. After The snow globe perhaps concentrates animation in
shaking, it is as if life has suddenly entered and then its most basic form. Animation is a type of giving
crept away again. The snow globe comes properly life technically. The life endowed to the snow globe
to life only when it is replete with a liquid that emerges out of the most basic gesture – a waving of
becomes invisible, functioning solely as a medium for the hand. The snow globe is animated for a moment by
im­peding and transporting bone, rice, polystyrene or an external action, brought from lifelessness into life;
glitter pieces until they settle. it sparks a memory or fantasy. Its animation is ignited
The snow globe meddles somehow with life and in the animation of the flakes and completed in the
lifelessness, though where the emphasis lies has been wistful and transported mind of the viewer.

25
Snow crystal photography, snow globes: two sites Little Nemo in Slumberland, about the nightly dream
where a flurry of contradictions is catalysed. Animated escapades of a little boy, provides an emblem of this.
dramas occur in both these small image worlds: a Snow has fallen in Nemo’s bedroom, a burgeoning drift
rapid flux, a shift from one state to another, reversals accumulating as he drifts into sleep. Once he is fully
of scale, an interplay of replication and uniqueness, covered by the thick snow Nemo burrows through the
sameness and difference, a summoning in both of snow blanket in search of his father’s room, but he
concentrated imaginative power. loses his bearings and finds himself in Jack Frost’s
domain. Unable to repress the sound of his breathing,
Ice and artifice and so breaking the silence, he is chased by polar bears
Where snow and ice are there are always opposites at through the snowy landscape back to his bed, where
work. Where there is opposition there is dynamism, Nemo wakes, as he does every week. The snow fell
mobility, movement and transformation – which may in a dream and seemed to fill the room itself. In his
be why it offers itself especially for utopian reverie, for dream Nemo’s room becomes a snow globe, and, like a
example in the Christmas card, the painting by Caspar snow globe, the room seems to be a microcosm of the
David Friedrich, the ice sculpture or palace. Under wider world inside just one part of it, a world within
snow colour is extinguished by whiteness. Roughness a world, reflex of the way in which the dream might
is overlaid by the smoothness of ice. And, furthermore, be seen as a repetition of the world within the smaller
ice and snow are made of water. This fluid, the fluid of globe of the head. But what the comic strip also
fluids, is frozen into crystals. What was always moving concentrates in its weekly encounters with snow, ice,
becomes still, until it melts again back into water. Ice storms, earthquakes, sudden climactic shifts, as well
crystals are the immobilized that is dynamic through as mobile cities, and shifting interiors, is a peculiarly
its interaction with environment. Ice is, therefore, a animated environment and an architecture of absolute
transient form, which is perhaps to say not a form at impermanence and drama, such as characterizes that
all, for it always presses towards formlessness again. ushered in by capitalist industrial modernity.
There is something materially present in the constitu- Little Nemo drifts to the snowdrifts, but he lives
tion of ice that allows it to annex to powerful fantasies in the city, and this is the realm that is most graphi-
of renovation. Ice is a product of transformation – of cally animated in the weekly stories. Here nature is
water – and it transforms environments. A comic strip contained or bursts out. New York and its buildings, its
from 1906, one episode in Winsor McCay’s series streets, docks, rivers and alleyways leap into storylines.

26
In its becoming motive, New York, or the city space, modernity. The presence of Spielraum allows, at least
is revealed in the comic strip as a place of modern imaginatively, the possibility of possibility, of the new,
anxiety about urban space, an unease generated by the of the different to all this.
built environment, with its monstrous power to crush, Winsor McCay was also, from 1911, an animator
oppress, damage, or, in turn, be damaged by humans – where his comic strips thematically set the city in
run amok. Little Nemo’s adventures feature humans motion, his animations used the rhythms of modernity
being pursued by tall buildings or humans knock- concretely. His first one transformed Nemo to the
ing buildings down, because magically proportions screen, tentatively. Inside the boxes of New York
have been suddenly and inexplicably reversed. Little offices, men conspire to give flat shapes life and
Nemo’s city is a place of constant disasters. Displayed colour. There is little narrative in this animation, which
in the elegant stretching and shrinking rectangles of consists of an unmotivated, illogical squashing and
the strip is a tangible anxiety about the relationship stretching, the very principle of cartooning. It could
between city inhabitants and their novel and rapidly be described as an example of the ‘optical illusion of
changing environments. And, to be crudely Marxist, movement’, though it is honest about its source and
in New York, the land was special, magical, with does not seek to deceive. It might better be described
extraordinary powers of transformation. Land value as a rumination on the passage between living and
rose rapidly. Land was sold or leased, buildings were drawing, between lifelessness and life, identity and
flung up swiftly, causing earthquakes across the city. It non-identity. It is not an illusion of movement but
was as if mud, stone, brick, concrete and steel spored presents movement itself, as a feat, rushing through
value of their own accord. If ever there were a com- the projector, the result, as the film makes clear, of
modity fetishism of land it was here on this little island thousands of drawings and gallons of ink.
– where buildings become animate or take on human Could the motion generated in these first studio-
characteristics, human weaknesses, and sometimes offices of mass cultural production be seen as a model-
humans assume the destructive force of tumbling ling of the dynamic, ever-changing forms of modernity?
buildings. To embed the peculiar energies of the city More specifically, it is a modelling of its seemingly
of capital further in the motives of the comic strip, motive force, the commodity economy – whose endless
Winsor McCay stretched Little Nemo’s panels verti- replications and innovations, and whose commodity
cally to accommodate the new skyscraper-ordained fetishism, are analogously evident in the animated
dimensions of city life. objects’ push beyond their own objectivity.
Slumberland is terrifying, not least because its small Animation, then, as rendition of commodity fetish-
worlds fling up newly invented horrors and dislodge- ism, that illusory hyperliveliness of objects, a topsy-
ments week after week. In his studies of modernizing turvy negation of the value that stems from labour.
Paris, Walter Benjamin specified a tempo characteristic What is animation but objects coming seemingly to
of industrial capitalist modernity: the eternal recur- life, without human intervention, so it appears. And
rence of the ever-same in the guise of the new. This yet it is also the realm in which such graphic rendi-
is the tempo of technologically reproduced culture tion might make social forms available to knowledge,
within capitalism, just as it is that of any commodity: conscious, in the sense of Walter Benjamin’s ‘optical
replication that resembles heterogeneity. It has its unconscious’ of photography and cinema, a new mode
horror-face in the endless movement of conveyor-belt of seeing beyond seeing, using the segmenting powers
commodity production. Cartooning is a particularly of the camera and cinematic technology on a dissected
graphic version of this hellish temporality. The cel image world that must be broken down in order to be
after cel or frame after frame, churned out again and made up again. As such animation might be not just the
again, means that structurally it is based on such a rep- illusion of movement but also the movement of illusion.
etition with difference. Generically, too, cartoons are Frozen social relations are warmed into life; the rigid
notorious for dishing up the ever-same product with the surface unthaws. Animation has its analytical, critical
smallest tweaks as stimulus to sales. But Slumberland face. It melts the congealed surface of daily life with
also possesses its utopian side. McCay’s ever-returning its analytical and utopian stance.
strips present the city as what Walter Benjamin terms As many have argued, animation contains within
in his thoughts on ‘The Work of Art in the Age of itself always a sense in which its objects and images,
Its Technical Reproducibility’ a Spielraum, a place drawn or modelled, are motile, flexible, open to pos-
of play, with room for manoeuvre, something that he sibility, able to extend in any direction, undertake any
theorizes as a beneficial characteristic of technological action or none. Sergei Eisenstein devised a category of

27
‘plasmaticness’ that he evoked in order to stress this the strategies of Dada and Surrealism but sharpens and
originary shape-shifting potential of the animated, the demolishes in their spirit their relationship to advertis-
way in which an object or image, drawn or modelled, ing and commodity culture. Paris has a project called
strains beyond itself, could adopt potentially any form, H.U.M.A.N.W.O.R.L.D., an acronym for Holistic and
thereby rescinding all back to a moment of ‘hope in the Utopian Multinational Alliance for New World Order
past’, a future potential, beyond current constraints.13 It and Research in Living and Dying (or formerly The
was not frozen water that Eisenstein evoked in relation New Perishable Gallery). In this his referent is anthro-
to this ecstatic plasmaticness – despite the references pology and the aim, he says, is a critical reflection on
to Snow White. It was its opposite and nemesis, fire, ‘multiculturalism and globalization’, an updating of
which, observes Eisenstein, ‘is capable of most fully the anthropological, ‘primitivist’ and internationalist
conveying the dream of a flowing diversity of forms’.14 fascinations that motivated the Surrealists and Dadaists
This is animation’s utopian axis. It is the one that Walter before him. H.U.M.A.N.W.O.R.L.D. is a collection, a
Benjamin emphasized in his reading of Mickey Mouse, trashy one, far trashier than André Breton’s collation
in the essay ‘Experience and Poverty’ from 1933. of tribal and curious items. Paris has been collecting
Mickey Mouse embodies the utopian aspiration for a packaging for several years. He collects packaging
technology-ravaged, yet technology-dependent, popu- that has faces on it. Much packaging has faces. Paris
lace.15 Mickey Mouse inhabits a miraculous universe archives the packages: producing a gallery of ideal
in which objects exchange properties – suddenly a cow types, making eye contact, commodity-masks, sorted
is a musical box or a skirt a parachute. In Benjamin’s according to genus, gender, family-product relations
and so on. Paris holds on to the packages
and their contents, as they perish. He says
the following:

Primarily intended to represent human


beings on an international scale,
H.U.M.A.N.W.O.R.L.D. is akin to a
traditional portrait gallery. Its constitu-
ents (referred to as ‘portrait-products’)
are supermarket products the packaging
of which features a realistic representa-
tion of a human being. These products
are generally of a perishable nature.
For any given product, a single speci-
men (packaging + contents) is entered
in H.U.M.A.N.W.O.R.L.D., with the
guarantee that it will never be replaced.
The products are treated as unique in-
dividuals that have been reified through
representation.16
analysis, Mickey Mouse is seen to fulfil the wish for a
harmonious reconciliation of technology and nature, This small image world threatens to grow vast.
a graphic recognition of Eisenstein’s ‘non-indifferent H.U.M.A.N.W.O.R.L.D.’s Community comprises three
nature’, in the hostile conditions of an age when techno- elements: the constituents (portrait-products) treated
logical change threatens to destabilize human existence, individually as reified beings, which are left to perish,
and also destroy it. But the benign union of technology something that the glorious shiny commodity bauble is
and nature has to be relegated to the dream world of never supposed to do; Sub-Community, the individuals
comics, photographs and cinema, where machinery (men, women, children) who, in real life, have sold
indulges humans, for in reality, in industrial capitalism, their faces to the products; Meta-Community, the
technology and nature – that is machinery and humans artificial lives (avatars) generated from the human-
– are dead set against each other, torn apart or tearing ism of the commodity. In a parallel virtual world
each other apart in labour and war. meta-community the commodities have a whole social
world in which they age and die – or, with the aid of
Still animation now computer technologies, give birth to new commodities,
A French artist by the name of Guillaume Paris is minglings of their attributes, and generate the meta-
producing small image worlds today. He has adapted community in forms of ‘artificial spirituality’.

28
Paris mediates the com-
modities in various ways,
through animating processes,
videoing them, digitalizing
them. He uses forensic
science to paint portraits of
the faces on packages envis-
aging how they might look
today. All these faces stare
out at us the viewers, making
us the object of art’s gaze in
its guise as commodity. In
various ways, Paris ‘extends
the humanism of the commodity to its logical conclu- And even if the packaging is largely indestructible, its
sion (and beyond)’. He bestows subjectivity on the com- immortality as object is compromised by its inevitable
modity, to a ludicrous degree, just as cartooning used slippage out of style and fashion: the mock historical
absurdism to unmask motive forces – of technology, rhythm of fashion at least poses the passage of time
of violence, in industrial capitalist society. as an issue.
One of Paris’s ploys is to find the models who Paris has also made a number of artworks that are
‘in real life have sold their faces to the commodity’ something between representation and sculpture. These
– these he locates across the world after some years’ he calls ‘permanent videos’. The form proposes some-
delay. Then he films their lips talking in the present thing quite untenable – an incoherent clash of stillness
about their dreams and hopes. These lips are then and mobility, of eternity and the ephemeral that should
montaged back onto a film of the commodity package. be impossible. Paris watched Disney animated films
Their older self turns into speaking commodities. He frame by frame (an apparently protracted labour that
explains it thus: negated the pleasure of the text, if ever an act did). He
wondered if some further meaning might be squeezed
Resuscitated (‘de-reified’) in such a fashion, they
are encouraged to express themselves subjectively, from this degraded epitome of rubbishy kitsch. He
and to communicate with each other. The interac- discovered thereby a banality that once mobilized
tive installation We Are The World constitutes a first displaces the material into telling a truth about itself
experiment in this direction. The installation brings and offers a space for some other-thinking in the flow
together, in a physical space, one portrait-product of time. Paris studied, for example, a scene in which
from each country of the G7. In the absence of any
Pinocchio lies face down in water for a few moments.
human beings, the portrait-products of this model
community speak among themselves, simultaneous- This animated piece of wood, who wishes to be human,
ly, each one expressing itself is almost killed – that is, almost
in its mother tongue. This returns to the deadness that he
activity ceases as soon as a is – but manages to survive and
visitor enters the space: the leap from the water. Except
animated objects are static
Paris found that in this scene
again, and the faces silent.
one frame is repeated. This
Processes of animation are used is the method of industrial
Kinder, 2003 (pastel on paper, frame, 34 x 31 x 4 cm),

here to mirror the overliveliness culture, the culture industry


of the commodity world that that Adorno and Horkheimer
would claim to be the world, eschewed. Its work is stand-
Lois Gibson for H.U.M.A.N.W.O.R.L.D

the one that we may purchase ardized. Short cuts are taken.
in order to prove ourselves Repetition occurs. Paris uses
alive. At the same time, in this fact of the material to loop
naturalizing this second nature the film. Pinocchio lies sub-
– through the contradictory merged and motionless in the
conservation and enstagement water forever, while the water
of its perishability – process gushes endlessly in this per-
assails the commodity object. manent video titled ‘Fountain’.

29
The animation circulates without ceasing: as indeed 2. The phrase ‘non-indifferent nature’ is, of course, to be
does the rhythm of production. And the join cannot be found where Eisenstein found it: in Hegel. It occurs
in his discussion of Chemism in paras 200–203 of the
seen – or, alternatively, in this context emerges out of Logic, where it is crucial to a discussion of motion,
the optical unconscious in order to be the only thing transformation and affinity in natural processes.
seen. A similar effect is played out in ‘Minding’, where 3. Walter Benjamin, ‘Kleine Geschichte der Photographie’
[1931] Gesammelte Schriften, volume II.1, p. 370. ‘Little
a perambulating owl, from Disney’s Bambi, its face
History of Photography’, in Walter Benjamin, Selected
always turned to the viewer, circles on a spot endlessly, Writings, volume 2: 1927−1934, Harvard Belknap Press,
without marking it ever, without moving forward in Cambridge MA, 1999 p. 508.
time one bit – stomping out something like the tem- 4. Walter Benjamin, Arcades Project, Harvard Belknap
Press, Cambridge MA, 1999, p. 206.
porality of hell that is capitalism in Walter Benjamin’s
5. Benjamin, ‘Little History of Photography’, p. 512.

Guillaume Paris, Fountain, 1994 (permanent video monitor on the floor, color, sound)
typology, and permanently startled. Sisyphus at work, 6. Gustav Hellmann, Schneekrystalle: Beobachtungen und
but this labour leaves no traces: an image perhaps of Studien, Rudolf Mückenberger, Berlin, 1893, Introduc-
the clean virtual work of immaterial labour, which tion, p. 9.
7. Ibid., p. 21
is the current myth of production. The owl’s eyes are 8. Ibid., p. 24.
never diverted: we are caught under his stare as much 9. Benjamin, ‘Little History of Photography’, p. 510. The
as he is fixed by ours. Nature is snared in the human line is repeated virtually word for word in Benjamin’s
‘Artwork essay’: see Benjamin, Selected Works volume
bind of production: it would be different, it would be
3, p. 117.
non-indifferent, but can only propose this as possibility. 10. Benjamin, ‘Little History of Photography’, p. 512.
This permanent animation is simply repetition, is return 11. T.W. Adorno, ‘Charakteristik Walter Benjamins’, Pris-
without heterogeneity, is bleak, except that the moment men: Kulturkritik und Gesellschaft, Deutscher Taschen­
buch Verlag, Munich, 1963, p. 237.
of difference can be found in the twist of the strip that
12. Peter Szondi, ‘Hope in the Past: On Walter Benjamin’
becomes its own critique. The surface and the deep [1961], Critical Inquiry, Spring 1978, pp. 500–501.
structure of the animation combine to utter the horrid 13. Sergei M. Eisenstein, Eisenstein on Disney, Methuen,
truth of the system that it upholds. London 1988, p. 11.
14. Ibid., p. 24.
15. Walter Benjamin, ‘Experience and Poverty’, Selected
Notes Writings, volume 2, pp. 734−5.
1. Walter Benjamin’s phrase for this is ‘eine andere Natur’. 16. Quotations from Paris and examples of the work can be
This has been variously translated as ‘a different nature’ seen on www.guillaumeparis.com/work.html and www.
and ‘another nature’. guillaumeparis.com/humanworld7.

30
Non-traduttore, traditore?
Notes on postwar European Marxisms
in translation

Gregory Elliott

Certainly in the English-speaking world, probably Authors have been allocated to broad linguistic
elsewhere, we lack the most rudimentary map of communities, rather than continental zones as such,
European Marxism since the 1970s. Over the last for several reasons. The most important, which also
two decades, there has been nothing comparable to accounts for the amalgamation of the Hispanophone
several titles which, whatever their other differences, and Lusophone into one category, is that such an option
featured roughly the same dramatis personae – the allows for registration of the major Latin American
age, golden or iron as you will, of György Lukács contribution. The ‘European Marxisms’ of my title
and Antonio Gramsci, Critical Theory and Existential should thus be read as shorthand for ‘Marxisms in
Marxism, the Della Volpean and Althusserian schools. European languages’.
The equivalent of André Tosel’s Développement du The number of representatives selected for each
marxisme en Europe occidentale depuis 1917 (1974), table – ten – is incorrigibly arbitrary, suggested by
Perry Anderson’s Considerations on Western Marxism what immediately sprang to mind in the case of Anglo­
(1976) and In the Tracks of Historical Materialism phone Marxism, which then imposed a template (not,
(1983), Martin Jay’s Marxism and Totality (1984), or I trust, a Procrustes bed) on the rest. So as to avoid
even (in a dismissive key) J.G. Merquior’s Western squaring subjectivism, authors have been listed in
Marxism (1985), remains to be written. Tosel’s chapters alphabetical order.
in Brill’s recent Critical Companion to Contemporary In the interests of breadth of coverage, any overlap
Marxism on trends in French and Italian Marxism, between the two tables was initially excluded. As
and on late Lukács and the Budapest School, approxi- readers pointed out, however, this had the effet pervers
mate most closely to it.1 But they do not sum up to of foregrounding novelty at the cost of masking conti-
the full-scale treatment signalled some years ago by nuities. The ‘no double entries’ rule has therefore been
Presses Universitaires de France. Meanwhile, Göran dropped and such figures as Eric Hobsbawm, Maurice
Therborn’s From Marxism to Post-Marxism promises Godelier and Adolfo Sánchez-Vázquez now assume
more route-maps out of Marxism than within it. 2 their due relief.
The notes below are prompted not by an idle Criteria for inclusion comprise some compound of
pleasure in drawing up and glossing league tables, individual prominence and general representativeness
but by a concern to get an overall sense of displace- within the culture in question. Yet it should be noted
ments in Marxist intellectual output since the 1970s that not all entries possess precisely the same status.
and the corresponding patterns of translation into In the Francophone case, for example, Althusser is
English. Their schematic character is compounded a proper name tantamount to a common noun (sub-
by tabular presentation. This might, however, possess suming Étienne Balibar, Dominique Lecourt, Pierre
some redeeming virtue inasmuch as it facilitates com- Macherey and Emmanuel Terray – but not Nicos
parison and contrast within and between tables. Poulantzas); and the same is true of Galvano Della
With all the risks that such an operation inevitably Volpe in the Italian instance (subsuming, say, Umberto
entails, the two tables aim approximately to identify Cerroni, Nicolao Merker, Giulio Pietranera and Mario
the outstanding Marxist thinkers published in English, Rossi – but not Lucio Colletti).
French, German, Italian and Spanish/Portuguese since Albeit rough, the periodization – 1945–1978 and
the Second World War. 1979–2007 – is ready, corresponding to two turning

31
points in the history of the European Left: the defeat abstain from judging the quality of any of the trans-
of the French Union of the Left interring Eurocom- lations to which they refer. But it stands to reason
munism in 1978; the victory of Thatcher pioneering that the one thing worse than no translation is poor
the radical Right in 1979. translation. 3
Taking my cue from Tosel’s reference to today’s
‘thousand Marxisms’, blooming if not contending, I Observations
have adopted deliberately a latitudinarian stance when
A few points of detail for 1945–1978:
it comes to what counts as Marxist. The implicit defin-
ing – not self-defining – characteristics used prove, on • Anglophone: Notwithstanding competing claims
rereading, to have involved a blend of the literary, the – especially those of Joseph Needham – J.D. Bernal
epistemological and the political; and would doubtless has been selected as typifying Werskey’s ‘visible
benefit from explicit discussion and critical inspection. college’ of British ‘scientific socialists’.
But in the absence of that, suffice it to say that I have • Francophone: While arguably a less original histo-
employed a distinction between revision of Marxism, rian than Pierre Vilar, and whatever the reputation
however radical, and repudiation of it – between the of his work after the study of the Parisian sans-
neo-, para, quasi- and plain Marxist, on the one hand, culottes, Albert Soboul has been chosen as the
and the professedly post-Marxist, on the other. This is inheritor and continuator of the Mathiez–Lefebvre
bound to be controversial on more than one occasion: tradition of republican historiography of the French
why, for instance, late Antonio Negri but not recent Revolution – a key dimension of Gallic Marxism
Balibar? (In the absence of an altogether compelling (witness François Furet’s fulminations against it).
response, I would simply venture that more continuity • Italian: Although dead in 1937, Gramsci has natu-
is discernible between Negri’s sometime operaismo rally been included here because of the postwar
and latter-day multitudinismo than between Balibar publication of the Prison Notebooks; and Ernesto
on proletarian dictatorship in the 1970s and Balibar Ragionieri, although perhaps less well known
on European citizenship in the 1990s.) outside Italy than Paolo Spriano or Giuliano Pro-
Designed to canvass other, better-informed propos- cacci, has ultimately been preferred to them as a
als for inclusion (and consequent exclusion), the tables Marxist historian on the grounds of his national
– less professional survey maps than amateur sketches reputation.
– hopefully correspond to something approaching other • Hispanophone/Lusophone: The influence of his
people’s intuitive sense of the landscape. Yet it must be theorization of Castroism – Revolution in the Revo-
stressed that much of what follows is based on second- lution?, originally published in Spanish – warrants
hand knowledge, hearsay even – primarily, but by no the Frenchman Régis Debray’s location here; while
means exclusively, for want of linguistic competence. the ‘dependency theory’ of Andre Gunder Frank
As such, it solicits correction of errors of commission – born in Germany, exiled in the USA, writing in
and omission alike. English – had its greatest impact in South America,
Last but not least: intended as biblio­graphical where he lived and worked in the 1960s and 1970s
reportage – nothing more – these notes nevertheless (Brazil/Chile), rendering him an honorary Latin.

Table 1  1945–1978

Anglophone Francophone Italian German Hispanophone/Lusophone

Anderson Althusser Badaloni Abendroth Aricó


Bernal Bettelheim Colletti Adorno Cardoso
Cohen Godelier Della Volpe Claudín Bahro
Dobb Gorz Gerratana Bloch Debray
Hobsbawm Goldmann Geymonat Habermas Frank
Miliband Lefebvre Gramsci Horkheimer Guevara
Nairn Mandel Luporini Lukács Laclau
Sweezy Poulantzas Ragionieri Marcuse Revueltas
Thompson Sartre Timpanaro Schmidt Sacristán
Williams Soboul Tronti Sohn-Rethel Sánchez

32
Table 2  1979–2007

Anglophone Francophone Italian German Hispanophone/Lusophone

Anderson Andréani Agosti Altvater Buey


Brenner Bidet Arrighi Backhaus Dussel
Clark Bois Burgio Gerstenberger Echeverría
Davis Duménil Canfora F. Haug Gilly
Eagleton Godelier Losurdo W.F. Haug Harnecker
Harvey Labica Magri Heinrich Rodriguez-Araujo
Hobsbawm Löwy Moretti Hirsch Rozitchner
Jameson Robelin Negri Negt Sader
Wood Tosel Prestipino Reichelt Sánchez-Vázquez
Wright Vovelle Preve Wolf Schwarz

The most striking thing to emerge from Table poses an obvious question: what, if anything, has been
1 is confirmation of the supremacy of continental lost as a result?
Marxisms in the first three postwar decades, with the Enjoying the benefit of hindsight for the earlier
Anglophone tradition lagging behind, except in histori- phase, where they are rooted in relatively settled
ography. The prominence of the latter within Anglo- reputations, judgements necessarily become vulnerable
Marxism emerges even more clearly if, to the galaxy to the hazards of foreshortening as we approach the
of Christopher Hill, Rodney Hilton, Eric Hobsbawm, present. That said, and setting individual details aside,
V.G. Kiernan, George Rudé, John Saville, Geoffrey de perhaps the most striking thing to emerge from Table
Ste Croix, and E.P. Thompson, are added Raymond 2 is the inversion in the relations between Anglo- and
Williams (a cultural critic, his Country and the City continental Marxisms as regards international diffusion
nevertheless manifestly pertains to it), and Maurice and reputation – if for no other reason than the global
Dobb (a political economist, his best-known book supremacy of Anglophone culture and the particular
– Studies in the Development of Capitalism – was a place of the US academy within it. Whereas at least
central reference for the Communist Party Historians’ half of the Anglophone authors, holders of chairs in
Group in which Hill and co. were formed, seeding North American universities, might non-controversially
the international ‘transition debate’ of the 1940s and be said to be of international renown, the same propor-
1950s). A sui generis tradition of Anglo-Marxist phil- tion cannot be ventured in other instances.
osophy began to emerge with G.A. Cohen’s Karl Whether or not cultural-linguistic comparative
Marx’s Theory of History at the turn of the 1970s, advantage translates into qualitative superiority, what
only to mutate in short order into a rational choice would be difficult to gainsay is a relative decline in the
anti-Marxism (Jon Elster et al.). Francophone and German sectors, with a less marked
For 1945–1978 there is a striking contrast between declension – if we exclude Gramsci as an exceptional
the fairly comprehensive translation of authors writing case – in the Italian and Hispanophone/Lusophone.
in French, German and Spanish/Portuguese – under the As things stand, by comparison with 1945–1978,
auspices of New Left Books, Monthly Review Press, little continental Marxism from the last three decades
Merlin Press, Allen Lane, Jonathan Cape, Routledge has been translated into English. Among that which
& Kegan Paul, Heinemann, and so on – and the very has, however, an unmistakable pattern emerges.
partial assimilation of their Italian counterparts (with Taking the names entered in Table 2, there is an
the exception of Della Volpe, Colletti and Timpanaro). overwhelming preponderance of French titles among
Whereas few truly major works by the former have books translated to date (excluding edited volumes):
been overlooked – Auguste Cornu’s Karl Marx et • seven by Michael Löwy
Friedrich Engels, Henri Lefebvre’s La Somme et le • five by Maurice Godelier
reste and Lukács’s Ästhetik are three exceptions; and • three by Michel Vovelle
whilst only one (admittedly central) Spanish figure • two by Guy Bois
– Manuel Sacristán – has been altogether neglected, • two by Gérard Duménil (with Dominique Lévy)
many of the highlights of Italian Marxism never made • one by Georges Labica
it into English and now presumably never will. This • one by Jacques Bidet.

33
For reasons that are not far to seek – the compara- with the persistence (until recently) of Rifondazione
tively ready availability of translation subventions from comunista, perhaps the greatest disservice has been
the French state – Verso, for example, has focused done to Italian Marxist culture.
overwhelmingly on Gallic titles in the last quarter- The legacy of Italian Marxism from the eras of
century. Moreover, for the most part these have been by the Second and Third Internationals can in essence
figures from Table 1 – Althusser (5), Guy Debord (2), be boiled down to Antonio Labriola and Gramsci.
André Gorz (3), Henri Lefebvre (3), Ernest Mandel (2), After a late start in 1957, when The Modern Prince
Jean-Paul Sartre (3) – or authors once associated with and Other Writings appeared in English, the latter is
their strain of Marxism (particularly the Althusserian) now well served in translation. Since 1971, in addition
– thus Balibar (4), Debray (6), Lecourt (1), Pierre to assorted anthologies, there have been published:
Macherey (1), Alain Badiou (4), Jacques Rancière (3), two volumes of selections from the Prison Notebooks
Daniel Bensaïd (1) and Henri Weber (1).4 The slack (Lawrence & Wishart); two collections of political
has not been picked up by surviving independent left writings (Lawrence & Wishart); one volume of cultural
presses (Merlin or Pluto Press) or thriving academic writings (Lawrence & Wishart); a complete edition of
imprints (Polity Press or Continuum). the prison letters (Columbia University Press), as well
Now that Jacques Bidet’s Que faire du ‘Capital’? as abridged offerings (Jonathan Cape, etc.); finally,
(1984) has finally appeared in the ‘Historical Materi- and most importantly, the ongoing translation of the
alism’ series at Brill, only three of the Francophone 1975 Italian edition of the Quaderni del carcere from
authors from Table 2 – Tony Andréani, Jean Robelin Columbia.
and Tosel – remain without an English translation of The same cannot be said of Labriola. Essays on the
a single book to their name. (Notwithstanding initial Materialist Conception of History was published in
plans for a Brill edition, Robelin’s important Marxisme English by the indefatigable Charles H. Kerr in 1908
et socialisation [1989] now seems likely, alas, to miss and reprinted by Monthly Review in 1967. Socialism
out.) and Philosophy appeared from the same imprint in
The ledger for the other categories is much barer. 1934 and was re-released by Telos Press in 1980. Hard
As regards German authors, the major translation pro- to come by outside the USA, like the Essays it has
grammes of recent years have been the Harvard edition long been out of print. Moreover, in addition to the
of Walter Benjamin’s works and Polity’s ongoing fact that neither is a reliable modern translation, both
release of titles by Theodor W. Adorno and Habermas. lack anything comparable to the editorial apparatus
By contrast, I am aware of a mere eight titles in English – scholarly introductions and annotations – that has
(or forthcoming) by figures from Table 2: distinguished English editions of Gramsci.
Turning now to Table 1, the striking thing is just
• one by Elmar Altvater
how few of the names in it have been translated.
• one by Heide Gerstenberger
Those titles that made it into English mainly derived
• two by Frigga Haug
from New Left Books/Verso and reflected the reigning
• two by Wolfgang Fritz Haug
priorities, political and intellectual, in Carlisle Street
• one (a 1970s’ classic) by Oskar Negt (with Alexan-
in the 1970s. Initial research suggests not much more
der Kluge).
than:
Hispanophone/Lusophone authors, all of them based
• three by Della Volpe
in Latin America, have fared marginally better,
• two by Colletti
mustering:
• two by Timpanaro
• seven by Enrique Dussel (the majority, however, on • one by Ludovico Geymonat
liberation theology) To these might be added various articles by Valentino
• one by Adolfo Gilly Gerratana that featured in New Left Review in the
• two by Marta Harnecker 1970s; and – among the names absent from the Italian
• one by Emir Sader (with Ken Silverstein) column in Table 1 – Manfredo Tafuri’s principal works
• two by Adolfo Sánchez Vázquez (both, however, on the history and theory of architecture.
from the 1960s) Quite apart from the absence of any titles from
• two by Roberto Schwarz. Nicola Badaloni (e.g. Pel il comunismo, 1972), Cesare
In view, however, of the quality (not to mention Luporini (e.g. Dialettica e materialismo, 1974),
quantity) of the literature it generated when buoyed or Mario Tronti (e.g. Operai e capitale, 1966), we
by the presence of the PCI, and continued to produce should register the massive under-representation both

34
of Geymonat – premier philosopher of science in 2007; and Moretti’s Graphs, Maps, Trees, 2005). At all
Western Marxism, editor and principal author of a events, English readers have rapid, easy access to their
multi-volume Storia del pensiero filosofico e scien- oeuvres. In the case of Negri – himself effectively a
tifico (1972) – and of the Della Volpeans. In striking mid-Atlantic author since embarking on collaboration
contrast to Althusser’s pupils and associates, whose with Michael Hardt – his brand of operaismo, pretty
works were translated concurrently with his own, Della much neglected in London or Minneapolis at the time,
Volpe’s followers – equally substantial, if not more so, has been widely rediscovered since 2000, in the wake
especially in intellectual history – drew a blank, with of Empire (translated from English into Italian, not
the exception of Colletti. Consequently, the names of vice versa). As a result of his celebrity, there has been
Cerroni, Rossi – author of a four-volume study of Marx an acceleration in the Anglicization of his material,
(1970–75) surpassing Cornu’s in scope – and Merker old and new, by imprints as diverse as Continuum,
– still publishing work of high quality (e.g. Europa Manchester University Press, Polity, Routledge and
oltre i mari. Il mito della missione di civiltà, 2006) Verso, with more doubtless in the offing.
– are virtually unknown in the Anglophone world. The case of Lucio Magri is unusual, if only because
Just as Italy produced what is arguably the finest he has authored but a single book as such – Consid-
individual account of the genesis of historical materi- erazioni sui fatti di maggio on May ’68 – a section of
alism out of the ‘German ideology’, with Rossi’s Da which was translated in Socialist Register the follow-
Hegel a Marx, so it boasts the two major attempts at ing year. Nevertheless, a good sample of his theoretical
a collective history of Marxism down to the 1970s, work, as well as his more topical political writing, is
courtesy of the Feltrinelli Foundation in 1974 and available in English.
Einaudi in 1978–82. A complete translation of the Other Italo-Italians, so to speak, have not fared
latter – the five-part Storia del marxismo edited by well. Two outstanding intellectual historians – the clas-
Hobsbawm and others – seems to have been planned sicist Luciano Canfora and the Germanist Domenico
by Harvester Press. In the event, however, only the first Losurdo – have had two or three books each translated
volume ever appeared. 5 of late. But this still leaves the bulk of their volumi-
In passing, it might more generally be noted that, nous oeuvres in undeserved obscurity. Two equally
aside from stray titles by Spriano, Procacci and productive leading philosophers – Giuseppe Prestipino
Giuseppe Boffa,6 a very rich tradition of Italian Marxist and Costanzo Preve – in common with the political
historiography has largely missed its rendezvous with theorist Alberto Burgio or the economist Gianfranco
Anglophone Marxist culture. Thus, for example, Gian La Grassa, have not enjoyed even that minimal degree
Mario Bravo’s work on pre-Marxian socialism and of attention. Thus, figures who loom large in Tosel’s
Marx and the First International, like that of Ragion- overview of Italian Marxism since 1975, as in Cristina
ieri on the Second and the Third, is familiar only to Corradi’s 2005 Storia dei marxismi in Italia, remain
specialists. strangers. Consequently, what are unquestionably major
This neglect continues into the present, where Aldo works – for example, Losurdo’s Nietzsche, il ribelle
Agosti, one of the world’s leading experts on the inter- aristocratico (2002) or Controstoria del liberalismo
national Communist movement – author, inter alia, of (2005), Preve’s Marx inattuale (2004) or Storia critica
an authoritative synthesis on European Communisms del marxismo (2007), to name only the most recent and
(Bandiere rosse, 1999) – does not rate a single English prominent – await discovery.8
translation.7
What of the other entries in Table 2? The overall Conclusions
picture is distorted by the ample representation in Other than in a bibliocentric conception of history,
English of three figures: the economist and systems cultural salience is no guarantee of political relevance;
theorist Giovanni Arrighi, the literary critic Franco the two can be inversely proportional. Thus, notwith-
Moretti, and the political philosopher Antonio Negri. standing the emergence of the ‘alter-globalization’
By virtue of their location in the US academy, the first movement(s) in Seattle on the eve of the new mil-
two are honorary Anglos, whose work either appears lennium, the lead sector in contemporary Marxism
well-nigh simultaneously in English and Italian (the – the Anglophone – remains largely cloistered in the
case of Moretti’s Modern Epic [1996] and Atlas of the academy, while its counterparts, all of them possess-
European Novel [1998]), or is originally published in ing solid organizational relays, can (or could) boast
their non-mother tongue (as with Arrighi’s The Long significantly greater degrees of presence in wider
Twentieth Century, 1994, and Adam Smith in Beijing, societies and polities.

35
Albeit to a lesser extent, the relative dearth of Hence a final thought: are today’s incommunicado
English translation of more recent European material Marxisms truly synchronized with the hour of social
appears to risk reproducing the postwar situation of forums, continental and global?
insular provincialism – with the difference that the
newly prosperous transatlantic branch of the family
now feels able to ignore its cross-Channel relatives. Notes
The days are long gone since Louis Althusser, An initial version of these notes was drafted in October
invited by New Left Review to respond to The Poverty 2004 and elicited a variety of reactions – some offering
of Theory, enquired of his correspondent: who is E.P. very helpful suggestions, others passably distracted. A
lengthy response by Peter Thomas indicated a degree of
Thompson? Even so, lest contrasts be overdrawn, convergence in our thinking and suggested that a joint
and an ‘inverted Podsnappery’ resuscitated, a brief venture might be worthwhile. In the event, this proved
glance at foreign translations of the Anglo-Marxist impossible, but what follows owes much to his input.
Thanks are also due to Peter Osborne, for helping me
names entered in Table 2 is in order. Even allowing
to clarify what I was – and was not – doing; and to
for the highly approximate figures yielded by a rapid John Kraniauskas for specific suggestions as regards
scan, the record is decidedly patchy. Hobsbawm is Hispanophone and Lusophone authors.
the exception that proves the rule: all his major texts 1. ���������������������������������������������������
See André Tosel, ‘The Development of Marxism: From
the End of Marxism–Leninism to a Thousand Marxisms
have been translated into French and German, while – France–Italy, 1975–2005’, and ‘The Late Lukács and
the Italian and Spanish reception has extended even the Budapest School’, trans. Gregory Elliott, in Jacques
further. At the other end of the scale, Ellen Meiksins Bidet and Stathis Kouvelakis, eds, Critical Companion
Wood (one each in German and Spanish) and Erik to Contemporary Marxism, Brill, Leiden and Boston
MA, 2008.
Olin Wright (a sole text in Spanish) have fared badly. 2. �������������������������������������������������������
For a pilot article, see Göran Therborn, ‘After Dialec-
Robert Brenner (a couple in German, one in Spanish) tics’, New Left Review II/45, May–June, pp. 63–114.
and T.J. Clark (two in French, one each in German 3. ������������������������������������
My favourite example: misprision of procès sans sujet
as ‘trial without a subject’ (Althusserian equivalent, per-
and Italian) are not much better served. Remarkably,
haps, of Kafka’s trial without an object).
in view of the stature and size of his oeuvre, Fredric 4. ���������������������������������������������������
Debord, Gorz, Lefebvre, Mandel and Sartre have, of
Jameson can only muster three titles in French, three course also been extensively translated by publishers
in German, two in Italian and four in Spanish. Perry other than Verso. Badiou’s most important works trans-
lated so far have appeared with Continuum (Theoretical
Anderson, Terry Eagleton and David Harvey are done Writings, trans. R. Brassier and A. Toscano, 2004; Being
something approaching justice. (Anderson rates six and Event [1988], trans. Oliver Feltham, 2005; The Logic
in French, five in German, five in Italian and seven of Worlds [2006], trans. A. Toscano, forthcoming 2009)
in Spanish; while the respective totals for Eagleton and SUNY (Manifesto for Philosophy [1989], 1999);
Rancière’s have appeared with US university presses
are one, seven, three and eight; and for Harvey zero, (The Ignorant Schoolmaster [1987], trans. Kristin Ross,
three, four and five.) The best recent performer is Stanford University Press, 1991; The Names of History
Mike Davis, much of whose work since the mid-1980s [1992], trans. Hassan Melehy, Minnesota University
Press, 1994; Disagreement [1995], trans. Julie Rose,
has made it into French (five), German (six) and
Minnesota University Press, 1999).
Italian (six), but rather less so into Spanish (two). 5. E.J. Hobsbawm, ed., The History of Marxism, Volume
Paradoxically or not, with the retirement of François I: Marxism in Marx’s Day [1978], Harvester Press,
Maspero in the early 1980s and the conversion of his Brighton, 1982.
6. Giuseppe Boffa, The Stalin Phenomenon [1982], trans.
house into La Découverte, the publishing culture most Nicholas Fersen, Cornell University Press, Ithaca NY,
resistant to contemporary Anglo-Marxism is the one 1992. Giuliano Procacci 1970, History of the Ital-
that has enjoyed the greatest attention from it: the ian People [1968], trans. Anthony Paul, Weidenfeld,
Gallic. Five of the Anderson titles in French date from London, 1970. Paolo Spriano, The Occupation of the
Factories: Italy 1920 [1973], trans. Gwyn A. Williams,
the 1960s and 1970s; the sixth, three decades later, is Pluto Press, London, 1975; Antonio Gramsci and the
a long essay on the Hexagon itself. Brenner, Harvey, Party: The Prison Years [1977], trans. John Fraser,
Wood and Wright are so many unknowns in Paris; Lawrence & Wishart, London, 1979; Stalin and the
European Communists [1983], trans. Jon Rothschild,
Clark, Eagleton and Jameson scarcely less so. (A straw
Verso, London, 1985.
in the wind? The three relevant Jameson titles appeared 7. �����������������������������������������������������
Amends are due to be made with I.B. Tauris’s publica-
in French more or less simultaneously, as recently as tion of Agosti’s biography of Palmiro Togliatti: Aldo
autumn 2007.) Even Hobsbawm has faced trials and Agosti, Palmiro Togliatti: A Biography [1996], I.B.
Tauris, London and New York, 2008.
tribulations outre-Manche, where Age of Extremes 8. For a brief English introduction to the work of Losurdo,
was only finally translated under the joint auspices of see Peter Thomas, ‘Historicizing Nietzsche’, New Left
a Belgian publisher and Le Monde diplomatique. Review II/31, January–February 2005, pp. 137–44.

36
Select bibliography of translations York: Random House.
——— 1981 [1979], Teachers, Writers, Celebrities: The Intel-
Althusser, Louis, 1969/1977 [1966], For Marx, trans. Ben lectuals of Modern France, trans. David Macey, London:
Brewster, London: Allen Lane/New Left Books. Verso.
——— 1971, Lenin and Philosophy and Other Essays, trans. ——— 1983 [1981], Critique of Political Reason, trans. David
Ben Brewster, London: New Left Books. Macey, London: Verso.
——— 1972, Montesquieu, Rousseau, Marx, trans. Ben Brews- ——— 1996 [1994], Media Manifestos: On the Technologi-
ter, London: New Left Books. cal Transmission of Cultural Forms, trans. Eric Rauth,
——— 1990, Philosophy and the Spontaneous Philosophy of London: Verso.
the Scientists & Other Essays, ed. Gregory Elliott and ——— 2007 [1996], Praised Be Our Lords: The Autobiogra-
trans. Ben Brewster et al., London: Verso. phy, trans. John Howe, London: Verso.
——— 1997 [1994], The Spectre of Hegel: Early Writings, ed. Della Volpe, Galvano, 1978a [1964], Rousseau and Marx
François Matheron and trans. G.M. Goshgarian, London: and Other Writings, trans. John Fraser, London: Lawrence
Verso. & Wishart.
——— 1999 [1995], Machiavelli and Us, ed. François Math- ——— 1978b [1960], Critique of Taste, trans. Michael Caesar,
eron, trans. Gregory Elliott, London: Verso. London: New Left Books.
——— 2003, The Humanist Controversy and Other Writings, ——— 1980 [1950], Logic as a Positive Science, trans. Jon
ed. François Matheron, trans. G.M. Goshgarian, London: Rothschild, London: New Left Books.
Verso. Duménil, Gérard, and Dominique Lévy, 1993, The Econom-
——— 2006, Philosophy of the Encounter: Later Writings, ics of the Profit Rate: Competition, Crises, and Historical
1978–1987, ed. François Matheron, trans. G.M. Gosh­ Tendencies in Capitalism, Aldershot: Edward Elgar.
garian, London: Verso. ——— 2004 [2000], Capital Resurgent: Roots of the Neo-
Altvater, Elmar, 1993 [1991], The Future of the Market: An liberal Revolution, trans. Derek Jeffers, Cambridge MA:
Essay on the Regulation of Money and Nature after the Harvard University Press.
Collapse of ‘Actually Existing Socialism’, trans. Patrick Dussel, Enrique 1981 [1974], A History of the Church in
Camiller, London: Verso. Latin America: Colonialism to Liberation (1492–1979),
Bensaïd, Daniel, 2002 [1995], Marx for Our Times: Adven- trans. Alan Neeley, Grand Rapids MI: Eerdmans.
tures and Misadventures of a Critique, trans. Gregory ——— 1985 [1980], Philosophy of Liberation, trans. Aquilina
Elliott, London: Verso. Martinez and Christine Morkovsky, Maryknoll NY: Orbis
Bidet, Jacques, 2007 [1984] Exploring Marx’s ‘Capital’: Books.
Philosophical, Economic and Political Dimensions, trans. ——— 1988, Ethics and Community, trans. Robert R. Barr,
David Fernbach, Leiden: Brill. Maryknoll NY: Orbis Books.
Bois, Guy, 1984 [1976], The Crisis of Feudalism: Economy ——— 1995 [1992], The Invention of the Americas: Eclipse
and Society in Eastern Normandy c. 1300–1550, Cam- of ‘The Other’ and the Myth of Modernity, trans. Michael
bridge: Cambridge University Press. D. Barber, New York: Continuum.
——— 1992 [1989] The Transformation of the Year One ——— 1996, The Underside of Modernity: Apel, Ricoeur,
Thousand: The Village of Lournand from Antiquity to Rorty, Taylor, and the Philosophy of Liberation, ed. and
Feudalism, trans. Jean Birrell, Manchester: Manchester trans. Eduardo Mendietta, Atlantic Highlands NJ: Hu-
University Press. manities Press.
Canfora, Luciano, 1989 [1988], The Vanished Library: A ——— 2001 [1985], Towards an Unknown Marx: A Commen-
Wonder of the Ancient World, trans. Martin Ryle, London: tary on the Manuscripts of 1861–63, ed. Fred Moseley,
Hutchinson Radius. trans. Yolanda Angulo, London: Routledge.
——— 2006 [2004], Democracy in Europe: History of an ——— 2003, Beyond Philosophy: Ethics, History, Marxism,
Ideology, trans. Simon Jones, Oxford: Blackwell. and Liberation Theology, ed. Eduardo Mendietta, Lan-
——— 2007 [1999], Julius Caesar: The People’s Dictator, ham: Rowman & Littlefield.
trans. Marian Hill and Kevin Whindle, Edinburgh: Edin- Gerratana, Valentino, 1973, ‘Marx and Darwin’, New Left
burgh University Press. Review I/82: 60–82.
Claudin, Fernando 1975 [1970], The Communist Movement ——— 1977a, ‘Althusser and Stalinism’, trans. Patrick Camill-
From Comintern to Cominform, trans. Brian Pearce and er, New Left Review I/101–102: 110–21.
Francis MacDonagh, New York and London: Monthly ——— 1977b, ‘Stalin, Lenin and “Leninism”’, trans. Patrick
Review Press. Camiller, New Left Review I/103: 59–71.
——— 1978 [1977], Eurocommunism and Socialism, London: ——— 1977c, ‘Heidegger and Marx’, trans. Kate Soper, New
New Left Books. Left Review I/106: 51–8.
Colletti, Lucio, 1972 [1969], From Rousseau to Lenin: Stud- ——— 1978, ‘The Citizen of Geneva and the Seigneur of Fer-
ies in Ideology and Society, trans. John Merrington and ney’, trans. Kate Soper, New Left Review, I/111: 62–72.
Judith White, London: New Left Books. Gerstenberger, Heide, 2007 [1990], Impersonal Power:
——— 1973 [1969], Marxism and Hegel, trans. Lawrence History and Theory of the Bourgeois State, trans. David
Garner, London: New Left Books. Fernbach, Leiden: Brill Academic Publishers.
Debray, Régis, 1967, Revolution in the Revolution? Armed Geymonat, Ludovico, 1965 [1957], Galileo Galilei: A Biog-
Struggle and Political Struggle in Latin America, trans. raphy and Inquiry into his Philosophy of Science, trans.
Bobbye Ortiz, Harmondsworth: Penguin. Stillman Drake, New York: McGraw-Hill.
——— 1970, Strategy for Revolution, London: Jonathan Gilly, Adofo, 1983 [1971], The Mexican Revolution, trans.
Cape. Patrick Camiller, London: Verso.
——— 1971, Conversations with Allende, trans. Ben Brewster, Godelier, Maurice, 1972 [1966], Rationality and Irrational-
London: New Left Books. ity in Economics, trans. Brian Pearce, London: New Left
——— 1973, Prison Writings, trans. Rosemary Sheed, New Books.

37
——— 1977 [1973], Perspectives in Marxist Anthropology, Left Books.
trans. Robert Brain, Cambridge: Cambridge University ——— 1981, The Politics of Combined and Uneven Develop-
Press. ment: The Theory of Permanent Revolution, London:
——— 1986a, The Making of Great Men: Male Domination Verso.
and Power among the New Guinea Baruya, trans. Rupert ——— 1992 [1988], Redemption and Utopia: Jewish Liber-
Swyer, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. tarian Thought in Central Europe – A Study in Elective
——— 1986b [1984], The Mental and the Material: Thought, Affinity, trans. Hope Heaney, Stanford: Stanford Univer-
Economy and Society, trans. Martin Thom, London: sity Press.
Verso. ——— 1993, On Changing the World: Essays in Political
——— 1999 [1996], The Enigma of the Gift, trans. Nora Scott, Philosophy from Karl Marx to Walter Benjamin, Atlantic
Cambridge: Polity Press. Highlands NJ: Humanities Press.
Gorz, André, 1973 [1967], Socialism and Revolution, trans. ——— 1998, Fatherland or Mother Earth? Essays on the
Norman Denny, New York: Doubleday. National Question, London: Pluto Press.
——— 1982 [1980], Farewell to the Working Class: An Essay ——— 2003 [1970], The Theory of Revolution in the Young
in Postindustrial Socialism, trans. Michael Sonenscher, Marx, Leiden: Brill.
London: Pluto. ——— 2005 [2001], Fire Alarm: Reading Walter Benjamin’s
——— 1989a [1988], Critique of Economic Reason, trans. ‘On the Concept of History’, trans. Chris Turner, London:
Gillian Handyside and Chris Turner, London: Verso. Verso.
——— 1989b [1959], The Traitor, trans. Richard Howard, Macherey, Pierre, 1998, In a Materialist Way: Selected
London: Verso. Essays, ed. Warren Montag, trans. Ted Stolze, London:
——— 1994 [1991], Capitalism, Socialism, Ecology, trans. Verso.
Chris Turner, London: Verso. Magri, Lucio, 1969, ‘The May Events and Revolution in the
Harnecker, Marta, 1987 [1985], Fidel Castro’s Political West’, trans. Chiara Ingrao and Chris Gilmore, in Social-
Strategy: From Moncada to Victory, trans. Margarita ist Register 1969, ed. Ralph Miliband and John Saville,
Zimmer­man, New York: Pathfinder Press. London: Merlin Press.
——— 2007 [1999], Rebuilding the Left, trans. Janet Duck- ——— 1970, ‘Problems of the Marxist Theory of the Revolu-
worth, London: Zed Books. tionary Party’, New Left Review I/60: 97–128.
Haug, Frigga, et al., 1987 [1980], Female Sexualization: A ——— 1971, ‘Italian Communism in the Sixties’, New Left
Collective Work of Memory, trans. Eric Carter, London: Review I/66: 37–52.
Verso. ——— 1982, ‘The Peace Movement and European Socialism’,
——— 1992, Beyond Female Masochism: Memory-Work and New Left Review I/131: 5–19.
Politics, trans. Rodney Livingstone, London: Verso. ——— 1991, ‘The European Left between Crisis and Refoun-
Haug, Wolfgang Fritz, 1986 [1983], Critique of Com­modity dation’, New Left Review I/189: 5–18.
Aesthetics: Appearance, Sexuality and Advertising in ——— 1995, ‘The Resistible Rise of the Italian Right’, trans.
Capitalist Society, trans. Richard Bock, Minneapolis: Elena Lledó, New Left Review I/214: 125–33.
University of Minnesota Press. ——— 2005 [2004], ‘Parting Words’, trans. Alan O’Leary,
——— 1987, Commodity Aesthetics, Ideology and Culture, New Left Review II/31: 93–105.
New York: International General. ——— 2008, ‘The Tailor of Ulm’, New Left Review II/51:
Labica, Georges, 1980 [1976], Marxism and the Status of 47–62.
Philosophy, trans. Kate Soper and Martin Ryle, Brighton: Mandel, Ernest, 1978a [1972] Late Capitalism, trans. Joris
Harvester Press. de Bres, London: Verso.
Laclau, Ernesto, 1977, Politics and Ideology in Marxist ——— 1989, Beyond Perestroika: The Future of Gorbachev’s
Theory, London: Verso. USSR, trans. Gus Fagan, London: Verso.
Lefebvre, Henri, 1971/1984 [1968], Everyday Life in the ——— 1995 [1992], Trotsky as Alternative, trans. Gus Fagan,
Modern World, trans. Sacha Rabinovitch, New York: London: Verso.
Harper & Row/Transaction. Negri, Antonio, 1988, Revolution Retrieved: Writings on
——— 1991a [1947], Critique of Everyday Life, Volume One: Marx, Keynes, Capitalist Crisis and New Social Subjects
Introduction, trans. John Moore, London: Verso. (1967–83), London: Red Notes.
——— 1991b [1974], The Production of Space, trans. Donald ——— 1991a [1979], Marx beyond Marx: Lessons on the
Nicholson-Smith, Oxford: Blackwell. Grundrisse, ed. Jim Fleming and trans. Harry Cleaver et
——— 2002 [1961], Critique of Everyday Life, Volume Two: al., London: Pluto Press.
Foundations for a Sociology of the Everyday, trans. John ——— 1991b [1981], The Savage Anomaly: The Power of
Moore, London: Verso. Spinoza’s Metaphysics and Politics, trans. Michael Hardt,
——— 2003 [1970], The Urban Revolution, trans. Robert Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Bononno, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. ——— 1999 [1992], Insurgencies: Constituent Power and
——— 2005 [1981], Critique of Everyday Life, Volume Three: the Modern State, trans. Maurizia Boscagli, Minneapolis:
From Modernity to Modernism (Towards a Metaphilosophy University of Minnesota Press.
of Daily Life), trans. Gregory Elliott, London: Verso. ——— 2003, Time for Revolution, trans. Matteo Mandarini,
Losurdo, Domenico 2001 [1991], Heidegger and the Ide- New York and London: Continuum.
ology of War: Community, Death, and the West, trans. ——— 2004a [1994], Subversive Spinoza: (Un)contemporary
Marella and Jon Morris, Amherst NY: Humanity Books. Variations, trans. Timothy S. Murphy et al., Manchester:
——— 2004 [1992], Hegel and the Freedom of the Moderns, Manchester University Press.
trans. Marella and Jon Morris, Durham NC: Duke Uni- ——— 2004b [2002], Negri on Negri: In Conversation with
versity Press. Anne Dufourmantelle, trans. Malcolm B. DeBevoise, New
Löwy, Michael, 1979 [1976], Georg Lukács – From Romanti- York and London: Routledge.
cism to Bolshevism, trans. Patrick Camiller, London: New ——— 2005a [1988], The Politics of Subversion: A Manifesto

38
for the Twenty-First Century, trans. James Newell, Cam- ——— 1991 [1985], Critique of Dialectical Reason, Volume
bridge: Polity Press. Two: The Intelligibility of History, ed. Arlette Elkaïm-
——— 2005b [1997], Books for Burning: Between Civil War Sartre and trans. Quintin Hoare, London: Verso.
and Democracy in 1970s Italy, trans. Arianna Bove et al., ——— 2001 [1964], Colonialism and Neocolonialism, trans.
London: Verso. A. Haddour et al., London and New York: Routledge.
——— 2007 [1970], Political Descartes: Reason, Ideology Schwarz, Roberto, 1992, Misplaced Ideas: Essays on Brazil-
and the Bourgeois Project, trans. Matteo Mandarini and ian Culture, ed. John Gledson, London: Verso.
Alberto Toscano, London: Verso. ——— 2001 [1990], Master on the Periphery of Capitalism:
Negt, Oskar, and Alexander Kluge, 1993 [1972], The Pub- Machado de Assis, trans. John Gledson, Durham NC:
lic Sphere and Experience: Toward an Analysis of the Duke University Press.
Bourgeois and Proletarian Public Sphere, trans. Peter Tafuri, Manfredo, 1976 [1973], Architecture and Utopia:
Labanyi, Jamie Owen and Assenka Oksiloff, Minneapolis: Design and Capitalist Development, trans. Barbara Luigia
University of Minnesota Press. La Penta, Cambridge MA: MIT Press.
Poulantzas, Nicos, 1978 [1978], State, Power, Socialism, Timpanaro, Sebastiano, 1975 [1970], On Materialism, trans.
trans. Patrick Camiller, London: New Left Books. Lawrence Garner, London: New Left Books.
Sader, Emir, and Ken Silverstein, 1991, Without Fear ——— 1976 [1974], The Freudian Slip: Psychoanalysis and
of Being Happy: Lula, the Workers’ Party and Brazil, Textual Criticism, trans. Kate Soper, London: New Left
London: Verso. Books.
Sánchez Vázquez, Adolfo, 1974 [1965], Art and Society: Vovelle, Michel, 1984 [1972], The Fall of the French Mon-
Essays in Marxist Aesthetics, trans. Maro Riofrancos, archy, 1787–1792, trans. Susan Burke, Cambridge: Cam-
London: Merlin Press. bridge University Press.
——— 1977 [1967], The Philosophy of Praxis, trans. Mike ——— 1990 [1982], Ideologies and Mentalities, trans. Eamon
Gonzalez, London: Merlin Press. O’Flaherty, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Sartre, Jean-Paul, 1963 [1960], Search for a Method, trans. ——— 1991 [1988], The Revolution against the Church: From
Hazel Barnes, Knopf, New York. Reason to the Supreme Being, trans. Alan José, Columbus:
——— 1974 [1972], Between Existentialism and Marxism, Ohio State University Press.
trans. John Matthews, London: New Left Books. Weber, Henri, 1981 [1981], Nicaragua: The Sandinista
——— 1976 [1960], Critique of Dialectical Reason, Volume Revolution, trans. Patrick Camiller, London: New Left
One: Theory of Practical Ensembles, trans. Alan Sheridan- Books.
Smith, London: New Left Books.

new from zone books

The Civil Contract of Photography


BY ARIELLA AZOULAY

This book compellingly rethinks the political and ethical status of


photography, revising our understanding of the power relations that
sustain and make possible photographic meanings. The crucial arguments
of the book concern two groups whose vulnerability and ßawed citizen-
ship have been rendered invisible due to their state of exception: the
Palestinian noncitizens of Israel and women in Western societies.
Essential reading for anyone seeking to understand how the disasters of
recent history and their victims have been represented, the book charts
new intellectual and political pathways in an unprecedented exploration
of the visual Þeld of catastrophe, injustice, and suffering in our time.
£25.95/$39.95 hardcover; 585 pp; 109 b&w, 10 color illus.; 6 x 9; ISBN 978-1-890951-88-7

Zone Books are available at all Þne bookstores or directly from The MIT Press, our distributor.
To order from the UK or continental Europe, please call 44 (0) 1243 779777 or email cs-books@
wiley.co.uk. To order from North America, please call 1-800-405-1619 or email orders@triliteral.org.
Online at www.zonebooks.org.

39
Introduction to Rozitchner

L
eón Rozitchner is one of the generation of Argentine intellectuals who emerged in the
1950s around the journal Contorno. As a psychoanalyst and Marxist – and massively
influenced, as were all his confrères, by Sartre and the phenomenological tradition
– he undertook a lengthy theoretical project that attempted to engage psychoanalytical categ­
ories in the understanding of politics, most notably in explaining and countering that most
protean and influential phenomenon of Argentine politics, Peronism – the baleful legacy
of Juan Domingo Perón himself, and its links to the catastrophic dictatorship of 1976–83.
From the seminal Freud and the Limits of Bourgeois Individualism (first edition 1972), in
which he developed an account of the relation of psyche and capital, and the revolutionary
implications of Freud’s supposedly ‘conservative’ social works, to the recent The Thing
and the Cross (1997), in which he explores the archaeology of capitalism in Augustinian
Christianity, Rozitchner has laboured to provide a categorial apparatus that links libido,
leadership and economic form. But he has also been a prolific writer on the conjuncture,
intervening for fifty years in debates on the Left across the continent. As a committed
supporter of the Cuban Revolution, he lived in Havana during the early years, where, on
the basis of interviews with captured Bay of Pigs invaders, he produced his important
analysis of bourgeois morality, Bourgeois Morality and Revolution (1963) – the basis of the
dilemmas addressed in Tomás Gutiérrez Alea’s film Memories of Underdevelopment (1968).
During the Argentine Junta’s period of power, the so-called Proceso or Process of National
Reorganization, he lived in Venezuela. Never a popular intellectual, always prepared fiercely
to oppose leftist pieties, he remains – now in his eighties – an imposing but strangely
ignored figure of the Latin American Left, almost completely unknown in the English-
speaking world, to the latter’s detriment.
‘Exile, War and Democracy’ was originally presented at a conference in 1984 on the
reconstruction of Argentine political culture after the dictatorship had allowed the return
of democracy (‘the Pact’) with the election of Raúl Alfonsín in 1983. As well as giving a
flavour of the textual quality of his work and his attentive but cutting style of commentary,
it develops some of the themes he discussed in his 1979 book on Perón, Perón – Between
Blood and Time, in which Marx, Freud and Clausewitz are combined to form a framework
of articulation. But perhaps what is most striking is his passionate denunciation of left-
Peronist and leftist fantasies that were in some ways complicit with or tributary to the
political debacles of the Process. This is the context for his harsh criticisms of Rodolfo
Puiggrós, a well-known sociologist (one of the first to criticize the work of Andre Gunder
Frank from a Marxist perspective) and member of the Argentine Communist Party, who
had migrated to Peronism to become part of its ideological apparatus. Almost alone in the
Argentine Left, Rozitchner opposed the Gadarene rush to support the Malvinas/Falklands
adventure, seeing this capture of the oppositional energy of the Left by the Junta’s irre-
dentist nationalism as a stunning defeat. Some of the key intellectuals involved in such
support, like José Aricó and Juan Carlos Portantiero, who had been exiled in Mexico, were
present at the conference Rozitchner addresses here. Rozitchner’s book Las Malvinas: de la
guerra sucia a la guerra limpia (1985) also raises interesting questions for those of us who
opposed the Thatcherite ‘recovery’ of the Falklands.

Philip Derbyshire and John Kraniauskas

40 Radical Philosophy 152 (November/December 20 08)


Exile, war and democracy
An exemplary sequence

León Rozitchner

The question we want to pose is this: how do we open of naked force, offensive war, the primacy of the war
up a field of democratic politics as we emerge from leader – the soldier become politician – as fundamental
terror and war? even in conditions of political peace. The central cat-
In my exposition I will start where the previous egory that regulates this project is the global concept
speaker, Feinemann, left off as he endorsed the of the ‘nation in arms’. These categories – impossible
categories that Perón had taken from Clausewitz to to develop in a dependent country – were the same
move from the discussion of war to that of political ones that Perón applied to the political field. This was
leadership. My analysis, which is at the same time a his ‘originality’. Clearly, however, it was impossible
response, tries to offer a different analysis of the space to think of true national liberation from within such a
of tolerance emerging as war disappears and politics conception of war, as the minds of our military were
appears and with it democracy. But in contrast to the governed by the categories of the enemy. Since it
formulations offered by Feinmann, my starting point was impossible for the military to assert control over
keeps in mind the category of war as a foundation external territory, they could only assert domination
from which to think and perhaps to understand the over what was internal to their own nation. They thus
problem of politics. asserted domination over their own people. This is
where General Perón applies the categories of war
The pre-eminence of the categories to the field of politics, so the latter becomes a field
of war in Perón’s politics of simulated confrontation, a pure representation of
The conception of war and politics that Feinemann a conflict of forces that is in fact avoided. Politics, in
finds in Clausewitz is the same as that developed by other words, is developed as if it were war, suggesting
General Perón. In a book that was the fruit of lectures a radical confrontation. But this very conception was
given in the Consejo Superior de Guerra, and which instrumental in the failure of the popular movement.
was later extensively used by the Peronist Left and the Terror was its culmination, along with the murder of
Montoneros (some of its chapters being re-edited and the very people who though ignorant of the origins of
published in Peronist political journals), Perón devel- this conception of politics in Perón’s misapplication of
oped his theory of war, following the interpretation Clausewitz, nevertheless constituted themselves as his
of Clausewitz that the French and German colonialist followers, saying: ‘we are Perón’s tactics’; the ‘armed
military (from Dudeldorf to Marshall Foch) had put wing’ of the Peronist body, they were subsequently
forward. He thus appropriated the categories used by snapped off by the General himself.
the most aggressively reactionary European military: Let us begin, then, by posing our problem from
these figures thought of war as a process of internal another point of view, offering a critique of the cat-
domination over their own people and as the external egories of war as developed by Perón and the Right,
conquest of foreign territories through which they and looking at them again in the light of how they
could expand the domain of their own nation. These emerge in Clausewitz.
categories were: the war of annihilation, the imposition
The double concept of war and politics
 Juan Pablo Feinemann is a historian and sociologist.
One of Feinemann’s first mistakes in his exposition of
 The Montoneros were the armed wing of the Peronist Youth, Clausewitz is the following: in Clausewitz there is not
annihilated along with the other guerrilla groupuscules in the early
years of the military terror. one theory of war but two, something Perón also failed

Radical Philosophy 152 (November/December 20 08) 41


to see. The first theory of war, a purely ‘objective’ one, War as illusion: the negation of politics as
which both the Right and Perón leaned on, is a ‘monist’ truce
theory that starts from an individualist conception, Clausewitz criticizes the illusory, purely imaginary,
centred fundamentally on the annihilation of the adver- daydream-like character of the first theory of war that
sary, the escalation of the conflict to extremes and the posits the end of war as the annihilation of the enemy
predominance of war over politics. Even Clausewitz through a presumed escalation of the conflict to its
criticized this as a ‘logical fantasy’, a spawn of the extremes. This illusory field is associated with the
imagination, because it began by conceiving war as a overbearing mentality of the military in the dominant
‘duel’ centred on the drives of an individual body and countries, who cannot conceive of a defensive, popular
ignoring the powerful energies of the collective body force, not just physical and technological but, above all,
of the people. moral. This force is also material, albeit with a mate-
There is a second theory of war, critical of the riality the colonialist military are ignorant of. Hence
former, and constituted as an account of a ‘wonder- the critique of war of annihilation: the people cannot
ful trinity’. This theory takes into account both the be annihilated. There is thus no final and definitive
appearance of new popular forces and the advance destruction of the enemy while there is resistance.
of the Napoleonic army which transformed the whole And if there is no annihilation, every war results
military horizon of the French Revolution, on the one in a truce, in the opening up of a political dimension.
hand, and the undefeated resistance of the Spanish Politics, there from the beginning, may seem to have
guerrilla war against those forces, on the other. It is disappeared in the deafening clamour of war, but it re-
this new experience that Clausewitz had to integrate emerges and reveals itself again at war’s end. The truce
into his theory of war. The ‘wonderful trinity’ is the at the end of the war implies that both attacker and
basis of every war and comprises: (1) the ‘natural’ defender have come to an equilibrium. This is because,
impulse of the people, which Clausewitz considers as despite appearances, equilibrium is not simply decided
a ‘blind’, merely natural force; (2) intelligence, which by the attacker. It signals rather the appearance of a
resides in the political cabinet and consists of the fundamental asymmetry between the attacker and the
right-thinking rationality of politics in war, which the defender, which is what leads to the truce and hence
people lack; and (3) the war leader, who articulates the the definition of peace. The fact is that although the
blind drives of the people with the forms of rationality attacker may be stronger on the offensive, the defender
elaborated by the cabinet and gives them soul and can be stronger on the defensive: they are of a different
will to integrate and push them forward. This second nature and of unequal force. And it is this fact – that
conception of war is radically different from the first. there are two different forces in confrontation – which
Clausewitz formulates it on the basis of defensive opens up the space of equilibrium we call truce, and
rather than offensive war – that is, from the perspective which is, in reality, the opening up of a political field
of a nation that is defending itself from an enemy that where war is continued by other means. Politics opens
is trying to occupy or has already occupied it. In other up as peace (a truce) between two wars: the one it
words, he transforms the categories of the powerful emerges from and the one it moves towards.
and colonizing, dominant force and reverses their It is obvious that Clausewitz is referring to war
perspective: how may its domination be confronted between nations and not to the confrontation of forces
and opposed from within one’s own nation? This leads within a single nation, as is the case with revolutionary
Clausewitz to recognize the predominance of so-called wars. His conception is important because it excludes
‘negative’ objectives over ‘positive’ ones. The colonizer the commonsensical appearance that separates politics
and conqueror, the forces attacking and attempting to from war, as if it were a matter of a radical or essential
occupy a foreign territory, have a ‘positive’ objective: opposition: we are in both, although we do not want
conquest. From the perspective of defence, and thus the to be. Because when Clausewitz tells us that ‘war is
defence of one’s own national territory – the position of just the continuation of the politics of the state by
every dependent country – positive objectives acquire other means’, he means both are politics. It is also
a different nuance: they simply become the attempt to true that there is a fundamental difference between
preserve what the powerful want to seize from us by the armed confrontation to the death of war, and the
force. In the face of pillage and aggression, we define peaceful truce of politics. But what is at issue in the
defence against an aggressor as ‘negative’. From this essence of the phenomenon that defines conflict is in
perspective, Clausewitz criticizes the first theory of reality an appearance if we do not keep sight of the
war – the one Perón defends. fact that politics is about the reorganization of forces.

42
Forgetting this could have fatal consequences for those resists this alien incursion and offers resistance and
who engage in the political field as if it were in reality defence on the ground. War begins with confrontation
– pure appearance of peace and not of truce – a formal and ends with a truce: not even the enemy’s surrender
field, a juridical pact and not an effective material field entails the end of the conflict. What opens up here is
where the struggle continues to develop, only here too the field of another resistance, politics, in which what
‘by other means’. This is what we are now seeing. As the war had not managed to settle continues to be
we emerge from terror and the unpunished domination elaborated, by other means. If there is no annihilation
of the military over the whole nation, it would appear – only the nuclear bomb promises that – it means that
that we are required to think this new political space the defeated enemy carries on with that peculiar and
that has been opened up from a formal, purely juridical specific force that resists annihilation. At some level,
angle that is radically opposed to any reference to the at the point where the war stopped, the attacker (and,
development of our own (defensive) forces. This is perhaps, victor) is stronger on the offensive, but the
because we continue to think with the categories of the one who resists is stronger in defence. The truce is the
forces that are on the offensive rather than with those point at which force, on its own, can do no more: here
on the defensive: with the simple concept of offensive violence ceases, and the new sphere of politics opens
physical force rather than from the perspective of that up in which the suspended conflict will continue to
other force which is stronger in defence. develop. The conception of politics and war held by
Peronist (and some non-Peronist) groups was shaped
The Right’s categories of war on the Left by a conception of the popular forces and armed
I think that this has been the consequence of thinking confrontation that General Perón had imposed through
politics and war with the categories of the Right and his interpretation of war and politics. And it is these
the Colonizer. As the political and military model for categories that prevent the appearance, constitution and
the Left, furthermore, it preceded the appearance of development of a new force in the space opened up by
terror. I also believe that it was a consequence of the the current truce – that is, in the new democracy that
way Perón deployed the apparent schema of radical followed the military terror.
confrontation in Argentina, taking under his power
(and organizing as his own) the forces that in reality The new force
he wished to contain and split – those of the workers What is required is that we set out the preconditions
– leading them to failure, destruction and to the death of this new force so that in our restored democracy
of so many of his followers. It was Perón who posed it is not tyrannized by a false choice: pure politics
the problem in terms of the categories of war: a or pure war. By this I mean that we do not posit a
simulated war that, as politics, deprived the people of purely formal politics, subject exclusively to a juridical
the material and moral bases on which any real con- schematism, which leaves out of consideration the new
frontation must be based. Because the truth is that he materiality and the new morality (and morale) that have
did everything necessary in this confrontation to strip to be created. I think that if we occlude the problem
the popular classes of their effective power and leave of the war from which the field of politics opened up
them disarmed, even though they appeared to have a we are condemned once more to the illusion of peace,
force, which ideologically, materially and morally they a peace that obscures the fact of violence and death
had been deprived of. on which it rests. We will also be condemned to shock
and surprise should terror erupt again, because we will
The popular forces are powerful have failed to recognize the depth of the enemy and his
on the defensive real force. We must recognize that in democracy, that
Hence our interest in taking up this problem again, is to say in truce, we need our own force to confront
but from a political position that does not move in the and contain the enemy. And the forceless formalism of
realm of appearance and does not exclude what is spe- Alfonsín’s Radical Party is insufficient for this task.
cific to each of the forces concerned. What is at issue In reality, politics is a field that opens up after a
in war is the following: paradoxically, the attacker, prior war – whether a long time in the past or not. And
the one on the offensive, does not want war. The it then appears as the result of a prior confrontation to
invader would prefer to take over the enemy terrain the death. Confrontation in war, we have seen, opens
peacefully, make the enemy give up the will to resist, up a site of transaction and formalized reconciliation
dominate him, and thus achieve the ‘positive’ object within the juridical field which establishes the new
at the least cost. War only begins when the defender norms that will regulate this confrontation of forces

43
without clear resolution. There are abundant examples tion that the enemy wants and is counting on – because
of this emergence from war. The Latin American it is stronger on the offensive. The irruption of military
national revolutions show clearly how a new juridical force is the limit of democracy. The military forms a
space, that of liberalism, opened up after a prior war. system with the political field that it engendered and
This defined the norms and laws that came to regulate had to expand as it emerged from the war with an
the economic, social and political relations of the area’s external enemy, Britain, that it lost. ‘The dirty war’
inhabitants with each other: a new sharing out of was not a war, but just the unleashing of terror against
power. This juridical field is in reality fenced in by the a disarmed, internal enemy, whose perpetrators have
power of the victor. In the last instance, I insist, there yet to be punished.
will be a reorganization of forces, seemingly in peace,
in order for the crucial confrontation to find another What is peculiar to the force of
attempt at resolution. Politics, once again, does nothing ‘a different nature’ for confronting
more than prepare for this. No one has yielded power military armed force
in peace, and politics is the extreme limit where this
So we are concerned with a force that is different from
transformation of quantity into quality is elaborated.
the merely armed force of military power. The nature
And in saying this we are not just talking in terms of
of this force cannot be perceived if it is considered
physical force, in ‘war’ language. We are talking about
merely as a collective accumulation inscribed in the
that force which is of a different nature to that of the
formal ‘representation’ of politics: it is a matter of
enemy. Only this force can avoid the armed confronta-
a real force. We are not fetishizing the
‘fighter’: the failure of that attitude among
the armed guerrillas is patent and obvious.
What we are saying is that this form of
‘offensive’ war was undertaken accord-
ing to the enemy’s categories, apparatus
against apparatus, military force against
military force. What we want to refer to
here is another force, which has another
materiality and another morality, a force
which is more effective in defence than in
offence. Under the conditions of democ-
racy, only such a power could be real and
different from military power which rests
on nothing more than physical force. But
as yet it can only be invoked, expressed
as a desirable end. Nor is it a question of
our wanting war, and precisely because
we do not want it, we have to reconsider
Daniel Santero, Eva Perón Punishes the Marxist-Leninist Child, 2005.

how to prevent our enemies from resorting


to it. We have constantly to keep in view
the limits of a merely formal approach to
the project of democracy and consider the
character of the truce that led to it, so that
within this new space we can create the
popular force that would consolidate and
conquer its real power in the materiality
that is peculiar to it. If not, I think that
we are going to be faced with another
disappointment in a few years’ time. Even
as we open up the field of democracy, we
will be unable to counteract that shadowy
power that confronts us, which is already,
preparing for our undoing.

44
Beyond illusion everything in the pursuit of a reality and politics
Hence I would like to talk about the responsibility that from another time whose origin they were ignorant
we all have to go beyond the fantasies and illusions of. Puiggrós, among many others, offered a theoretical
that brought us to the current situation. It is not just and historical basis for this new Left: his critique of
an ‘intellectual’ or theoretical problem: it is a ques- the abstract and dependent character of Communist
tion of constructing a different reality and making internationalism led him to stress the specifically
it visible. And in the attempt to learn from our past national content, what was specific and creole (that is,
experience and correct its mistakes and errors, we will Latin American) about our road to socialism. But this
use two examples, two political positions, both with critique of the theory and practice of the Argentine
their ‘before’ and ‘after’, where the mistakes that we Communist Party did not prevent him from remaining
are trying to point out are clearly revealed. The first attached to the same old modality of Stalinism, even
example we will consider is that of Puiggrós. Here if this time it was nationally rooted. The dispersion
we see the passage from Peronism in power (1973) of the social whole and hence the atomization of its
to its expression after the military had imposed their forces – individuals and opposing interests, groups
dictatorship (1977). The second example is the position and levels of reality in which these find themselves
taken on the Malvinas War by the Socialist Discussion dispersed (ideology, history, economy, politics, trade
Group in Mexico (1982) and the subsequent political unions, armed forces) – find their unification in the
positions adopted by two of its members in 1984. The Leader, who must contain and direct them towards
first passage reveals the failure of a political project national socialism:
that had no real moral and material basis, which This dispersion paralyses any tendency for change
finished up in exile. The second reveals how the and shows the lack of a global and realistic con-
fantasy of a war to recover the Malvinas collapsed ception of social and techno-scientific revolutions
and was replaced by the acceptance of democracy in … and manifests itself in the furious opposition to
the leadership that is indispensable to push them
its purely formal aspect, a political field from which
forward.
war would now be excluded and politics would be a
social ‘pact’. Puiggrós thus outlines the key ideas, the two conditions
Perhaps in these examples it is a matter of thinking for the move to socialism:
through the concept of democracy which underlay both
1. A global and realistic conception of socialist revo-
political projects and in both cases led, albeit uncon-
lution that inevitably would have to develop in
sciously, to their failures. In part this was because of
Argentina.
the conception of popular power that these projects
2. The inevitable necessity of the leadership of General
sought to create, a conception that proved to be no
Perón to attain it.
longer viable. What is at issue is the following: what
sort of relation is there between the formal and the The exceptional nature of the moment, the unique-
material, the individual and the collective, the subjec- ness of the opportunity, does not escape him: ‘We
tive and the objective, between what we have now and Argentines are living the decisive moment of our
what we can hope for? What project would carry the history which will mark our destiny for the coming
relation between forces? In short, what is the relation centuries’.
between politics and war, peace and violence? How, In Puiggrós’s conception, whose basic category
then, can force and power be conceived? of the ‘historical dialectic’ is the accentuation of the
nationally particular (which would be the concrete)
First passage: from triumphalist Peronism opposed to the universal (which would be the abstract),
to military terror – Rodolfo Puiggrós the dispersed collective in our reality, so different
In 1972 Rodolfo Puiggrós wrote Where Are We Going, to any other, finds its specific and distinctive unity
Argentines, a book in which he outlines the road by in the human figure of the Leader, Perón, where the
which Argentina under the leadership of General Perón two combine, as a point of departure. The totality in
would arrive at national socialism, and hence the most its dispersion converges in him: hence everyone must
developed form of social democracy. The year 1972 surrender his own self and submit to Perón’s superior
was when Argentine youth were feverishly caught up in leadership. A happy sacrifice of the subjective: ‘Party
Perón’s imminent return: it was also the year when the based liberalism is incompatible with the democracy
guerrilla movement was developing with uncontainable of the working classes’. And this peculiar democracy
intensity. They were prepared to risk and sacrifice is conceived as having

45
A single leadership that would centralise and drive its liberal conception: ‘the freedom of the press has
forward the revolutionary activity of millions of been defined in liberalism as the freedom to publish
Argentines (which) will save us from the great ideas, opinions and news without previous censorship
catastrophe and place us on the threshold of the
and without legal action.’ And he then claims that
vanguard of 21st century humanity.
its ‘transcendence’ has been realized during General
The singleness of leadership means not only that Perón’s government under the direction of his secretary
it does not allow for co-participants but also that it is Apold in the Secretariat of Press and Broadcasting.
that supreme orientation of the interdependent techno- And the so-called pluralism of political parties
scientific revolutions, the union of theory and practice, would also be ‘transcended’ and supplanted by the
the dialectical synthesis of ideology, politics, history, single party:
economics, trade unionism and the armed forces.
Peronism [is] the greatest movement of the masses
Since we want to understand this new force, the ever known in Argentina. Though the antagonism
human foundation of its power, its ‘different nature’, between liberal party politics and revolutionary
it is useful to stress what Puiggrós makes of it. We popular nationalism is still played out in it, it can
thus read his conclusion: it is the integration of the count on the backing of the workers and students
individuals in the Leader that will solve the equation who have chosen the road of the struggle for a so-
cialism that grows from the seeds that already exist
and determine the new meaning of human rights
in their own country.
within the democratic society that transcends the limits
of bourgeois individualism. The single party, then, led by Perón, against the
Puiggrós thus sets himself against the Rights of fragmentation of liberal party politics:
Man and the Citizen. These principles that bourgeois
Never in the history of the nation have the popular
liberalism proclaims in law at the same time as it
masses reached such a level of politicization and
denies them in application in fact are also decisively such clarity about their objectives.
negated by Puiggrós, as if what is stated in them were
a mere mystification. He does not understand that at This politics rejected the Rights of Man as bour-
the juridical level they constitute a historic conquest geois and dissolved the subjugated individuality of
which, distorted in reality, nevertheless remain a goal men into the dictates and leadership of the Leader,
to be attained. On the contrary, forgetting the tension who maintained the appearance of his power on the
and the social conflict that exist between facts and basis of a military and economic structure that was
law, and refusing to inscribe the full application of the antagonistic to him. The corruption of union leaders
Rights of Man as a specific goal for a truly socialist consolidated the apparent power of the masses but
process, Puiggrós contents himself with flatly and limited to a strictly economistic perspective. All this
blithely asserting that they must be ‘transcended’ in constructed an ‘as if’: the fantasy of a real power
Peronism, in fact embedding their negation to the without a moral and material base. Collective organiza-
benefit of a state centralized under the leadership of tion in the service of the leader produced a simulation
General Perón. at the level of politics of preparedness for a real
confrontation, for war, yet without material basis and
The negation of the Rights of Man support. This is why it dissolved at a stroke, without
Puiggrós considers ‘individual freedom’ as an abstrac- resistance to the military coup which began and found
tion and mystification. With the rule of the strong state, support inside the ranks of Peronism itself. Thus
the mendacious idea appears that ‘all men are free by Peronism culminates in terror against its own forces,
nature’ and ‘free through the rule of law’, as if this encouraged by General Perón.
idea of freedom were not the expression of a historical But what is at issue for us, as we said at the outset,
struggle and the juridical reassertion of a conquest yet is the creation of a real force in the sphere of politics
to be achieved: the historical struggle is about the shift that would not leave the popular classes disarmed
from purely formal to material validity. And he accepts and defeated in the face of its enemies’ political and
its ‘transcendence’ – its negation – in the Peronist state. military offensive. It is a question of a real power not a
Individual freedom, negated in its effective essence by fantasized one, an apparent one, a mere representation
liberalism, becomes unnecessary and dispensable in that in reality is impotent both to resolve the conflict
the organization of the centralized state. of interests in the field of politics and to prevent
The same thing happens with the ‘freedom of the the emergence of idealist solutions to an unequal
press’, which Peronism would claim to carry beyond confrontation.

46
Outcome and verification impulse directed by the Leader now yields the real and
In 1977, when he was already in exile, Puiggrós pub- effective meaning of its limit: a means to put pressure
lished his confession and recantation. Here he negated on Perón’s enemies, without its own force:
everything that he had previously adored. He reveals Perón’s task was to stick the masses together. Why
the real basis of the fantasy and illusions that had been did Perón fall? What collapsed was Peronism.
nurtured in those young people who had believed in the
power that their fathers and the intellectuals had taught He enumerates the forces that continued to command
them to extol and had put forward as an alternative, as Peronist social reality, persisting in their own power
though there were a real revolution at stake. without being effectively opposed:
In an interview that appeared in The Argentine Perón’s politics towards the military was not one
Case, published in Mexico in 1977, the writer who had of ideological capture given there was no coherent
previously demanded the univocal leadership of the ideology. It was a politics of bribes and privileges.
Leader confesses. Not only does he explain how Perón Instead of tying the military, it corrupted them.
conquered the workers’ organizations from his base in
And the same thing happened with the leadership of
the military but also how he replaced their Marxist and
the workers:
leftist leadership, granting by gift of power what had
previously been the result of a hard social struggle. The leading organization of the workers’ movement
On the basis of his power, Perón dictated the resolu- the CGT [General Confederation of Workers] was
formed with groups of parvenus and people on the
tion of industrial conflicts and strikes, using the threat
make who got rich. Obviously they gave some-
of military intervention on behalf of the workers:
thing to the workers, at the same time as they were
The strike is won like this and the Communist Peter getting rich themselves and reaching an accommo-
is replaced by Colonel Perón. This happened in all dation with the government, or they wouldn’t have
the trade unions and explains how in a short time, been leaders.
weeks or days, the Argentine workers’ movement is
transformed. The old leaders, with years of struggle And Puiggrós’s judgement of Perón contrasts with
like Peter himself, are replaced by new ones who his previous conviction, put forward only a few years
have no idea what socialism or any sort of social before. But he knew all this before:
change is about, but who are very conscious of the
need to raise the standard of living of the workers. Perón was enormously opportunistic.
In this way, the Peronism of Perón and Evita is Now Perón got entangled. In 1946 he could harmo-
a movement born without its own ideology, it is nise many sectors, but in 1973 he wanted to be on
pragmatist. good terms with God and the Devil.
Perón was tied up against it. There are aspects of
Perón had no precursors, preparation or knowledge
his psychology and private life which have a great
of social struggles. He was ambitious but not in the deal of importance here.
pejorative sense.
Perón had come to power conditioned by a series of
What Puiggrós had previously held to be the basis contrasting ideologies and interests.
of revolutionary and socialist drive, he now confesses
to be the original sources of failure, something hidden And so, speaking from exile and failure, the very
in the mythical account of Peronist history. people who knew the falsity and weakness of the
project they had justified to the youth of Argentina
The problem for the Peronist masses was not social
transformation … It was a heterogeneous move-
confess to its and their own inadequacies. Yet even
ment. In it there were Nazis, right wing nationalists, as they recognize how this weakness and distorted
liberal nationalists – reformists, socialists and com- content had alienated the Peronist workers from their
munists like us. All this was mixed up. And Perón own interests, and therefore deprived them of a real
was always conscious that this heterogeneity of his and effective sense of their force, the Peronist guerrilla
movement was his major weakness. But he knew
movement still finds endorsement:
how to overcome it thanks to the growth in the
economy in the nation during this period. Greater Young students and many professionals slowly
income improved the situation of the workers as came closer to and were won by Peronism. This
well as profits of the bosses. is how the first armed, popular [!] movements
emerged, clumsily like everything always happens:
And Perón – Puiggrós adds – never allowed the masses full of gaps, without experience … The Monton-
in practice to be more than a means of pressure. What eros emerged from Catholic nationalism. Eventually
had previously been the foundation of the revolutionary they arrived at Marxism … But with a little spirit

47
of struggle, perhaps unconsciously these groups triumphalist euphoria (1972) and the cruel confirma-
slowly matured until they came to support national tion of failure in the face of the terror imposed by the
socialism. Military Junta (1977) as revealed in Puiggrós. Now we
The problem that worries me here is when Puig- are going to consider the positions taken during the
grós, at the end of this process, has to deal with the Proceso itself, on the occasion of the Malvinas War,
painful experience that meant not only political failure by the Socialist Discussion Group (SDG) formed by
but the terrible and desolate fact of the death of his Argentine exiles living in Mexico (1982) and the new
own son. conception of politics outlined by various members of
the group after the defeat and failure, when democracy
The last time I saw my son was the night in which was reintroduced into Argentina (1984). Here we see
I came here, that is in 1974. We didn’t say goodbye,
the same mechanisms at work in a group of intellectu-
because neither he nor I knew that we were coming
here. He wrote to me, saying: Dad, we won’t see als of the Left. First, reality is covered over, then a
each other again. Another time he wrote a letter to later political position replaces an initial programme in
me in which he said that he was with his comrades which fantasy and illusory solutions were preponder-
but for the first time he felt alone. I tried to imagine ant. But fantasy and illusion are going to reappear,
what was happening: I was in a state of enormous we believe, although now in the contradictory aspects
anxiety, I knew that he was going to his death, but
of conflict and peace, in the new programme for
that he had no other road. He could not give up. I
found out when I got back to Mexico: imagine the democracy.
situation, my only son, 26 years old, he’d been my
secretary. When he told me he was a rebel, what The reasons for supporting the armed
sort of rebel? They had to live their lives, and the ‘recovery’ of the Malvinas
slogan they fought under, was ‘No surrender’. What made it possible for the members of the SDG to
support the recovery of the Islands undertaken by the
Death now shrouds both father and son, but beyond
Military Junta can be found in the following theoreti-
this fact I want to reflect on Puiggrós’s pathetic words
cal assertions formulated in the 1982 document they
as a father, in no way to condemn him but, as a father
published during the war:
myself, to understand the legacy we are bequeathing
our children. ‘I knew that he was going to his death 1. It was necessary to abandon our subjective and
and had no other road’, ‘the slogan they fought under affective experience of the origin of the Junta,
was “No surrender”’. Is this really the way to create as well as the ‘a priori’ rationality that resulted
life or is it simply the glorification of death? And when from our previous political experience, since these
he says ‘No surrender’, we would want to read that were both based on logical fallacies. According to
one should not abandon oneself, but stay alive so as to the theoretical method that the Group offered us,
maintain the coherence of the stakes of our fight, but we should abandon as fallacious that fundamental
not to obey the call to the ritual of sacrifice and death. – rational and affective – experience because it was
I insist on this: I am not judging him as a father. I am opposed to an ‘objective’ and true grasp of reality.
simply drawing the consequences of what must have The two fallacies result from trying to ‘explain a
been for him a most painful experience, consequences phenomenon exclusively in terms of its origins’. This
we cannot responsibly ignore. I am thinking of the means that we have to erase our subjective experi-
necessary elaboration of our responsibility for crucial ence as our means of assessing the significance of
actions that led to the useless sacrifice of a whole the Junta. We should also reject as a ‘fallacy’ ‘the
generation of young people, and not just of them, attribution of a priori coherence to political events’.
determined in great part by the falsity and fantasy of Here we are invited to abandon the rationality which
a conception of politics. This mortal fantasy had its made it possible for us to take positions since the
genesis a long time ago, and the intellectuals whose Junta came to power, a rationality that hitherto we
responsibility should be to tell the truth have a share have considered to be a necessary index of truth.
in the blame that is not minimal. 2. It was necessary to abandon political ethics in order
to assert an opportunism indifferent to values in
Second passage: from support for the political activity. This allows the SDG to invert the
armed ‘recovery’ of the Malvinas hierarchy of values, so that the main enemy is now
to the democratic ‘pact’ the British rather than the Military Junta. Which
In the second example we will use to verify our thesis, means saying that at least at the military level we
we will leave the positions taken during Peronism’s should establish an alliance of common objec-

48
tives, even if wrong ones, with the genocidaires that theoretical conceptions continued to be regulated
in power. by the categories of the Right.
3. Once the subjective as a place where truth could
also be elaborated is removed, the absolute and The absence of ‘self-criticism’
current index of political truth becomes the ‘objec- and the new solution
tive’, scientific, direct or immediate ‘just interests After this, we might have expected self-criticism, but
of the people’ – that is, the working class. The there was none. Let us see whether theoretical work
political process is thus regulated by the mechanism does not necessarily imply critical work in the theorist,
of history, in its simplest and most linearly deter- and whether this requirement is essential for thinking
ministic version. Where the working class expressed or not. And this is what is shown by an article written
itself immediately and directly in support [of the by two members of that same Socialist Reflection
War] was the place of truth for the social scientist Group published in Punto de Vista, number 21, August
of the Left. 1984, in Buenos Aires. Here again what was once
4. This led to a fundamental conclusion that the adored is abandoned, and a new solution is offered for
problem of morals, that is ethics, should be excluded a different confrontation with the raw reality that has
from political confrontation, as if it had no value to be seasoned and cooked again.
of its own and had no contribution to make to the It is the passage from the rule of the Military
constitution of political force. And this led in con- Junta (1982) to the implantation of democracy in
sequence to thinking that victory could be achieved 1984. And once again the experience that dictated
with any politics, any power, any economy or any the failure of previous theory and politics dictates the
morality, a conclusion that the simplest objective new mode of understanding and the new position (no,
logic would have rejected. And to think that it is not self-criticism): simply a new theory and a new
only physical force, without morale or morality conception.
that leads to victory in social conflicts. In the case And what is specifically asserted is:
of the Malvinas, it led to a claim that a victory for
• The previously negated subjectivity and the ethics
the Junta’s war aims would also be an advance for
which had been happily put to one side now receive
the popular forces and a raising of their conscious-
encomia:
ness. The assertion and affirmation of pure force as
political power. The recovery of the topic [sic] of subjectivity, as
5. All this implied that it was only politico-economic well as the rebirth [sic] of investigations into the
conditions within an ‘objective’ strategy that should relation between ethics and politics have always
been produced in situations of crisis.
be the basis of our politics and that we should
discard any concerns with the meaning and effectiv- The crisis displaces ‘objectivity’ in favour of
ity of the popular forces which have to be created, ‘subjectivity’: it produces actors and projects.
as if this specific force, of a different nature, as The crisis produces a recovery of questions of
we have seen, were not determinant in the political ethics.
struggles with a class opposition. Hence in the [The crisis teaches us] to go beyond a schema
Malvinas War, it meant laying stress on what could of political action that is a prisoner of abstract
be won economically and strategically at national dichotomies that separate ‘objective conditions’
and international level, that is endorsing ‘objective’ from ‘subjective conditions’.
gains for the nation, while obscuring the fundamen- To save the subjectivity of the actors, the explo-
tal contradictions within the nation itself. sion of subjectivity that constitutes it.

And these assertions, in which reflective subjectivity


Separation, then, between the objective and the subjec-
is only included as a ‘topic’, where the separation
tive, the past and the present, the internal and external,
between the subjective and objective, this time in
the individual and collective, and hence, at the very
theory, is extended, are backed up with a bibliog-
moment where the SDG claimed the most objective
raphy of the international great and good. But our
far-sightedness, a blindness in the face of reality.
extensive, elaborate, theoretical critique, published
Because this attitude turned out to be completely
over the last twenty years in their own country, is
fallacious, given the result and consequences of the
conflict. It showed us not only that fantasy and illusion
 The article ‘Social Crisis and Democratic Pact’ is signed by
were being projected onto the political field, but also Emilio de Ípola and Juan Carlos Portantiero.

49
completely ignored: Paggi, Habermas, Gramsci, inequalities, in language, and finally in bodies’. An
Crozier, Friedberg, Frankfurt School, Adler, Bern- equivalence, it is said, between war and politics. But
stein, yes; Rozitchner, no. I think that this conception does not do justice to
Clausewitz, who thought of politics as the field of
• What is now recovered is the ‘irreducibly
truce. Perhaps Foucault himself has abandoned that
in­determinate, that is to say political, character, in
essential distinction that differentiates the power ‘of a
all its human density and fullness, of ‘the social
different nature’ of the forces in confrontation, where
subsystems’, as against the political, strategic and
war which turns into truce, because it is necessary
economic, mechanical and abstract determinism
for both contending parties: one is stronger on the
that had placed the direct and immediate defini-
offensive, but the other is stronger in defence.
tion of its truth and meaning in a particular social
This conception maintains the effective presence
class:
in politics of the potential specificity of each force
Identities that appear to be subsumed in a par- and on that basis allows us to think democracy as a
ticular centre, ‘class’ for example, or ‘nation’ … field of elaboration of forces, without war necessarily
fragment in a multiple manner. predominating, precisely because we are in a situation
of truce. Here each side has its own, specific force,
And what is rejected is the relation between people
but the one on the defensive, Clausewitz reminds us,
and state proper to populism – now described as
is stronger. So, if our authors previously asserted with
specular:
Crozier that politics ‘rests on a relation of forces’, the
With the crisis certainties have collapsed, liberat- ‘pact’ they offer us cannot just be a voluntaristic one.
ing new sets of questions: not only the centrality It cannot be put forward as purely formal leadership in
attributed to certain social subjects (the prole-
which everyone would be compelled to take part and
tariat) has been interrogated.
hide the fact (simulate) that it is the relation of forces
But the crisis they flag up so repetitively is only that constitutes the limits and possibility of attaining
really a crisis and useful for predicting political the formal pact. It is not the will that establishes it
history when it is their own thought that has gone – if indeed the will means anything as a concept (and
into crisis. And their own crisis takes on world we already know that ‘good will’ is what is postulated
dimensions. as the necessary accompaniment for purely formal
rationality to enter historical reality and assert itself
• But what is most important is something else: to
as true). It is not the will, however good it is, which
the previous affirmation of the war unleashed to
establishes this pact, but the material recognition of
‘recover’ the Malvinas, and which they supported,
an equilibrium that of necessity leads the stronger to
now, by contrast, they oppose a sharp negation of
open up that space of truce called ‘politics’. Is it not
the war to allow the passage to pure politics, which
perhaps utopian to think that democracy, currently, at
would exclude war altogether. And what they put
least among us, corresponds to that condition which
forward is the venerable and originary notion of the
requires the ‘pact’: ‘that there exists if not a culture
‘pact’ as the rational foundation of the democratic
then at least a democratic will solidly rooted in the
political accord that has been initiated in Argentina.
social actors’? Who can seriously think that all the
All that remains of the complex equation between
social actors will accept the surrender of their own
politics and war is their disjunction: either war or
privileges that led the country to destruction and
politics. And naturally, since the war was lost, it is
murder, torture and death as political system, to save
excluded, leaving only the political pact.
a system that is inimical to them?
What we see in this passage from 1982 to 1984
War and politics once more is the appearance of a thought that has lived through
crisis, and although this time it coincided with one
The authors write that Foucault criticizes this concep-
more crisis of the system, this thought in and of
tion of politics, as he tries to ‘rethink politics according
crisis continues to be dependent in its basic, political
to the categories of war’ where politics would be ‘a
formulations on a new utopia: an abstract rationalism
war continued by other means’. In the politics that
that excludes the reality of the forces present. Does
does not forget its foundation in force, ‘political power’,
it not make us suspect that it is another case of the
says Foucault, ‘would have the role of perpetually
appearance of fantasy in politics?
reinscribing that relation of forces by means of a type
of silent war, inscribing it in institutions, in economic Translated by Philip Derbyshire

50
reviews

Anything is possible
Quentin Meillassoux, After Finitude: An Essay on the Necessity of Contingency, preface by Alain Badiou, trans.
Ray Brassier, Continuum, London and New York, 2008. viii + 148 pp., £16.99 hb., 978 0 826 49674 4.

Philosophical speculation can regain determinate things are so much as the possibility that they might
knowledge of absolute reality. We can think the nature always be otherwise.
of things as they are in themselves, independently of It is the trenchant force of this affirmation, no
the way they appear to us. We can demonstrate that doubt, that accounts for the enthusiasm with which
the modality of this nature is radically contingent Meillassoux’s work has been taken up by a small
– that there is no reason for things or ‘laws’ to be or but growing group of young researchers exasperated
remain as they are. Nothing is necessary, apart from with the generally uninspiring state of contempo-
the necessity that nothing be necessary. Anything can rary ‘continental’ philosophy. It’s easy to see why
happen, in any place and at any time, without reason Meillassoux’s After Finitude has so quickly acquired
or cause. something close to cult status among some readers who
Such is the ringing message affirmed by the remark- share his lack of reverence for ‘the way things are’.
able French philosopher Quentin Meillassoux in his The book is exceptionally clear and concise, entirely
first book, After Finitude, originally published by devoted to a single chain of reasoning. It combines a
Seuil in 2006. Against the grain of self-critical and confident insistence on the self-sufficiency of rational
self-reflexive post-Kantian philosophy, Meillassoux demonstration with an equally rationalist suspicion of
announces that we can recover ‘the great outdoors, mere experience and consensus. The argument implies,
the absolute outside of pre-critical thinkers’, the utterly in tantalizing outline, an alternative history of the
‘foreign territory’ that subsists in itself, independently whole of modern European philosophy from Galileo
of our relation to it. And when we begin to explore and Descartes through Hume and Kant to Heidegger
this foreign land that is reality in itself, what we learn and Deleuze. It is also open to a number of critical
is that objections. In what follows I reconstruct the basic
there is no reason for anything to be or to remain sequence of the argument (also drawing, on occasion,
thus and so rather than otherwise.… Everything on articles published by Meillassoux in the last few
could actually collapse: from trees to stars, from years), and then sketch three or four of the difficulties
stars to laws, from physical laws to logical laws; it seems to confront.
and this not by virtue of some superior law whereby The simplest way to introduce Meillassoux’s general
everything is destined to perish, but by virtue of the
project is as a reformulation and radicalization of what
absence of any superior law capable of preserving
anything, no matter what, from perishing. he on several occasions describes as ‘Hume’s problem’:
Neither events or laws are governed, in the end, that pure ‘reasoning a priori’ cannot suffice to prove
by any necessity other than that of a purely ‘chaotic that a given effect must always and necessarily follow
becoming – that is to say, a becoming governed by from a given cause. There is no reason why one and
no necessity whatsoever’. (Meillassoux, ‘Potentiality the same cause should not give rise to a ‘hundred dif-
and Virtuality’, Collapse 2, March 2007, p. 59)
ferent events’. Meillassoux accepts Hume’s argument
For Meillassoux, as for Plato or Hegel, philosophy’s as unanswerable, as ‘blindingly obvious’: ‘we cannot
chief concern is with the nature of absolute reality, but rationally discover any reason why laws should be
as Meillassoux conceives it the nature of this reality so rather than otherwise.’ Hume himself, however
demands that philosophy should think not ‘about what (along with both Kant and the main thrust of the
is but only about what can be’. The proper concern analytical tradition), retreats from the full implications
of a contemporary (post-metaphysical, post-dogmatic of his demonstration. Rather than ditch the concept of
but also post-critical) philosophy is not with being but causal necessity altogether, he affirms it as a matter
with may-being, not with être but with peut-être. If of ‘blind faith’. Whether this belief is then a matter
Meillassoux can be described as a ‘realist’, then, the of mere habit (Hume) or an irreducible component of
reality that concerns him does not involve the way transcendental logic (Kant) is, as far as Meillassoux is

Radical Philosophy 152 (November/December 20 08) 51


concerned, a secondary quarrel. Ever since, analytical Rational reflection encourages us to posit the
philosophers have tended to assume that we should absence of sufficient reason and to speculate about
abandon ontological speculation and retreat instead to the potentialities of this absolute time: it is only our
reflection upon the way we draw inductive inferences experience, precisely, that holds us back. Our ordinary
from ordinary experience, or from ordinary ways of sensory experience discourages us from abandoning a
talking about our experience. superstitious belief in causality. Conversion of Hume’s
In keeping with a tactic he deploys elsewhere in problem into Meillassoux’s opportunity requires, then,
his work, Meillassoux himself quickly turns Hume’s a Neoplatonic deflation of experience and the senses.
old problem into an opportunity. Our inability ration- However far we might push such deflation, though, it
ally to determine an absolute necessity or sufficient obviously remains the case that the world we experi-
reason underlying things, properly understood, can ence is not chaotic but stable. How might we explain
be affirmed as a demonstration that there is no such everyday empirical consistency on the basis of radical
necessity or reason. Rather than try to salvage a contingency and the total absence of causal necessity?
dubious faith in the apparent stability of our experi- If physical laws could actually change for no reason,
ence, we should affirm the prospect that Hume refused would it not be ‘extraordinarily improbable if they did
to accept: there is no reason why what we experience not change frequently’?
as constant laws should not break down or change at This question frames a second stage in Meillas-
any point, for the simple reason there is no such thing soux’s argument. Since the earth so regularly rotates
as reason or cause. The truth is not just that a given around the sun, since gravity so consistently holds
cause might give rise to a hundred different effects, us to the ground, so then we infer that there must be
but that an infinite variety of ‘effects’ might emerge some underlying cause which accounts for the consist-
on the basis of no cause at all, in a pure eruption of ency of such effects. Meillassoux claims to refute
novelty ex nihilo. such reasoning by casting doubt on the ‘probabilistic’
The vision of the acausal and anarchic universe that assumption that underlies it. An ordinary calculation of
results from the affirmation of such contingency is probabilities – say, the anticipation of an even spread
fully worthy of Deleuze and Guattari’s appreciation for of results from a repeated dice-throw – assumes that
those artists and writers who tear apart the comfortable there is a finite range of possible outcomes and a
normality of ordinary experience so as to let ‘a bit of finite range of determining factors, a range that sets
free and windy chaos’ remind us of the tumultuous the criteria whereby a given outcome is more or less
intensity of things: likely in relation to others. At this point, following
Badiou’s example, Meillassoux plays his Cantorian
If we look through the aperture which we have
trump card.
opened up onto the absolute, what we see there is
a rather menacing power – something insensible, It is precisely this totalization of the thinkable
and capable of destroying both things and worlds, which can no longer be guaranteed a priori. For we
of bringing forth monstrous absurdities, yet also of now know – indeed, we have known it at least since
never doing anything, of realizing every dream, but Cantor’s revolutionary set-theory – that we have
also every nightmare, of engendering random and no grounds for maintaining that the conceivable is
frenetic transformations, or conversely, of produc- necessarily totalisable.
ing a universe that remains motionless down to its
ultimate recesses, like a cloud bearing the fiercest Cantor showed that there can be no all-inclusive set of
storms, then the eeriest bright spells, if only for an all sets, leaving probabilistic reason with no purchase
interval of disquieting calm.… We see something on an open or ‘detotalized’ set of possibilities: ‘laws
akin to Time, but a Time that is inconceivable for which are contingent, but stable beyond all prob-
physics, since it is capable of destroying, without
ability, thereby become conceivable’ (‘Potentiality and
cause or reason, every physical law, just as it is
Virtuality’).
inconceivable for metaphysics, since it is capable
of destroying every determinate entity, even a god, On this basis, Meillassoux aims to restore the rights
even God. of a purely ‘intelligible’ insight – that is, to reinstate the
validity of pre- or non-critical ‘intellectual intuition’
Without flinching from the implications, Meillassoux and thereby challenge the stifling strictures of Kant’s
attributes to such ‘time without development [devenir]’ transcendental turn. Rather than elaborate a merely
the potential to generate life ex nihilo, to draw spirit ‘negative ontology’, he seeks to elaborate ‘an ever
from matter or creativity from stasis – or even to resur- more determinate, ever richer concept of contingency’,
rect an immortal mind from a lifeless body. on the assumption that these determinations can then

52 Radical Philosophy 152 (November/December 20 08)


be ‘construed as so many absolute properties of what produced through pure replication or reiteration, indif-
is’, or as so many constraints to which a given ‘entity ferent to any sort of pattern or ‘rhythm’). Perhaps an
must submit in order to exercise its capacity-not-to-be absolutely arbitrary discourse will be adequate to the
and its capacity-to-be-other’. absolutely contingent nature of things (‘Time Without
A first constraint required by this capacity entails Becoming’, talk at CRMEP, Middlesex University,
rejection of contradiction. The only law that survives May 2008).
the elimination of causal or sufficient reason is the law The main obstacle standing in the way of this
of non-contradiction. A contradictory entity would be anti-phenomenological return ‘to the things them-
utterly indeterminate, and thus both contingent and selves’, naturally, is the widely held (if not tautological)
necessary. In order to affirm the thesis that any given assumption that we cannot, by definition, think any
thing can be anything, it is necessary that this thing reality independently of thought. Meillassoux dubs the
both be what it is here and now, and forever capable modern currents of thought that accept this assumption
of being determined as something else. In other words, ‘correlationist’. A correlationist humbly accepts that
where Kant simply posited that things-in-themselves ‘we only ever have access to the correlation between
existed and existed as non-contradictory, Meillassoux thinking and being, and never to either term considered
claims to deduce the latter property directly from the apart from the other’, such that ‘anything that is totally
modality of their existence. a-subjective cannot be’. Nothing can be independently
What does it mean, however, to say that such of thought, since here ‘to be is to be a correlate’.
things exist? Meillassoux’s approach to this question Paradigmatically, to be is to be the correlate of either
circumscribes a second, more far-reaching determina- consciousness (for phenomenology) or language (for
tion of contingency: absolute and contingent entities or analytical philosophy).
things-in-themselves must observe the logical principle Kant is the founding figure of correlationist phil-
of non-contradiction, and they must also submit to osophy, of course, but the label applies equally well,
rigorous mathematical measurement. Here again, Meil- according to Meillassoux, to most strands of post-
lassoux’s strategy involves the renewal of perfectly Kantian philosophy, from Fichte and Hegel to Heidegger
classical concerns. In addition to an affirmation of the or Adorno. All these philosophies posit some sort of
ontological implications of the scientific revolution, fundamental mediation between the subject and object
it involves the absolutization of what Descartes and of thought, such that it is the clarity and integrity of
then Locke established as a thing’s primary qualities this relation (whether it be clarified through logical
– those qualities like its dimensions or weight, which judgement, phenomenological reduction, historical
can be mathematically measured independently of the reflection, linguistic articulation, pragmatic experimen-
way an observer experiences and perceives it – that tation or intersubjective communication) that serves
is, independently of secondary qualities like texture, as the only legitimate means of accessing reality. The
colour, taste, and so on. But whereas Descartes con- overall effect has been to consolidate the criteria of
ceived of such qualities in geometric terms, as aspects ‘lawful’ legitimacy as such. Correlationism figures
of an extended substance, Meillassoux takes a further here as a sort of counter-revolution that emerged in
step, and isolates the mathematizable from extension philosophy as it tried, with and after Kant, to come to
itself, so as then terms with the uncomfortably disruptive implications
to derive from a contingency which is absolute,
of Galileo, Descartes and the scientific revolution.
the conditions that would allow me to deduce the Post-Copernican science had opened the door to the
absolutization of mathematical discourse [and thus] ‘great outdoors’: Kant’s own so-called ‘Copernican
ground the possibility of the sciences to speak about turn’ should be best understood as a Ptolemaic attempt
an absolute reality …, a reality independent of to slam this door shut.
thought. (‘Speculative Realism’, Collapse 3, 2007,
How, then, to reopen the door? Since a correla-
p. 440)
tionist will assume as a matter of course that the
Meillassoux admits that he has not worked out a full referent of any statement ‘cannot possibly exist’ or
version of this deduction, but the closing pages of After ‘take place [as] non-correlated with a consciousness’,
Finitude imply that his approach will depend on the so then Meillassoux claims to find the Achilles heel
presumption that ‘what is mathematically conceivable of correlationism in its inability to cope with what he
is absolutely possible’, coupled with an appreciation for calls ‘ancestral’ statements. Such statements refer to
the absolutely arbitrary, meaningless and contingent events or entities older than any consciousness, events
nature of mathematical signs qua signs (e.g. signs like the emergence of life, the formation of Earth, the

Radical Philosophy 152 (November/December 20 08) 53


origin of the universe, and so on. In so far as correla- its knowledge of the absolute through facticity.’ In
tion can only conceive of an object that is given to a knowing that we know only contingent facts, we also
subject, how can it cope with an object that pre-dates know that it is necessary that there be only contingent
givenness itself? facts. We know that facticity itself, and only facticity
Now Meillassoux realizes that in order to overcome itself, is not contingent but necessary. Recognition of
the Ptolemaic–correlationist counter-revolution it is the absolute nature or absolute necessity of facticity
impossible simply to retreat from Kant back to the then allows Meillassoux to go on to complete his
‘dogmatic’ metaphysics of Descartes, let alone to the deduction ‘from the absoluteness of this facticity those
necessity- and cause-bound metaphysics of Spinoza properties of the in-itself which Kant for his part took
or Leibniz. He also accepts that you cannot refute to be self-evident’ – that is, that it exists (as radically
correlationism simply by positing, as Laruelle does, contingent) and that it exists as non-contradictory. By
a mind-independent reality. In order to overcome the affirming this necessity of contingency or ‘principle
correlational obstacle to his acausal ontology, in order
to know mind-independent reality as non-contradictory
and non-necessary, Meillassoux thus needs to show
that the correlationist critique of metaphysical necessity
itself enables if not requires the speculative affirmation
of non-necessity.
This demonstration occupies the central and most
subtle sections of After Finitude. The basic strategy
again draws on Kantian and post-Kantian precedents.
Post-Kantian metaphysicians like Fichte and Hegel
tried to overcome Kant’s foreclosure of absolute reality
by converting correlation itself, the very ‘instrument
of empirico-critical de-absolutization, into the model
for a new type of absolute.’ This idealist alternative
to correlationist humility, however, cannot respond in
turn to the ‘most profound’ correlational decision – the
decision which ensures, in order to preserve the ban on
every sort of absolute knowledge, that correlation too is
just another contingent fact, rather than a necessity. As
with his approach to Hume’s problem, Meillassoux’s
crucial move here is to turn an apparent weakness into of factuality’, Meillassoux triumphantly concludes, ‘I
an opportunity. The correlationist, in order to guard think an X independent of any thinking, and I know
against idealist claims to knowledge of absolute reality, it for sure, thanks to the correlationist himself and
readily accepts not only the reduction of knowledge his fight against the absolute, the idealist absolute’
to knowledge of facts: the correlationist also accepts (‘Speculative Realism’, p. 432).
that this reduction too is just another fact, just another Unlike Meillassoux, I believe that the main problem
non-necessary contingency. But if such correlating with recent French philosophy has been not an excess
reduction is not necessary then it is of course pos- but a deficit of genuinely relational thought. From
sible to envisage its suspension: the only way the this perspective, despite its compelling originality
correlationists can defend themselves against idealist and undeniable ingenuity, Meillassoux’s resolutely
absolutization requires them to admit ‘the impossibility absolutizing project raises a number of questions and
of giving an ultimate ground to the existence of any objections.
being’, including the impossibility of giving a ground First, the critique of correlation seems to depend
for this impossibility (‘Speculative Realism’). on an equivocation regarding the relation of thinking
All that Meillassoux now has to do is absolutize, in and being, of epistemology and ontology. On balance,
turn, this apparent failure. We simply need to under- Meillassoux insists on the modern ‘ontological requi-
stand ‘why it is not the correlation but the facticity site’ which stipulates that ‘to be is to be a correlate’
of the correlation that constitutes the absolute. We of thought. From within the correlational circle, ‘all
must show why thought, far from experiencing its we ever engage with is what is given-to-thought, never
intrinsic limits through facticity, experiences rather an entity subsisting by itself.’ If a being only is as the

54 Radical Philosophy 152 (November/December 20 08)


correlate of the thought that thinks it, then from a cor- there is no primordial power or divine providence
relationist perspective it must seem that a being older that determines being or the meaning of being to be a
than thought can only be ‘unthinkable’. A consistent certain way. What Meillassoux infers from this critique
correlationist, Meillassoux says, must ‘insist that the of metaphysical necessity, however, is the rather more
physical universe could not really have preceded the grandiose assertion that there is no cause or reason
existence of man, or at least of living creatures’. As for anything to be the way it is. This inference relies
far as I know, however, almost no one actually thinks on a contentious understanding of the terms ‘reason’,
or insists on this, apart perhaps from a few fossilized ‘cause’ and ‘law’. It’s been a long time since scientists
idealists. They don’t think this because correlationism confused ‘natural laws’ with logical or metaphysical
as Meillassoux defines it is in reality an epistemologi- necessities, and it is perfectly possible, of course, to
cal theory, one that is perfectly compatible with the reconstruct the locally effective reasons and causes
insights of Darwin, Marx or Einstein. There’s nothing that have shaped, for instance, the evolution of aerobic
to prevent a correlationist from thinking ancestral vertebrate organisms. There was nothing necessary or
objects or worlds that are older than the thought that predictable about this evolution, but why should we
thinks them, or indeed older than thought itself; even doubt that it conformed to familiar ‘laws’ of cause and
from an orthodox Kantian perspective there is little effect? What does it mean to say that the ongoing con-
difference in principle between my thinking an event sequences of this long process might be transformed in
that took place yesterday and an event that took place an instant – that we might suddenly cease to breathe
six billion years ago. As Meillassoux knows perfectly oxygen or suffer the effects of gravity? Although
well, all that the correlationist demands is an acknowl- Meillassoux insists that contingency applies to every
edgement that when you think of an ancestral event, event and every process, it may be that the only event
or any event, you are indeed thinking of it. I can think that might qualify as contingent and without reason
of this lump of ancient rock as ancient if and only if in his absolute sense of the term is the emergence of
science currently provides me with reliable means of the universe itself.
thinking it so. Meillassoux’s acausal ontology, in other words,
Genuine conquest of the correlationist fortress would includes no account of an actual process of transforma-
require a reference not to objects older than thought but tion or development. There is no account here of any
to processes of thinking that proceed without thinking, positive ontological or historical force, no substitute
or objects that are somehow presentable in the absence for what other thinkers have conceived as substance, or
of any objective presence or evidence – in other words, spirit, or power, or labour. His insistence that anything
processes and objects proscribed by Meillassoux’s own might happen can only amount to an insistence on
insistence on the principle of non-contradiction. This the bare possibility of radical change. So far, at least,
is the problem with using a correlationist strategy (the Meillassoux’s affirmation of ‘the effective ability of
principle of factuality) to break out of the correlation- every determined entity’ to persist, change or disappear
ist circle: until Meillassoux can show that we know without reason figures as an empty and indeterminate
things exist not only independently of our thought but postulate. Once Meillassoux has purged his speculative
independently of our thinking them so, the correlation- materialism of any sort of causality he deprives it of
ist has little to worry about. Anyone can agree with any worldly historical purchase as well. The abstract
Meillassoux that ‘to think ancestrality is to think a logical possibility of change (given the absence of any
world without thought – a world without the givenness ultimately sufficient reason) has strictly nothing to do
of the world.’ What’s less obvious is how we might with any concrete process of actual change. Rather
think such a world without thinking it, or how we like his mentor Badiou, to the degree that Meillas-
might arrive at scientific knowledge of such pre-given soux insists on the absolute disjunction of an event
objects if nothing is given of them. from existing situations he deprives himself of any
Along the same lines, Meillassoux’s rationalist cri- concretely mediated means of thinking, with and after
tique of causality and necessity seems to depend on Marx, the possible ways of changing such situations.
an equivocation between metaphysical and physical or The notion of ‘absolute time’ that accompanies
natural necessity. The actual target of Meillassoux’s Meillassoux’s acausal ontology is a time that seems
critique of metaphysics is the Leibnizian principle of endowed with only one dimension – the instant. It may
sufficient reason. He dispatches it, as we’ve seen, with well be that ‘only the time that harbours the capacity
a version of Hume’s argument: we cannot rationally to destroy every determinate reality, while obeying
demonstrate an ultimate reason for the being of being; no determinate law – the time capable of destroying,

Radical Philosophy 152 (November/December 20 08) 55


without reason or law, both worlds and things – can equivocate, as if the abstract implications of Cantorian
be thought as an absolute.’ The sense in which such an detotalization might concern the concrete set of pos-
absolute can be thought as distinctively temporal is less sibilities at issue in a specific situation – for example,
obvious. Rather than any sort of articulation of past, in an ecosystem or in a political conflict. He seems to
present and future, Meillassoux’s time is a matter of think that the Cantorian transfinite – a theory that has
spontaneous and immediate irruption ex nihilo. Time is strictly nothing to do with any physical or material
reduced, here, to a succession of ‘gratuitous sequences’. reality – might underwrite speculation regarding the
The paradigm for such gratuitous irruption, obviously, ‘unreason’ whereby any actually existing thing might
is the miracle. Meillassoux argues that every absolute suddenly be transformed, destroyed or preserved.
‘miraculous’ discontinuity testifies only to the ‘inexist- In short, Meillassoux seems to confuse the domains
ence of God’ – that is, to the lack of any metaphysical of pure and applied mathematics. In the spirit of
necessity, progress or providence. It may be, however, Galileo’s ‘mathematization of nature’, he relies on pure
that an argument regarding the existence or inexistence mathematics in order to demonstrate the integrity of
of God is secondary in relation to arguments for or an objective reality that exists independently of us – a
against belief in this quintessentially ‘divine’ power – a domain of primary (mathematically measurable) quali-
supernatural power to interrupt the laws of nature and ties purged of any merely sensory, subject-dependent
abruptly reorient the pattern of worldly affairs. secondary qualities. But pure mathematics is arguably
The argument that allows Meillassoux to posit a the supreme example of absolutely subject-dependent
radically open miraculous time depends on reference thought – that is, a thought that proceeds without
to Cantor’s ‘de-totalization’ of every attempt to close reference to any sort of objective reality ‘outside’
or limit a denumerable set of possibilities. A still more it. No one denies that every mathematical measure-
absolute lack of mediation, however, characterizes ment is ‘indifferent’ to the thing it measures. But
Meillas­soux’s appeal to mathematics as the royal road leaving aside the question of why an abstract, math-
to the in-itself. Cantor’s transfinite set theory concerns ematized description of an object should be any less
the domain of pure number alone. The demonstration mind-dependent or anthropocentric than a sensual
that there is an open, unending series of ever larger or experiential description, there is no eliding the
infinite numbers clearly has decisive implications for fundamental difference between pure number and an
the foundations of mathematics, but Meillassoux needs applied measurement. The idea that the meaning of the
to demonstrate more exactly how these implications statement ‘the universe was formed 13.5 billion years
apply to the time and space of our actually exist- ago’ might be independent of the mind that thinks
ing universe. In what sense is our material universe it only makes sense if you disregard the quaintly
itself infinite? In what sense has the evolution of life, parochial unit of measurement involved (along with
for instance, confronted an actually infinite (rather the meaning of words like ‘ago’, to say nothing of
than immensely large) number of actual possibili- the meaning of meaning tout court). As a matter of
ties? It is striking that Meillassoux pays little or no course, every unit of measurement, from the length
attention to such questions, and sometimes treats the of a metre to the time required for a planet to orbit
logical and material domains as if they were effectively around a star, exists at a fundamental distance from
interchangeable. the domain of number as such. If Meillassoux was
Admittedly, you can make a case for the equation of to carry through the argument of ‘ancestrality’ to its
mathematics and ontology in the strict sense, as Badiou logical conclusion, he would have to acknowledge that
does, such that post-Cantorian theory serves to articu- it would eliminate not only all reference to secondary
late what can be thought of as pure being-qua-being qualities like colour and texture but also all conven-
(once being is identified with abstract and absolute tional primary qualities like length or mass or date as
multiplicity, i.e. a multiplicity that does not depend well. What might then be known of an ‘arche-fossil’
on any preliminary notion of unit or unity). Such an (i.e. a thing considered independently of whatever is
equation requires, however, that ontological questions given of it, including its material extension) would
be strictly preserved from merely ‘ontic’ ones: as a have to be expressed in terms of pure numbers alone,
matter of course, a mathematical conception of being rather than dates or measurements. Whatever else such
has nothing to say about the material, historical or (neo-Pythagorean?) knowledge amounts to, it has no
social attributes of specific beings. A similar ‘onto- obvious relation to the sorts of realities that empirical
logical reduction’ must apply to Meillassoux’s reliance science tries to describe, including realities older than
on Cantorian mathematics. Here again he seems to the evolution of life.

56 Radical Philosophy 152 (November/December 20 08)


After Finitude is a beautifully written and seduc- uncaused contingency, however, offers us little grip on
tively argued book. It offers a welcome critique of the means of their material transformation. The current
the ambient ‘necessitarian’ world-view, that pensée fascination with his work, in some quarters, may be
unique which tells us ‘there is no alternative’, and a symptom of impatience with a more traditional
which underlies both the listless political apathy and conception of social and political change – not that
the deflating humility of so much contemporary phil- we might abruptly be other than we are, but that we
osophy and critical theory. In the rationalist tradi- might engage with the processes whereby we have
tion of the Enlightenment and of ideology-critique, become what we are, and might now begin to become
Meillassoux launches a principled assault on every otherwise. A critique of metaphysical necessity and
‘superstitious’ presumption that existing social situa- an appeal to transfinite mathematics will not provide,
tions should be accepted as natural or inevitable. His on their own, the basis upon which we might renew a
insistence that such situations are actually a matter of transformative materialism.

Peter Hallward

The geek code


Christopher Kelty, Two Bits: The Cultural Significance of Free Software, Duke University Press, Durham NC,
2008. 378 pp., £51.00 hb., £12.99 pb., 978 0 82234 242 7 hb., 978 0 82234 264 9 pb.

Is programming software a mode of public speech? downloading, identity theft, and the licensing of HIV/
Christopher Kelty’s Two Bits provides an answer care- AIDS medicines? Kelty’s reasoning is that the issues
fully integrated with a proposal, in this cultural anthro- each of these disparate epistemological domains raise
pology of an important series of historical developments were first ‘figured out and confronted’ by historical
that have been inadequately studied outside their actors in the free software movement. Free software
specific domains. Surveying debates around ‘open’, is never simply a matter of operational, binary code;
‘free’ or ‘shared’ software, Kelty’s answer is that free its historical significance is that it prioritizes getting
software, as privately developed but publicly shared code developed while reflecting a shared ‘moral and
code, has its own specific subjects, material resources technical’ order, a social imaginary. It thus becomes
and commons. Its citizens are those he characterizes something along the lines of a historical force that
as ‘geeks’ who ‘get it’; its resources, software develop- disrupts relations of power and knowledge in par-
ment, sharing and use; its commons, any medium ticular socio-technical configurations. Not all Internet
(paper or digital network) through which software and publics are ‘recursive publics’, then, not all recursive
the discourses enabling its use and re-use are shared, free software publics have relied on Internet-based
along with the resources thus archived. His central distribution, nor are all ‘open software’ projects ‘free’.
proposal is that geeks’ construction of a contingent, Free software precisely emphasizes freedom; it’s an
constantly modulated software commons results in a interventionist mode of building and facilitating code
‘recursive public’ emerging in the building, sharing, as a kind of socio-technical speech, a ‘collective,
usage and revision of free software, a public now technical experimentation’. So while the free software
considerably broadened beyond its historical origins in movement approximates something like a historical
shared UNIX code and commentaries, and including force, disrupting hierarchies of knowledge produc-
explicit engagements with legal discourses, organized tion, Kelty’s description also gives free software the
advocacy, and interface or database design for archiv- force of a futurity – as long, that is, as software gets
ing, revising and accessing potentially any form of programmed, shared and revised.
scholarly knowledge as shareable ‘source code’. It makes sense, then, that in Kelty’s analyses of his
This notion of a ‘recursive public’ underwrites informants’ stories, the meanings of ‘technology’ or
what are broad claims about the cultural significance ‘software code’ change from one informant or context
of a movement Kelty chronicles from roughly the to the next, and that these historical mutations in
early 1970s to the present. Why does free software meaning provide both the rationale for his study and
impact everything from email to social networking the form of his argument. Kelty’s case studies begin
sites, the production of ‘traditional knowledge’, music with interviews with contemporary ‘geeks’, and then

Radical Philosophy 152 (November/December 20 08) 57


loop back towards a historical reconstruction of the adherents of ‘open software’ refuse the notional
unauthorized distribution of Xeroxed copies of Ken re­orientations by which he treats, say, software com-
Thompson’s UNIX code with accompanying commen- mentary or scholarly texts as constitutive of free soft-
tary in Australian comp-sci classrooms, discussions ware’s ‘source code’. This allows him to emphasize
of Richard Stallman’s and Linus Torvalds’s respective vibrant publicity as one of free software’s defining
contributions, finally ending with ongoing efforts to characteristics. However, I found three claims essential
redefine copyright licences at the Creative Commons to his description of the discursive dynamism and
project, and to provide free online scholarly texts, for productivity of free software, as the commons of a
potentially any conceivable academic domain, at the recursive public, particularly troubling.
Conexions project (in which academic texts are con- First of all, Kelty warns his reader that she’ll find
sidered as source code, producing a distinct model of little of the conventional cultural anthropological mate-
online scholarly content and access from, say, projects rials and methods instantiated here. ‘Nearly everything
like Wikipedia). These comparisons are among the [relevant] is archived’, he claims, so that free software
most interesting materials in Two Bits. The narrative as an anthropological resource provides its own ‘self-
trajectory also registers Kelty’s own entry into the documenting history’. This claim relieves Kelty of the
world of free software production. Two Bits begins need to historicize and theorize important conceptual
with his education by ‘geeks’, and closes with Kelty’s notions informing his descriptions of free software’s
description of his contributions to Creative Commons ‘moral and technical’ social imaginary. For example,
and Conexions. Overall, it’s an elegant formulation. his frequent use of the term ‘bootstrapping’ supports
The histories he recounts are often fascinating in the self-evidentiality of free software’s socio-technical
their contradictions, and his own participation in Con- dynamism. In fact, however, ‘bootstrapping’ was a
exions provides the appropriate happy ending of an pragmatic and theoretical term discussed by figures
observer transformed into a participant, an evangelized like Douglas Engelbart, who theorized ‘bootstrap-
geek who ‘gets it’ and starts building. Taking cultural ping’ as a ‘third way’ of institutional organizational
anthropology beyond participant observation, Two Bits design. Engelbart’s ideas about organizational theory
supplies a syllogistic demonstration of the power of a originated in part with concerns about potential Soviet
‘recursive public’ and the virtuous circle of free soft- dominance in information technology. But in Two
ware development broadened far beyond its historical Bits, what are often terms and concepts central to the
origins. postwar development of US cybernetic communication
Yet can the ‘moral and technical’ order that Kelty networks are embedded into Kelty’s observations as
describes be both the origin and the output of changes innocent, descriptive terms.
as diverse as he suggests, to the extent of informing, The other side of the historical coin is that the
for example, the logics according to which the proper- only expression of networked public expressivity Kelty
tized outputs of global pharmaceuticals industries were imagines for the history of the Internet/web are those
situationally de-licensed? While Kelty at times limits predicated on, or conceivably inspired by, the rhetorics
the applicability of his notional ‘recursive public’, and histories of the ‘software-code-as-speech’ para-
his commitment to it, and the ways many of the digm which he prefers. There’s no mention of other
transitions he describes turn on notional or conceptual networking projects of the 1970s wherein activists
shifts, he asserts this public’s power to encompass tended to identify social needs without regard to data
entire regimes of transactions which are dependent or software, configuring whatever was technologically
on far more complex historical factors. Licensing and available around expressing those needs, and filling
de-licensing of HIV/AIDS drugs arguably has had in whatever was required to pull the project off with
rather more to do with conflicts around sovereignty human insight, discussion, specialized labour and
and territoriality, conflicting regimes of human rights coordination – not software – in order to ‘release’
and state responsibilities, global movement by human human or social ‘potential’ more in terms of an explic-
agents, and careful, failed or radically irresponsible itly politically conceived mode of participation than of
health-care policies by nation-states. It’s more likely a moral and technical mode of software production as
that such larger conflicts and dynamics inform those participation. Such experiments were more plentiful
of the free software movement, rather than the other than we might imagine reading many contemporary
way around. histories of networked sociality, including this one.
Kelty’s concluding discussion of software, law, And while Kelty is probably correct in locating a
culture and digital publicity is timely, because many particularly powerful dynamism in the free software

58 Radical Philosophy 152 (November/December 20 08)


model, it seems crucial to me to at least wonder why Internet/web lies in the public distribution of knowledge
earlier alternatives no longer seem dynamic, even as modifiable software code. (See the Pew Internet and
viable, especially in the US context. The movement American Life Project at www.pew­internet.org.) As of
from a much broader range of mid-twentieth-century 2006, the most popular Internet/web activity among
social projects configuring technology around social online US teens was finding entertainment that they
needs, to late-twentieth- and early-twenty-first-century neither created nor modified. Girls have also outpaced
projects configuring sociality around building software boys at creating their own website content; US girls
code and negotiating legal code, may well suggest that not only post more personal photos than boys but are
what Kelty is describing as a resistant, restive social more restrictive in determining who can see the photos
imaginary is rather a reflection of a dominant, techno- they post. We could hardly have a stronger statement
logical and legal imaginary which has subsumed prior about the use and necessity of both non-programming
and more varied historical imaginations of technics publics and categorically anti-recursive expressivity in
and sociality. This question isn’t raised specifically Internet/web-mediated sociality determined around a
in Two Bits, because Kelty’s discussions often turn factor – gender – which Kelty explicitly discounts.
discursive lions like ‘bootstrapping’ or ‘social imagi- The same survey shows that 79 per cent of black
nary’ into rhetorical lambs; and because, if ‘nearly teens online in the USA are likely to search for web-
everything is archived’ online which matters now, he based information about colleges and universities on the
feels no need to consider models beyond what ‘geeks’ Internet/web compared to 55 per cent of teens overall.
are willing to believe about software’s digital publicity. My guess is that these teens are looking for a viable
Kelty’s geeks ‘get it’, and ‘it’ is a credo: affirming that transposition in lifeworlds even as they operate a mode
software development and the discourse of knowledge of recursive sociality: the web as medium helps them
as software define the participatory subjectivity for design their potential locability within physical sites of
those Kelty thinks are most engaged in contemporary knowledge production, sociality and growing up. The
knowledge production, and so reaping its gains, in one Internet/web can’t provide this in and of itself, suggest-
form or another. ing lessons for academics and pedagogues distinct from
Kelty’s characterization of the subject of free soft- the distance-learning models provided by websites like
ware’s recursive public is a second concern. He clari- Conexions, where the contribution and revision of
fies in a substantive footnote that corporealities such as ‘scholarly texts’ proceeds according to the integration
gender, age, class, ethnicity, sexuality, and so on, matter of database design and legal permissions. The simplest
less than the credo of ‘getting it’. Yet recent surveys generalization to be made here may be that a model
of teen usage of the Internet/web contradict Kelty’s of recursive publics which subsumes social imaginar-
argument that the primary public productivity of the ies into technological and jurisprudential imaginaries

Radical Philosophy 152 (November/December 20 08) 59


may be undescriptive, or possibly outdated. Kelty’s prompt consideration of the ways in which technologi-
study offers much for consideration, but it collapses a cal imaginaries and social imaginaries are routinely
range of concerns around technicity and mediality, and overlapped in descriptions of the Internet/web. Yet
emphasizes more a technosocial than a socio-technical that discussion requires some additional terms and
mediation of knowledge production. It may well be that histories to be introduced, whether from other studies
recursive publics of geeks work differently, and may of the Internet’s development (Castells’s version had
be defined through exclusions rhetorically maintained four, conflicting governmental, technical, social and
around, say, the ability to code, but in fact they are economic imaginaries, for example) or from histori-
subtly substantiated in terms appropriated from larger cal or theoretical accounts of corporeality, culture,
gender, sexuality, national, racial, ethnic or dis/ability technics, virtuality, and so forth. For example, in
imaginaries. considering why Kelty insists on ‘free’, as opposed
My third concern has to do with the responsi- to ‘open’ or ‘shared’, software production, one might
bilities of the cultural anthropologist for observation recall Marcuse’s 1966 preface to Eros and Civilization:
of media or technology histories. Glaring errors of ‘I hesitate to use the word – freedom – because it is
observation about mass media history appear in the precisely in the name of freedom that crimes against
text. For example, while summarizing his dis­covery humanity are being perpetrated.’ Not only are the
that geeks everywhere from New England to Berlin histories and actualities of the production of knowl-
can be characterized as those who ‘get it’, he refers edge determined far beyond the limits of geeks who
to a Funkturm, or radio tower, standing behind challenge, say, health-care provisioning by arranging
Berlin’s Alexanderplatz station. This reference must for the outsourcing of its technical functions (with the
be to the Fernsehturm, the television tower built by predictable profit-taking and disillusionment they gain,
Scandin­avian engineers under contract to produce a as Kelty takes care to report), but larger questions need
functional monument to the DDR’s command over to be raised about shared knowledge conceptualized as
East Berlin, a marker of mediological dominion over the virtuous, private production of shareable ‘source
a contested geopolity, and a warning about its territo- code’.
rial violation. (Berlin’s Funkturm is in fact located Two Bits collapses the distinction between the tech-
in the former West Berlin, having been rebuilt there nical medium and technical relations of production,
after it was bombed in World War II. Meanwhile rather than upholding a difference between them.
Alexander­platz’s Fernsehturm has been retrofitted On this point, Bernard Stiegler’s recent rereading
for both digital television broadcast and tourism.) of Marcuse helps explain why any virtuous logic
Getting the data on the tower’s name and function of recursive public knowledge, doubly articulated as
right would have been a minor fact check – but software production and intellectual property, may
such errors make the book less usable and betray embed a confusion between the technical means of
a lack of interest in local media histories. Two Bits support (the medium) and labouring conditions (the
produces a model of software as technicized expres- relations of production). ‘The supports and the relations
sion by and for a re­cursive digital public which can of production are in co-evolution’, Stiegler believes, but
never be verified other than in the dimensions of a they are primordially discordant. Kelty’s geeks’ admi-
‘collective, experimental technical system’, that is, rable capacity for conceptually redefining software
those dimensions destined to be expressed in terms code as discourse in a virtuous and growing circle of
of the Internet as ‘singularity’. But it’s the larger, knowledge production at times approaches something
cumulative dynamics of technics transforming into of a cure-all designed to fill a melancholy gap opened
mass media which constitutes the singularity, and at where the logic of a public sphere no longer coheres.
least some of the larger history of this singularity has But you can’t share or revise what sovereign govern-
to be explicated with reference to the often violent ments or multinationals manage to keep secret, and it
histories in which it arises. might well be that much of the recursive use of the
I’d appropriate the good bits from Two Bits. The Internet/web has nothing to do with the production of
notion of a recursive public, when kept in check, allows verifiable knowledge as software, fact, proposition, art
for a distinction between contributing to a digital or critique – at all.
commons and simply plagiarizing others’ work, while Kelty’s virtuous recursive public, when he grants
the treatment of scholarly text as source code is a it conceptual powers beyond its historical capacities,
provocative proposal about web-based production of invokes an unstated sacrifice. Raising knowledge-as-
academic knowledge. Discussion of these ideas might software-as-intellectual property to the level of a cure

60 Radical Philosophy 152 (November/December 20 08)


for what ails digital publics also subjects knowledge historical materialism. The Poulantzas revival can be
production to the terms of its encoding as both software seen in three recent edited collections on his work
code and as (even minimalist) law. Such knowledge, and/or that of Miliband: Paradigm Lost: State Theory
whatever its norms or its relations to power, becomes Reconsidered (2003), edited by Aronowitz and Bratsis;
then doubly compounded in axiomatic complexity even Poulantzas Lesen (2006), edited by Bretthauer, Gallas,
as it is reduced to being a subset of itself: the produc- Kannankulam and Stuetzle; and Class, Power, and the
tion of software code made coextensive with digital State in Capitalist Society (2007), edited by Wetherley,
law. If the larger demand is to guide capital towards a Barrow and Burnham; as well as a revised edition of
different conclusion than that it can imagine for itself, Alex Demirovic’s German-language monograph. The
we’ll want to wonder more carefully whether the cure present Verso Reader is another important contribution
for what ails the hyperindustrial production of the to this resurgence of interest in his work.
planetary is to warrant now shifting ontologies, epis- James Martin has performed a valuable service in
temologies and ethics with knowledge which becomes gathering, newly translating or republishing, as well
productive primarily at the point where knowledge can as introducing, eighteen essays and interviews that
enact the interoperability of copyright agreements and cover the full scope of Poulantzas’s intellectual and
source code. political interests. The essays range from his human-
ist existentialo-Marxist early work through his more
James Tobias
structuralo-Marxist period to his development of a
new relational account of the state and state power
influenced not only by Marx, Engels and Gramsci
but also by Foucault and Lefebvre. As part of this

Revived comprehensive coverage, the editor includes material


that highlights the impact of Poulantzas’s early studies
in law (a legitimate route in the Greece of his student
Nicos Poulantzas, The Poulantzas Reader: Marxism, days, especially as his father was a well-known lawyer,
Law and the State, ed. and intro. James Martin, Verso,
to the study of sociology and politics as well as phil-
London and New York, 2008, vii + 437 pp., £60.00
hb., £19.99 pb., 978 1 84467 199 1 hb., 978 1 84467 osophy) and legal philosophy. Likewise, he includes
200 4 pb. early essays that reveal the significance in the early
post-doctoral period of the Italian philosopher and
Nicos Poulantzas was a virtually obligatory reference political leader, Antonio Gramsci. Indeed, I suspect
point in theoretical discussions of the state in the that it was their shared interest in Gramsci, on whom
1970s and 1980s, by virtue of his debate with Ralph Martin has also written extensively, that led him to
Miliband in the pages of New Left Review. Yet he want to bring the range of Poulantzas’s work to a new
seemed to have died a lingering intellectual death after generation of readers. The influence of Gramsci is
his suicide thirty years ago in 1978. By the 1990s, often ignored in commentaries that connect Poulantzas
there were few who referred to him positively in the mostly to the influence of Althusserian Marxism.
Anglophone world, and even then they often did so The Poulantzas Reader starts with an introduction
gesturally. In his adopted academic homeland, France, by the editor which provides much useful background
he was ‘disappeared’ from intellectual life along with information about political conditions in Greece when
other so-called structural Marxists in the 1980s, and Poulantzas was growing up, attended university and
in his native Greece he lives on primarily through served in the Greek navy, before moving to Germany
an eponymous party foundation linked to the Greek and then, quickly, to Paris. This is important because
Communist Party. it helps to locate his enduring interest in issues of
More recently, however, the work of Nicos Poulantzas state theory, the nature of liberal bourgeois democracy,
is reappearing, not only in the field of state theory exceptional regimes and political strategy. Martin also
but also in terms of his more general writings in summarizes Poulantzas’s later intellectual trajectory,
Marxist theory and political strategy. The same trend identifying its distinct phases – existentialo-Marxism,
emerged somewhat earlier in relation to one of his so-called structural Marxism, the emergence of a
theoretical influences, Louis Althusser, where, again, relational approach to social classes and the state
the benefits of distance have led to a rediscovery of through his engagement with contemporary political
the theoretical power and contemporary relevance issues and strategic debates, and the final syn­thesis
of a much misunderstood approach to key issues in and self-proclaimed completion of the Marxist theory

Radical Philosophy 152 (November/December 20 08) 61


of the state. In addition, the editor provides useful Although I am familiar with all eighteen essays in
contextualization and summaries of the eighteen this Reader, it was still a pleasure to read them in one
individual contributions by Poulantzas selected for sitting and to rediscover yet again what an exciting and
this Reader. I was particularly impressed with Mar- inspiring theorist Poulantzas was. In particular, these
tin’s decision to exclude the first exchanges in the essays reveal the extent to which, however forbiddingly
Poulantzas–Miliband debate and to content himself theoreticist his arguments may sometimes appear, they
with a brief summary of what was at stake. For this were motivated by political and strategic problems
debate did much to hinder an appreciation of the true rather than simple academic concerns. In this sense, his
magnitude of Poulantzas’s wide-ranging contributions key theoretical transitions were never prompted exclu-
to Marxist theory. Instead he has included the final sively by theoretical questions but always grounded
intervention in the debate by Poulantzas, comment- in pressing political issues. This is especially evident
ing after an interlude of six years, on lessons learnt, in his interviews and more journalistic pieces rather
critical ontological and methodological questions, and than in his monographs, and it is therefore good to see
the importance of adopting a consistently relational two interviews included in this Reader. In addition to
approach to the state. their intrinsic interest, these interviews also illuminate
As the subtitle of the Poulantzas Reader makes Poulantzas’s understanding of the strategic significance
clear, the essays include: of his work.
1. Various interventions at different times into con- Another crucial point that emerges from Martin’s
temporary Marxist theoretical and strategic debates Reader is the complexity of Poulantzas’s thought. He
among Marxists – including the nature of Marxism never followed one theoretical current single-mindedly
and the limitations of alternative approaches to Marxist but always sought to synthesize different traditions
analysis, such as Sartrean existentialism, economism, and to integrate material relevant to different fields of
humanism, Althusserian structuralism, and empiri- social life so that he could better understand a given
cism; the specificity of Marxist historical inquiry theoretical problem or a specific conjuncture. In this
(covering issues of periodization and class analysis as sense, his theoretical work cannot be reduced to the
well as the historical specificity of economic, political successive influences of Sartre, Gramsci, Althusser or
and ideological class domination in the development Foucault; there is always a distinctive Poulantzasian
of the English state); the significance of Gramsci as a appropriation of these great thinkers, shaped by his
theorist of hegemony; and both the nature of crises in continuing concern with ‘an autonomous science of
Marxism and the forms and extent of the contemporary politics’ and the specificity of the capitalist type of
crisis of Marxism in the 1970s. state. At the same time these essays reveal Poulant-
2. Early work on law – a theme to which Poulantzas zas’s growing awareness of the dangers of ‘politicism’
would return in one form or another throughout the – that is, a one-sided concern with the capitalist
remainder of his work, whether in terms of the signifi- type of state to the neglect of its embedding within
cance of sovereignty, the suspension of liberal democ- a capitalist social formation, its articulation with the
racy and constitutional government in fascism and social relations of capitalist production, and its over­
military dictatorships, the relation between violence determination of other types of social relation. This
and law, the threats posed by authoritarian statism, or can be seen in the increasing reintegration of general
the importance of human rights. and specific issues of political economy, class relations,
3. The question of the state – especially the histori- the mental–manual division of labour, the periodiza-
cal specificity of the capitalist type of state and the tion of capitalism, internationalization, new forms of
possibilities that this opens for what Gramsci called state intervention in the economy, the incompress-
an autonomous theory of politics; the problem of the ibility of economic crisis tendencies, and the political
normal state and exceptional regimes; the growing mediation of economic crisis-tendencies and struggles
trend towards authoritarian statism; the distinctive through political struggles conducted in and through
features of political (as opposed to economic or ideo- the institutional materiality of the state. For it was only
logical) crisis and the forms of a crisis of the state; when Poulantzas returned from the state as a distinc-
the distinctive problems posed by comparative analysis tive theoretical object to a more general concern with
of states, including the dependent state in dependent political economy that he could produce his original
capitalism; the nature of the state in state socialism; synthesis and plausibly claim to have completed the
and, lastly, the problems of a democratic transition to Marxist theory of the state.
democratic socialism. Bob Jessop

62 Radical Philosophy 152 (November/December 20 08)


Proclus and forgotten trajectories of Kant in aesthetic
Tools of thought geometric ‘sense reason’, which are ‘to be traced out
of the Critique of Pure Reason and embodied in the
Peg Rawes, Space, Geometry and Aesthetics: Through figure of the reflective subject in the later Critique of
Kant and towards Deleuze, Palgrave Macmillan, Judgement’.
London and New York, 2008. 256 pp., £45.00 hb.,
Rawes, in this context (as frequently elsewhere in
978 0 230 55291 3.
the book), explicitly invokes the figure of anamnesis,
Geometry is typically associated with the principles exemplified by her assertion that Kant repeats part of
of ‘scientific’ exactitude and management of space, Plato’s Meno – namely the famous Socratic example
as well as with the kind of ‘black-boxed’ efficacy and of the slave boy with intuitive geometric understanding
mastery that characterize the discipline in its absolute – and that Proclus, in assigning ‘the imagination to
or universal modality as quintessential exemplar of a position of mediation between the intelligible and
apodictic knowledge. If applied geometry is recogniz- sensible realms’, is a precursor to the third Critique.
able by the tools of compass and the ruler, it is such The first two chapters make a strong case, on this basis,
tools which, specifically in their practical deployment, for revealing a minor tradition of geometric thought
famously serve Kant in making the distinction, in the within, and in some senses against, philosophy, and
Critique of Judgement, between a priori imagination certainly against orthodox accounts of the functioning
and reflective judgement, and between geometrical of geometry within the dominant tradition. The inspi-
construction and the higher geometry. For Peg Rawes, ration for chapter 2 on Proclus, ‘Folding–Unfolding’, is
however, it is Kant’s dalliance with the basic tools of undeniably Deleuzean, and The Fold is clearly not far
geometry itself that is, in its way, most telling. In the from the author’s mind at this juncture, as well as when
philosopher’s very attention to these utilities lies the she moves towards a detailed engagement with the dis-
basis of the thesis developed in her book. tinct modalities of expression in Spinoza and Leibniz,
‘We are at a moment, I believe, when our experi- as these are articulated, in turn, in chapters 4 (‘Pas-
ence of the world is less that of a long life devel- sages’) and 5 (‘Plenums’). In her innovative chapter on
oping through time than that of a network that Spinoza, Rawes argues that the term ‘passages’ names
connects points and intersects with its own skein.’ the quality of Spinoza’s Ethics, most notably in the
This diagnosis of Foucault resonates with the general Scholia. These passages have a function beyond that
proposal made in Space, Geometry and Aesthetics. of a discursive demonstration of a geometric method,
Geometry is given back to the body, or the body back and entail, rather, a performative ‘figurational’ strategy.
to geometry – nowhere more so than in Husserl’s The uniqueness of Leibniz’s geometric method, Rawes
assertion, cited by Rawes, that, rather than being an proposes, is, by contrast, his conception of the plenum
instance of irrefutable reason, geometry is a ‘living as a topological figure enabling the paradoxical border
science’, which is constituted by an internal genetic of monadic interior and exterior (which is perhaps
or ‘living “tradition”’. most succinctly proposed in the late concept of the
If this explains the book’s main title, Rawes’s sub- ‘vinculum substantiale’, not discussed here) ‘rather
title, Through Kant and towards Deleuze, also proves than a finite limit’ between them. Leibniz’s role in
to be an accurate description of her concerns, albeit in producing the conditions for a thought of a properly
what would seem, initially, to be a more perverse way. immanent conception of temporality thus prepares the
For while we get plenty of Kant, we encounter almost way for the chapter on Bergson’s more emphatically
no direct discussion of Deleuze at all. The majority of topological geometric method. For Rawes, Bergson’s
the references to his work appear in footnotes, notably specific contribution to the history of sense-reason
to chapters 3 and 4, and we only ever get the sense that arises from the fact that ‘duration produces topologi-
he is indeed on the horizon (a moot term which is itself cal relations between philosophy and the subject that
subject to extended exegesis in chapter 6). Accurate dramatically reconfigure the nature of science, phil-
though it may be, then, it does lead one to ponder osophy and life’.
the apparently idiosyncratic inclusion of Deleuze’s The Deleuze towards whom the book is steering is
name here. Closer inspection reveals that this comes not therefore, as the author (with welcome subtlety)
down to the author’s need to proclaim the influence demonstrates, to be located at the end of a career, from
on her methodology of Deleuze’s idea of a ‘minor’ Proclus to Husserl, of the concept of ‘sense-reason’.
tradition. In Deleuze’s case, this tradition is made up The inclusion of a final chapter on Husserl, in place
of Hume–Spinoza–Nietzsche; in Rawes’s case, it is of the Deleuze which the book is still supposedly

Radical Philosophy 152 (November/December 20 08) 63


moving towards, is in fact to be explained rather by for scholars of Adorno. Such a constellation has a
elements of Husserl’s thought which, Rawes argues profound relevance today – one which Morgan makes
(largely in footnotes), are compatible with Deleuze. present throughout the book.
And it is, arguably, true that there is indeed more of Central to Morgan’s argument is Auschwitz, an
an affinity between the two philosophers than might event which, for Adorno, ‘changes the very nature of
commonly be expected, particularly in their respective any affirmative attempt at thinking the absolute, the
concepts of sense (the convergence being most obvious core of the metaphysical tradition’. It is one thing to
in Deleuze’s 1969 book Logic of Sense itself). make this assertion, another carefully to consider the
Rawes, who is a lecturer at the Bartlett School nature of this change: Auschwitz represents not only
of Architecture in London, writes with a keen eye the logical consequence of the dominance of identity
for connections between architectural design, the thinking, but also a paralysis that changes – or, more
visual arts and geometrical minor philosophy (in this specifically, limits – how we are able to think. As such,
regard, there is an especially rewarding paragraph it is not a culmination but a ‘caesura which reveals a
on the importance of drawing as ‘postulate’ rather latent meaning in all that has gone before’. Morgan
than ‘axiom’ in Proclus on page 56). That intention addresses the difficulty of accounting for the damage
is explicitly announced in her introduction, and the done to life from a subject-position that is itself affected
difficult task of giving palpable coordinates to an by this damage, considering not only the consequences
apparently ineffable and abstract domain allows the of suffering for a conception of the subject based on
book to participate in potentially fruitful exchange ‘a body that thinks’, but also the glimpses, within
with recent books by Rajchman, Massumi, Grosz and damaged life, of life as it might be lived. These occur
Goetz, each of whom has participated in an engage- most prominently within aesthetic experience, which
ment with space and/or architecture in the movement Morgan initially approaches through discussion of
either to or from a ‘Deleuzean’ aesthetics. Deleuze, Aesthetic Theory, and in particular Adorno’s account
then, is simultaneously everywhere and nowhere in of the ‘shudder’: a phenomenon that consists in the
particular in this richly suggestive and ceaselessly subject’s recognition, in contemplation of an artwork,
inventive book – like a kind of wind, as he himself of its own limitedness, which results in a process of
liked to characterize Spinoza’s Ethics. self-forgetting and disappearing into the work. Such
experience constitutes a ‘trace of “life” in an emphatic
Garin Dowd
sense, life in the sense of a reconciled relation between
subject and object that is non-subsumptive’. This is,
however, not a foundational experience, but a ‘reveal-

Life less unexamined ing outcome of a process of experience’, a speculative


immediacy that represents a potential. The theme is
further developed in the five ‘figures of exhaustion’ set
Alastair Morgan, Adorno’s Concept of Life, Continuum,
out towards the book’s end, in which Morgan analyses
London and New York, 2007. xi + 163 pp., £65.00 hb.,
978 0 826 49613 3. the dissolution of subjectivity in Adornian accounts
of the experience of literature and music as mimetic
Given that Adorno’s attitude towards Lebens­philosophie rationality opens up the possibility of reconciliation.
could be described as, at best, ambivalent, the attempt This dissolution consists in the ‘recognition of life as
to construct a philosophy of life out of his work might deadened’, which in turn produces a sense of loss, con-
seem a perversely unrewarding task – a difficulty fronting the horror of the mimesis of deadened life.
exacerbated by the fact that, as Morgan acknowledges, If I have a major complaint regarding Adorno’s
where Adorno does deploy a concept of life it is ‘not an Concept of Life it is that it sometimes reads as if
emphatic concept of life but damaged life as the form other thinkers have been brought in only so as to
of life within capitalism’. Morgan states that his aim is plug, as it were, the gaps in Adorno’s thought. At
to ‘defend Adorno’s dialectical philosophy as a means times this danger is acknowledged, as is the case with
of articulating a concept of life that evades either a the presentation of John Dewey’s account of aesthetic
biological reductionism or the hypostasization of life as experience. But at other points Morgan seems to move,
a process beyond the human that requires the dissolu- as if seamlessly, between sources as if they constitute
tion of the human subject’. Yet the attempt to construct parts of a single oeuvre split between two authors. This
a constellation of the different uses of concepts of life is most obviously the case in the material discussing
within his work is not simply an interesting exercise Giorgio Agamben’s concept of bare life. It is claimed

64 Radical Philosophy 152 (November/December 20 08)


that Agamben has ‘developed Adorno’s thinking’, or pitfalls, advancing an attentive reading of Adorno’s
that he ‘articulates Adorno’s thought’, with hardly a thought that is neither a refutation nor an unthinking
word exploring the broader nature of the relationship defence of every one of his claims. Rather it offers an
between their work, or with more than a glancing argument constructed through his works, investigating,
acknowledgement of the potential problems posed developing and interrogating a concept of life around,
by Agamben’s Foucauldian and Heideggerian influ- and through, his writings on diverse subjects. It not
ences. Instead, what is articulated is more a fleeting only provides a diagnosis of some of the problems that
juxtaposition than a detailed comparative study. This we face in damaged life, but also presents possibilities
is illuminating for Adorno’s texts, but at the same of thinking ways out of it.
time slightly unsatisfying, as the combination seems
Josh Robinson
almost overly felicitous. Indeed, perhaps the most
disappointing aspect of Morgan’s study is that the sec-
tions addressing thinkers other than Adorno – among
them figures as diverse as Agamben, Dewey, Michel
Henry, John McDowell and Emmanuel Levinas – often
Sharing
consist of little more than presentations of aspects
Nick Hewlett, Badiou, Balibar, Rancière: Re-thinking
of their thought. What is said is always astute and a
Emancipation, Continuum, London and New York,
relevant point of comparison, but they are not on the 2007. 208 pp., £65.00 hb., 978 0 826 49861 8.
whole treated with either the critical attention or the
Todd May, The Political Thought of Jacques Rancière:
intricacy of response afforded to the writings of either
Creating Equality, Penn State University Press and
Adorno or his direct critics. Edinburgh University Press, University Park PA and
This differs starkly from Morgan’s discussions of Edinburgh, 2008. 224 pp., £60.00 hb., £18.99 pb., 978
thinkers to whom Adorno makes more explicit refer- 0 271 03449 2 hb., 978 0 271 03450 8 pb.
ence, whether as an acknowledgement of influence
or as an unambiguous critique. Adorno’s treatments These two new books addressing the work of Jacques
of Nietzsche, Freud, Lukács, Husserl and Heidegger Rancière exemplify opposing strategies for introducing
are presented adroitly so as to draw out the points of a philosopher’s thought: one focusing on the context
interest for the understanding of his concept of life. of emergence in order to explain its motivations and
This adeptness is perhaps at its most visible in the shortcomings, the other obviating that context and
discussions of the work of Walter Benjamin, perhaps developing the thought into territories its author does
unsurprisingly given that Adorno’s explicit engagement not. Each book also exhibits effects typical of its
with Benjamin’s work, and the lengthy correspondence strategy. In the case of Hewlett’s Badiou, Balibar,
between them, make it considerably easier to trace both Rancière, the initial accessibility of the contextual
lines of influence and points of disagreement. He not approach runs into difficulties in engaging the thought
only recounts which of Adorno’s arguments have their on the level it demands. In May’s Political Thought of
origins in Benjamin’s thought, but also uses points Jacques Rancière, the possible hermeticism of a ‘theo-
of influence and subtle disagreement to illuminate retical’ approach nonetheless ultimately enables a criti-
the nuances of these arguments – whether through cal expansion of the philosopher’s initial proposal.
Adorno’s insistence, in relation to Benjamin’s essay on Badiou, Balibar, Rancière introduces its three
the artwork, that ‘the liquidation of subjectivity in the French philosophers by placing them within ‘the intel-
reception of film cannot be recuperated in terms of a lectual and political tradition which embraces the
subjective experience, because it has no experience as notion of human emancipation’. It provides a brief
Erfahrung to rely on’, or through the observation, in and clear presentation of their work (though some-
relation to Adorno’s account of the dialectical image, times inaccurate, as when it asserts the individual
that even metaphysical experience is mediated between character of Rancière’s subject or its pre-existence to
subject and object, and necessarily contains an inelimi- the political ‘event’), explaining the context in which
nable material moment. it originated and, on that basis, it identifies perceived
Andrew Bowie has claimed that scholarly work on limitations in their theories. May’s text, rather than
Adorno tends either to seek to demonstrate, despite the presenting Rancière’s political thought (as its title
important insights within his work, that his project as a suggests), elaborates a model of democratic politics
whole is fundamentally flawed, or to attempt to defend and a notion of active equality by taking as its starting
the indefensible. Morgan’s study avoids both of these point Rancière’s discussion of politics, which it opposes

Radical Philosophy 152 (November/December 20 08) 65


to liberal political theory and aligns with anarchism. are made on their grounds. In Hewlett’s assessment of
Managing to overcome the oddness of relating these Badiou, Balibar and Rancière, the presuppositions of
three disparate tendencies (liberalism, anarchism the biographical approach become apparent: first, the
and Rancière), it develops a functioning model of demand for coherence between an author’s theories and
democratic politics, through a critical engagement with his or her life (a coherence that, for different reasons,
Rancière’s thought. Hewlett, on the other hand, can is not present in any of the three); and second, an idea
only provide an introduction that ultimately strips the of propriety based on a conception of theory as the
three philosophers he discusses of the emancipatory suspicious opposite of the real world and the practices
potential he identifies in them. that take place within it.
Despite celebrating Badiou, Balibar and Rancière However, in Rancière’s work, this opposition
as ‘the most engaged philosophy since Sartre and between the abstraction of theory and the rigours of
Althusser’, Hewlett identifies their Althusserian origins the real is not tenable. His philosophy starts with the
and the intellectual and political situation in France recognition of practices – in which there are always
since the 1980s as part of the reason why the three both discursive and extra-discursive elements – and
of them fail in delivering a satisfactory model of continues with an attempt to understand the world in a
political emancipation. Their philosophies necessarily way that can contain those practices and, importantly,
belong to their time and biography, of which they are allow for new ones. In order to allow for new practices
symptomatic; their positions, as responses to the stag- (and not only ‘appropriate’ ones), theory must identify
nation of the Left in the face of a liberal conception possible obstructions to their emergence, and conceive
of democracy, become part of the diagnostic of such of a scenario where obstacles are minimized. This
stagnation. This failure is further identified by Hewlett version of Rancière’s thought is the one that May takes
as a result of a certain degree of theoreticism – a lack up in his book.
of consideration of ‘the rigours of the material world’ May starts with an account of the liberal and
due to their academic position; a criticism that echoes libertarian political theories of John Rawls, Robert
the one E.P. Thompson made of Althusser. Accord- Nozick and Amartya Sen. He continues by opposing
ing to Hewlett, the insufficient reference that their to them a notion of active equality based on Rancière’s
works make to the material world results in abstract model of democracy, which he then associates with
constructions that are unable to account for or provide Peter Kropotkin, Pierre-Joseph Proudhon and Mikhail
models for emancipatory practice. Additionally, for Bakunin’s communist anarchism. Here the counter-
Hewlett, Badiou’s ‘isolationist purism’ (and presumably intuitive confrontation of three disparate traditions
also Rancière’s), manifested in his refusal to engage allows May to illuminate Rancière’s thought, test it in
with ‘ordinary activists’, results in a position that is specific political contexts, question some of his conclu-
‘unrealistic’ rather than ‘politically appropriate’. This sions, and propose some departures. The key departure
empiricist critique seems to locate access to the real – an ethical version of Rancière’s democratic politics
in the descriptive abilities of the social sciences and – is, however, inconsistent with Rancière’s conception
the practical wisdom of the seasoned activist, though of politics. May constructs this ethical reading around
it is unclear whether for Hewlett this can also happen the notions of sharing and trust, which he obtains
in a third way – through the intuition of acting politi- through the partial translation of Rancière’s partage
cal subjects. In any case, there is a privileging of an as ‘sharing’ (rather than the couple ‘share/divide’ that
experiential element as the guarantor of the propriety Rancière insists on) and a mistranslation of confiant as
of both theory and practice. ‘trusting’ (rather than, as the original context demands,
Rancière himself has often warned against socio- ‘confident’). For Rancière, any attempt to define a
logical, historiographic or biographical accounts of specific attitude and behaviour as the model for politics
political events and cultural products, as their attempt is also an attempt to keep politics from happening.
to explain simultaneously determines and delimits So, although May’s identification of ethical behaviour
what is possible within politics or culture. His warning as essential to the process of political subjectivation
is obviously not to be taken as a prohibition against responds to the emancipatory goal that, as Hewlett
reconstructing his own thought in those terms, but points out, is at the heart of Rancière’s philosophy,
rather perhaps as a simple word of caution. This it responds in a way that, by trying to consolidate
caution tries to pre-empt not only determinism, but emancipation, creates obstacles to it.
also the interpretive schemas that are implied by a
historical/biographical reading, and the demands that Pablo Lafuente

66 Radical Philosophy 152 (November/December 20 08)


Letters

Critical views of South Africa


In ‘Beware Electocrats: Naomi Klein on South Africa’ apartheid-era loot, leaving South Africa with one of the
(the Commentary in RP 150, July–August 2008), world’s highest current account deficits today.
Ronald Suresh Roberts plays sophist with your readers. Roberts mocks Klein for citing a ‘supposedly’ con-
First, Klein’s Shock Doctrine chapter can and should straining IMF loan in 1993; indeed, explicit conditions
be read directly. Second, Roberts makes repeated inter- included wage restraint and shrinkage of the fiscal debt
pretive mistakes. If, as he claims, the African National ratio. The IMF also compelled Mandela to reappoint
Congress (ANC) government ‘successfully litigated the apartheid-era finance minister and central bank
against intellectual property rights that had stymied governor in May 1994.
cheap generic antiretrovirals’, why did Mbeki get away Third, politically, Roberts is a talk-left apologist for
with AIDS denialism for so long, and why did he fight a walk-right neoliberal neo-nationalist regime that has,
(in the country’s highest court) against the Treatment remarkably, worsened inequality, unemployment and the
Action Campaign’s insistence on making those medi- environment since 1994. Thus as ‘a direct participant’
cines available to millions who need them? in the Truth and Reconciliation Commission debates,
If, as Roberts claims, the ANC supports dramatic Roberts ‘explicitly advocated a systematic focus and
land reform, why has less than 5 per cent of available rejected precisely the narrow torture-based approach
land been redistributed and why was large-scale land that Klein criticizes’ – but neglects to mention that he
expropriation removed from the party’s legislative obviously failed, leaving the Commission absent in the
agenda in August 2008? struggle to rectify structural apartheid-caused inequal-
If, as he claims, the ANC ‘privatized nothing stra- ity through reparations demands upon big capital.
tegic other than the telephone company’, why was In this struggle, Mbeki tellingly takes the side of
a $1 billion apparatus (the Municipal Infrastructure the Bush, Brown and Merkel regimes, alongside three
Investment Unit) established at the Development dozen corporations currently being sued for apartheid-
Bank of Southern Africa with World Bank and US era profiteering under the US Alien Tort Claims Act.
AID support, readily embraced by the water ministry Fourth, descending to trivial personal insult, Roberts
Roberts worked for, specifically to promote public– dismisses Klein as ‘stubbornly Orientalist’. And,
private partnerships? perhaps flowing from the rough treatment Percy Ngo-
In reality, Mbeki’s team tried to privatize a great nyama and I gave his Mbeki biography (www.nu.ac.za/
deal – Telkom, two state airlines, electricity generation ccs/default.asp?2,40,3,1255), Roberts smears the Centre
capacity, toll roads, a middle-class resort network, and for Civil Society (CCS), which hosted Klein when
many municipal services (water, bus transport, rubbish, she was drafting the South Africa chapter of Shock
electricity) – and in all cases, any objective observer Doctrine. Roberts claims that CCS ‘at times accepted
would declare the result a failure. money from USAID’ (yes, once, for an activist-training
Roberts is just as weak on macroeconomics, such as project in 2002–03) but ignores the well-known fact
the feared ‘cash crunch that [apartheid-era, inherited] that USAID defunded CCS soon after the then-director,
debt repudiation would entail as retaliating banks Adam Habib, opposed the war on Iraq – and was later
shut down credit lines’. Argentina in 2002–03 proves branded a ‘terrorist’ and banned from entry into the
otherwise, and in any case South Africa did not expand USA. Ford has not extended new funding to CCS since
its foreign debt much after 1994, while mobilization the time I arrived there in late 2004. Similar rebuttals
of domestic resources could have been accomplished can be offered regarding William Mervin Gumede, a
with prescribed asset requirements on local financiers, far more reliable Mbeki watcher (according to Roberts,
a well-tested strategy. merely Klein’s ‘black native informant’).
Roberts also reports that currency controls were With less status quo bias, Roberts could put his
‘thick on the ground, a result of the apartheid regime’s considerable talents to better use.
earlier battles with capital flight’, without revealing Patrick Bond
that the ANC lifted them in 1995 and 1999, allowing Director, University of KwaZulu–Natal
rich whites and big capital to permanently expatriate Centre for Civil Society

Radical Philosophy 152 (November/December 20 08) 67


Reply to Bond
When I wrote that ‘Klein is content to recycle the by contrast, insisted that native submissiveness is a
impressions of a small and like-minded clique of ana- central trope of imperialism’s own propaganda (hence
lysts’ like Patrick Bond, I only guessed at what Bond imperialism’s infamously premature ‘Mission Accom-
confirms: his Centre for Civil Society (CCS) indeed plished’ banner in Iraq). Despite her anti-imperialist
‘hosted Klein when she was drafting the South Africa intentions, Klein’s account converges with empire’s
chapter of Shock Doctrine’. Klein’s uncharacteristically own story about itself.
weak South Africa chapter is a casualty of ideological I am a ‘talk-left apologist for a walk-right neo-
capture. liberal neo-nationalist regime’ (phew!). Posturing as
Bond evades my central argument: in a book that ‘independent’ critic, Bond sniffs that I ‘worked for’
seems to celebrate the wills of electorates, Klein a government ministry. Actually, I was the minister’s
strangely portrays electorates as susceptible to coma- personally appointed counterweight to, and critic of,
inducing ‘shocks’ that paralyse their wills. He sallies departmentally generated advice.
forth instead on matters of detail, but argues principally And here, caught red-handed in bad faith, is how
by non sequitur. That the democratic government ‘suc- Bond presented himself at a seminar on 3 September
cessfully litigated against intellectual property rights 2008, where he again attacked my RP commentary
that had stymied cheap generic antiretrovirals’ is not and, for that different audience, bolstered his cred-
an ‘interpretive mistake’ but a fact easily verifiable ibility thus: ‘I also worked for the water minister, as a
at the Pretoria High Court (see, e.g., http://academic. budget advisor, at exactly the same time as [Roberts].’
udayton.edu/health/06world/africa01.htm). Bond’s error (Bond’s own seminar notes are at www.nu.ac.za/ccs/
is astonishing. default.asp?2,68,3,1597). Bond’s cynical gyrations do
South Africa’s property clause expressly contem- Klein no good.
plates and encourages land reform. Klein specifically
Ronald Suresh Roberts
wrote the opposite. Dodging what I wrote, Bond attri-
butes to me the ill-defined suggestion that the ANC
‘supports dramatic land reform’ (which incidentally Editorial note  Roberts’s RP Commentary misattributed
Canadian citizenship to Patrick Bond as a result of an in-
it does, but that was not my point about Klein’s house error, for which the author bears no responsibility.
constitutional carelessness). Bond again hopes for a
careless readership when he writes that Mbeki’s team
‘tried’ to privatize lots. Klein of course wrote that the
ANC in fact privatized massively. This fake ‘fact’ but-
tresses her entire ‘shock’ thesis. On debt cancellation,
exchange controls, the pre-democracy IMF loan and
the Truth Commission Bond similarly rewrites what I
wrote. In each case he retreats from Klein’s specifics,
which I disputed.
Klein, I wrote, produces ‘well-meaning and yet stub-
bornly Orientalist representations of African politics’.
Bond rewrites: ‘descending to trivial personal insult,
Roberts dismisses Klein as “stubbornly Orientalist”’.
The point is fundamental, not trivial or personal.
‘With the Karl Marx epigraph at the front of his
Orientalism (“They cannot represent themselves, they
must be represented”) Edward Said meant to caution
not only against callow imperialists but also against
benignly orientalist protectors who trample upon native
political agency in the most well-meaning ways.’ Those
words opened my commentary. Klein argues that
shock jockeys in various times and places succeeded
in reducing their victims to political passivity. Said,

68 Radical Philosophy 152 (November/December 20 08)

Você também pode gostar