Você está na página 1de 5

> FEATURES 02

Barbara Kruger Untitled (Your gaze hits the side of my face) 1981

Dave Beech argues that beauty is


political not despite the fact that it
feels subjective but precisely because
it feels subjective

The Politics of Beauty


AVANTGARDISM INTERRUPTED THE HISTORICAL LINK BETWEEN ART AND BEAUTY.
IN RECASTING BEAUTY AS IDEOLOGICALLY COMPLICIT WITH POLITICAL POWER,
WHILE SIMULTANEOUSLY CULTIVATING A SENSITIVITY TO THE REPRESSED VALUE
OF UGLINESS, AVANTGARDISM POLITICISED BEAUTY.
To see beauty as politically loaded is to brand private, subjective
likes and dislikes as unintentional carriers of coded social information.
Today, of course, this kind of political and social inscription (whether understood in terms of ideology, the social
function of cultural distinction, suspicion about art’s institutions, the question of elitism or the social history of art and
taste) is common currency, but it is a specifically modern conception.
Ancient, classical, medieval, Renaissance and Enlightenment thinkers did not trouble themselves about how soci-
ety weaves its way through our intimate experiences. The history of the emergence of this modern conception of
socially inscribed behaviour is charted by Michael Rosen in his book On Voluntary Servitude where he argues that after

5.07 / ART MONTHLY / 306 5


02 FEATURES >

Marcel Duchamp concerned with knowing whether a thing is beautiful


Fountain 1917 or ugly; whether it is logical, probable or fanciful – we
pursue the ugly … And for the sake of strategy, since
we must always be on the alert to avoid backsliding
into habits which had become natural in the course of
a long tradition – to prevent the beautiful, the noble,
the exalted, the charming, the well-ordered, the per-
fect from catching the beast by the tail.’
The two most thoroughgoing avant-garde critiques
of beauty come from the leading thinkers of Dada and
Surrealism respectively, Marcel Duchamp and André
Breton. Duchamp’s rules for selecting the Ready-
mades, which he reported to be chosen according to
complete visual indifference, deliberately left no room
for beauty in art. Breton’s theory of ‘convulsive beauty’
took a different tack, violating the boundaries of tradi-
tional beauty with an intense experience of the object
based on the hysteric rather than the aesthete.
Art after avantgardism tended to preserve the
Avant Garde’s suspicion of beauty even when its
politicisation had been cooled. Clement Greenberg,
for instance, preferred to talk about works being
‘good’ or ‘successful’ rather than ‘beautiful’. After
that, Pop was vulgar, Minimalism was literal, Concep-
tual Art was opposed to the visual and Postmodernism
was either more interested in the sublime or regarded
beauty as one of art’s institutionalised discourses.
the 18th Century, society was seen for the first time as So, when Dave Hickey argued that the concept of
an active, behaviour-forming system or machine in beauty could be revived as a meaningful term for art
which individual belief and conduct are explained as criticism in the late 80s and early 90s, he was pit-
functional for or produced by society. ting himself against the entire history of Modernism
What is characteristic of premodern thinking is the and avantgardism, as well as the academics and
conviction that society is simply the aggregate of indi- curators of contemporary art’s institutions that he
vidual choices and actions. However, Adam Smith’s explicitly attacked. Unimpressed by the history of the
‘invisible hand’ and Hegel’s ‘cunning of reason’ initiat- politicisation of beauty, Hickey complains in his
ed a new conception of how individual actions were 1993 book The Invisible Dragon: Four Essays on
inextricably tied up with a greater whole. These were Beauty, ‘if you broached the issue of beauty in the
faint promises of what was to come – a fully fledged American art world of 1988, you … ignited a conver-
theory of the ways in which society infiltrates the sation about the market’.
thoughts, feelings and actions of individuals in even Hickey seemed to be stumped by the idea that
the most private and subjective experiences. artists, curators and writers might be wary of beauty,
Paul Ricoeur calls this modern interpretation of the and makes no mention whatsoever of the history of
relationship between the individual and society the avantgardism that animates the modern nervousness
‘hermeneutics of suspicion’. It was inaugurated, he says, towards beauty. While it is not true that the art market
by the works of Marx, Freud and Nietzsche. Ideology, was the source of the problem of beauty in art, I
the unconscious and the ‘will-to-power’ share a vital would suggest that the politicisation of beauty left
theoretical commitment to structures beyond the indi- beauty nowhere else to go.
vidual which decisively shape subjectivity itself. As a Hickey’s response to the contemporary art world’s
result, statements made by individuals about their inten- overwhelming resistance to beauty in the 80s was to
tions, beliefs and conduct cannot be accepted uncritical- switch the blame from the market (which he regards
ly. Rather, the suspicion is that individuals are inevitably as wholly benevolent) to art’s institutions (which he
prey to forces that they cannot control – forces of which despises in their every detail) and swap the problem
they are often entirely unaware. from that of beauty itself to the exclusion of beauty.
When avantgardism took up the hermeneutics of Hickey doesn’t blame artists for what he sees as the
suspicion in its diverse forms of cultural dissent, the underestimation of beauty in art; he blames art’s pub-
resistance to beauty was part and parcel of the resis- lic institutions and the academic bureaucrats who he
tance to bourgeois culture generally. ‘Except in strug- imagines set the agenda according to their own nar-
gle, there is no more beauty’, wrote FT Marinetti in row self-interests.
the 1905 Futurist Manifesto. Likewise, the Dadaist Amelia Jones, identifying herself as ‘just the type
Georges Ribemont-Dessaignes put the Avant Garde’s of “art professional” Hickey would surely excoriate’,
antipathy to beauty in stark terms: ‘One is no longer defends the critique of beauty by historicising and

6 306 / ART MONTHLY / 5.07


> FEATURES 02

contextualising ‘beauty discourse’ in her 2002 book


Aesthetics in a Multicultural Age. Jones roots out the >> The whole debate on beauty and
‘colonialist, sexist, and heterosexist assumptions’ of
beauty discourse, insisting that the rhetoric of beauty
aesthetics today is best understood as
‘merely veils privilege’.
Although Hickey’s ‘vernacular beauty’ is meant to
revolving around the tension between the
have ‘democratic appeal’, Jones is concerned ‘to interro- individual and society. The point is not to
gate the particular exclusions that are at work in any dis-
course that naturalizes “beauty”’, seeing in the logic of take sides but to rethink the question of
aesthetic judgements of this type not a direct route
between artwork and individual, but a historically, politi- beauty and debates on the aesthetic as
cally and culturally suffused product of social division
and inequality. Beauty, in such circumstances, has to be rooted in the fundamental tensions,
loaded. And no less so than when its privileges are inter-
nalised to the point of invisibility.
divisions and structures of modern,
As it stands, Jones’s complaint against Hickey has a
lot to recommend it, specifically the central conviction of
capitalist society.
the hermeneutics of suspicion that the social inscribes
itself into individual conduct and that it is therefore
socially produced. And yet, Jones’s critique expresses acquisition as if by an ‘iron cage’, which Adorno later
this modern predicament too forcefully – in too deter- rechristened the ‘totally administered society’.
ministic a fashion. Beauty is not simply a cryptic double Rational calculation structures the actions, events
for privilege, exclusion and power. and things in the modern world, ultimately including
The hermeneutics of suspicion does not thereby the consciousness, feelings and pleasures of those who
merely replace talk about individuals with talk about live in it. The key social relations of modern life – buy-
society (a hermeneutics of social certainties); it draws ers and sellers, managers and workers, experts and
out the tension between individual experience and clients, and so on – bring individuals together through
the social structure. This tension is played out in the anonymous processes of organisation, mediated by
contemporary debate over beauty as it is mapped in forms of rationality. Even the care industries are
James Elkins’ Art History Versus Aesthetics. Over and accounted for, monitored and managed in a unitised,
over again, a tug-of-war is staged between those who, anonymous and instrumental manner.
like Hickey, are interested in individual aesthetic Rather than detecting these social forces behind
experience, and those, like Jones, who want to his- the back of beauty, therefore, we can expect beauty
toricise and contextualise individual experience itself to be transformed internally by the rise of disen-
socially and politically. chantment, rationalisation and bureaucracy and the
Similarly, at one end, contemporary Adornian philo- historical marginalisation of ritual, myth, metaphysics
sophical aesthetics endorses aesthetic judgement against and magic. This is why, for instance, Modernism
the social critique of art, while, at the other end, the cri- either eliminated or streamlined beauty to steer clear
tique of the beauty industry sees the individual’s insecu- of the suspiciously decorative.
rities as exploited for profit. Stripped of traditional relations and forms of com-
In fact, the whole debate on beauty and aesthetics munity, the bulk of modern sociality is markedly asocial.
today is best understood as revolving around the tension Competition, rivalry, antagonism, instrumentality and
between the individual and society. The point is not to take exploitation are characteristic of the salient structural
sides but to rethink the question of beauty and debates on relations of contemporary society. Not only does subjec-
the aesthetic as rooted in the fundamental tensions, divi- tivity adapt to such conditions; it is also turned into an
sions and structures of modern, capitalist society. object of instrumental reason.
Modernity is characterised, in Max Weber’s terms, Kant’s philosophy of beauty stands uncomfortably
by disenchantment, rationalisation and bureaucracy. at the cusp of this modern world, no longer able to
Standardisation, efficiency, methodicalness and hard presume the individual subject’s asocial sovereignty,
work combine in modernity to produce what Weber, Kant labours to regulate a space for uncorrupted sub-
in his 1904-05 The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of jectivity by identifying all the major threats to it and
Capitalism, called the ‘specific and peculiar rational- then systematically eliminating them from aesthetic
ism of Western culture’. judgement properly conducted. For Kant, the subjec-
Weber sees this rationalisation embedded primari- tive was, if adequately protected, a route to universali-
ly within the two dominant social structures of mod- ty, but for alienated modern social life, the subjective
ern society – the capitalist economy and its state. was now framed by a peculiarly asocial version of
According to Weber, individuals within such enter- social life.
prises and institutions do not just happen to act Beauty’s version of modern asociality is fully formed
instrumentally, they are obliged to do so. Which is when its function is to express cultural and social dis-
why Weber describes the fate of the modern individ- tinctions as natural or subjective ones. To perpetuate
ual as constrained by the rationality of economic this ideological fiction requires a concept of the subject

5.07 / ART MONTHLY / 306 7


01 FEATURES >

that seems to exist independently of social forces – one beauty. No single code or measure of beauty can be
that can be universalised without suspicion. Historically, asserted because this would always be thought of, within
this subjective position has belonged to those who the modern conditions associated with the hermeneutics
regard their taste as educated, cultivated and true. Only of suspicion, as privileging one sector of society or one
those who benefit from the cultural profits of aesthetic culture over all others.
distinction have an interest in the fiction that beauty If this leads to aesthetic relativism, that is only
originates in subjective judgement and culminates in because the covert social processes that have made
universal taste. That is known in economics as securing beauty seem to be singular and universal have at last
a monopoly for one’s own private interests. been made transparent and open to critique. But we
Beauty might seem like something that we know need to be clear about something: Hickey’s revival of
when we see it, but the hermeneutics of suspicion beauty would not liberate anybody from the estab-
refers such experiences to hidden motives, unintended lished regime of intellectual taste if, as was the case
consequences, structural conditions and spurious before avantgardism, art’s institutions were dominat-
rationalisations – in short, the economies of taste. We ed by an authorised version of beauty. What is more,
continue to see beauty around us but this can no Hickey’s liberatory version of beauty, which seems to
longer be the kind of elevated experience that might place the individual in an unmediated relation to the
stand outside ordinary disputes, hierarchies and ten- artwork, would only be possible if (and only if) indi-
sions. I want to call this historical process the seculari- viduals derived their tastes, feelings and pleasures
sation of beauty. entirely spontaneously, subjectively and asocially – ie
The philosophy of beauty from Plato to Kant may in ways that seemed natural before the 18th Century
have been ethically charged, but it did not theorise and became naïve and improbable thereafter.
how individual pleasures, choices and tastes are Modern social relations bring about two contradic-
always unwittingly charged with social content. Beau- tory conceptions of beauty: one is the conviction that it
ty becomes secular through the same historical is a purely private, subjective experience; and the other
process by which art sheds its aura. As social rela- is that beauty, like all subjective experiences, is socially
tions take on an anonymous, mechanised and inscribed. Each, in effect, represents one side of the
abstract manner, beauty itself becomes subject to tension between individual and society that structures
rationality, commodity exchange and calculation. modern capitalism. To choose one of them is to fail to
Beauty gets tied up with design, style and marketing. see how beauty has been transformed immanently by
Losing its innocence in this way, beauty comes to feel the forces of modern alienation.
saccharine or even violent. At the same time beauty Our understanding of beauty can no longer assume
loses its advantage over vulgarity, primitivism, func- (or insist on) the individual’s autonomy to make
tionalism or any number of beauty’s rivals. Within judgements without unintended consequences or to
Modernism, beauty has no more to recommend it take pleasure without risking structural and ideologi-
than the chaotic, the accidental, the miserable, the cal complicity and culpability. At the same time, the
ruined or the overlooked. reduction of the individual to the social does not ade-
Beauty has become utterly contentious. Instead of quately register the modern tension between individ-
being an aesthetic category of experience in which sub- ual and society. Beauty is political not despite the fact
jective feelings of pleasure are expressed, beauty has that it feels subjective but precisely because it feels
been fragmented – no judgement of beauty can be made subjective. Beauty enters us into a world of dispute,
without it being compared with equivalent judgements contention and conflict at the very moment when we
made by people with different racial, gender, class or cul- feel ourselves to be at ease. ❚
tural inscriptions. This is why the secularisation of beau-
ty is necessarily and irreversibly also the politicisation of DAVE BEECH is an artist.
Child, 2002 © the artist 2007
David Shrigley, Strange Toy for Strange

Cult Fiction – Art Paula Rego’s Epstein’s Rock Drill


and the Comic Book Nursery Rhymes until 30 September
4 May – 1 July Until 20 May
Lucian Freud
Suzanne Treister – Guest Star Portraits and Andrew Tift
HEXEN 2039 Rolf Harris – ‘Portrait of Kitty’
27 April – 8 July Her Majesty, 1948 – 2006
The Queen 2005 26 May – 2 September
28 April – 10 June

The New Art Gallery Walsall


Gallery Square
Walsall WS2 8 LG
T: 01922 654400
F: 01922 654401

8 306 / ART MONTHLY / 5.07

Você também pode gostar