Você está na página 1de 10

0163-769X/09/$20.

00/0 Endocrine Reviews 30(3):204 –213


Printed in U.S.A. Copyright © 2009 by The Endocrine Society
doi: 10.1210/er.2008-0031

Ethical Issues in Stem Cell Research


Bernard Lo and Lindsay Parham
Program in Medical Ethics, the Division of General Internal Medicine, and the Department of Medicine, University of California San
Francisco, San Francisco, California 94143

Stem cell research offers great promise for understanding basic specific to embryonic stem cell research. In any hSC research, however,
mechanisms of human development and differentiation, as well as the difficult dilemmas arise regarding sensitive down-stream research,
hope for new treatments for diseases such as diabetes, spinal cord injury, consent to donate materials for hSC re-search, early clinical trials of hSC
Parkinson’s disease, and myo-cardial infarction. However, human stem therapies, and oversight of hSC research. These ethical and policy issues
cell (hSC) research also raises sharp ethical and political controversies. need to be discussed along with scientific challenges to ensure that stem
The der-ivation of pluripotent stem cell lines from oocytes and em-bryos cell research is carried out in an ethically appropriate manner. This
is fraught with disputes about the onset of human per-sonhood. The article provides a critical analysis of these issues and how they are
reprogramming of somatic cells to produce induced pluripotent stem cells addressed in current policies. (Endocrine Reviews 30: 204 –213, 2009)
avoids the ethical problems

I. Introduction tent cells into specialized cells that could be used for
II. Multipotent Stem Cells transplantation.
A. Cord blood stem cells However, human stem cell (hSC) research also raises sharp
B. Adult blood stem cells ethical and political controversies. The derivation of pluri-potent
III. Embryonic Stem Cell Research stem cell lines from oocytes and embryos is fraught with disputes
A. Existing embryonic stem cell lines regarding the onset of human personhood and human
B. New embryonic stem cell lines from frozen embryos reproduction. Several other methods of deriving stem cells raise
C. Ethical concerns about oocyte donation for research IV. fewer ethical concerns. The reprogramming of somatic cells to
Somatic Cell Nuclear Transfer (SCNT) produce induced pluripotent stem cells (iPS cells) avoids the
A. Ethical concerns about SCNT V. ethical problems specific to embryonic stem cells. With any hSC
Fetal Stem Cells research, however, there are dif-ficult dilemmas, including
VI. Induced Pluripotent Stem Cells (iPS Cells) consent to donate materials for hSC research, early clinical trials
A. Downstream research of hSC therapies, and over-sight of hSC research (2). Table 1
VII. Stem Cell Clinical Trials summarizes the ethical issues that arise at different phases of stem
A. Risks and prospective benefits in stem cell clinical cell research.
trials
B. Informed consent in early stem cell clinical trials VIII.
Institutional Oversight of Stem Cell Research II. Multipotent Stem Cells
A. The Stem Cell Research Oversight Committee (SCRO) B.
Use of stem cell lines derived at another institution Adult stem cells and cord blood stem cells do not raise special
ethical concerns and are widely used in research and clinical care.
However, these cells cannot be expanded in vitro and have not
I. Introduction been definitively shown to be pluripotent.

S TEM CELL RESEARCH offers great promise for under-standing


basic mechanisms of human development and differentiation, as well
A. Cord blood stem cells

as the hope for new treatments for dis-eases such as diabetes, spinal Hematopoietic stem cells from cord blood can be banked and
cord injury, Parkinson’s disease, and myocardial infarction (1). are widely used for allogenic and autologous stem cell
Pluripotent stem cells perpet-uate themselves in culture and can transplantation in pediatric hematological diseases as an al-
differentiate into all types of specialized cells. Scientists plan to ternative to bone marrow transplantation.
differentiate pluripo-

B. Adult blood stem cells


First Published Online April 14, 2009
Abbreviations: ART, Artificial reproductive technology; hESC, hu-man Adult stem cells occur in many tissues and can differen-tiate
embryonic stem cell; hSC, human stem cell; iPS cells, induced pluripotent
stem cells; IRB, institutional review board; IVF, in vitro fertilization; SCNT,
into specialized cells in their tissue of origin and also
somatic cell nuclear transfer. transdifferentiate into specialized cells characteristic of other
Endocrine Reviews is published by The Endocrine Society (http:// tissues. For example, hematopoietic stem cells can differen-tiate
www.endo-society.org), the foremost professional society serving the into all three blood cell types as well as into neural stem cells,
endocrine community. cardiomyocytes, and liver cells.
204
Lo and Parham • Ethical Issues in Stem Cell Research Endocrine Reviews, May 2009, 30(3):204 –213 205

TABLE 1. Ethical issues at different phases of stem cell research ever, such opposition to stem cell research is not monolithic. A
number of pro-life leaders support stem cell research using frozen
Phase of research Ethical issues
embryos that remain after a woman or couple has completed
Donation of biological Informed and voluntary consent infertility treatment and that they have decided not to give to
materials
Research with hESCs Destruction of embryos another couple. This view is held, for example, by former First
Creation of embryos specifically Lady Nancy Reagan and by U.S. Senator Orrin Hatch.
for research purposes
1. Payment to oocyte donors On his Senate website, Sen. Hatch states: “The support of
2. Medical risks of oocyte
retrieval embryonic stem cell research is consistent with pro-life, pro-
3. Protecting reproductive family values.
interests of women in “I believe that human life begins in the womb, not a Petri dish
infertility treatment or refrigerator . . . . To me, the morality of the situation dictates
Use of stem cell lines derived Conflicting legal and ethical
that these embryos, which are routinely discarded, be used to
at another institution standards
Stem cell clinical trials Risks and benefits of improve and save lives. The tragedy would be in not using these
experimental intervention embryos to save lives when the alternative is that they would be
Informed consent discarded” (6).

Adult stem cells can be isolated through plasmapheresis. They A. Existing embryonic stem cell lines
are already used to treat hematological malignancies and to
modify the side effects of cancer chemotherapy. Fur-thermore, In 2001, President Bush, who holds strong pro-life views,
autologous stem cells are being used in clinical trials in patients allowed federal National Institutes of Health (NIH) funding for
stem cell research using embryonic stem cell lines already in
who have suffered myocardial infarction. Their use in several
existence at the time, while prohibiting NIH funding for the
other conditions has not been validated or is experimental, despite
derivation or use of additional embryonic stem cell lines. This
some claims to the contrary (3).
policy was a response to a growing sense that hESC research held
great promise for understanding and treating degenerative
III. Embryonic Stem Cell Research diseases, while still opposing further destruc-tion of human
embryos. NIH funding was viewed by many researchers as
Pluripotent stem cell lines can be derived from the inner cell essential for attracting scientists to make a long-term commitment
mass of the 5- to 7-d-old blastocyst. However, human embryonic to study the basic biology of stem cells; without a strong basic
stem cell (hESC) research is ethically and politi-cally science platform, therapeutic breakthroughs would be less likely.
controversial because it involves the destruction of hu-man
embryos. In the United States, the question of when human life President Bush’s rationale for this policy was that the embryos
begins has been highly controversial and closely linked to debates from which these lines were produced had already been
over abortion. It is not disputed that em-bryos have the potential destroyed. Allowing research to be carried out on the stem cell
to become human beings; if im-planted into a woman’s uterus at lines might allow some good to come out of their destruction.
the appropriate hormonal phase, an embryo could implant, However, using only existing embryonic stem cell lines is
develop into a fetus, and become a live-born child. scientifically problematic. Originally, the NIH announced that
over 60 hESC lines would be acceptable for NIH funding.
Some people, however, believe that an embryo is a person with However, the majority of these lines were not suitable for
the same moral status as an adult or a live-born child. As a matter research; for example, they were not truly plu-ripotent, had
of religious faith and moral conviction, they believe that “human become contaminated, or were not available for shipping. As of
life begins at conception” and that an embryo is therefore a January 2009, 22 hESC lines are eligible for NIH funding.
person. According to this view, an embryo has interests and rights However, these lines may not be safe for trans-plantation into
that must be respected. From this perspec-tive, taking a blastocyst humans, and long-standing lines have been shown to accumulate
and removing the inner cell mass to derive an embryonic stem mutations, including several known to predispose to cancer. In
cell line is tantamount to murder (4). addition, concerns have been raised about the consent process for
Many other people have a different view of the moral status of the derivation of some of these NIH-approved lines (7). The vast
the embryo, for example that the embryo becomes a person in a majority of scientific ex-perts, including the Director of the NIH
moral sense at a later stage of development than fertilization. Few under President Bush, believe that a lack of access to new
people, however, believe that the embryo or blastocyst is just a embryonic stem cell lines hinders progress toward stem cell-
clump of cells that can be used for research without restriction. based transplanta-tion (8). For example, lines from a wider range
Many hold a middle ground that the early embryo deserves of donors would allow more patients to receive human leukocyte
special respect as a potential human being but that it is acceptable agent matched stem cell transplants (9).
to use it for certain types of research provided there is good
scientific justification, careful oversight, and informed consent Currently, federal funds may not be used to derive new
from the woman or couple for donating the embryo for research embryonic stem cell lines or to work with hESC lines not on the
(5). approved NIH list. NIH-funded equipment and labora-tory space
Opposition to hESC research is often associated with op- may not be used for research on nonapproved hESC lines. Both
position to abortion and with the “pro-life” movement. How- the derivation of new hESC lines and re-
206 Endocrine Reviews, May 2009, 30(3):204 –213 Lo and Parham • Ethical Issues in Stem Cell Research

search with hESC lines not approved by NIH may be carried out pay freezer storage fees), to donate them to another infertile
under nonfederal funding. Because of these restrictions on NIH woman or couple, or to discard them. If a patient chooses to
funding, a number of states have established pro-grams to fund discard the embryos, it would be possible to instead remove
stem cell research, including the derivation of new embryonic identifiers and use them for research. Still another possibility
stem cell lines. California, for example, has allocated $3 billion involves frozen embryos from patients who do not respond to
over 10 yr to stem cell research. requests to make a decision regarding the disposition of frozen
Under President Obama, it is expected that federal fund-ing embryos. Some IVF practices have a policy to discard such
will be made available to carry out research with hESC lines not embryos and inform patients of this policy when they give
on the NIH list and to derive new hESC lines from frozen consent for the IVF procedures. Again, rather than dis-card such
embryos donated for research after a woman or cou-ple using in frozen embryos, it is logistically feasible to dei-dentify them and
vitro fertilization (IVF) has determined they are no longer needed give them to researchers.
for reproductive purposes. However, fed-eral funding may not be However, the ethical justifications for allowing deidenti-fied
permitted for creation of embryos expressly for research or for biological materials to be used for research without consent do
derivation of stem cell lines using somatic cell nuclear transfer not always hold for embryo research (13). For example, one
(SCNT) (10, 11). rationale for allowing the use of deidentified materials is that the
ethical risks are very low; there can be no breach of
B. New embryonic stem cell lines from frozen embryos confidentiality, which is the main concern in this type of research.
A second rationale is that people would not object to having their
Women and couples who undergo infertility treatment often materials used in such a manner if they were asked. However, this
have frozen embryos remaining after they complete their assumption does not necessarily hold in the context of embryo
infertility treatment. The disposition of these frozen embryos is research. A 2007 study found that 49% of women with frozen
often a difficult decision for them to make (12). Some choose to embryos would be willing to donate them for research (12). Such
donate these remaining embryos to research rather than giving donors might be of-fended or feel wronged if their frozen
them to another couple for reproductive purposes or destroying embryos were used for research that they did not consent to.
them. Several ethical concerns come into play when a frozen Deidentifying the ma-terials would not address their concerns.
embryo is donated, including in-formed consent from the woman
or couple donating the embryo, consent from gamete donors
involved in the cre-ation of the embryo, and the confidentiality of 3. Consent from gamete donors. Frozen embryos may be created
donor information. with sperm or oocytes from donors who do not participate any
further in assisted reproduction or childrearing. Some people
1. Informed consent for donation of materials for stem cell argue that consent from gamete donors is not re-quired for
research. Since the Nuremburg Code, informed consent has been embryo research because they have ceded their right to direct
re-garded as a basic requirement for research with human sub- further usage of their gametes to the artificial reproductive
jects. Consent is particularly important in research with hu-man technology (ART) patients. However, gamete donors who are
embryos (13). Members of the public and potential donors of willing to help women and couples bear children may object to
embryos for research hold strong and diverse opinions on the the use of their genetic materials for research. In one study, 25%
matter. Some consider all embryo research to be unacceptable; of women who donated oocytes for infertility treatment did not
others only support some forms of re-search. For instance, a want the embryos created to be used for research (17). This
person might consider infertility re-search acceptable but object percentage is not unexpected because reproductive materials have
to research to derive stem cell lines or research that might lead to special significance, and many people in the United States oppose
patents or commercial products (14). Obtaining informed consent embryo re-search. Little is known about the wishes of sperm
for potential fu-ture uses of the donated embryo respects this donors concerning research.
diversity of views. Additionally, people commonly place special
emo-tional and moral significance on their reproductive materials, There are substantial practical differences between obtain-ing
compared with other tissues (15). consent for embryo research from oocyte donors and from sperm
donors. ART clinics can readily discuss donation for research
with oocyte donors during visits for oocyte stim-ulation and
2. Waiver of consent. In the United States, federal regulations on retrieval. However, most ART clinics obtain do-nor sperm from
research permit a waiver of informed consent for the research use sperm banks and generally have no direct contact with the donors.
of deidentified biological materials that cannot be linked to Furthermore, sperm is often do-nated anonymously to sperm
donors (16). Thus, logistically it would be pos-sible to carry out banks, with strict confidenti-ality provisions.
embryo and stem cell research on deiden-tified materials without
consent. For example, during IVF procedures, oocytes that fail to As a matter of respect for gamete donors, their wishes
fertilize or embryos that fail to develop sufficiently to be regarding stem cell derivation should be determined and
implanted are ordinarily dis-carded. These materials could be respected (13). Gamete donors who are willing to help women
deidentified and then used by researchers. Furthermore, if and couples bear children may object to the use of their genetic
infertility patients have fro-zen embryos remaining after they materials for research. Specific consent for stem cell research
complete treatment, they are routinely contacted by the IVF from both embryo and gamete donors was recommended by the
program to decide whether they want to continue to store the National Academy of Sciences 2005 Guidelines for Human
embryos (and to Embryonic Stem Cell Research and
Lo and Parham • Ethical Issues in Stem Cell Research Endocrine Reviews, May 2009, 30(3):204 –213 207

has been adopted by the California Institute for Regenerative ing, infection, and complications of anesthesia (25). These risks
Medicine (CIRM), the state agency funding stem cell research may be minimized by the exclusion of donors at high-risk for
(18, 19). This consent requirement need not imply that em-bryos these complications, careful monitoring of the num-ber of
are people or that gametes or embryos are research subjects. developing follicles, and adjusting the dose of human chorionic
gonadotropin administered to induce ovulation or canceling the
4. Confidentiality of donor information. Confidentiality must be cycle (25).
carefully protected in embryo and hESC research because Because severe hyperovulation syndrome may require
breaches of confidentiality might subject donors to un-wanted hospitalization or surgery, women donating oocytes for re-search
publicity or even harassment by opponents of hESC research should be protected against the costs of complications of
(20). Although identifying information about do-nors must be hormonal stimulation and oocyte retrieval (19). The United States
retained in case of audits by the Food and Drug Administration as does not have universal health insurance. As a matter of fairness,
part of the approval process for new ther-apies, concerns about women who undergo an invasive pro-cedure for the benefit of
confidentiality may deter some donors from agreeing to be science and who are not receiving payment beyond expenses
recontacted. should not bear any costs for the treatment of complications. Even
Recently, confidentiality of personal health care informa-tion if a woman has health insurance, copayments and deductibles
has been violated through deliberate breaches by staff, through might be substantial, and if she later applied for individual-rated
break-ins by computer hackers, and through loss or theft of laptop health insurance, her premiums might be prohibitive.
computers. Files containing the identities of persons whose Compensation for re-search injuries has been recommended by
gametes or embryos were used to derive hESC lines should be several U.S. panels
protected through heightened security measures (20). Any (26) but has not been adopted because of difficulties calcu-lating
computer storing such files should be locked in a secure room and long-term actuarial risk and assessing intervening fac-tors that
password-protected, with access limited to a minimum number of could contribute to or cause adverse events.
individuals on a strict “need-to-know” basis. Entry to the Requiring free care for short-term complications of oocyte
computer storage room should also be restricted by means of a donation is feasible. In California, research institutions must
card-key, or equiv-alent system, that records each entry. Audit ensure free treatment to oocyte donors for direct and prox-imate
trails of access to the information should be routinely monitored medical complications of oocyte retrieval in state-funded
for inap-propriate access. The files with identifiers should be research. The term “direct and proximate” is a legal concept to
copy-protected and double encrypted, with one of the keys held determine how closely an injury needs to be con-nected to an
by a high-ranking institutional official who is not involved in event or condition to assign responsibility for the injury to the
stem cell research. The computer storing these data should not be person who carried out the event or created the condition.
connected to the Internet. To protect information from subpoena, Commercial insurance policies are available to cover short-term
investigators should obtain a federal Certificate of complications of oocyte retrieval. CIRM allows state stem cell
Confidentiality. Human factors in breaches of confidentiality grants to cover the cost of such insur-ance. The rationale for
should also be considered. Personnel who have access to these making research institutions respon-sible for treatment is that they
identifiers might receive additional background checks, are in a better position than individual researchers to identify
interviews, and training. The personnel responsible for insurance policies and would have an incentive to consider
maintaining this confidential database and contacting any donor extending such cover-age to other research injuries.
should not be part of any research team.

hESC research using fresh oocytes donated for research raises 2. Protecting the reproductive interests of women in infertility
several additional ethical concerns as well, as we next discuss treatment. If women in infertility treatment share oocytes with
(21). researchers— either their own oocytes or those from an oocyte
donor—their prospect of reproductive success may be
C. Ethical concerns about oocyte donation for research compromised because fewer oocytes are available for repro-
ductive purposes (21). In this situation, the physician carry-ing
Concerns about oocyte donation specifically for research are
out oocyte retrieval and infertility care should give pri-ority to the
particularly serious in the wake of the Hwang scandal in South
reproductive needs of the patient in IVF. The highest quality
Korea, in which widely hailed claims of deriving hu-man SCNT
oocytes should be used for reproductive pur-poses (21).
lines were fabricated. In addition to scientific fraud, the scandal
involved inappropriate payments to oo-cyte donors, serious
As discussed in Section B. 2, in IVF programs some oocytes
deficiencies in the informed consent process, undue influence on
fail to fertilize, and some embryos fail to develop sufficiently to
staff and junior scientists to serve as donors, and an unacceptably
be implanted. Such materials may be donated to research-ers. To
high incidence of med-ical complications from oocyte donation
protect the reproductive interests of donors, several safeguards
(22–24). In California, some legislators and members of the
should be in place (20). For the donation of fresh embryos for
public have charged that infertility clinics downplay the risks of
research, the determination by the embryologist that an embryo is
oocyte donation (19). CIRM has put in place several protections
not suitable for implantation and therefore should be discarded is
for women donating oocytes in state-funded stem cell research.
a matter of judgment. Similarly, the determination that an oocyte
has failed to fertilize and thus cannot be used for reproduction is a
1. Medical risks of oocyte retrieval. The medical risks of oocyte judgment call. To avoid any conflict of interest, the embryologist
retrieval include ovarian hyperstimulation syndrome, bleed- should not know
208 Endocrine Reviews, May 2009, 30(3):204 –213 Lo and Parham • Ethical Issues in Stem Cell Research

whether a woman has agreed to research donation and also should comprehension has also been carried out with respect to oocyte
receive no funding from grants associated with the research. donation for clinical infertility services.
Furthermore, the treating infertility physicians should not know
whether or not their patients agree to do-nate materials for
IV. Somatic Cell Nuclear Transfer (SCNT)
research.
Pluripotent stem cell lines whose nuclear DNA matches a
3. Payment to oocyte donors. Many jurisdictions have conflict-ing specific person have several scientific advantages. Stem cell lines
policies about payment to oocyte donors. Reimburse-ment to matched to persons with specific diseases can serve as in vitro
oocyte donors for out-of-pocket expenses presents no ethical models of diseases, elucidate the pathophysiology of diseases,
problems because donors gain no financial ad-vantage from and screen potential new therapies. Lines matched to specific
participating in research. However, payment to oocyte donors in individuals also offer the promise of personalized autologous
excess of reasonable out-of-pocket expenses is controversial, and stem cell transplantation.
jurisdictions have conflicting policies that may also be internally One approach to creating such lines is through SCNT, the
inconsistent (27, 28). technique that produced Dolly the sheep. In SCNT, repro-
Good arguments can be made both for and against paying gramming is achieved after transferring nuclear DNA from a
donors of research oocytes more than their expenses (29). On the donor cell into an oocyte from which the nucleus has been
one hand, some object that such payments induce women to removed. However, creating human SCNT stem cell lines has not
undertake excessive risks, particularly poorly educated women only been scientifically impossible to date but is also ethically
who have limited options for employment, as oc-curred in the controversial (34, 35).
Hwang scandal. Such concerns about undue influence, however,
may be addressed without banning pay-ment. For example, A. Ethical concerns about SCNT
participants could be asked questions to ensure that they
understood key features of the study and that they felt they had a 1. Objections to creating embryos specifically for research. Some
choice regarding participation (19). Also, careful monitoring and people who object to SCNT believe that creating embryos with
adjustment of hormone doses can minimize the risks associated the intention of using them for research and destroying them in
with oocyte donation (25). A further objection is that paying that process violates respect for nascent human life. Even those
women who provide research oocytes undermines human dignity who support deriving stem cell lines from frozen embryos that
because human biological materials and intimate relationships are would otherwise be discarded sometimes reject the intentional
devalued if these ma-terials are bought and sold like commodities creation of embryos for research. In rebuttal, however, some
(14, 30). argue that pluripotent entities created through SCNT are
On the other hand, some contend that it is unfair to ban biologically and ethically distinct from embryos (36).
payments to donors of research oocytes, while allowing women to
receive thousands of U.S. dollars to undergo the same procedures 2. Objections to human reproduction using SCNT. There are
to provide oocytes for infertility treatment (29). Moreover, several compelling objections to using SCNT for human re-
healthy volunteers, both men and women, are paid to undergo production. First, because of errors during reprogramming of
other invasive research procedures, such as liver biopsy, for genetic material, cloned animal embryos fail to activate key
research purposes. Furthermore, bans on payment for oocyte embryonic genes, and newborn clones misexpress hun-dreds of
donation for research have been criti-cized as paternalistic, genes (37, 38). The risk of severe congenital defects would be
denying women the authority to make decisions for themselves prohibitively high in humans. Second, even if SCNT could be
(31). On a pragmatic level, without such payment, it is very carried out safely in humans, some object that it violates human
difficult to recruit oocyte donors for research. dignity and undermines traditional, fun-damental moral, religious,
and cultural values (34). A cloned child would have only one
genetic parent and would be the genetic twin of that parent. In this
4. Informed consent for oocyte donation. In California, CIRM has view, cloning would lead children to be regarded more as
instituted heightened requirements for informed consent for “products of a designed manufacturing process than ‘gifts’ whom
oocyte donation for research (19). The CIRM regulations go their parents are prepared to accept as they are.” Furthermore,
beyond requirements for disclosure of information to oocyte cloning would violate “the natural boundaries between
donors (19). The major ethical issue is whether donors ap-preciate generations” (34). For these reasons, cloning for reproductive
key information about oocyte donation, not simply whether the purposes is widely considered morally wrong and is illegal in a
information has been disclosed to them or not. As discussed number of states. Moreover, some people argue that because the
previously, in other research settings, research participants often technique of SCNT can be used for reproduction, its devel-
fail to understand the information in de-tailed consent forms (32). opment and use for basic research should be banned.
CIRM thus reasons that disclosure, while necessary, is not
sufficient to guarantee informed con-sent. In CIRM-funded
research, oocyte donors must be asked questions to ensure that 3. Use of animal oocytes to create SCNT lines using human DNA.
they comprehend the key features of the research (19). Evaluating Because of the shortage of human oocytes for SCNT research,
comprehension is feasible be-cause it has been carried out in some scientists wish to use nonhuman oocytes to derive lines
other research contexts, such as in HIV prevention trials in the using human nuclear DNA. These so-called “cytoplasmic hybrid
developing world (33). According to testimony presented to embryos” raise a number of ethical concerns. Some opponents
CIRM, evaluation of fear the creation of chimeras—mythical beasts
Lo and Parham • Ethical Issues in Stem Cell Research Endocrine Reviews, May 2009, 30(3):204 –213 209

that appear part human and part animal and have charac-teristics searchers have been trying to eliminate safety concerns about
of both humans and animals (39). Opponents may feel deep moral inserting oncogenes and insertional mutagenesis. Repro-
unease or repugnance, without articulating their concerns in more gramming has been successfully accomplished without known
specific terms. Some people view such hybrid embryos as oncogenes and using adenovirus vectors rather than retrovirus
contrary to a moral order embodied in the natural world and in vectors. A further step was the recent demonstra-tion that human
natural law. In this view, each species has a particular moral embryonic fibroblasts can be reprogrammed to a pluripotent state
purpose or goal, which mankind should not try to change. Others using a plasmid with a peptide-linked reprogramming cassette
view such research as an inappropriate crossing of species (47, 48). Not only was reprogram-ming accomplished without
barriers, which should be an immutable part of natural design. using a virus, but the transgene can be removed after
Finally, some are con-cerned that there may be attempts to reprogramming is accomplished. The ultimate goal is to induce
implant these embryos for reproductive purposes. pluripotentiality without genetic manipulation. Because of
unresolved problems with iPS cells, which currently preclude
In rebuttal, supporters of such research point out that the their use for cell-based therapies, most scientists urge continued
biological definitions of species are not natural and immu-table research with hESC (49).
but empirical and pragmatic (40 – 42). Animal-animal hybrids of
various sorts, such as the mule, exist and are not considered iPS cells avoid the heated debates over the ethics of em-
morally objectionable. Moreover, in medical re-search, human bryonic stem cell research because embryos or oocytes are not
cells are commonly injected into nonhuman animals and used. Furthermore, because a skin biopsy to obtain so-matic cells
incorporated into their functioning tissue. In-deed, this is widely is relatively noninvasive, there are fewer concerns about risks to
done in research with all types of stem cells to demonstrate that donors compared with oocyte donation. The President’s Council
cells are pluripotent or have dif-ferentiated into the desired type on Bioethics called iPS cells “ethically unproblematic and
of cell. In addition, some concerns can be addressed through strict acceptable for use in humans” (39). Nei-ther the donation of
oversight (40), for example prohibiting reproductive uses of these materials to derive iPS cells nor their derivation raises special
embryos and limiting in vitro development to 14 d or the ethical issues.
development of the primitive streak, limits that are widely
accepted for other hESC research. Finally, some people regard A. Downstream research
repugnance per se an unconvincing guide to ethical judgments.
People dis-agree over what is repugnant, and their views might Some potential downstream uses of iPS cell derivatives may be
change over time. Blood transfusion and cadaveric organ so sensitive as to call into question whether the original somatic
transplan-tation were originally viewed as repugnant but are now cell donors would have agreed to such uses (50). iPS cells will be
widely accepted practices. Furthermore, after public discus-sion shared widely among researchers who will carry out a variety of
and education, many people overcome their initial concerns. studies with iPS cells and deriv-atives, using common and well-
accepted scientific practices, such as:

• Genetic modifications of cells


V. Fetal Stem Cells • Injection of derived cells into nonhuman animals to dem-
onstrate their function, including the injection into the brains
Pluripotent stem cells can be derived from fetal tissue after of nonhuman animals.
abortion. However, use of fetal tissue is ethically controver-sial • Large-scale genome sequencing
because it is associated with abortion, which many peo-ple object • Sharing cell lines with other researchers, with appropriate
to. Under federal regulations, research with fetal tissue is confidentiality protections, and
permitted provided that the donation of tissue for research is • Patenting scientific discoveries and developing commer-cial
considered only after the decision to terminate pregnancy has tests and therapies, with no sharing of royalties with donors
been made. This requirement minimizes the possibility that a (51).
woman’s decision to terminate pregnancy might be influenced by
These standard research techniques are widely used in other
the prospect of contributing tissue to research. Currently there is a
types of basic research, including research with stem cells from
phase 1 clinical trial in Batten’s disease, a lethal degenerative
other sources. Generally, donors of biological ma-terials are not
disease affecting children, us-ing neural stem cells derived from
explicitly informed of these research proce-dures, although such
fetal tissue (43, 44).
disclosure is now proposed for whole genome sequencing (52,
53).
VI. Induced Pluripotent Stem Cells (iPS Cells) Such studies are of fundamental importance in stem cell
biology, for example to characterize the lines and to dem-onstrate
Somatic cells can be reprogrammed to form pluripotent stem that they are pluripotent. Large-scale genome se-quencing will
cells (45, 46), called induced pluripotential stem cells (iPS cells). yield insights about the pathogenesis of dis-ease and identify new
These iPS cell lines will have DNA matching that of the somatic targets for therapy. Injection of human stem cells into the brains
cell donors and will be useful as disease models and potentially of nonhuman animals will be re-quired for preclinical testing of
for allogenic transplantation. cell-based therapies for many conditions, such as Parkinson’s
Early iPS cell lines were derived by inserting genes en-coding disease, Alzheimer’s disease, and stroke.
for transcription factors, using retroviral vectors. Re-
210 Endocrine Reviews, May 2009, 30(3):204 –213 Lo and Parham • Ethical Issues in Stem Cell Research

However, some downstream research could also raise eth-ical entific rationale, transparency, oversight, or patient pro-tections”
concerns. For example, large-scale genome sequencing may (58). Although supporting medical innovation under very limited
evoke concerns about privacy and confidentiality. Do-nors might circumstances, the International Soci-ety for Stem Cell Research
consider it a violation of privacy if scientists know their future has decried such use of un-proven hSC transplantation.
susceptibility to many genetic diseases. Further-more, it may be
possible to reidentify the donor of a dei-dentified large-scale These clinical trials should follow ethical principles that guide
genome sequence using information in forensic DNA databases or all clinical research, including appropriate balance of risks and
at an Internet company offering personal genomic testing (54, benefits and informed, voluntary consent. Addi-tional ethical
55). Other donors may object to their cells being injected into requirements are also warranted to strengthen trial design,
animals. For example, they may oppose all animal research, or coordinate scientific and ethics review, verify that participants
they may have religious objections to the mixing of human and understand key features of the trial, and ensure publication of
animal species. The injection of human neural progenitor cells negative findings (59). These measures are appropriate because of
into nonhuman animals has raised ethical concerns about animals the highly innovative nature of the intervention, limited
develop-ing characteristics considered uniquely human (56, 57). experience in humans, and the high hopes of patients who have
Still other donors may not want cell lines derived from their no effective treatments.
biological materials to be patented as a step toward devel-oping
new tests and therapies. People are unlikely to drop such
A. Risks and prospective benefits in stem cell clinical trials
objections even if the cell lines were deidentified or even if many
years had passed since the original donation. Thus there may be a The risks of innovative stem cell-based interventions in-clude
tension between respecting the autonomy of donors and obtaining “tumor formation, immunological reactions, unex-pected
scientific benefit from research, which can be resolved during the behavior of the cells, and unknown long-term health effects” (58).
process of obtaining consent for the original donation of Evidence of safety and proof of principle should be established
materials. through appropriate preclinical studies in rel-evant animal models
or through human studies of similar cell-based interventions.
It would be unfortunate if iPS cell lines that turned out to be Requirements for proof of principle and safety should be higher if
extremely useful scientifically (for example because of robust cells have been manipulated extensively in vitro or have been
growth in tissue culture) could not be used in addi-tional research derived from pluripotent stem cells (58).
because the somatic cell donor objected. One approach to avoid
this is to preferentially use somatic cells from donors who are Even with these safeguards, however, because of the highly
willing to allow all such basic stem cell research and to be innovative nature of the intervention and limited experience in
contacted for future sensitive research that cannot be anticipated humans, unanticipated serious adverse events may occur. In older
at the time of consent (50). Donors could also be offered the clinical trials of transplantation of fetal dopaminergic neurons
option of consenting to additional specific types of sensitive but into persons with Parkinson’s dis-ease, transplanted cells failed to
not fundamental downstream research, such as allogenic improve clinical outcomes (60, 61). Indeed, about 15% of
transplantation into other humans and reproductive research subjects receiving transplan-tation late developed disabling
involving the creation of totipo-tent entities. dyskinesias, with some need-ing ablative surgery to relieve these
adverse events (60, 61). Although the transplanted cells localized
Because these concerns about consent for sensitive down- to the target areas of the brain, engrafted, and functioned to
stream research also apply to other types of stem cells, it would produce the in-tended neurotransmitters, appropriately regulated
be prudent to put in place similar standards for con-sent to donate physio-logical function was not achieved. Participants in phase I
materials for derivation of other types of stem cells. However, trials may not thoroughly understand the possibility that hESC
these concerns are particularly salient for iPS cells because of the transplantation might make their condition worse.
widespread perception that these cells raise no serious ethical
problems and because they are likely to play an increasing role in
stem cell research.
B. Informed consent in early stem cell clinical trials
Problems with informed consent are well documented in phase
VII. Stem Cell Clinical Trials I clinical trials. Participants in cancer clinical trials commonly
expect that they will benefit personally from the trial, although
Transplantation of cells derived from pluripotent stem cells the primary purpose of phase I trials is to test safety rather than
offers the promise of effective new treatments. How-ever, such efficacy (62). This tendency to view clinical research as providing
transplantation also involves great uncertainty and the possibility personal benefit has been termed the “therapeutic misconception”
of serious risks. Some stem cell therapies have been shown to be (32, 63). Analyses of cancer clin-ical trials reveal that the
effective and safe, for example he-matopoietic stem cell information in consent forms gen-erally is adequate. However, in
transplants for leukemia and epithelial stem cell-based treatments early phase I gene transfer clinical trials, researchers’ descriptions
for burns and corneal disorders (58). However, “there are some of the direct benefit to participants commonly were vague,
clinics around the world already exploiting patients’ hopes by ambiguous, and inde-terminate (64).
purporting to offer effective stem cell therapies for seriously ill
patients, typ-ically for large sums of money, but without credible Participants in phase I stem cell-based clinical trials might
sci- overestimate their benefits and underestimate the risks. The
Lo and Parham • Ethical Issues in Stem Cell Research Endocrine Reviews, May 2009, 30(3):204 –213 211

scientific rationale for hSC transplantation and preclinical results to protect human subjects, as well as the expertise of IRB
may seem compelling. In addition, highly optimistic press members. There should be a sound scientific justification for
coverage might reinforce unrealistic hopes. using human oocytes and embryos to derive new human stem cell
Several measures may enhance informed consent in early stem lines. However, IRBs usually do not carry out in-depth scientific
cell-based clinical trials (59). First, researchers should describe review. Some ethical issues in hESC research do not involve
the risks and prospective benefits in a realistic man-ner. human subjects’ protection, for example the concern that
Researchers need to communicate the distinction be-tween the transplanting human stem cells into nonhuman animals might
long-term hope for effective treatments and the uncertainty result in characteristics that are regarded as uniquely human.
inherent in any phase I trial. Participants in phase I studies need
to understand that the intervention has never been tried before in
humans for the specific condition, that researchers do not know A. The stem cell research oversight committee (SCRO)
whether it will work as hoped, and that the great majority of
participants in phase I studies do not receive a direct benefit. An institutional SCRO with appropriate scientific and eth-ical
expertise, as well as public members, should be convened at each
Second, investigators in hESC clinical trials should discuss a institution to review, approve, and oversee stem cell research (18,
broader range of information with potential participants than in 69, 70). The SCRO will need to work closely with the IRB and, in
other clinical trials. The doctrine of informed consent requires cases of animal research, with the Institutional Animal Care and
researchers to discuss with potential participants information that Use Committee. Because of the sensitive nature of hSC research,
is pertinent to their decision to volunteer for the clinical trial (65). the SCRO should include nonaffil-iated and lay members who
Generally, the relevant information concerns the nature of the can ensure that public concerns are taken into account.
intervention being studied and the risks and prospective benefits.
However, in hESC transplan-tation, nonmedical issues may be
prominent or even decisive for some participants. Individuals B. Use of stem cell lines derived at another institution
who regard the embryo as having the moral status of a person
would likely have strong objections to receiving hESC Sharing stem cells across institutions facilitates scientific
transplants. Although this in-tervention might benefit them progress and minimizes the number of oocytes, embryos, and
medically, such individuals might regard it as complicit with an somatic cells used. However, ethical concerns arise if researchers
immoral action. Thus researchers in clinical trials of hESC work with lines that were derived in other ju-risdictions under
transplantation should inform eligible participants that conditions that would not be permitted at their home institution.
transplanted materials orig-inated from human embryos. Researchers and SCROs need to dis-tinguish core ethical
standards that are accepted by interna-tional consensus—
Third, and most important, researchers should verify that informed consent and an acceptable bal-ance of benefits and risks
participants have a realistic understanding of the clinical trial —from standards that vary across jurisdictions and cultures.
(59). The crucial ethical issue about informed consent is not what Using lines whose derivation vi-olated core standards would
researchers disclose in consent forms or discussions, but rather erode ethical conduct of re-search by providing incentives to
what the participants in clinical trials understand. In other others to violate those standards.
contexts, some researchers have ensured that par-ticipants
understand the key features of the trial by assessing their The review process should focus on those types of hSC
comprehension. In HIV clinical trials in developing countries, derivation that raise heightened levels of ethical concern (71).
where it has been alleged that participants did not understand the hSC lines derived using fresh oocytes and embryos require in-
trial, many researchers are now testing each participant to be sure depth review because of concerns about the medical risks of
he or she understands the essential features of the research (33). oocyte donation, undue influence, and setbacks to the
Such direct assessment of par-ticipants’ understanding of the reproductive goals of a woman undergoing infertility treatment.
study has been recom-mended more broadly in contexts in which
misunderstand-ings are likely (26). We urge that such tests of Dilemmas occur when donors of research oocytes receive
comprehension be carried out in phase I trials of hSC payments in excess of their expenses and such payments are not
transplantation (58, 59). permitted in the jurisdiction where the hSC cells will be used. For
Careful attention to consent in highly innovative clinical trials example, the United Kingdom enacted an explicit policy to allow
might prevent controversies later. In early clinical trials of organ such payment after public consultation and debate and provided
transplantation, the implantable totally artificial heart, and gene reasons to justify its decision (72–75). Jurisdictions that ban
transfer, the occurrence of serious adverse events led to payments should accept such carefully considered policies as a
allegations that study participants had not truly understood the reasonable difference of opinion on a complex issue. Concerns
nature of the research (66 – 68). The resulting ethical about payment should be less if lines were derived from frozen
controversies brought about negative publicity and delays in embryos remaining after IVF treatment and donors were paid in
subsequent clinical trials. the reproductive context. Such payments, which were carried out
before donation for research was actually considered, are not an
inducement for hESC research (71).
VIII. Institutional Oversight of Stem Cell Research

Human stem cell research raises some ethical issues that are Other dilemmas arise with hESC lines derived from em-bryos
beyond the mission of institutional review boards (IRBs) using gamete donors. As previously discussed, explicit
212 Endocrine Reviews, May 2009, 30(3):204 –213 Lo and Parham • Ethical Issues in Stem Cell Research

consent for the use of reproductive materials in stem cell research Schill KE, Siegel A, Solter D, Suter SM, Verfaillie CM, Walters LB,
should be obtained from any gamete donors as well as embryo Gearhart JD, Faden RR 2003 Safety issues in cell-based intervention
trials. Fertil Steril 80:1077–1085
donors (13, 76). An exception may be made to “grandparent” 10. 2009 Stem cell bill is reintroduced. The New York Times, February 27,
older lines derived from frozen embryos cre-ated before such 2009; A15
explicit consent became the standard of care, for example before 11. Hulse C 2009 Democrats debate methods to end stem cell ban. The New
the 2005 National Academy of Sciences guidelines (76). Use of York Times, January 3, 2009; A11
such older lines is appropriate because it would be unreasonable 12. Lyerly AD, Faden RR 2007 Embryonic stem cells. Willingness to donate
frozen embryos for stem cell research. Science 317:46 – 47
to expect physicians to comply with standards that had not yet 13. Lo B, Chou V, Cedars MI, Gates E, Taylor RN, Wagner RM, Wolf L,
been developed (71). It would also be acceptable to grandparent Yamamoto KR 2003 Consent from donors for embryo and stem cell
lines if gamete donors agreed to unspecified future research or research. Science 301:921
gave dispositional control of frozen embryos to the woman or 14. Radin MJ 1996 Contested commodities. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press
couple in IVF. However, the derivation should be consistent with 15. 1998 Assisted reproductive technologies. New York: The New York State
the ethical and legal standards in place at the time the line was Task Force on Life and the Law; 165–169
derived. 16. 1999 Research on human stored biologic materials. Rockville, MD:
In summary, hSC research offers exciting opportunities for National Bioethics Advisory Commission
scientific advances and new therapies, but also raises some 17. Kalfoglou AL, Geller G 2000 A follow-up study with oocyte donors
exploring their experiences, knowledge, and attitudes about the use of
complex ethical and policy issues. These issues need to be their oocytes and the outcome of the donation. Fertil Steril 74: 660 – 667
discussed along with scientific challenges to ensure that stem cell
research is carried out in an ethically appropriate manner. 18. National Research Council and Institute of Medicine 2005 Guide-lines
for human embryonic stem cell research. Washington, D.C.: National
Academies Press
19. Lomax GP, Hall ZW, Lo B 2007 Responsible oversight of human stem
cell research. The California Institute for Regenerative Medi-cine’s
Acknowledgments Medical and Ethical Standards. PLoS Med 4:e114
20. Lo B, Zettler P, Cedars MI, Gates E, Kriegstein AR, Oberman M,
Received July 10, 2008. Accepted March 10, 2009. Reijo Pera R, Wagner RM, Wuerth MT, Wolf LE, Yamamoto KR
Address all correspondence and requests for reprints to: Dr. Bernard Lo, 2005 A new era in the ethics of human embryonic stem cell research.
University of California San Francisco Program in Medical Ethics, 521 Stem Cells 23:1454 –1459
Parnassus Avenue, Suite C-126, San Francisco, California 94143. E-mail: 21. Levens ED, DeCherney AH 2008 Human oocyte research: the ethics of
bernard.lo@ucsf.edu. donation and donor protection. JAMA 300:2174 –2176
This work was supported by National Institutes of Health (NIH) Grant 1 22. Holden C 2006 Korean stem cell scandal. Schatten: Pitt panel finds
UL1 RR024131-01 from the National Center for Research Re-sources ‘misbehavior’ but not misconduct. Science 311:928
(NCRR) and NIH Roadmap for Medical Research and by the Greenwall 23. Chong S 2006 Scientific misconduct. Investigations document still more
Foundation. Its contents are solely the responsibility of the authors and do not problems for stem cell researchers. Science 311:754 –755
necessarily represent the official view of NCRR or NIH. 24. Chong S, Normile D 2006 Stem cells. How young Korean research-ers
helped unearth a scandal. Science 311:22–25
B.L. is co-chair of the California Institute for Regenerative Medicine 25. National Research Council and Institute of Medicine 2007 Assess-ing
Scientific and Medical Accountability Standards Working Group. the medical risks of human oocyte donation for stem cell re-search.
Disclosure Summary: The authors have no conflicts of interest to declare. Washington, D.C.: National Academies Press
26. 2001 Ethical and policy issues in research involving human partic-ipants.
Rockville, MD: National Bioethics Advisory Commission
27. Spar D 2007 The egg trade—making sense of the market for human
References oocytes. N Engl J Med 356:1289 –1291
28. 2007 Donation. Chap 8. Fertil Steril 87:S28
1. Committee on the Biological and Biomedical Applications of Stem 29. Hyun I 2006 Fair payment or undue inducement? Nature 442:629 – 630
Cell Research, Commission on Life Sciences, National Research
Council, Board on Neuroscience and Behavioral Health, Institute of 30. Holland S 2001 Contested commodities at both ends of life: buying and
Medicine 2002 Stem cells and the future of regenerative medicine. selling gametes, embryos, and body tissues. Kennedy Inst Ethics J
Washington, D.C.: National Academies Press 11:263–284
2. Lo B 2009 Resolving ethical dilemmas in clinical research. Phila-delphia: 31. Steinbock B 2004 Payment for egg donation and surrogacy. Mt Sinai J
Lippincott Williams, Wilkins Med 71:255–265
32. Appelbaum PS, Lidz CW 2008 The therapeutic misconception. In:
3. Smith S, Neaves W, Teitelbaum S 2007 Adult versus embryonic stem
Emanuel EJ, Grady C, Crouch RA, Lie RK, Miller FG, Wendler D, eds.
cells: treatments. Science 316:1422–1423; author reply, 1422– 1423
The Oxford textbook of clinical research ethics. New York: Oxford
4. 2004 Monitoring stem cell research. Washington, D.C.: The Presi-dent’s University Press; 633– 644
33. Woodsong C, Karim QA 2005 A model designed to enhance in-formed
Council on Bioethics
consent: experiences from the HIV prevention trials net-work. Am J
5. 1994 Report of the Human Embryo Research Panel. Bethesda, MD:
Public Health 95:412– 419
National Institutes of Health
34. 2002 Human cloning and human dignity: an ethical inquiry. Wash-
6. July 17, 2001. Statement of Senator Orrin G. Hatch on stem cell research.
ington, D.C.: The President’s Council on Bioethics
Available at: http://hatch.senate.gov/public/index.cfm? FuseAction
35. 1997 Cloning human beings. Rockville, MD: National Bioethics Ad-
PressReleases.Print&PressRelease_id fca0c5e3–40c8–4cd3-822e-
visory Commission
efff0f2633de&suppresslayouts true&IsTextOnly True. Accessed
36. McHugh PR 2004 Zygote and “clonote”—the ethical use of embry-onic
December 18, 2008
stem cells. N Engl J Med 351:209 –211
7. Streiffer R 2008 Informed consent and federal funding for stem cell
37. Jaenisch R 2004 Human cloning—the science and ethics of nuclear
research. Hastings Cent Rep 38:40 – 47
transplantation. N Engl J Med 351:2787–2791
8. Alanso-Zaldivar R, Kaplan K 2007 Loosening of stem cell limits
38. National Research Council and Institute of Medicine 2002 Scien-tific
backed. Los Angeles Times, March 20, 2007; A1
and medical aspects of human reproductive cloning. Washing-ton, D.C.:
9. Dawson L, Bateman-House AS, Mueller Agnew D, Bok H, Brock DW,
National Academies Press
Chakravarti A, Greene M, King PA, O’Brien SJ, Sachs DH,
Lo and Parham • Ethical Issues in Stem Cell Research Endocrine Reviews, May 2009, 30(3):204 –213 213

39. 2005 White paper: alternative sources of human pluripotent stem Wong AL, Zoloth L, Daley GQ 2008 New ISSCR guidelines un-
cells. Washington, D.C.: The President’s Council on Bioethics derscore major principles for responsible translational stem cell re-search.
40. Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority 2007 Hybrids and Cell Stem Cell 3:607– 609
chimeras: findings of the consultation. Available at: http://www. 59. Lo B, Kriegstein A, Grady D 2008 Clinical trials in stem cell trans-
hfea.gov.uk/en/1581.html. Accessed September 22, 2007 plantation: guidelines for scientific and ethical review. Clin Trials 5:517–
41. Robert JS 2006 The science and ethics of making part-human ani-mals in 522
stem cell biology. FASEB J 20:838 – 845 60. Olanow CW, Goetz CG, Kordower JH, Stoessl AJ, Sossi V, Brin MF,
42. Baylis F, Robert JS 2007 Part-human chimeras: worrying the facts, Shannon KM, Nauert GM, Perl DP, Godbold J, Freeman TB 2003 A
probing the ethics. Am J Bioeth 7:41– 45 double-blind controlled trial of bilateral fetal nigral trans-plantation in
43. Clinical trial overview: neuronal ceroid lipofuscinosis (NCL, often Parkinson’s disease. Ann Neurol 54:403– 414
called Batten disease). Available at: http://www.stemcellsinc.com/ 61. Freed CR, Greene PE, Breeze RE, Tsai WY, DuMouchel W, Kao R,
clinicaltrials/clinicaltrials.html. Accessed March 4, 2009 Dillon S, Winfield H, Culver S, Trojanowski JQ, Eidelberg D, Fahn S
44. 18 December 2008 StemCells, Inc. receives FDA approval to ini-tiate 2001 Transplantation of embryonic dopamine neurons for severe
clinical trial of HuCNS-SC cells in a myelin disease. Avail-able at: Parkinson’s disease. N Engl J Med 344:710 –719
http://www.stemcellsinc.com/news/081218.html. Ac-cessed March 3, 62. Joffe S, Cook EF, Cleary PD, Clark JW, Weeks JC 2001 Quality of
2009 informed consent in cancer clinical trials: a cross-sectional survey. Lancet
45. Takahashi K, Tanabe K, Ohnuki M, Narita M, Ichisaka T, Tomoda K, 358:1772–1777
Yamanaka S 2007 Induction of pluripotent stem cells from adult human 63. Lidz CW, Appelbaum PS, Grisso T, Renaud M 2004 Therapeutic
fibroblasts by defined factors. Cell 131:861– 872 misconception and the appreciation of risks in clinical trials. Soc Sci Med
46. Park IH, Arora N, Huo H, Maherali N, Ahfeldt T, Shimamura A, 58:1689 –1697
Lensch MW, Cowan C, Hochedlinger K, Daley GQ 2008 Disease- 64. Henderson GE, Davis AM, King NM, Easter MM, Zimmer CR,
specific induced pluripotent stem cells. Cell 134:877– 886 Rothschild BB, Wilfond BS, Nelson DK, Churchill LR 2004 Un-
47. Kaji K, Norrby K, Paca A, Mileikovsky M, Mohseni P, Woltjen K 1 certain benefit: investigators’ views and communications in early phase
March 2009 Virus-free induction of pluripotency and subsequent excision gene transfer trials. Mol Ther 10:225–231
of reprogramming actors. Nature 10.1038/nature07864 65. Berg JW, Lidz CW, Appelbaum PS 2001 Informed consent: legal
48. Woltjen K, Michael IP, Mohseni P, Desai R, Mileikovsky M, theory and clinical practice. 2nd ed. New York: Oxford University Press
Ha¨ma¨la¨inen R, Cowling R, Wang W, Liu P, Gertsenstein M, Kaji
K, Sung HK, Nagy A 1 March 2009 piggyBac transposition re-programs 66. Fox RC, Swazey JP 1992 Spare parts. New York: Oxford University
fibroblasts to induced pluripotent stem cells. Nature 10.1038/nature07863 Press
67. Couzin J, Kaiser J 2005 Gene therapy. As Gelsinger case ends, gene
49. International Society for Stem Cell Research 2008 Endorse the open therapy suffers another blow. Science 307:1028
letter. Support all forms of stem cell research. Available at: http:// 68. Steinbrook R 2008 The Gelsinger case. In: Emanuel EJ, Grady C,
www.isscr.org/ScienceStatementEndorsers.cfm. Accessed January 7, 2009 Crouch RA, Lie RK, Miller FG, Wendler D, eds. The Oxford textbook of
50. Aalto-Setala K, Conklin BR, Lo B 24 February 2009 Obtaining consent clinical research ethics. New York: Oxford University Press; 110 –120
for future research with induced pluripotent cells: oppor-tunities and 69. Zettler P, Wolf LE, Lo B 2007 Establishing procedures for institu-tional
challenges. PLoS Biol 10.1371/journal.pbio.1000042 oversight of stem cell research. Acad Med 82:6 –10
51. Korobkin R 2007 Stem cell century. New Haven, CT: Yale University 70. National Research Council and Institute of Medicine 2008 Amend-
Press ments to the National Academies’ guidelines for human embryonic stem
52. Caulfield T, McGuire AL, Cho M, Buchanan JA, Burgess MM, cell research. Washington, D.C.: National Academy Press
Danilczyk U, Diaz CM, Fryer-Edwards K, Green SK, Hodosh MA, 71. Lo B, Parham L, Broom C, Cedars M, Gates E, Giudice L, Halme
Juengst ET, Kaye J, Kedes L, Knoppers BM, Lemmens T, Meslin DG, Hershon W, Kriegstein A, Kwok PY, Oberman M, Roberts C,
EM, Murphy J, Nussbaum RL, Otlowski M, Pullman D, Ray PN, Wagner R 2009 Importing human pluripotent stem cell lines derived at
Sugarman J, Timmons M 2008 Research ethics recommendations for another institution: Tailoring review to ethical concerns. Cell Stem Cell
whole-genome research: consensus statement. PLoS Biol 6:e73 4:115–123
53. McGuire AL, Caulfield T, Cho MK 2008 Research ethics and the 72. Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority 2007 The Code of
challenge of whole-genome sequencing. Nat Rev Genet 9:152–156 Practice. 7th ed. Available at: http://www.hfea.gov.uk/en/371. html.
54. Lowrance WW, Collins FS 2007 Ethics. Identifiability in genomic Accessed October 16, 2008
research. Science 317:600 – 602 73. Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority 2007 Donating eggs
55. McGuire AL, Gibbs RA 2006 Genetics. No longer de-identified. Science for research: safeguarding donors. Available at: http://www.
312:370 –371 hfea.gov.uk/en/1417.html. Accessed October 18, 2008
56. Greely HT, Cho MK, Hogle LF, Satz DM 2007 Thinking about the 74. Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority 2006 The regula-tion
human neuron mouse. Am J Bioeth 7:27– 40 of donor-assisted conception: a consultation on policy and reg-ulatory
57. Greely HT, Cho MK, Hogle LF, Satz DM 2007 Response to open peer measures affecting sperm, egg and embryo donation in the United
commentaries on “Thinking about the human neuron mouse.” Am J Kingdom. Available at: http://www.hfea.gov.uk/docs/ SeedConsult.pdf.
Bioeth 7:W4 – 6 Accessed October 18, 2008
58. Hyun I, Lindvall O, Ahrlund-Richter L, Cattaneo E, Cavazzana- 75. Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority 21 February 2007
Calvo M, Cossu G, De Luca M, Fox IJ, Gerstle C, Goldstein RA, HFEA statement on donating eggs for research. Available at: http://
Hermere´n G, High KA, Kim HO, Lee HP, Levy-Lahad E, Li L, Lo B, www.hfea.gov.uk/cps/rde/xchg/SID-3F57D79B-EF42B079/hfea/
Marshak DR, McNab A, Munsie M, Nakauchi H, Rao M, Rooke HM, hs.xsl/1491.html. Accessed March 8, 2007
Valles CS, Srivastava A, Sugarman J, Taylor PL, Veiga A, 76. 2005 Guidelines for human embryonic stem cell research. Washington,
D.C.: National Academy Press

Você também pode gostar