Você está na página 1de 21

The Orchestral Revolution

Haydn and the Technologies of Timbre

EMILY I. DOLAN

ii
ii

CAMBRIDGE
UNIVERSITY PRESS
CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSI'l'Y :nrnss
Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town,
Singapore, Sao Paulo, Delhi, Mexico City

Cambridge University Press


The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 8RU, UK

Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York
To my mother and the memory of my father,for everything.
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781107028258

© Emily I. Dolan 2013

This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception


and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements,
no reproduction of any part may take place without
the written pern'lission of Cambridge University Press.

First published 2013

Printed and bound in the United Kingdom by the MPG Books Group

A mtaloguerecordfor this publicationis availablefrom the BritishLibrary

Libraryof CongressCatalogingin Publicationdata


Dolan, Emily I,
The orchestral revolution : Haydn and the technologies of timbre/ Emily I. Dolan.
p. cm.
Includes bibliographical-references and index.
ISBN 978-1-10?-02825-8 (Hardback)
1. Haydn, Joseph, 1732-1809-Critidsm and interpretation, 2. Instrumentation and
orchestration-History. 3. Orchestra-History-18th centmy, I. Title.
ML410.H4D65 2012
784-.2092-dc23
2012018848

ISBN 978-1-107-02825-8 Hardback

Cambridge University Press has no responSibility for the persistence or


accuracy of URLs for external or third-party internet websites referred to
in this publication, and does not guarantee that any content on such
websites is, or will remain, accurate or appropriate,
52 Lessonsat the ocularharpsichord

professed that "when it comes to musical color, the musician is left entirely to
his own devices;
' ' oreh estrati'on." 71
£1or that 1s
2 The idea of timbre
The notion of color, then, highlighted those aspects of music that were
difficult, skirted reason, and trafficked with the irrational. Tones
demanded a special vocabulary with which to discuss them; to trace the
metaphor of color in the eighteenth century is to trace those elements of
music that challenged contemporary notions of what music was and what
it could do. The next two chapters will explore the birth of the concept of "Pitch is nothing other than tone color measured in one direction"
timbre and the changing discourses about insti·uments in the eighteenth Arnold Schoenberg, Harmonielehre
1

century. The varied uses of the color metaphor during the century were
prereqnisites for the modern conception of timbre as musical color; the
analogy between color and timbre implies certain ways of conceptnahzmg An elusive object
music, To trace the history of timbre is, at the same time, to chart the
emergence of the modern conception of the power of music. Writing abont timbre is difficult. When Alexander Ellis translated
Hermann von Helmholtz's Lehre von den Tonempfindungenin 1885, he !- ;

avoided the word altogether on etymological grounds. "Timbre:' he wrote,


71 E. T. A. Hoffmann) Kreisleriana:"ExtremelyRandom Thoughts,"h·ans, in E. T. A. Hojfmann's
"properly a kettledrum, tl1en a helmet, then the coat of arms surmounted
Musical Writings:Kreisleriana, The Poet and the Composer, Music Criticism,ed. D, Charlton
(Cambridge University Press, 1989), p. 113, with a helmet, then the official stamp bearing that coat of arms (now used
in France for a postage label), and then the mark which declared a thing to
be what it pretends to be, Burns's 'guinea's stamp; is a foreign word, often
odiously mispronounced, and not worth preserving."2 Timbre evades
predse definition and rigorous analysis. Most descriptions of timbre are
negative, resorting to a description of what it is not: for instance, we say
that timbre is the quality that distinguishes a flute and an oboe when they
play the same pitch at the same dynamic level. Part of this reflects the
problems timbre posed to the science of acoustics: until Helmholtz's
,
i pioneering work in the mid nineteenth century, no one had attempted
I
! to explain the acoustical phenomena behind timbre. And explaining it ws1s
no small feat: the first part of Helmholtz's Lehre von den Tonempfindungen
(first published in 1863) was dedicated to the problem of timbre - called
Klangfarbe in this treatise - a problem that was, he wrote, "perfectly
puzzling" ("vollkommen riitselhaften"). His solution lay in his investi-
gations into what he called the form of vibration,that is, the occurrence of
upper partial tones in compound notes. Timbre, he found, depended on
the strength and weal<ness of the upper partials. Yet our perception of

1
"Die KlanghOhe ist nicht anderes als Klangfarbe, gemessen in einer Richtung." A. Schoenberg,
Harmonielehre(Vienna: Universal Edition, 1922), p. 506,
2
H. von Helmholtz, Die Lehre von den Tonempfindungenals physiologischeGrundlagefur die
Theorieder Musik (Braunschweig: J. Vieweg, 1863), trans, A. Ellis as On the Sensationsof Tone
(London: Longmans, Green, 1885), p. 24n. Ellis translated Klangfarbeas "quality of tone."
53
54 The idea of timbre An elusiveobject 55

timbre - or at least what we generally think of as timbre - depends upon dullness and brightness, or between harshness or softness."6 After a
other sonic dements snch as attack and decay as well as conntless other lengthy discussion of the acoustical foundations of pitch and volume -
noises: breaths and bow strokes, the taps and clacks produced by the the acoustical basis of which were understood at the time - Rousseau
mechanism of an instrument and the body of the musician in the act of turned his attention to the third aspect of sound:
performance. When listeners hear the envelope of a note with the attack
and decay cut off, they struggle to identify the instrument. 3 The The difference between sounds described by timbre cannot be accounted for by a
sound's pitch or volume. An oboe would be difficult to mistake for a flute: it could
most accurate definitions become magnificently inclusive: W. Dixon
not soften its sound to the same degree. The sound of a flute would always have a
Ward, a founder of psychoacoustics, described timbre as a "wastebasket"
certain je ne sais quoi of softness and pleasantness, while that of an oboe would
attribute - timbre is eve1ythingthat remains after accounting for a tone's
have a certain dryness and harshness, which makes it impossible to confuse the
pitch and dynamic level.4 two. What could we say about the different timbres of voices with the same force
Within musical scholarship of the past hundred years, timbre has and pitch?7
occupied a decidedly marginal position. Traditionally, it has been con-
sidered a "secondary paran1eter)J; even if such a classification does not The problem for Rousseau and his contemporaries was that it was
necessarily impose a value judgment, questions of timbre have often been challenging to say anything about timbre. He goes on to explain,
ignored in analysis. Musicologists and theorists who turn to questions of No one I know has examined this aspect, which may have as many difficulties as
timbre must justify their analytic focus.5 the others since the quality of timbre cannot depend on the number of vibrations,
But timbre is everywhere. Even when we cannot speak of pitch - with which determines whether a sound is low or high, or on the intensity of these
instruments like cymbals, for exampk - we can still speak of timbre. And same vibrations, which determines whether a sound is loud or quiet. There must
although the overtone series plays a central role in shaping the timbre of a therefore be found among the aspects of sound a third quality different from these
tone, the absence of overtones does not imply an absence of timbre: the two that can explain this last property; this does not seem very easy to me; we
pure sine wave has its own striking qualities which have been harnessed for must refer to the Principesd'acoustiqueof M. Diderot if we wish to further address
this issue. 8
expressive ends. Yet, for all of its inescapability, timbre also has a history. l1

That is to say, there was a time before timbre. As we have noted, the word The Principesgenerauxd'acoustiqueto which Rousseau referred was the I
1/
,II,
itself entered musical discourse only in the eighteenth century. In Decem- first of Diderot's Memoires sur differents sujets de mathematiques, pub- "
I
ber 1765, after an extended delay due to problems with censorship, the lished in 1748, The reference was a false one: Diderot's essay explores the
final ten volnmes of Diderot's Encyclopedieappeared. In the article on
sound ("Son"), Jeail")acqnes Rousseau mentions the idea of timbre. He 6
a
"II ya trois choses considerer dans le son: 1, le degre d'elcvation entre le grave & l'aig\t: 2, celui
begins: "There are three aspects of sound to consider: 1. the range between de vehemence entre le fort & le foible: 3, & la qualite du timbre qui est encore susceptible de
low and high, 2. the degree of intensity between loud and quiet, 3. the a
comparaison du sourd l'Cclatant, ou de l'aigu au doux." J.-J.Rousseau, "Son," in D. Diderot
and J. d'Alembert (eds.), Encyclopidie:ou Dictionnaireraisonnedes sciences,des arts et des
quality of its timbre, which is always subject to the comparison between
mitiers (Paris, 1751-72), vol. XV, pp. 345-47, at p. 345.
7
a
"Quant la difference qui se trouve encore entr~ les sons par la qualite du timbre, il est
evident qu'elle ne tient ni au degre de gravite, ni m&me a celui de force. Un hautbois aura
3 The psychologist James J. Gibson has discussed this phenomenon in The SensesConsideredas a
beau se mettre exactement l'unisson d'une flUte, il aura beau radoucir le son au meme degre,
PerceptualSystems(Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1966); P. Schaeffer, in TJ-aite des objetsmusicaux: le son de la flUte aura toujours je ne sai quoi de doux & de moelleux, celui du hautbois je ne
Essaisinterdisciplines(Paris: .Editions du Seuil, 1966), likewise also explores how manipulated sai quoi de sec & d'aigi·e, qui emp&chera qu'on ne puisse jamais les confondre. Que dirons-nous
tones alter the perception and understanding of timbre. des differents timbres des voix de mCme force & de mi':me porti!:e?" Ibid.
4
w. D. Ward, "Psychoacoustics," in A. Glorig (ed.), Audiometty: Principlesand Practices 8
[P]ersonne que je sache n'a encore examine cette partie, qui peut-&tre, aussi-bien que les autres,
(Baltimore: Williams & Wilkins Co,, 1965)1 pp. 48-71, at p. 55. se trouvera avoir ses difficulte/l: c;ar la qualitC de timbre ne peut dependre, ni du nombre de
5
Recent scholarship has seen an increase of attention to questions of timbre and orchestration. vibrations qui font le degre du grave U I'aigu, ni de la grandeur ou de la force de ces mCmes
i
John J,Shcinbaum, for example, has written on issues of orchestration in relation to Gustav vibrations qui fait le degre du fort au foible. II faudra done trouver dans les corps sonores
Mahler; he does not simply write about Mahler's orchestration, but thematizes his focus on une troisieme modification diffCrente de ces deux, pour expliquer cette derniere propriete; ce
timbre. See "Adorno's Mahler anr;l the Timbral Outsider:' Journalof the RoyalMusical qui ne me paroit pas une chose trap aisee; ii faut recourir aux principesd'acoustiquede
Association,131/1 (2006), 38-82, M. Diderot, si l' on veut approfondir cette matiere." Ibid.
56 The idea of timbre Eighteenth-cent~,ytimbre 57

production of pitch, but does not tackle issues of tone quality. Rousseau music that only provided pleasure through its sonorities was composition-
also defined timbre separntely in its own entry, attempting not only to ally deficient. The idea that one could talk about and evaluate music's
describe what timbre is, but also to explain the value of different qualities. sounds, outside of the context of a composition or performance, heralded
The entry runs to only four sentences in its entirety: a new conception of music and musical instrmnents> one bound to new
A sound's timbre describes its harshness or softness, its dullness or brightness. Soft ontologies of musical tone. Indeed, as this chapter will explore, our ability
sounds, like those of a flute, ordinarily have little harshness; bright sounds are '.o speak of tones as beautiful is conditioned by the messy interface of
often harsh, like those of the vielleor the oboe. There are even instruments, such mstruments and aesthetics that emerged in the eighteenth century.
as the harpsichord, which are both dull and harsh at the same time; this is the
worst timbre. The beautiful timbre is that which combines softness with bright-
9
ness of soundi the violin is an example,
Eighteenth-centurytimbre
This brief article is notable as the first explicitly musical definition of the
concept of timbre, in isolation from particular performances. 10 It signaled a Rousseau's definition of timbre marked the beb>inningof a new discourse
major change within musical discourse, marking a turn toward concerns of about instrumental sonority. Yet the language he used - his confined palette
perception, a new attention to music's immediacies. As explored in Chapter of soft, harsh, bnght, dull - seems impoverished in comparison to the rich
J, many eighteenth-century thinkers sought to connect music with notions language used by later writers to describe instrumental sound. Less than a
of imitation, since mnsic's meaning depended on how well it could depict, hundred years late1; Hector Berlioz drew upon a vast and colorful vocabu-
imitate, or express human emotions or the outside world. When discus- lary to describe instruments in his Grand traite d'instrumentation et
sions turned to music's immediate sensations, it was usually to show how d'orchestrationmodernes(1844). Chapter 6 explores this rich text in more '

detail, but a brief glimpse is warranted here: the treatise often reads like a 111
I
9
"Tymbre, s,m, en Musiquc-, on appelle ainsi cette qualitCdu son par laquelleil est aigre au doux.> sweeping introduction to a cast of characters. Berlioz informs us which I

sourd ou eclatant. Les sons doux ant ordinairement peu d'edat comme de la fll1te;lessons , instruments are pleasant, sweet, and joyous; which are grotesque, sad, or
a
eclatants sont sujets l'aigreur, comme lessons de la vielle au du hautbois. ll ya meme des
instruments, tels que le clavecin, qui sont il.-la-foissourds & aigrcs, & c'est le plus mauvais tymbre. melancholy; and which ought to be used more often and which should be
Le beau tymbreest celui qui rellnit la douceur Ul'Cdat du son; on en peut donner le violin pour avoided. He rapturously tells us that "there is nothing like the telling
exemple." Rousseau, "Tymbre;' in Diderot and d'Alembert (eds,), Encyclopedie, vol. XVI, p. 775. 11
sweetness of twenty e strings activated by twenty well-controlled bows.
Rousseau most likely wtote this article a number of years before it was published. He reports in his
Confessions, "The two authors had just been working on a DictionnaireEncycloj}edique [sic], which This is the orchestra's truly feminine voice, at once passionate and chaste
was initially supposed to be nothing more than a translation of Chambers, similar to that of the heart-rending and gentle, able to weep and moan and wail, or sing and i
Dictionnairede medecineby James, which Diderot had just translated. He wanted me to contribute
something to this second enterprise, and he offered me the musical articles, which I accepted, and
unplore and dream, or break out in joy as no other instrument can."11 He :,J
;, I
which I executed in a great hurry and very badly during the three months he had given me and all c01~~lai~sthat violas are ,underu~ed, and en~icescomposers by speaking of
the other authors who were supposed to work on the enterprise, but I was the only one who t~e part1cula1pun~ency' of the mstrument s lower register and the "espe-
.finished in the agreed time," Confessions (Paris: Hatier, 1999), p. 119, quoted in P. Blom, cially sad and pass10nate character" of the higher notes. 12 The oboe for
Enlighteningthe World:Encydopedie, the Bookthat'Changedthe Courseof History(New York:
Palgrave Macmillan, 2004), pp. 44--45. It is likely, then, the Rousseau's entry was written in 1749. Berlioz, fa~Isa a profoundly expressive instrument; for him, its "sp~cial
10 As late as the 1770s, Sulzer still argued that single musical tones were not inherently expres~ive; characteristics convey candor, nalve grace, sentimental delight, or the
it was only through thoughtful performance that tones became infused with expression: "One suffering of weaker creatures.»13 By contrast the flute, he remarks> is an
can certainly hear passionate notes in music that are, by themselves and with no help of the
composer, painful, sad, tender, or gay. But such impressions come about through the artistry of instrument "almost lacking in expression:' 14 The bassoon has a "propensity !
·1
''

the singer and belong properly to performance. This has notl1ing to do with the writing of a to sound grotesque when exposed": by employing the instrument's middle
good melody, except perhaps in so far as the composition might offer the singer or player some
guidance as to how the written notes may be performed with feeling," J, G. Sulzer, Allgemeine
11
Theorieder schonenKilnste(Leipzig: Weidemann, 1771-74), trans, in N. K. Baker and H. Berli~z, Grand traite d'instrumentationet d.'orchestration
modernes(Paris: Schonenbergcr,
T, Christensen (eds.), Aestheticsand the Art of MusicalCompositionin the German 1844, rev, 1855), trans. H, .Macdonald as Berlioz'sOrchestrationTreatise:A Translationand
Enlightenment:SelectedWritingsof Johann GeorgSulzerand HeinrichChristophKoch Commentaiy (Cambridge University Press 2002) p 34
12 13 '
14 Ibid., ' ' '
(Cambridge University Press, 1995), pp. 91-92. Ibid., p. 35. Ibid,, p. 104. p. 140.
58 The idea of timbre
Eighteenth-centurytimbre 59

register, Giacomo Meyerbeer was able to produce a "pale, cold, cadaverous Dictionnaire de l'Academiefranroise (1762) timbre is explicitly linked to
sound" in the resurrection of the nuns in Robertle diable,15 the sound of the human voice: "It is used sometimes figuratively for even
The difference between the two thinkers' perception of sonority is one of the sound of the voice, And in this sense, one says of a beautiful voice:
kind and not merely degree, Rousseau defined timbre as a discrete concept, there's a beautiful timbre. This voice has a silver timbre." 18 A similar
but he did not assign it a place of importance within musical composition. definition can be found in Jean-Fran,ois Ferand's Dictionnaire critique
Recall that we saw in the previous chapter how he argued that the heart of de la languefran,aise (Marseille, 1787-88).
music lay in melody, which he equated with design; harmony and "sound" .When applied to sound in the eighteenth century, one meaning of
(by which he implied timbre) were "merely colors:' By contrast, Berlioz <'tu~bre" was sin1ply "resonance"; Rousseau himself used the word thus
viewed the proper use of instrumental sonorities as fundamental to the in Emile, in a description of how a girl might seek to appear attractive:
structure of music; correct co1nposition is impossible without an intimate
knowledge of the properties of instruments. The notion of timbre entered She can already seek to give a pleasant turn to her gestures and a flattering accent
musical discourse in two stages: first, it became a discrete concept; only later to _her voice) to mainlain her composure, walking lightly, assuming gracious
~tt1tudes, and choosing everytl1ing to her advantage. The voice's range increases)
did it become associated with color and character. This later transformation
it gets stronger and gains timbre; the arms are developed; tl1e step becomes sure;
will be explored in the next two chapters. Here we shall focus on the early
and she sees that, however she is dressed, there is _anart of getting looked at. 19
conception of timbre and what it can tell us about how people listened and
thought about music and musical instruments. The initial attention paid to instrumental sonority did not consider
The etymology of "timbre" sheds light on its early meanings. Rousseau instruments in a network of contrasting and complementary colors, but
was the first to define timbre in explicitly musicalterms, but the word has rather evaluated each sonority on its own. Rousseau, rather than describ- ,I
I

a rich history and has been used for diverse concepts. The word was ing t~e instruments' characters, evaluated their quality, measured against 'i,i
,
derived from the Latin noun tympanum, meaning a drum or bell (which the smgle standard of the sound of singing voice. This is implicit in his '
.,.'·
'·,1
is reflected by the original spelling tymbre in the Encyclopedie).In the fitst definition in Encyclopedie,in which he offered a ranking of the best and I•
edition of the Dictionnaire de /'Academic fran,oise (1694), "timbre" is worst timbres. His discussion was governed by a notion of beauty that is
defined as a kind of bell with a clapper inside that is struck by a hammer. halfway between early eighteenth-century conceptions of music and
In the third edition of 1740, the definition is expanded and hints at the Berlioz's view of instrumental timbre. In this period, instrumental son-
changing notion of timbre: "It is said sometimes, for the sound yielded by orities began to be granted real value, but their worth was nonetheless
the timbre [i.e., the bell]: this timbre is too bright:' 16 Timbre here is both dominated by the valne system that held vocal music in the highest
the bell that gives the sound, and the sound tl1at the bell makes. The fifth esteem.
edition of the Dictionnairede Trevoux ( 1752) - officially the Dictionnaire Rousseau's conception of the beauty of instrumental tone - what we
universe/fran,ois et latin - lays bare the complexity of this word: the entry might call his standard of the singing tone - points to another way of \,
first connects the word to "bell;' both cowbells and carillons, then quotes thmkmg about voice and melody in this period. In addition to shape, flow,
the above passage from the Dictionnaire de l'Academiefran,oise to show and rhythm of melody, the actual sound of the singer's voice - her
how it can be used to describe sound, and then, before giving definitions nuances, her control, her timbre - was equally prized. Instruments that
! !
of six other uses of "timbre," comments at length on the multiple and
sometimes elusive meanings of the word. 17 In the fourth edition of the lB "11se pren d que Ique101s
< • •
figuremcnt pour Le son m&me de la voix. Et dans ce sens on <lit d'une
belle v~ix, Viola un beau timbre. Cette voix a un timbre arge.ntin.1'Dictionnairede l'AcadCmie
1
franroise,4th edn., 2 vols. (Paris: Bernard Brunet 1762) vol JI p 835
Ibid., pp. 113-14. 19 ) ' ' ' ' '
"
16 "On peut deja a a
chercher <1donner un tour agreable ses gestes, un accent flatteur sa voix) a
"II se dit quclquefois, pour Le son que rend le timbre. Ce timbre est trop Cclatant,""Timbre:' COl~p.oserSOU maintien, .\ marcher avec Jegerete) (l prendre des attitudes gracielJses, et i\
in Dictionnairede l'AcadCmiefranroise, 3rd edn., 2 vols. (Paris: Jean-Baptiste Coignard, 1740), d~ms1r partout ses avantages. La voix s'etend, s'affermit, et prend du timbre; Jes bras se
vol. II, p. 770.
17 ~eveloppent, la dem~rche s'assu~~) et l'on s'apen;o~t que, de quelque maniere qu'on soit mise,
See Dictionnaireuniverse!franrois et latin, 7 vols, (Paris: La compagnie des libraires assodes, 1
1Yaun art de se faire regarder. J.-J.Rousseau) Emile, ou De l'Cducation,4 vols. (Paris:
1752), vol. Vil, pp. 87-88. Duchesne) 1762), vol. IV, p. 32.
60 The idea of timbre Eighteenth-centurytimbre 61

could imitate the voice were similady esteemed in this period. In the entry The problem of singing keyboards also belonged to the realm of instru-
on "Instrumentalmusik" in AllgemeineTheorieder schonenKunste,Johann ment making. The invention of the pianoforte, of course, grew out of the
3
Georg Sulzer, writing with Johann Kirnberger, argued: "Among all instru- desire to give the performer more dynamic control over the music.2 In
ments that can produce expressive tones, the human voice is without the eighteenth century, the cembaloconforte e piano was one of a number
doubt the one to be preferred. One can deduce from this the fundamental of new instruments invented to overcome the technological shortcomings
maxim, then, that the most excellent instrument is that which is most of existing keyboard instruments.
capable of imitating the human voice. By this reasoning, the oboe is one The period saw a flurry of activity surrounding "sustaining" keyboards.
of the best:'20 The idea was not new: Leonardo da Vinci drew np sketches for a keyboard
Johann Joachim Quantz, in his Versucheiner Anweisung die Plate tras- instrument that used a rosined wheel to activate and sustain tones; the
versierezu spielen(1752), advised that the "most pleasing sonnd (sonus)" earliest actual instrument was Hans Haiden's Geigenwerkof 1575. The
on the flute was that which is "more similar to a contralto than a soprano, performer used a foot treadle to set a number of rosined wheels in motion.
or which imitates the chest tones of the human voice:' 21 In other words, When keys were depressed, the corresponding strings were lowered onto
he assumed that the tone of his instrument would be compared with the these wheels. The speed of the wheels controlled the volume, so that by
human voice; his task was to give his readers more precise information varying the speed of the treadle the performer could implement a cres-
about how the flute imitated the voice. Throughout his treatise, singing cendo or decrescendo. Various inventors attempted to improve upon
and flute playing are intimately linked. Haiden's design in the following centuries: C. P. E. Bach, for example,
This is especially apparent in the instruments that struggled the most to praised a Bogenklavierby Johann Hohlfeld, writing that "the fine invention
imitate the voice, namely keyboard instruments. The common keyboard of our celebrated Holefeld [sic], which mal<esit possible to increase or i
I
instruments of the period either lacked the ability to sustain tones, as is the decrease the registration by means of pedals, while playing, has made the
harpsichord, particularly the single-manual kind, a much-improved
I
case with clavichords, harpsichords, and pianos, or to vary the dynamic
level fluidly, as with organs and harpsichords. Part of this "problem" instrument, and, fortunately, eliminated all difficulties connected with
belonged to the domain of performance, and could be "solved" through the performance of a piano. If only all harpsichords were similarly con-
proper technique; for example, at the beginning of his Versuchuber die structed as a tribute to good taste!"24 Most subsequent sustaining pianos
wahre Art das Clavierzu spielen,C. P. E. Bach complained, were built on the same basic hurdy-gurdy principles as Haiden's instru-
ment; that is, they used rosined wheels or bows to activate strings.
Keyboardists can be heard who after torturous trouble have finally learned how
The most snccessful of these instruments in this period to combine the
to make their instruments sound loathsome to an enlightened listener. Their
tone and control of the human voice with the conveniences of a keyboard
playing lacks roundness) clarity, forthrightness, and in their stead, one hears only
was not actually a keyboard instrnment. Rather it was the armonica,
hacking, thumping, and stumbling. All other instruments have learned how to
sing. The keyboard alone has been left behind, its sustained style obliged to make
invented by Benjamin Franklin in 1761 (Fig. 2.1). The glass harmonica,
way for countless elaborate figures.22 as it is more commonly known, consisted of a series of tuned glass bowls
threaded onto a spindle, and set in motion by a foot treadle. The glass
20
harmonica was a sophisticated version of the musical glasses - water-filled
Sulzer, AllgemeineTheorieder sch8nenKllnste,trans. in Bal<erand Christensen (eds.), Aesthetics
and the Art of Musical Compositionin the GermanEnlightenment,p. 97.
crystal glasses played by rubbing the rims. The musical glasses had become
2-1 "Ueberhaupt ist auf der Fl6tc der Ton (s01ms) der allergef'alligste, welcher mebr einem increasingly popular in Europe in the decades leading up to Franklin's
Contraalt als Sopran; oder wclcher denen T6nen, die man bey dem Menschen die Bruststimme
ncnnt, ahnlich ist." J,J,Quantz, VersucheinerAnweisungdie FIOtetraversierezu spielen;mit
verschiedenen,zur Befdrderungdesguten Geschmackesin der praktischenMusik dienlichen
23 The story of the invention of the piano is the subject of a number of studies, so I will not repeat
Anmerkungenbegleitet,und mit Exempeln(Berlin: J. F. Voss, 1752), p. 41, trans. E. Reilly as On
Playingthe Flute (Boston: Northeastern University Press, 1985), p. 50. it here, See E. M, Good, Giraffes,BlackDragons,and OtherPianos:A TechnologimlHistoryfrom
22
C. P. E. Bach, Versuchllberdie wahreArt das Clavierzu spielen(Berlin: C. F. Hennig, 1753), Cristoforito the Modern Grand (Stanford University Press, 2001).
24 Bach, Essayon the TrueArt of PlayingKeyboardInstruments,pp. 368-69, In 1783 Bach wrote a
trans, W. J, Mitchell as Essayon the TrueArt of PlayingKeyboardInstruments(London: Cassel,
1951), p. 31. Sonatafitr das Bogenklavier,H280 (W65.48).
62 The idea of timbre
Eighteenth-centurytimbre 63

a trip to England in 1757 and set to work improving the instrument;


his version allowed for a mnch easier execution of chords and passagework
and soon became immensely popular. Virtuoso performers such as
Marianne Kirchgessner and Marianne Davies toured with their glass
harmo11icas and a variety of c01nposers> including Mozart, wrote music
II for the instrument.
Franklin himself described the instrument's tones as "incomparably
sweet beyond those of any other [instrument] ."26 As Heather Hadlock
has documented, many heard the glass harmonica as a perfect comple-
ment to the human voice: Ann Ford had already praised the musical
glasses as a dignified accompaniment to singing. That voice was often
gendered female: in 1785, a series of witty epigrams appeared in the
Whitehall Evening Post likening women to various instruments; first the
violin (in order to support the marrying of older women, who like fiddles,
improve with use and age), then the Aeolian harp, here a sign of incon-
stancy ("every note, or flat or sharp/depends upon the wind"). These
analogies were followed by the final one: "Woman, l say, Dame or Lass/
ls an Harmonica of Glass/Celestial and Complete . . . When rightly
touch'd, its every tone/Is ravishingly sweet."27
Fradklin's instrument impressed audiences both in Europe and America:
Philip Vickers Fithian recorded his impressions hearing the wealthy colonist
Robe1t Carter perform on the glass harmonica in Virginia in 1773:
Fig. 2.1 An image of Benjamin Franklin's glass harmonica. Franklin described his instrument in great
detail in his letter to Rev. Father Beccaria (July 13, 1762), which was later published in Experimentsand It is the first time I have heard the Instrument. The Music is charming! He play'd,
Observationson Electricity,.1\1ade
at Philadelphiain America,by Benjamin Franklin,L.L.D,and F.R.S.To Water parted from the Sea. - The Notes are dear and inexpressively Soft, they
whichareAdded, Lettersand Paperson PhilosophicalSubjects(London: David Henry, 1769), pp.427-33. For swell aitd are inexpressively grand; & either it is because the sounds are new, and
practical purposes, the instrument's appearance echoed Newton's equation of sound and color: Frallklin therefore pleased me, or it is the most captivating Instrument I have Ever heard.
writes, "To distinguish the glasses the more readily to the eye, I have painted the apparent parts of the The sounds very much resemble the human voice, and in my opinion they far
glasses within side, every semitone white, and the other notes of the octave the seven prismatic colours, exceed even the swelling Organ. 28
viz. C red; D, orange; E) yellow; F, green; G, blue; A, Indigo; B, purple; and C, red again" (pp. 432-33).
The composer and glass harmonica performer Karl Leopold Rollig
''i
invention: Gluck was known to dazzle several audiences with his prowess
!
invented a keyboard version of the instrument; in a review of it in
on the musical glasses; the Irish musician Richard Pockrich (c.1690-1759) Cramer's Magazin der Musik, the anthor begins by remarking, "most
was especially famous for his performances of Handel's Water Music, readers will have had the opportunity to hear this indescribably beautiful
which he performed on a special set of glasses to which he gave the
26
name "the angelic organ."25 Franklin heard the musical glasses during "L'arrhonica: Lettre del Signor Benjamin Franklin al padre Giambatista Beccaria regio
professore di fisca nell' universit<\ dell'Torino dall' Ingelsa recata nell' Italiano:' July 13, 1762
(Turin, 1769), in The Worksof BenjaminFranklin,ed. J, Sparks (Boston: Hilliard, Gray, & Co.,
25 1840)j vol. VI, pp. 245-50; quoted in H. Hadlock, "Sonorous Bodies: Women and the Glass
His instrument met a bitter end when a large sow gained entrance to his performance and
Harmonica," Joumal of the AmericanMusicologicalSociety,53/3 (2000), 507--41, at p. 508.
overturned it. See B. Boydell, "Mr. Pockrich and the Musical Glasses," Dublin Historical 27
"Helicon Bag:' vVhit'ehall EveningPost(Dec. 13-15, 1785), 4.
Record,44 (1991), 25-33, and A. Hyatt King, "Some Notes on the Armonica," Monthly 28
Journaland Lettersof Philip VickersFithian, 1773-1774; A Plantation Tutorof the Old
MusicalRecord,86 (1956), 61-69.
Dominion,ed. H. D. Farish (Charlottesville: Dominion Books, 1968), p. 37.
64 The idea of timbre
r Treatiseson instrumentation 65

instrument themselves, which exceeds the sweetness and softness of all muddy lower register, slow response, inability to execute rapid pas-
[other] tones, including the human voice."29 Consistently> writing about sages, and its nasty habit of causing its performers to become ill -
the glass harmonica concentrated specifically on its sonority; the actual ultimately undermined the instrument's usefulness. Critics often
music composed for and performed on the harmonica often does not doubted whether the glass harmonica was capable producing powerful
feature prominently, if at all, in discussions of the instrlllnent. Its tone was music. After a concert by glass harmonica virtuoso Mai'ianne Kirch-
beautiful, regardless of the music performed on it. gessner, a reviewer for the Morning Chronicle remarked that "the
Like the concept and rhetoric of timbre, the glass harmonica reflected an dulcet notes of the instrument would be delightful indeed, were they
emerging fascination with 111usic'simmediate qualities: its striking tone more powerful and articulate; bnt that we believe the most perfect
fostered discussions of sonority independent of particular performances. execution of the instrument cannot make them. In a similar room,
The concept and the instrument each represent a different reaction to the and an audience less numerous, the effect 1nust be enchanting." 31
same phenomenon; yet both mark a midway point between early eighteenth- A number of inventors followed Riillig's example and attempted to
century aesthetics and our modern conception of timbre. Rousseau ranked improve the glass harmonica by incorporating a keyboard to mediate
instruments according to the beauty of their tones measured against the between the performer and the glasses. They hoped that this addition
voice; the sonority of the glass harmonica was likewise judged by the same would allow for more rapid execution and prevent the performer from
vocal standard. Underlying such comparisons is the idea of mimesis. suffering nerve damage from direct contact with the vibrations of the
The glass harmonica's immediate sonority was considered beautiful in bowls. Starting in the 1780s, a string of inventors independently
and of itself, bnt importantly, that rhetoric was enabled by the instru- produced keyboard harmonicas, with names such as the Tastenharmo-
ment's restricted range. Composers and performers did not have to discuss nika and Clavier-harmonica. In spite of the efforts of these inventors,
the kind of music performed on it partly because the instrument's mech- these experiments proved unsuccessful; not only were the tones still
anism limited the range of styles it could perform. This was understood at slow to speak, but the keyboard removed the nuance possible when a
the time: Riillig, for example, in his Uber die Harmonika, ein Fragment performer played directly on the glasses.32 Although these experiments
(1787), tells his readers that the glass harmonica could not perform music led to an obsession with instruments that captured the ideal voice of
filled with sudden changes of affect.' 0 The harmonica sidestepped the nature early in the nineteenth century, the glass harmonica and the
criticisms lodged against so 1nuch instnunental 1nusic - the many accus- other instruments it inspired were later relegated to the margins of
ations that music without words careened through a dizzying number of organology. 33 To rediscover them - and to understand why they
jarring transitions or that it resembled paint splattered upon a canvas. intrigued inventors and delighted audiences - is to arrive at a new
Likewise, there was no question here of silly imitations of inappropriate understanding of the kind of attention paid to instrumental sonority
subjects, for the harmonica could imitate the one thing that was worth in this period.
imitating: the human voice. Not only was the glass harmonica considered
to approximate the human voice more closely than any previous instru-
Treatises on instrumentation
ment, but it was praised for being an ideal voice, even better than human.
The harmonica distinguished itself by its ability to be discussed and
The singing voice offered both rational text and the sensual immediacies
judged using the criteria previously reserved for vocal mnsic: it conformed
of tone. The sound of the singing voice conld imply the presence
to the dominant aesthetics in both sound and style.
However, the glass harmonica was not a perfect instrument. Though 31
Anon., "Sixth Concert: 17th March 1794. Mr. Salomon's Concert. Hanover Square:' Moming
its tone enthralled its listeners, the many faults of its mechanism - its Chronicle(Mar. 18, 1794), quoted in H. C.R. Landon, The Symphoniesof JosephHaydn
{London: Universal Edition, 1955), p. 515.
32
For a thorough discussion of the history of the Tastenharmunikaand similar instruments see,
29
"Instrumente. lnstrumentmacher," in Carl Friedrich Cramer (ed.), Magazin der Musik (1787), P. Sterk!, KlingendeGliiser(Bern: Peter Lang, 2000), pp. 53ff.
! I 1389-99, at p. 1389,
33
See E. L Dolan, "E. T. A. Hoffmann and the Ethereal Technologies of 'Nature Music,"'
30
Hadlock, "Sonorous Bodies," p. 521. Eighteenth-CenturyMusic, 5/1 (2008), 7-26.
66 The idea of timbre Treatiseson instrumentation 67

of a suug text and therefore suggest the text's meaningfulness: the flute, for example, is not suited for styles of music such as "the airs of
instruments designed to imitate it drew upon that meaningfulness de1nons, furies, warriors, storms, sailors, and many others"; rather it
while remaining estranged from it. Singing tone was an imp.erative in should be reserved for "tender and pathetic pieces, accompaniments, small
good instrumental playing, and it was manifest as well in treatises on airs and brunettes,and in Sonatas and the Concertos it should be reserved
instrumentation that began to appear in the mid-eighteenth centmy. for the best masters who do not misuse it:m
These eady instrumentation treatises are only rarely discussed in the Rather than embracing each instrument for its particular chm-acteris-
secondary literature, and when they are mentioned, they are treated tics, then, Ancelet sees any specific characteristics as limitations. His
merely as precursors to Berlioz. 34 This teleological approach glosses over notion of instrumental sonority is therefore pragmatic - some instru-
many of the intricacies of these treatises; worse, it prevents us from ments can be employed in all situations, and are very useful; others
understanding these documents on their own terms, and seeing how cannot, and are therefore of limited use. Furthermore, Ancelet's concep-
they attest to the compositional concerns and the ways of listening of tion of the relationship between instruments and tompositions reveals
their period. much about a broader conception of "character)) in music. Character, for
We can identify a collection of eighteenth-century instrumentation Ancelet, arises first and foremost through aspects of composition unre-
treatises that share the same basic approach to instruments, despite beii1g lated to instrumentation; well-chosen instruments serve to embellish and
published over the course of a number of years. One of the earliest enliven the preexisting musical character. In Berlioz's orchestration trea-
I
systematic discussions of instruments can be found in Ancelet's Observa- tise, by contrast, instruments will appear as the foundation for musical
tions sur la musique, /es musiciens, et les instruments of 1757. This small character: the composer draws upon the individual character of the
pamphlet is not a true instrumentation treatise, since it does not give any instruments to create the overall character of the music. 38
technical information about the instruments discussed. Ancelet does, Technical treatises on instruments appeared only a few years after
however, reveal much about his conception of the value of the different A:ncelet's pamphlet. In 1764, the clarinetist Valentine Roeser published a
instruments and the relationship between a composition and the instru- modest treatise, Essaid'instruction:A /'usagede ceux qui composentpour la 11:,,1
ments that execute it. Like Rousseau, he praises the violin: "It is certain:' clarinetteet le cor.Avec des remarquessur l'harmonie et des exemplesa deux ,,, I

Ancelet writes, "that the violin is the most beautiful and most perfect of clarinettes,deux cars et deux bassons.Roeser provides the composer with
the instruments, because of its quality of sound, its range, and its execu- basic technical information about the two instruments: the keys in which
tion, which embraces all kinds and characters of music." 35 As this passage the instruments were manufactured, their range, notation, and so forth.
suggests, Ancelet held that instruments should be evaluated for their About the clarinet, he explains: I'
'.1,,,
expressive compass, a view shared by many of his contemporaries. 36 The
We distinguish up to three kinds of sound in the Clarinet; the first, which is from {j
Fa in the small octave up to Sib of the first octave, is called Chalumeaubecause it I'
1'1,
34
Hans Bartenstein, for example, is flrst and foremost concerned with identifying those moments is very soft. The second, which is from Si~natural of the first octave to Ut#, is I,''
that point toward Berlioz's conception of instrumental character and the role of orchestration called Clarionor Clarinette,because it is more sonorous and brilliant. The third,
within a composition as a whole, See his "Die frnhen Instrumentationslehren bis zu Berlioz:'
Archivfiir Musikwissenschaft,28/2 (1971), 97-118.
35
"Il est certain que le violin est le phis beau & le plus parfuit des instrumcns, par la qualite du
37
son, par son etendue & par son execution, qui embrasse tousles genres & !es caracteres de "Si !'on veut parler exactement sur le chapitre de la FIUte, on conviendra qu'elle n'embrasse pas
Musique," Ancelet, Observationssur la musique,Jesmusiciens,et Jesinstruments(Amsterdam: tousles gemes & les caracteres de Musique, tels que sont les airs de Demons, de Furies, de
Aux dCpens de la compagnie, 1757; repr. Geneva: Minkoff, 1984), p. 11. Guerriers, de TempCtes, de Matelots, & de plusieurs autres, clans lesquels elle n'est pas du
36
'fhis is not to say that the notion that instruments had their own characters was totally foreign. moins employee en principal: elle sent done mieux placee dans les morceaux tendres & 1.
Rousseau, in the entry on "Instruments" in the Bncyclopedie, noted that "the character of pathetiques, dans les accompagnemens, dans les petits airs & !es brunettes, que clans Jes Sonates
instruments forms a very important part of the composer's study. They are the different voices & les Concerto rCserves aux meilleurs Maitres, qui ne doivent point eux-mCmes en abuser."
through which he speaks to our cars." Quoted and trans. in D. Charlton, FrenchOpera, Ancelet, Observationssur la musique,les musiciens,et Jesinstruments,pp. 27-28.
38
1730-1830:Meaning and Media (Brookfield, VT: Ashgate, 2000), section V, pp, 1-31, at p. 3, Ancelet's notion of instrumental sonority is also entrenched in a performative notion of timbre:
Rousseau's notion of character differs, I believe, from later eighteenth~ceutury concepti0ns of each instrument is introduced with names of the leading masters on the instrument, past and
instrumental character. present.
68 The idea of timbre Treatiseson instrumentation 69

which is from lhe Re of the third Octave up to Fa, could be called sharp, because it draws upon a richer vocabula1y. He tells us the flute is suited to pieces that
is very strong and we cannot soften it like the former ones. 39 are "slow and pathetic:' and that the flauto piccolo"perfecrly imitates the
Roeser's description of the clarinet's tone employs the same language as songs of birds and nightingales:' 41 In the section on the clarinet, he not only
Roussean's definition of timbre: rather than describing the character of the touches upon the sound qualities of the different registers of the instrument,
different registers of the instrument, he informs the reader (and would-be as Roeser did, but also includes a lengthy section entitled "De la qualite du
composer) when the clarinet sounds soft, bright, and sharp. At the end of son, et de la propriete de chaque espece de clarinettes." According to
the section, Roeser suggests that although he has many other things to say Francoeur, the clarinet in G is the "largest and softest" of the clarinet family,
about the clarinet, he and is not commonly used in orchestras; its sound "is sad and lugnbrious,
which is why one makes nse of it only for somber effects and in funeral
is afraid of making this small work too obscure and of befogging the Reader. The pieces.')42 The clarinet in A, by contrast, '(has an extremely soft tone, 1nuch
most certain rule, and the best for composing for the clarinet, is to aim to produce
less dark and with a greater range than that in G. It is appropriate to tender
a pleasant and natural melody, to avoid large leaps and overly chromatic features: 43
and gracious airs:' The clarinets in B-flat and B-natural, C, and D are very
finally, follow the rule that says: one needs to compose or to sing for the heart and
sonorous, and appropriate to ((very noisy pieces, such as overtures, sy1n-
ear, to touch, and not to astonish, 40
phonies, and lively airs"; the clarinet in C is particularly appropriate for the
After explaining the technical properties of the horn, Roeser concludes the ((noise of wat:' 44 Like Ancelet, Francoeur discusses the instruments in tenns
treatise with examples of how the clarinet and horn might be used in of the characters to which they are appropriate; however, his description of
combination with bassoons. The treatise concludes with examples of six- the different clarinets goes beyond their mechanisms: he attributes to each
part wind writing, and sage words of advice about avoiding fifths and size of clarinet its own emotionalcharacter.
thirds in the bassoons in order to maintain a clear harmony. He stresses Othon Vandenbroeck's Traite general de taus /es instruments a vent a
compositional clarity; issues of expression and of character do not enter /'usagedes compositeurs(1793) is similarly focused on the mechanisms of
into his discussion. Roeser is most concerned with what contributes to the instruments. The main section of the treatise is devoted to the horn;
mnsical beauty. Knowing how to handle the instrument in different keys is the other instruments are disposed of in cursory fashion. Vandenbroeck
essential to making it sound beautiful. rarely addresses issues of tone quality: rather he focuses on instruments'
Louis-Joseph Francoeur's more comprehensive Diapasongeneralde taus range and chromatic capability. Only in his discussion of the oboe does he
/es instrumentsavent (1772) encompassed nearly all instruments in cnrrent remark, "The oboe is a very old instrument, which beautifully approxi-
use (he omitted iµstruments such as the musette, fife, sackbut, and cornet). mates the human voice, in particular the female voice:' 45 Like the earlier
Francoenr's treatise resembles that of Roeser: it is devoted chiefly to supply- writers, then, Vandenbroeck prizes those instruments that offer the
ing the reader with precise technical information about each instrument but greatest flexibility and voice-like beauty.
Attention to sonority also crept into musical discussions not devoted to
39
"On distingue jus qu'a trois sortes dans l'etendue de la clarinette; le premier qui est depuis the handling of instruments. In 1773 Johann Friedrich Dau be ( 1730-1797)
le Fa de la petite Octave jusqu' au Si b, mol de la premiere Octave, est appellCChalumeau, parce
qdil est trCs dome. Le second q\1i est depuis le Si naturel de la premiere Octave jus qu'a
l'Ut # de la troisieme est appelle Clairon ou Clarinette parce qu'il est plus sonore et plus 41
L.-J, firancoeur, Diapasongeneralde i-ousles instrumentsavent avecdesobservationssur chacun
brillant. Le troisiCme qui est depuis le Re de la troisiCme Octave jusqui'au Fa, pcut etre d'eux (Paris: Des Lauriers, 1772; repr. Geneva: Minkoff, 1972), pp. 2, 9,
appelli§aigU,parce qu'il est tres fort et qu'on ne peut l'adoucir comme les precedents." 42
"le Son en est triste et lugubre c'est pomquoy on n'en fait usage que dans les effets sombres et
V. Roeser, Essaid'instruction:A ['usagede ceux qui composentpour la clarinetteet le cor,Avec les morceaux fonCbres."Ibid., p. 23.
des remarquessur l'harmonieet des exemplesa deux clarinettes,deux corset deux bassons 43
"a le son fort doux beaucoup moins sombre et a plus d'Ctendue que celle en Sol, elle est propre
(Paris: Le Menu & Casteaux, 1764; repr., Geneva: Minkoff, 1972), pp, 3-4. aux airs tendres et grncieux &c." Ibid., p. 23, i
:,1
40 44
"contentC d'en donner les rCglesles plus nCcessaires:craignant de rendre ce petit Ouvrage trap "Elle est propre aux morceaux de grand bruit, commc Ouvertures, Simphonies, Airs vifs, &c,"
obscur et embrouiller le Lecteur. La RCglela plus sure et la meilleure de Composer pour la Ibid., p. 24.
Clarinette, c'est d'avoir pour but un Chant agrCable-etnature!, d'Cviter grands [saults] et les 45
"Le Hautbois est un Instrument trCSancien et qLiiapproche beaucoup de la voix humaine
Traits trap Chramatique. En fin de suivre la rCglequi dit: qu'il faut Composer ou Chanter pour prindpalement de la voix de femme," 0. Vandenbroeck, Trait-e generalde tousles instrumentsa
le Cceur et !'Oreille; i1faut toucher et ne pas etonner." Ibid,,p. 12, vent a/'usagedes compositeurs(Paris: Boyer, 1793; repr, Geneva: Minkoff, 1974), p. 58.
f
70 The idea of timbre
The beginningof Enlightenmentaesthetics 71

published his comprehensive composition treatise Der musikalischeDilet-


we do not associate with eighteenth-century writing about 1nusic."50
tant: Eine Abhandlung der Komposition.16 Throughout the treatise, Daube
Indeed, as Bent points out, Koch makes no mention of tone quality in
continually instructs his reader to pay attention to the immediate sound of
his considerably later treatise on composition, However, these treatises did
the musical material. For example, in the section on harmony and chords,
not discnss instrumental sonority using the language of color and charac-
he discusses the effect of spacing and instrumentation:
ter that became standard in the nineteenth century. The idea of timbre
the effect of harmony is multifarious. A chord in which the intervals are spread that was rendered as Klangfarbein nineteenth-century Germany impli~d
out far from one another creates an altogether different impression than a chord the presence of a well-developed orchestral tradition, one that emerged
in which they are quite close together. Furthermore, the ruling chord in C major,
only dming the late eighteenth century, as the orchestra reached its final
for example, sounds excellent when it is heard in the middle of the scale. Its effect
solidification and consolidation. It was this context that allowed for
is good on the organ, harpsichord, or piano, but still better when played by two
comparison: to speak of the color of an instrnment situates that instru-
violins and a violoncello. If it is heard on wind instruments of one family or of
several, with or without string instruments, the effect is different in each case.47
ment in a spectrum of colors produced by an array of instruments. The
treatises of the eighteenth century, therefore, should not be seen as mere
Instrumentation is also a concern for contrapuntal passages: precmsors: rather, they reveal a different value system at work. Their
one especially must make certain to choose instruments capable of imitation. emphasis on beautiful tone implicitly ranked certain sonorities as better
Likewise, the motives or figures to be imitated must be selected in accordance with or worse than others. Yet this notion of beauty - that is, tl1e idea that
the nature of the instruments. For example) a figutc from the main melody would sonority could be beantiful in and of itself - was a necessary precursor to
be suitable for imitation by the second voice>and probably by the viola) but not by the later conception of Klangfarbe.
the brass. 48

Like the instrumentation treatises of this period, Daube's discussion of


the immediate sonnd of instruments focnses primarily on questions of The beginning of Enlightenment aesthetics
beauty and clarity: the composer should take care to use instruments in '
1.,!!

'; I
ways that best suit the harmony and textme of the piece. Yet he also is
The new attention paid to instrumental sonority in this period forms part '
I;:
aware of the effect that instrumentation has on musical expression:
of a much larger development in the eighteenth century, namely, the birth
It remains true that the characteristic tone quality of each instrument also contrib- of modern aesthetics. That the concept of timbre should be tied - indeed
utes greatly to the expression of the affects. The unison is said to exactly coincide intimately bound up with - aesthetic discourse is not immediately obvi-
among all the instruments, and yet everyone, even one uninformed about music, ous. "Aesthetics" came to mean the study of art and the inqniry into ideas
hears the difference between each of the instruments, All insti;uments used during of beauty and ideal forms. But to equate aesthetics with the discourse of ,'
antiquity as well as at the present time differ from one another in tone quality) [a ,,,
form and its attendant modes of inquiry is to leap ahead to the nineteentl1
characteristic] which results from the nature of the instrument and remains
century. The origins of the aesthetic were far more hnmble: before it was
peculiar to it alone. 49
bound to art and seeped with the language of idealism, aesthetics was the
In his preface to the translated edition of Daube's treatise, Ian Bent study of the relationship between immediate sensation and the higher
remarks that Danbe has "an awareness of the sonic world of music that orders of cognition. The aesthetic was that force which built steps between
46
the throne of cognition and the diverse, messy, and vibrant world of
Before the publication of the treatise in 1773, Dnube produced a weekly publication, published sensation and feeling. Aesthetics in its original sense was, in Baumgarten's
by Joseph KU.rzbockenand called Der musikalischeDilettante,which largely reproduced the
information contained in Daube's 1756 treatise Geneml-Bafi.This serial publication should not
words, "a science of how things are to be known by means of the senses,"51
47
be confused with the 1773 treatise. a "science of sensitive cognition"; it was an inquiry into the ptocess by
J. F. Dnube, Der musikalischeDilettant:Eine Abhandlungder Komposition(1773), trans.
S. P. Snook-Luther ns The MusicalDilettante:A Treatiseon Compositionby J, F. Daube 50
Ibid., p. x,
(Cambridge University Press, 1992), pp. 37-38, 5
48
Ibid., pp. 144-45. 49
Ibid., pp. 38-39. l A, G. Baumgarten, Meditationesphilosophicaede nonnullisad poema pertinentibus(Halle:
J. Grunerti, 1735), pp. cxv-cxvi.
72 The idea of timbre
The beginningof Enlightenmentaesthetics 73

which our sensations of the outside world were translated into higher
time, and was shaken when his authorship was discovered." He aban-
orders of cognition, an exploration of how om· senses modulate the
doned the publication of the Viel'tes Wdldchen:Uber Riedels Theorie der
outside world for our interior world of ideas. Aesthetics was a study of
schonenKiinste(the fourth "Little Forest"); it was not published until well
mediation, and dealt in equal measure with irn1nediate sensation and
after his death. While the first three Walderfocused primarily on the visual
abstract reason.
and literary arts, the fourth included a lengthy discussion of music and a
Just as the birth of Enlightenment aesthetics was an inquiry into the proposal for a radical new aesthetics of music. 54
human senses and mediation, it also brought attention to objects - the
Central to his discussion of music was a critique of Rameau's theory of
instruments - that functioned as extensions of the senses. The inextric-
the bassefondamental. As explored in the previous chapter, Rameau's ideas
ability of attention to timbre and the discourse of aesthetics is made
in the Traite de l'harmonie faced considerable criticism in his lifetime,
explicit in the philosophy of Johann Gottfried Herder, who turned to
despite his lasting influence on music theory. Because of Rameau's criti-
music several times during his career. Although his writing on folk song
cisms of Rousseau, and his continued insistence that the corps sonore
and his notion of the "religious contemplation" of music are familiar
was the fundamental principle behind a wide range of natural phenom-
today, a good deal of his writing on music remains little known. The same
enal Ra1neau 1nade enemies, smnewhat ironically, with d'Ale1nbert.
is true of a large body of his philosophical writing: though Herder initiated
D'Alembert had, in 1752, helped popularize Rameau's theory with his
a wide range of philosophical inquiry, the subsequent generations of
publication of Elemens de musique theorique et pratique suivant /es prin-
philosophers who followed his lead - Hegel, Schleiermacher, and
cipesde M. Rameau. But after Rameau's attacks on the musical entries in
Nietzsche, for example - are today better known. But it was precisely ;: ''i
the Encyclopedie,d'Alembert soon became openly critical of him. His entry
because his scholarly interests were so catholic - ranging from the study of
"fondamental" simmers with hostility and contempt for Rameau's theory:
the origin of language to the philosophy of history, from the theorization
of national culture to the remit of aesthetics - that it is today difficult to What will we say about what has been suggestedlately,that geometry is founded .I
pick any single text as representative of Herder's oeuvre. However, recent upon the resonance of the corpssonore,because geometry, it is said, is founded
scholarship has seen, if not a renaissance, at least a renewal of interest in upon proportions, and that the corpssonoregenerates them all? Geometricians
Herder's work. 52 We are slowly beginning to reassess the importance and would not be grateful if we take seriously such assertions, We willpermit ourselves
only to say here that the consideration of proportions and progressions is entirely ·,,
,I
relevance of Herder's thought for later thinkers.
useless to the theory of musical art. 55 ',,'
I:: I
Herder first turned to music early in his career. In 1764, he took up
his first teaching position at the Domschule of Riga; in the years that Thongh the criticisms of d' Alembert and Rousseau have been explored in
followed he published his first two books, Fragmente uber die neuere musical scholarship, Herder's critique has received far less attention. 'r
deutsche Literatur (1766-67) and Kritische Walder oder, Betrachtungen, D'Alembert objected to Rameau's theory because so much of it was
: !,
die Wissenschaftund Kunst des Schonen betreffend,nach Massgabeneuerer based on sensory input rather than rigorous scientific reasoning;
Schriften (1769), containing three "Critical Forests." He pnblished Herder, on the other hand, believed that Rameau made too little of
anonymously, which was not an unusual practice for philosophers at this sensory input. Pushing the entire discussion of music outside of the ,i!

53
52 On Herder's unmasking, see W. Koepke, Johann GottfriedHerder (Boston: Twayne Publishers,
See, for example, scholarship such as Herder:PhilosophicalWritings,ed. M. N. For~ter 1987), pp. 16-20.
(Cambridge University Press, 2002); M. Kessler and V. Leppin (eds.), Johann GottfriedHei~er: 54
See R. E. Norton, Herder'sAestheticsand the EuropeanEnlightenment(Ithaca: Cornell
AspekteseinesI,ebenswerkes(Berlin: De Gruyter, 2005); J. Zammito, Kant, Herd~~and the Birth University Press, 1991), pp. 150-56.
of Anthropology(University of Chicago Press, 2002); J, G. Herder, SelectedWritingson. 55
"Fondamental," in Diderot and d'Alembert (eds.), Encyclop{!die,trans. in T. Christensen,
Aesthetics,trans, G. Moore (Princeton University Press, 2006); M. Gelbart, The Invention of
"FolkMusic'' and "ArtMusic":EmergingCategoriesfrom Ossianto Wagner(Cambridge Rameau and Musical Thoµght (Cambridge University Press, 1993), p. 262. See also
T. Christensen, "Music Theory as Scientific Propaganda: The Case of d'Alembert's Blemens
University Press, 2007); H. Adler and W. Koepke (eds.), A Companionto the Wotks of Johann
de musique,"Journalof the History of Ideas,50/3 (1989), 18-11, and "Eighteenth-Century
GottfriedHerder(Rochester: Camden House, 2009); P. V. Bohlman, "Herder's Nineteenth
Science and the c01pssonore:The Scientific Background to Rameau's Principle of Harmony;'
Century," Ninefeenth~CenturyMusic Review,7/1 (2010), 3-21.
Journalof Music Theory,31/1 (1987), 23-50.
74 The idea of timbre
The beginningof Enlightenmentaesthetics 75

realm of mathematics, Herder argued that the art of music lay not in the Physics and mathematics: how do they differentiate and determine tones? By the
generation of harmony or the primacy of melody, but in music's powerful oscillations of the string in a given time, by the proportion of the tensioned forc;e,
impact on the listener. of the physical constitution and length. of the string. And what is it that is
For Herder, aesthetics was as much a study of human perception as it calculated from these proportions in the tone? Nothing except proportions,
was an appraisal of works of art. As a whole, the Viertes Wiildchen highness and lowness) strength and weakness, intervals, simultaneity and non-
explores the role of sensation in cognition and aesthetic judgments. simultaneity, etc.: nothing but proportions, which in the sciences) to which they
The work was conceived as a critique of the theories of Friedrich Justus belong, suffice to recognize the tone in them, and from this knowledge to derive
Riedel. In 1767, Riedel had published his Theorie der schonen Kiinste und consequences; however, as we shall see, they are worthless for the aesthetics of
tones. They explain nothing aboutsimpletones;nothingof theirforceon the senseof
Wissenschaften, in which he propounded his notion of how immediate,
hearing;nothingof their beauty,individuallyor combined;about everything,they
umeflective sensations affected cognition; Herder set out to show how
explainnothing.Thus [proportions] do not contain a single iota of the philosophy
sensation is never unreflective, and that it is impossible to separate of the beautiful in the art of tones [TonartigSchOnen].
58
sensation from cognition and judgment. 56 Rather, all sensation implies
cognition. Herder writes: For Herder, no true aesthetics of music existed yet; in his eyes, musical
discourse was still divided between the study of the mathematics of
To recognize a thing clearly, even in the slightest degree, means that one has
music - as carried out by Euler, Diderot, Mersenne, Sauveur, and
already distinguished it; and no distinction ever occurs without judgment> and a
cl'Alembert - and that of musical practice, such as the treatises by Leopold
judgment is no longer an immediate feeling, And to recognize something dis-
Mozart, C. P. E. Bach, and Quantz. In particular, Herder took Rameau's
tinctly: that requires a clear cognition of its subordinate concepts as such, as the
distinguishing marks of the whole, and thus involves an act of the inner workings theory to task, for Rameau had attempted to unify theory and practice by
of reason. 57 explaining both sides through mathematics: in Rameau's theory, acoustics ,,1
masqueraded as aesthetic theory: '

The idea that sensation always already implied cognition has deep impli-
Still fewer concern themselves as to how tone, as tone, affectsus. Not the physicist,
I
,I
cations for musical aesthetics. Whereas many eighteenth-century thinkers
were suspicions of music because it seemed so dependent on fleeting who knows it only as resonance. He trackt; it from the string through the air, from
the air to the ear, through the entire organ of hearing to the nerves, but still only as
sensations (and thus lacked appropriate educational and moral value),
resonance. Thus how can he know how resonance affects the nerves when it is no
Herder was able to embrace music because it stimulated judgment and
longer resonance, but a simple tone? How this tone functions in the soul and
cognition. His discussion of music in the Viertes Wiildchen reveals that he moves it?59
was familiar with Rameau)s 1nusical theory, Rousseau's -entries on 1nusic
for the Encyclopedie,and the various debates and conflicts surrounding the 58
"Physik und Mathematik, wie unterscheiden und bestimmen die TOne?Aus den Schwingungen
primacy of melody or harmony and the corps sonore. Capitalizing on the
der Saite in einer gegebnen Zeit, nach Proportion des spannenden Gewichts, des KOrperlichen
llnplications of his conception of sensation, Herder's radical move was to Inhalts und der Lange der Saite. Und was ists, was aus diesen Verhiiltnissen im Tone selbst
insist aggressively that the human listener - and his bodily and mental bcrechnet wird? Nkhts als selbst Verhiiltnissen, H6hen und Tiefen, Stiirke und Schwiiche,
Intervallen, Gleich- und Unglcichzeitiges usw. lauter Verhiiltnisse, die in den Wissenschaften,
reaction to music - be made an integral part of the study of music. He
fi.ir die sie gehOren genug sind, im in ihnen den Ton zu erkennen, und ans dicsen Kiinntissen
demands that the study of the musical art be a study of the ways in which Folgen abzuleiten, die aber, wie wir sehen wollen, fi.ir die .Asthetik der Tone durchaus nichts
humans respond to tones, not the study of the physics of sound or the sind. Sie ~rklaten nichts vom einfachenTOneselbst,·nichts von der Energiedesselbenaufs GehOr;
nichtsvon derAnmut derselben,einzelnund in der Folge;von allemNichts.Es gibt also mit lhnen
calculation of mathematical ratios:
noch kein Jota zur Philosophic des Tonartig Sch6nen." Herder, ViertesWiildchen,in Werke,vol.
II; Herderund die Anthropologieder Aufklarung,ed. W. Pross (Munich: Carl Hanser Verlag,
1987), p. 140,
56 59
For an extended discussion of Ricdel's philosophy, see Norton, Herder'sAestheticsand the "Noch weniger bekilmmern sich beide, wie Ton als Ton auf uns wUrkt'.Nicht der Physike1;
EuropeanEnlightenment,pp. 159-62. der ihn bloB als Schall kcnnct. Der verfolgt ihn van Saite <lurch die Luft, van Luft zum Ohr,
57
J. G. Herder, SiimmtlicheWerke,ed. B. Suphan (Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung, <lurch alle Geht:irgiinge des Olll'Szur Nerve; aber nach immer als Schall. Wie will er also wissen,
1877-1913), vol. IV, p. 6, quoted and trans. in Norton, Herder'sAestheticsand the European wie die Nerve von dem, was nicht mehr Schall, was nur einfacher Ton ist, getroffon wird?
Enlightenment;p. 162, wie dieser in die Seele wili·kt, und sie bewegt?" Ibid., p. 142.
' ,

76 The idea of timbre The beginningof Enlightenmentaesthetics 77

Rameau's theory came no closer to providing a true philosophy of music, Herder's demand that the "philosopher of tone-pleasure" turn away from
for Rameau only saw single tones as corporeal manifestations of an the study of harmony did not imply that he located the true heart of music
underlying abstract concept, expressible as a series of mathematical ratios within melody, as other writers in the eighteenth century did. Rather he
and proportions. Herder writes: advocated the study of singletones and how they penetrate the soul of the
The relationshipof the overtones,says Rameau, which one hears resonating espe- listener at "the first moment of sensation)) Cerste Mo111entder Sensa-
cially in the main tone of a long string, and which make up his great, perfected tion"), He writes, "[The] ea,; as an ea,; cannot senseproportions ... the
chord. One knows that Rameau built his entire harmony from this experience, basis of all music lies in the first moment of sensation, in simple tone-
and his interpreter, d'Alembert>his entire system of music. Now, it does not pleasure."62Herder, like Hegel after him, adopted Gottfried Wilhelm
concern us here from which principle one can explain and produce all musical Leibniz's concept of the monad, a simple substance "where no parts,
laws, or whether the Rameauian one - which I very much doubt - is the main neither extension, nor figure, nor divisibility is possible:' 63 Single tones,
principle. But it is certain that this does not in the least explain the effect of music when considered aesthetically as tones and not mathematically as reson-
on the soul.60 ance, admit no division; they are characterized by their own "accents of
For Herder, the question was not whether Rameau's theory of the corps passion," and can combine to produce melody:
sonorewas true or not; rather he believed that the study of music could not First nothing but simple, effective moments in music) single pitched accents of
begin with the study of harmony. Like Rameau, Herder believed harmony passion - that is the first thing (the student of music) feels and collects, and this
to be a natural phenomenon: Rameau took that belief as the foundation of becomes a musicalmonadology,a philosophy of the elementsof music.Because ifhe
his musical theory; Herder used the same notion to dismiss harmony as an connects them by the chain of succession) by the pleasure they cause the ear, by
aestheticelement. If chords were the natural outcome of the resonance of their effect on the soul, it becomes melody. 64
sounding bodies, as Rameau believed them to be, then they were unable to
The power that Herder found in musical monads was something that
inform an nnderstanding of how a tone affects a human listener. The
was not understood through physics: he heard a quality in single tones
distinction between resonance (Scha/0 and tone (Ton) is important for that went beyond volume and pitch:
Herder: the former implies a kind of composite of natural phenomena,
while the latter belongs properly to the realm of aesthetics. Resonance is Experience shows that certain, distinct tones make different impressions on us,
what is out there; tone is what we experience. independent of their height or depth, strength or weakness, length or shortness, by
their inner nature. The one strikes us, as it were, more smoothly and brightly;
Even if Rameau's account were, in and of itself, as true as it today perhaps appears another, roughly and more gloomily. The one seems to wake up and elevate our
to be false,for the philosopherof tone-pleasure(Wohllaut],it is a dry, one-sided, nerves, the other turns them down and puts them to sleep. The one strains them
sterile experience, Chords are mere resonance, and all harmonies of chords are into astonishment, another melts them into gentle feeling. This is our experience,
mere resonance ... Students of tone-pleasure, do you thereby comprehend even and it should become our fw1damental principle. 65
the smallest part of the inner being of a tone? Of the power of a single accent over
the soul?61
Schalle ... Schiilerdes Wohllauts weiBestdu damit auch <laskleinste Etwas vom innerlichen
Moment Eines Tones?Etwasvon Einer Kraft Bines einzelnen Accentsauf die Seele?"Ibid,,p. 160.
62
"Ohr, als Ohr kein Verhiiltnisempfinden kann, und dochim erstenMoment der Sensation,im
60
"Verhilltnisin den Beit0nen,sagt Rameau, die man insonderheit bei einer groben Saite dem simplen Wohllaut,die BasisallerMusik liegt."Ibid., p. 144.
63
Haupttone nachschallen horet, und die seinen gr6Ben vollkommenen Akkord ausmachen. See G. W. von Leibniz, Monadologyand Other PhilosophicalEssays,trans. P. Schrecker and
Man weiE, daB Rameauauf diese Erfahrung alle seine Harmonie, und sein Erkliirer d'Alembert A. M. Schrecker (New York: Macmillan/Library of Liberal Arts, 1965).
sein ganzes System von Musik gebauet hat. Nun gehts uns hier nicht an) aus welchem M "Erst lauter einfache, wlirksame Momente der Musik, einzelne Tonaccente der Leidenschaft -
Gnmdsatze man alle Hauptgesetze der Musik erklaren und hervorwiilzen kiinne;noch ob der das ist <lasErste, was [der Schiiler der Musik] fiihlt und sammlet, und <laswird cine
Rameausche, wie ich sehr zweifle,der erste Grundsatz sei; abet das ist gewiB,daB dieser die MusikalischeMonadologie,eine Philosophic ihrerElemente.Denn verbindet er sic <lurchdas
Wilrkung der Musil<auf die Seele gar nicht erklare," Ibid,) p. 143, Band der Folge,in ihrer Annehmlichkeit auf Ohr, in iluer Worksamkeit auf die Seele:das wird
61
"Ware die Rameausche Erfahrung also auch an sich so wahr, als sic jetzt schon vielleicht an sich Melodie." Herder, ViertesWaldchen,in Werki;vol. II, p. 161.
65
scheinbare Unwahrheit ist, fi.irden Philosophen des Wohllauts ist sie eine trockne, einseitige, "Es ist Erfahi'Ung,classgewisseeinfache Tcine,unabhangig von HOhe und Tiefe, von Starke und
unfruchtbare Erfahnmg. Akkord ist nur Schall, und alle Harmonien von Akkorden nur Schwiiche,von Lange und Kiirze, if1rerinnernArt nach,verschiedne Eindrilcke auf uns machen.
I'

78 The idea of timbre


We are all instruments 79

Herder, of course, describes timbre in this passage - it is the quality that this is why his project was truly an aesthetic inquiry: he sought to
remains beyond pitch and volume. He even refers to the word itself ("so understand music in terms of mediation and experience.
far the French call it timbre"). He continues, appealing to a listener:

You, you who know nothing but the strength and weakness) of the height and
depth of a tone, pay attention: does the sound of a flute and of a shawm, a lute and We are all instruments
violin, a trumpet and a Nachthorn-where no strength or weal<11ess,no height and
depth can be the topic of discussion - still have the same natureand, as it were, a
Timbre - and its immediate and powerful ability to convey a sense of
specificsubstanceof sound?Does each of these sounds have the same effect on your
agitation or calm - was for Herder a proof that a listener, in hearing such
feeling?66
impassioned tones) did not experience a mere «raw" sensation, but s01ne-
Like so many other writers, Herder is forced here to define timbre thing always already imbued with aesthetic qualities. The very process
negatively; he can only say that it depends neither on the number of of discerning different instruments already meant having an aesthetic
vibrations nor on their intensity. But the difference between timbre and experience. Herder addressed issues of music and its expressive power
other qualities like pitch and volume is greater for Herder, who clearly sees that remained intractable problems from within Immanuel Kant's
timbre as something distinct from pitch and volume, governed by an philosophy. Yet it was not until the publication of Herder's Kalligonein
entirely different set of criteria. Pitch and volume were measurable, 1800 that his musical aesthetics were articulated publically. Kalligonewasa
abstract qualities; timbre was embodied and immediately sensible. That response to, and a meta-critique of, Kant's Kritik der Urteilskraft( Critique
timbre was, at the time, intractable to scientific analysis only bolstered its of Judgment, 1790), tl1e third and final work of his critical project. Herder
non-mathematical status; timbre wasn't a quality, but it was the direct occasionally addressed Kant directly, in fiery language:
experience of the tone itself.
Youi then, you who despise the music of tones and can gain nothing from it if it
Rudolf Bockholdt pointed out an irony in Herder's argument in a brief
doesn't have words) stay far away from have nothing to do with it! Keep away from
essay on Herder's Viertes Wiildchen:naturally, the production of timbre
itl Consider it as a play in which "purposive-purposeless" instruments are exer-
has a physkal explanation. Indeed, timbre originates in the subtleties of dsed! But you) musicians, write above your music hall in the manner of Plato the
the overtone series, the very same phenomenon that Herder rejected in words: "No hater of the Muses may enter!" 68
this same text. 67 But though Herder might have been surprised to learn
that timbre was dependent on the overtone series, it would not impinge Herder challenged, among other things, tl1e series of binary oppositions
on his larger argument. A physical description of timbre would hardly between types of beauty and types of aesthetic judgments t11atformed the
!· :,,,:1
have satisfied his demand for a musical monadology: he longed for a study center of Kant's aesthetic proje,t. Kant distinguishes between, among
of how the tones affected the listener, not how they were produced. And others, form and presentation; design and color; free beauty and accessory
beauty; reflection and sensation; beauty and agreeableness; culture and
itl
'',,
'

charm. In each dyad, the former contributes to, or is a necessary compon-


Der eine triffi uns gleichsam glatter und heller; ein ander rauher und finstrer. Der eine scheit
ent of, "pure" aesthetic judgments, in which the object is truly beautiful,
unsre Nerve aufzuwecken und zu erheben; der andre niederzuschmiegen und cinzuschlafern. while the latter contributes to "material" aesthetic judgments, in which the
Der einc strengt sie zum Staunen an; ein andrer schmelzt sie in sanftes Gefi.ihlhin - dies ist object is either merely agreeable, or else is contingently beautiful. Kant
Erfahrung, tJnd sie soil uns Grundsatz werden." Ibid., p. 146. writes:
66
Du, der du von Nichts als von Starke und Schwiiche,von HOhe und Tiefe der Tone einen
Begriffhast, gib Acht, ob der Schall einer FlOteund einer Schallmei, eine Laute und Geige,
einer Trompete und einest Nachthorns auch in der Vcrmischung aller TOne,wo von keiner ;:·1'
Stii.rkeund Schwii.che,von keiner HOhe und 'fiefe die Rede sein kann>noch EinerlieArt und 6a "Habt ihr also, ihr, die ihr die Musik der Tone also solche verachtet, und ihr nichts abgewinnen
gleichsam Eine specifischeMassedes Klangeshabe? Ob jeder dieser ganzen Schalle gleiche konnt, ohne Worte nichts mit ihr; so bleibct ihr fern. Setzet sic als ein Spiel an, worinn sich
Wilrkung auf Deine Empfindbarkeit habe?" Ibid., p. 147, 'zweckmiiBig-zwecklos'lebendige Instrumcnte Uben. 1hr aber, Tonki.instler,schreibt eurem
67
R. Bockholdt, '"Von unten herauf,' nicht 'von oben herab': Zu Herders Betrachtungen iiber
Musiksaal nach Art des Plato die Worte vor: 'Kein Muse.nlosergehe hinein!"' Herder, Kalligone
Kunst und Musik," Musik Tlieorie,15/3 (2000), 247-54. (Leipzig: Johann Friedrich Haitknock, 1800), vol. II, pp. 169-70.
--~-,·

80 The idea of timbre We are all instruments 81

There are two kinds of beauty, free beauty (pulchritude vaga) and merely acces- When we unpack Kant's notion of musical sensation, his dean divisions
sory beauty (pulchritude adhaerens). Free beauty does not presuppose a concept between ldnds of aesthetic judgments and kinds of beauty begin to disinte-
of what the object [is meanl] to be. Accessory beauty does presuppose such a grate. Musical sensation - tone - and color continually waver between the
concept, as well as the object's perfection in terms of that con~ept. The free ki1_1ds aesthetic categories of the "beautiful" and the merely "agreeable." Here Kant
of beauty are called (self-subsistent) beauties of this or that thmg. The other kmd calls upon the familiar delineation between color and design. In Kant's view,
of beauty is accessory to a concept (i.e., it is conditioned beauty). And as such design, because it has form, is the source of an object's beauty. Color and
[accessory beauty] is attributed to objects that fall under the concept of a tone (by analogy), because they belong to the "presentation" of the object,
. 1ar purpose. 69
part1cu are merely agreeable: one can speak of the "charm" of a color or tone, but
Unlike the imitative theories that dominated much of eighteenth-century not of their beauty. Yet Kant continually hints at the possibility that a color
aesthetics, Kant's concept of beauty radically breaks away from notions of or tone could be beautiful in and of itself. He writes, for example:
representation, eschewing notions of purpose and imitation. Within Kant's
Most people will declare a mere color, such as the green color of a lawn, or a mere
theory, intrinsic purposiveness would only demote the object from a free
tone (as distinct from sound and noise), as for example that of a violin, to be
beauty to a dependent beauty. Here Kant seems to rescue music from the
beautiful in themselves, even though botli seem to be based merely on the matter
criticisms of vagueness made by so many earlier thinkers: of presentations, i.e., solely on sensations, and hence deserve only to be called
Flowers are free natural beauties. Hardly anyone apart from the botanist knows agreeable. And yet it will surely be noticed at the same time that sensations of
what sort of thing a flower is [meant] to be, , . Hence the judgment is based on no color as well as of tone claim to deserve being considered beautiful only insofar as
perfection of any kind, no intrinsic purposiveness to which the combination of the they are pure,And that is an attribute that already concerns form. 71
,I
manifold might refer. Many birds (the parrot, the humming-bird) the bird of Kant suggests here that this property of purity can be judged only by I
. !!I
paradise) and a lot of crustaceans in the sea are [free] beauties thcmsel~es [and]
knowledge of the form of the vibrations of air or light that constitute the
belong to no object determined by concepts as to its purpose, but we like them
tone or color. This concept of pure color or tone is bracketed as a theoretical
a
freely and on their own account. Thus designs la grecque,the foliage on ~orders
possibility rather than a working component of his aesthetics. He then
or on wallpapet\ etc. mean nothing on their own; they represent nothmg) ~o
object under a determinate concept, and are free beauties. What we call fantasias proceeds to downplay the importm1ce of such raw materials by arguing
in music (namely, music without a topic [Thema]), indeed all music not set to that they fill a subsidiary role in aesthetic judgments, and cannot make an
words, may also be included in the same class.
70 object beautiful. They can be added to the object, but "all they do is to make
the form intuitable more precisely, determinately, and completely, while
A pure judgment of taste, it follows, occurs when an object is judged they also enliven the presentation by means of their charm, by arousing and
according to its form alone, ignoring any purpose or function. An ancient sustaining the attention we direct towards the object itself."72
cooking utensil, for instance, can still be considered as a work of art: we Later, when discussing the divisions of the fine arts, Kant revisits the
may make judgments about its form, its shape and proportions, ignoring aesthetic status of color and tone, and again entertains the possibility
any function or the object's suitability for accomplishing this function. that the very act of sensing already implies a ldnd of formal reflection.
The application of Kant's formal theory to music would appear straight- He writes:
forward: instrumental music, like birds and wallpaper designs, would be
judged according to its "outward form." For the nineteenth-century the- we cannot say with certainty whether a color or a tone (sound) is merely an
orists who followed Kant, music's form was the way in which the composer agreeable sensation or whether it is of itself already a beautiful play of [compon-
has organized the sounds into an overarching structure. Kant, however, had ent] sensations and as s1,1chcarries with it, as we judge it aesthetically, a liking for
its form. Just consider the rapidity of the vibration of light, or in the case of tones,
no comparable notion of musical form, and never discusses music in terms
of the air, which probably far exceedsall our ability to judge directlyin perception
of melody and harmony, but rather as a "play of sensations:'
the ratio in the temporal division [produced] by these vibrations. 73

6g I. Kant, Critiqueof Judgment,trans. W. S. Pluhar (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, 1987),P· 76. 71 72 73


70 Ibid., p. 70. Ibid., p. 72. Ibid., p. 194.
Ibid., pp. 76-77,
~~------- --- "--"----~---·-•y

82 The idea of timbre


We are all instruments 83

If we can judge the "temporal division" of the vibrations - that is, the
Helmholtz investigated nearly a century later when he sought to under-
form of the vibration - then these sensations can be beautiful in and of
stand ti1:1bre;like _Herder, Kant also turned to timbre, although perhaps
themselves. If we merely sense the effect of the vibrations, then we never
unknowmgly. But 1twas Kant's dismissal of music that galvanized Herder's
connect colors and tones with anything more than agreeableness. Though
return to musical aesthetics, leading to the publication of Kalligone.
direct perception of the vibration's form seems impossible, Kant reminds
As a whole, Ka/ligonealternates between describing Herder's own aes-
us that people can be, in spite of keen vision or hearing, color-blind or
thetic theory - which often takes the foi·m of dialogs between three
tone-deaf, in which case they lack an innate ability to judge the sensation's
characters - and attacking Kant's Kritik der Urteilskraft.Though Ka/ligone
"temporal division." In turn this implies that we are usually able to judge
addresses the arts in general, the project is centered on rescuing music
the form of the vibration of a tone or color, a fact that has important
from Kant's low ranking. The importance of this work has been under-
ramifications for music as an art: 1
played in most accounts of Herder's oeuvre as well as in musical
If we consider all of this, we may feel compelled to regard sensation of color and tone aesthetics." Though this text marked an explicit return to mt1sicalaesthet-
not as mere sense impressions,but as the effect of our judgingof theform we find in ics, it would be.wrong to suggest that Herder's thoughts on the topic had
the play of many sensations. However, the difference that one or the other opinion not developed smce the ViertesWi:ildchen, or that no other part of his oeuvre
wouldmake to our judgingof the basisof music would affectthe definitiononly in sheds any light on his conception of the relationship between listener and
this: we would declaremusic either,as we did above,to be the beautiful[schon]play music. Music and the importance of sensation infiltrate Herder's philoso-
of sensations(of hearing),or [to be the play]of agreeablesensations.Onlyunder the phy as a who!~. Indeed, Herder's theory of the inseparability of cognition
first kind of explicationwill music be presentedwholly as fine [sch/in]art, while and sensation is most strongly articulated with respect to music.
under the second it would be presented (at least in part) as agreeableart. 74
For example, in Herder's essay "Vom Erkennen und Empfinden den
Music is thus pushed to the threshold between beauty and agreeable- z:,vo Haupthiiften der menschlichen Seele" ("On Cognition and Sensa-
ness. While Kant's ambivalence over the status of musical sensation lion, the Two Main Forces in the Human Soul", 1775), he continues the
ultimately seems of little consequence to the aesthetic project of the Kritik arguments laid out in the ViertesWaldchen.He complains that contempor-
der Urteilskraft, it is one reason for Kant's difficulties with music ary metaphysics, most directly referring to Kant, among others, was too
altogether. Because he sees music fundamentally as a "play of sensations" far removed from lived experience: "what a dead, wooden clock the soul
and does not discuss other aspects of musical form, he forces music to and the science of the soul has now become. In all the mutual perceptions
assume the same fate as its constituent parts, and therefore to waver of thought and sensation it lacks deep derivation fruitfulness and
between the categories of the agreeable and the beautiful. Music can truth ·" 78 Th e 1'd ea th at one could discuss the mind ' and cognition ' in
stimulate the mind, but because it is fundamentally sensation, it can never ~bstract t~rms, apart from feeling and sensation, was a philosophical
fuel cognition. However, Kant did rank music highly on account of its nnposs1bility for Herder: sensation and cognition are one and the same:
"charm and mental agitation ... though [music] speaks through nothing
Is the whole mountain of our cognition supposed to be accumulated without I
but sensations without concepts, so that unlike poetry it leaves us with
feeling?ls the most godlikeforce of our soul supposed to build with less reward
nothing to meditate about, it nevertheless does agitate the mind more
diversely and intensely, even if merely temporarily." 75 In the end, when he
77
judges the arts according to "the culture they s4pply to the mind;' Kant RbO e~t N orton argues that 1t
·· 1snot connected to Herder's earlier thought, and accordingly does
was obliged to demote music to "the lowest place among the fine arts;' not -~1scussthe.work in his study on Herder's aesthetics, John Neubauer briefly mentions
awarding highest rank to painting and sculpture. 76 Kalltgonebut, like Norton, sees little connection between it and Herder's earlier writing
th . . 00
aes etics, Instead expressing dismay that Herder never finished the project of a musical
Yet there is something quite remarkable in Kant's discussion of tone and mon_adologythat he outlines in the Viertes Wi.:ildchen.See J. Neubauer, The Emancipationof
its perception: his attention to the "form of vibration" was precisely what Music[~om~anguage:Departurefrom Mimesis in Eighteenth-CenturyAesthetics(New Haven:
Yale Umverstty Press, 1986), p. 160.
78
Herd~r'. "Yorn Erkennen und Empfinden den zwo Hauptkraften der menschlichen Seele" ("On
74
Ibid,, p. 194 75 76 Co~~1t1on and Sensation, the Two Main Forces of the Human Soul:' 1775), in Philoso hical
Ibid., p, 198. Ibid., p. 200, W1'ttings,p. 182. p
84 The idea of timbre The little clavichords in our souls 85

than a bee, and to fly the goal of cognition like a shot arrow, like a ray of light, string~play of all manners of thought and sensation, human nature, who tuned
quicldy and also just as without feeling? No! In cognition there lives sensation, the you? V\!ho strung you? Who plays on you? Who listens to you?81
deepest, most spiritual, godlike sensation! Error and ignorance are night and fog;
truth is brightness and sun, bound up with the feeling, "This is the right place to In a later version of the same essay, he writes: ((The extent to which we
bel," as on the mountain of the 'fransfiguration. The quickest judgment of the soul participate in what surrounds us, how deeply love and hate, disgust and
is affirmation or denial, i.e. in cruder terms) only expression of good or bad, of revulsion, vexation and pleasure, plant their roots in ns - this tunes the
harmony or discord, of pain or pleasurc. 79 string-play of our thoughts, this makes us into the human beings we
82
are." In shunning the abstract, Herder created a philosophical framework
The lively inseparability of sensation and cognition governs our deep
in which individual sensations could be appreciated for their own value.
response to music. But for Herder, we do not simply respond to music, we
Indeed, Herder, because of his holistic approach, believed that regard for
are ourselves a kind of musical instrument, one capable of responding to a
the individual was precisely what was lost in philosophical generalizing.
variety of sensory input. Kant, with his emphasis on enduring concepts,
He writes: "Metaphysics reveals the unity in everything splendidly, but
seems to conceive of the mind as a library capable of preservation; for
does it also reveal as distinguishingly the eachness in each thing?"83 And
Herder, the mind is an instrument, designed to respond dynamically to a
later: "Natural science was unable to arrive at forces as long as people
i! variety of sensations. Throughout his writing, Herder refers to hnman
failed to regard each individual thing as what it is, as unique, as long as
nature as "string-play," tuned and played upon by outside forces. Indeed,
they always only imputed to it what it could be or should be in general:' 84
this is why mnsic is so important for Herder, for it "plays on the clavi-
When Herder returned to music in Kalligone,he was able to draw upon
chord within us which is our own innermost being." In other words, we
these ideas, which he had developed in the thirty years after the Viertes
respond to music because we are always alreadymusical.80 The human-as-
Wiildchen.Indeed, rather than representing a breal<from his early aesthetic
instrument metaphor was of course centuries old, but in Herder that
thinking, Herder's Kalligonereinforced his theory of sensation, not by
metaphor is vital. The "clavichord within us" is not merely a way of
producing an aesthetics of single tones, but by developing further the
describing an abstract structure, but a way of being in and reacting to
theory of how humans respond to musical sensation.
the world around us.
In discussing cognition and sensation, Herder frequently invokes the
metaphor of a string instrument to explain how humans respond to
The little clavichords in our souls
sensory input. He writes:

Contradictions in the human being, apparent enemies, to what extent do you Herder's metaphor of the string-play of our minds gained new significance
mutually support each other?Where do you eliminateeach other? I-lowdo you in Kalligone.It had served as a useful way of explaining how humans
relate to the happiness of each human being and of all human beings? You great responded dynamically to a variety of sensory input; in the context of
musical aesthetics, however, the metaphor suggested a natural affinity
between musical sensation and the human mind. Indeed, throughout
7
" Sollte der ganze Berg unseres Erkennens ohne Gefuhl zusammengetragen seyn? Sollte die Kalligone,musical sensation seems to accrue increasing power and signifi-
Gottfihnlichte Kraft unser Seele,unbelohnter als eine Beine bauen und zum Ziel <las cance. In chapter 3, several of his characters discuss how tones communi-
Erkennens, wie ein geschoi3nerFfeil, wie ein Lichtsral, schnell und eben auch so Geflihllos cate to human listeners:
fliegen?Nein! Im Erkennen wohnt Empfindung, die innigste, geistigste, Gott8hnliche
Empfindung! Inthum und Unwi:Benheitist Nacht und Nebel: Wahr)leit ist Glanz und Sonne,
81
mit dem GefllhI, "Hier ist gut seyn!" verbunden, wie auf dem Berge der Verklanmg. Das Herder, "Vom Erkennen und Empfinden den zwo Hauptkriiften der menschlichen Socle"
schnellste Urtheil der Seele ist Bejahung oder Verneinung, d, e, mit grObern Ausdrticken, nur (1775), in PhilosophicalWritings,p. 184.
82
AuBerung des Guten oder Uebcls, der Einstimmung oder des Misklanges,des Schmerzes oder Herder, "Vom Erkennen und Empfinden der menschlichen Seelc" ("On the Cognition and
VergnUgens."Ibid., p. 179, Sensation of the Human Soul," 1778), in PhilosophicalWritings,p. 196.
80 83
There is a powerful connection between Herder's theory oflanguage aod his idea of humans as Herder, "Vom Erkennen un<lEmpfinden den zwo Hauptkriiften der menschlkhen Seele"
being "already" musical. See C. Taylor, PhilosophicalArguments (Cambridge, MA: Harvard (1775), in PhilosophicalWritings,p. 180.
84
University Press, 1995), pp. 79-99, Ibid., p. 181.
86 The idea of timbre
Conclusion 87

A: A blow disturbs a body; what docs that sound say? "the art of tone and the art of color [are] fully equated; as though colors
n: "I have been disturbed; thus my parts are vibrating and coming together again." withoctt drawing can be set equal to tones as a medium of art." 86 Tones,
A: Do they also say this to us? unlike colors, are imbued with a kind of ((significative power" that reveals
B: Through and through) we are resilh;nt beings; our em\ the hearing-chamber of both the nature of the instrument giving forth the tone and the consti-
the soul, is an auditorium [Akroaterion],an echo-chamber of the finest kind. tution of the listener who hears that tone:
A: So if single tones arouseus, what do intermittent tones do?
n: They renew and amplify the vibration, like a tuba; they reawaken, In the whole of nature, all elastic bodies upon being struck or stroked make known
A: And long, continuoustones? (audibly or less audibly to us) their interior,that is, their excited and restorative
n: They extend the emotion by prolonging the vibration. They create an incredibly forces.This we call noise[Schall),and more finelyexcited, sound[Klang);sound,
powerful effect. which sets every similarly organized object into same vibration, and in sensitive
A: And tones that get louderor softer)riseor fall, that are sloweror fastet; more beings brings about an analogous sensation. 87
serious'or lightet;that are increasinglyor decreasinglyintense,harsh or soft,
Herder's philosophy did not seek to elevate instrumental music above
regularor lrregulatjthat is, shocks, blows) breaths, waves, emotion ~nd
vocal inusic; in turning to timbre and to conceptualizing the human
pleasure - what effoct do all these have on us?
listene1· as a kind of instrument he elevated instruments - and the role
B: Similar responses, as every involuntary reaction of our emotions to music. TI1e
passion within us rises and falls, it leaps or slips and falls away slowly. Now they play in mediating and modulating sound - within philosophical
they are more agitated, now they retreat; now they are weaker and now discourse. Of course, Herder was not the first thinker to equate human
stronger. The movement and the way they move varies with each beings to instruments: the metaphor of the human being as a string
Modulation, with each striking accent, with each change of key. Music plays instrument goes back to antiquity. Bnt what is strildng about Herder's
on the clavichord within us, which is our innermost nature. 85 use of tl1e metaphor was the differentiation between each listener. We are
each a different kind of instrument; our disposition determines the par-
Later in Kalligone, when Herder addresses Kant's evaluation of music
ticular way in which we respond to the sensations that we take in from the
directly, he takes up the same argument about the nature of tone versus
world around us. Humanity, for Herder, was a kind of vast and diverse
that of color. While Kant treated the sensation of color and tone as similar
instrumental ensemble.
problems (recall that he entertained the possibility that the act of sensing a
color might imply a ldnd of formal judgment), Herder scoffs at the
possibility that the two types of sensation could be discussed together:
Conclusion
85
''A, Ein Stols erschiittert den KOrper; was sagt sein Schall? B. "Ich bin e~·schiittert; so vibriren
meine Theile und stellen sich wieder her," A. Sagen sie dies auch uns? B. Durch und <lurch sind When Herder called for a musical monadology - when he demanded tl1at
wir elastische Wesen; miser Ohr, die GehOrkammer unsrer Seele ist ein Akroaterion, eine philosophers understand musical sound as it was experienced by listeners -
Echokammer der feinsten Art. A. Wenn also ein einzelner Ton aufweckt,was tlmn abgesetzte he did more than show tl1e inextricability of timbre and aesthetic discourse.
cinzelne Tone? B. Sie erncuen und verstarken die Erschiitterung; sic wecken, wie eine Tuba,
wiederholt auf. A. Und langgezogene, anhaltendeTOne?B. Sie dehnen die Empfindung, indem Herder reveals that timbre is the human experience of sound: it is the
die Erschiitterung anhiilt. Sie wirken ungemein machtig. A. Und wachsendeoder abnehmende, concept to which we must turn to describe the immediacies of how sounds
steigendeoder sinkendeTOne, ein langsameroder sclmeller,ernsthafteroder hiipfender, strike our ears, how tl1eyaffect us. It is the word we need when we want to
andringender,7uri/ckweichender, hart- oder weicher,gleich-oder -ungleichmiissiger Fortgangder
Tone, d. i. der St6Be, Schlage, Hauche, Wellen, der RUhrungen und VergnUgen, was wirken sie
auf unser GemLlth?B. Gleichartige Regungen, wie jeder die Musik begleitende unwillkUhrliche 86
"VoUCnds}"'arben- und Ton~;Ton-, und Farbenkunstzusammengestellt; als ob Farben ohne
Ausdruck u11SrerAffekten zeigt. Das leidenschaftliche in uns (w 01Jµtxov) hebet skh und
Zeichnung sich als Medien der Kunst Tc\nen gleichstellen lieBen." Ibid.1 vol. II, pp. 150-51.
sinkt, es hti.pft oder schleicht und schreitet langsam, Jetzt wird es andringend-, jetzt 87
"In der gesammten Natur alle elastischen KOrper auf einen StoB oder Strich (uns horbar
zurilckweichend-, jetzt schwacher-, Jetzt starker gerilhrt; seine eigne Bewegung, sein Tritt
oder minder hOrbar) ihr Inneres,d. i. ihre errcgten und skh wieder herstellenden Krafte zu
veritndert sich mit jeder Modulation, mit jedem treffenden Accent, geschweige mit einer
erkennengeben.Dies nennen wir Schall,und feiner erregt, Klang,Klang, der jede iihnliche
verii.nderten Tona1i, Die Musik spielt in uns ein Clavichord, das unsre eigne innigste Naturist."
Orgartisation in gleiche Schwingung versetzt, und bei empfindenden Wesen eine analoge
Herder, Kalligone,vol. I, pp, 115-17.
Empflndung wirket." Ibid., vol. II, pp. 151-52.
88 The idea of timbre
Conclusion 89

discuss sound in terms of its particularities and peculiarities. To put it


For Carl DahJhaus, this is a typical attempt to express the inexpressible
another way>to talk about timbre is to value sound as sound, and not as
in music: {(it is just the arbitrariness;' he concludes, uthe unbounded
a sonic manifestation of abstract principles. The new discourse about timbre
imagination with which Tieck wounds prosaic logic, that tnrns this exe-
and instruments in the eighteenth century did not correspondor coincide
gesis into a poetic text, that lets the reader imagine what is granted the
with the birth of the aesthetic; this discourse was the birth of the aesthetic.
hearer of absolute music: an experience that overcomes him for an instant,
The construction of 1nusicalaesthetics meant attending to music's im1nedi- 90
but which cannot be held fast." Dahlhaus largely treats the content of·
ate sensations and its mediating technologies, its instruments. This is what it
Tieck's prose poem as predetermined romantic rhetoric; for Dahlhaus, it
means to talk about instrumental sonority, and it was precisely that atten-
differs from other early romantic poetic attempts to write about music
tion that gave rise to a new language about musical tones.
only in surface detail. But essential to the thinking of Tieck and his
Attention to the "eachness1' of musical sounds undergirds romantic
contemporaries is the assumption that the sensual experience of music
aesthetics. Within the ardent praise of music by early romantics, for
was something not only aesthetic, but also potentially profouncl1y moving.
example, is the assumption that musical sound is inherently beautiful.
Indeed, what Tieck expresses so viscerally in the passage above is music's
While Herder argued that tones should be distinguished as a medium by
ability, through its powerful medium of tones, to affect the mind and soul.
the power they exert over a listener, Wilhelm Wackenroder used the
Talk of how "luster shines upon luster" and the sparlding play of color
metaphor of the Virgin birth to explain the natural expressivity of the
speak to the receptiveness of human listeners to the rich experience of
musical medium. He argued that "no other art has a raw material which is, musical sound.
in and of itself, already impregnated with such divine spirit. Its vibrating
If timbre thwarts systematic analysis, if it refuses to be disciplined, it is
material with its ordered wealth of chords comes to meet the creating
precisely because timbre stands at the inauguration of modern musical
hands halfway and expresses beautiful emotions." 88 Ludwig Tieck, his
discourse. It cannot be easily analyzed as a parameter because ultimately
friend and collaborator, heard in sound an entire synesthetic experience:
timbre is not a parameter at all: it is aesthetic attention itself. The birth of
But what words should I resort to, should I grasp, in order to express the power of the attention to timbre is also a condition of possibility for orchestration,
I that heavenly music, with its full tones) its charming reminiscences, has over our for - as we will see in the next two chapters - orches/ration is the art of
heart? With its ai1gelicpresence, it enters the soul immediately and breathes manipulating instrumental timbre. To explore this snbject, we shall move
heavenly breath. Oh, how all memories of all bliss fall and flow back into that out of the realm of aesthetic philosophy and into the world of the
one moment, how all noble feelings, all great emotions welcome the guest! Like composer who was powerfully and intimately associated with the art of
magical seeds, how rapidly the sounds take root within us, and now there's a orchestration in the eighteenth century: Joseph Haydn.
rushing of invisible, fiery forces, and in an instant a grove is rustling with a
thousand wonderful flowers, with incomprehensibly rare colors, and our childhood
and an even more distant past are playing and jesting in the leaves and among one in uns Wurzeln, und mm treibt's und drangt's mit unsichtbaren Fenerkraften, und im
another, color gleams upon color, luster shines upon luster, and all the light, the Augenblick rauscht ein Hain mit tausend wunderbaren Blumen, mit unbegreiflich seltsamen
Farben empor, unsre Kindheit und eine noch fri.ihere Vergangenheit spielen und scherzen auf
sparkling, the rain of beams, coaxes out new luster and new beams of light.89
den Bliittern und in den Wipfeln, Da werden die Blumen el'l'egt und schreiten <lurch einander,
I
I
Farbe fonkelt an Farbe, Glanz erglanzt auf Glanz, und all' <las Licht, der Funkelschein, der
. I' 88 Strahlenregen lockt neuen Glanz und neue Strahlen hervor," L. Tieck, "Unmusikalische
W. I-I. Wackenroder, "Das eigenti.'lmlicheinnere Wesen der Tonkunst," in WilhelmHeinrich Toleranz," in W. H. Wackenroder, Werkeund Briefe (Heidelberg: L. Schneider, 1967),
I
'
Wackemoder:Werkeund Briefe(Munich: Carl Hanser Verlag, 1984), p. 220; WilhelmHeinrich pp. 249-58, 236, quoted in C. Dahlhaus, The Idea of AbsoluteMusic, tnms. R, Lustig
Wackenroder's Confessionsand Fantasies,trans, M. H, Schubert (University Park: Pennsylvania (University of Chicago Press, 1989), pp. 68-69.
90
State University Press, 1971), p. 189. Dahlhaus, The Idea of AbsoluteMusic, p. 69,
89
"Welcb,e Worte aber soll ich fassen und ergreifen, um die Kraft Kund zu machen, die die
himmlische Musik mit ihren vollen Tonen, mit ihren liebreizenden Anklangen Uber unser Herz
erzeigt? Sie tritt unmittelbar mit ihrer Engelsgegenwart in die Seele, und haucht himmlischen
Odem aus, 0, wie stlirzen, wie flieBen im Augenblick alle Erinnenmgen aller Seligkeiten in
den einen Moment zurikk, wie brelten sich dem Safte alle edlen Gefii.hle, alle groBen
Gesinmmgen entgegen! Wie schnell, gleich zaubcrhaften Samenk6rnern, schlagen die T6ne

Você também pode gostar