Você está na página 1de 27

ARTICLE IN PRESS

Origin and evolution of


human consciousness

Franco Fabbroa,b,*, Damiano Cantonec, Susanna Feruglioa, Cristiano Crescentinia


a
Cognitve Neuroscience Laboratory, DILL, University of Udine, Udine, Italy
b
PERCRO Perceptual Robotics Laboratory, Scuola Superiore Sant’Anna, Pisa, Italy
c
Industrial Technical Institute “A. Malignani”, Udine, Italy
*Corresponding author: Tel.: +39-3480-171338, e-mail address: franco.fabbro@uniud.it

Abstract
The study of the origin and evolution of consciousness presents several problems. The first
problem concerns terminology. The word consciousness comes from the Latin term conscı̆en-
tı̆a that means “knowledge shared with others.” However, the term consciousness also refers to
several other aspects involving both its levels (sleep, coma, dreams and waking state) and
contents (subjective, phenomenal and objective). A second issue is the problem of other minds,
namely, the possibility to establish whether others have minds very like our own. Moreover,
human consciousness has been linked to three different forms of memory: procedural/implicit,
semantic and episodic. All these different aspects of consciousness will be discussed in the
first part of the chapter. In the second part, we discuss different neuroscientific theories on
consciousness and examine how research from developmental psychology, clinical neurology
(epilepsy, coma, vegetative state and minimal state of consciousness), neuropsychology
(blindsight, agnosia, neglect, split-brain and ocular rivalry), and comparative neuropsycho-
physiology contribute to the study of consciousness. Finally, in the last part of the chapter
we discuss the distinctive features of human consciousness and in particular the ability to
travel mentally through time, the phenomenon of joint intentionality, theory of mind and
language.

Keywords
Problem of other minds, Phenomenic consciousness, Auto-noetic consciousness, Neuropsy-
chology, Theory of mind, Mental time travel, Language and culture

Progress in Brain Research, ISSN 0079-6123, https://doi.org/10.1016/bs.pbr.2019.03.031


© 2019 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.
1
ARTICLE IN PRESS

2 Human consciousness

1 Introduction
The word consciousness comes from the Latin term conscı̆entı̆a that means
“knowledge shared with others” (Charlton and Short, 1879). In fact, the Latin term
conscı̆entı̆a stems from the combination of two words: scio (I know) and cum (with)
(Zeman, 2002). The etymology of the term thus indicates that consciousness refers to
a form of shared, relational or social knowledge (Dunbar, 2014; Graziano, 2015).
Although much has been written about consciousness in recent decades, what
consciousness is still largely remains an enigma (Baars, 1997; Damasio, 2010;
Dehaene, 2014; Dennett, 2017; Edelman, 2006; Gazzaniga, 1987, 2011; Humphrey,
2011; Kock, 2012; Metzinger, 2009; Nagel, 2012; Revonsuo, 2009; Searle, 2004;
Tononi, 2012; Velmans, 2009). This is partly due to the difficulty of defining what
is meant by the term “consciousness.” As Adam Zeman pointed out, in neuroscience
the term “consciousness” refers to different aspects, such as: the waking state
(“conscious” as “awake”); awareness of sensory experiences and psychological pro-
cesses such as thoughts, emotions, memories, imagination and language (“conscious”
as “aware of”); or consciousness as a synonym of “mind,” which implies the ability to
know, think, understand, remember, believe, etc. (Zeman, 2002).
Moreover, in both common language and neuroscience, “consciousness” has
been linked to self-awareness. According to Zeman, there are at least five different
ways of understanding self-awareness (Zeman, 2002). The first corresponds to the
awareness of being at the center of the attention of another human being (“self-
conscious” as “embarrassment-prone”); the second to the awareness of one’s own
sensations, perceptions and actions (“self-conscious” as “self-detecting”); the third
to the ability to recognize one’s own image in the mirror (“self-conscious” as “self-
recognizing”) (see also Gallup, 1970; Rochat and Zahavi, 2011); the fourth to the
awareness of one’s own mental states and those of others (“self-conscious” as
“aware of awareness”), an aspect called Theory of Mind (Baron-Cohen, 2003,
2011; Dunbar, 2014); finally, self-awareness is also intended as narrative self-
awareness (“self-consciousness” as “self-portraiture and autobiography”) (see also
Ananthaswamy, 2015; Feinberg, 2009; Gottschall, 2012).

2 Epistemological aspects
More than a century ago, the psychologist William James (1842–1910) argued that
consciousness is not a static thing but a process (James, 1904). This position appears
to be in agreement with ideas supported by theoretical physics that everything that
exists appears to be a process (Rovelli, 2018; Smolin, 2013). For human beings, con-
sciousness corresponds mainly to subjective experience, that is, to the ability to have
sensations and perceptions, which have been defined qualia within the field of phi-
losophy of mind (Jackson, 1986; Nagel, 1974). Human beings, as well as all living
ARTICLE IN PRESS

2 Epistemological aspects 3

organisms, are characterized by a physical space, corresponding to the body (self ),


which is separated from the rest of the world (not self ) (Humphrey, 1992).
Characterizing the differences between knowing ourselves and knowing the
world around us, namely, the first- and third-person perspectives, is crucial in the
study of consciousness and has generated the problem of “epistemic asymmetry”
(Velmans, 2009). A similar issue seems to also involve other scientific disciplines,
which do not seem to be completely reducible to one another (for example, biology
does not seem to be reducible to physics, nor psychology to biology) (Anderson,
1972; Polany, 1968). In the latter case one can speak of “epistemological pluralism”
(Fabbro et al., 2018).
Specific psychological characteristics typical of human beings, such as Theory of
Mind, cognitive empathy and verbal communication, corroborate the idea that all
humans are conscious. This universally widespread belief has been challenged by
solipsism, which maintains the impossibility of ascertaining the existence of other
conscious minds besides our own (the problem of other minds) (Allen and
Trestman, 2017; Russell, 1921).
Erwin Schr€ odinger (1887–1961) believed all scientific research, and physics in
particular, is based on two undisputed assumptions: first, the so-called “Hypothesis P,”
connected to the problem of solipsism, which examines the following questions:
“What are the perceptions of another man? How can I even know that he has perceptions?
How can I know that he is capable of feeling and thinking something?” (Schr€odinger,
1935) and second, the use of the terms “sensations” and “perceptions” by physicists
without knowing what they really are (Schr€odinger, 1967). In fact, the natural attitude
of ordinary scientists is to implicitly assume that reality is independent of the mind;
this attitude, called naive realism, has been strongly criticized by phenomenology
(Gallagher and Zahavi, 2008).
According to Schr€ odinger, Hypothesis P is not a trivial question; it simply goes
beyond the limits of science. For example, one may wonder if all human beings see
the color red in the same way (Humphrey, 2006). The case of individuals with color
blindness, such as Wilhelm Conrad R€ ontgen (1845–1923), indicates the significance
of the question: in fact before diagnosis, people with color blindness believe that they
see colors like everyone else.
A central question in the study of consciousness is whether this is a specific men-
tal activity of human beings, as claimed by the French philosopher Rene Descartes
(1596–1650), or if it is also present in other living creatures with complex nervous
systems (Blackmore, 2005; Panksepp and Biven, 2012; Panksepp et al., 2017). From
a philosophical point of view, this is a problem similar to solipsism. Consequently it
may be very difficult, perhaps impossible, to establish with certainty whether other
living species have phenomenal consciousness (subjective experience) or not. One
possibility is to address the question of consciousness in humans and other animal
species in a pragmatic way by: (1) rejecting both the positions of those who consider
the study of animal consciousness an unsolvable mystery (e.g., Thomas Nagel,
Colin McGinn, Steven Pinker), and of those who, such as Nikolaas Tinbergen
ARTICLE IN PRESS

4 Human consciousness

(1907–1988), consider this research useless, because “subjective phenomena cannot


be observed objectively in animals” (Tinbergen, 1951, p. 4); (2) assuming, until
proven otherwise, that all vertebrates, and some species belonging to other phyla,
can experience variable levels of sensations, perceptions and subjective experiences
(Fabbro et al., 2015; Feinberg and Mallatt, 2016; Godfrey-Smith, 2016).

3 On the nature of consciousness


According to the English psychologist Kenneth Craik (1914–1945), one of the
fundamental properties of the mind consists in the ability to represent the world
in order to simulate the possible effects of one’s behavior (Craik, 1943). This ability
consists of three steps: the transduction of sensory stimuli into neural patterns; their
re-elaboration in different symbols, which allow a representation of the world and to
perform simulations of it; and the conversion of mental plans into muscular activi-
ties. This perspective was endorsed by the paleoneurologist Harry Jerison, according
to whom the main function of the nervous system concerns the ability to construct
mental models of reality. For Jerison, the ability to represent the world and elaborate
simulations constitutes biological intelligence (Jerison, 1973, 1991). This is the abil-
ity to represent, in a more or less detailed way, the real world (von Uexk€ull and
Kriszat, 1967). According to this perspective, the world, as we know it, and the self,
are the most complex and elaborate “objects” of biological intelligence.
The idea that the brain generates models is derived from mathematical theories of
systems, which have highlighted the need for each regulator to create a model of
what is regulated (Conant and Ashby, 1970). To manage survival and reproduction,
the brain of a complex organism must create a mental model of the world and the self.
Cognitive neuroscience data indicate that both the world and the self are a construc-
tion of our brain (Frith, 2007; Libet, 2006), which creates the illusion that they are
real. Put in philosophical terms, the models of the world and self are “transparent”
(Metzinger, 2009; Revonsuo, 2006). For this reason, the German philosopher
Thomas Metzinger has proposed a comparison of consciousness to virtual reality,
which likens the brain to a system similar to the most complex flight simulators, with
both the operation of the aircraft and that of the pilot being completely simulated,
referred to as total flight simulator (Metzinger, 2009, 2018). The images or represen-
tations of the self and world generated by the brain are generally effective, allowing
the individual to maintain homeostasis, orient him or herself in the world, and pursue
personal self-realization.
However, the representations of the world and self-generated by the mind can
sometimes be incongruous, as happens in visual and somatic illusions, for instance
in the so-called rubber-hand illusion, in the illusion of being in another person’s
body, or in out-of-body experiences (Botvinick and Cohen, 1998; Lenggenhanger
et al., 2007; Metzinger, 2009). Moreover, in dreams, the deafferentated brain is
able to generate a truthful image of reality (Hobson, 1988; Hobson et al., 2014).
ARTICLE IN PRESS

4 Characteristics of human consciousness 5

Table 1 Philosophical theories on the ontological nature of consciousness.


Philosophers/
scientists Neuroscientists

Substance dualism: two independent 


Pitagoras, Plato, Rene Charles
substances exist: the mental and the Descartes, Roger Sherrington, John
physical Penrose Eccles
Idealistic monism: the mind is the only George Berkeley,
existing substance; the external world is Johann G. Fichte, Georg
either mental itself, or an illusion created W. F. Hegel, Giovanni
by the mind Gentile, Edmund
Husserl
Property dualism: the world is composed Aristoteles, Hilary Roger Sperry,
of one kind of physical substance, but Putnam, Max Velmans, Gerald Edelman,
there are two distinct kinds of properties: Karl Popper Giovanni Berlucchi
physical properties and mental
properties
Material monism: the variety of existing Julien O. de la Mettire, Antonio Damasio,
things can be explained in terms of a Paul Churchland, Stansilav
single reality or substance Thomas Metzinger, Dehaene, Atti
Gilbert Ryle, John Searle Revonsuo,
Salvatore M. Aglioti
Neutral monism: the mental and the Betrand Russell, William
physical are two ways of describing the James, David Chalmers
same elements, which are themselves
“neutral,” that is, neither physical nor
mental
Ontological agnosticism: the relationship Henry Bergson, Thomas Franco Fabbro
between consciousness and brain Nagel
cannot find an exclusively physical and/
or biological explanation

The nature of illusions and dreams is believed to be of fundamental importance


in understanding the problem of mind and consciousness (Metzinger, 2009;
Revonsuo, 2009).
The ontological nature of consciousness has been the subject of several philo-
sophical and neuroscientific debates. In this regard, several philosophical theories
have been put forward, among the most widespread are: the dualism of substance,
idealistic monism, property dualism, monist materialism and neutral monism
(Kriegel, 2007; Savoldi et al., 2013; Seager, 2007; Searle, 1997) (Table 1).

4 Characteristics of human consciousness


According to the Austrian psychologist Franz Brentano (1838–1917), human con-
sciousness always involves a content concerning the world, the body or the mind it-
self. Thus, consciousness is always awareness of something (Bodei, 2015). This
ARTICLE IN PRESS

6 Human consciousness

characteristic is called intentionality (Brentano, 1874; Gallagher and Zahavi, 2008).


The content of consciousness, for example the cherry tree I see out the window, can
be an object that belongs to the world I am observing (third-person perspective), or it
can be a personal experience, such as the smell of a flower or the experience of pain
(first-person perspective) (Revonsuo, 2006, 2009; Velmans, 2009). Thus, in regard
to consciousness, one can recognize primarily cognitive aspects, defined as noetic—
from the ancient Greek word νο~ υς (noûs), meaning intellect or intelligence (Lesher,
1973)—in addition to aspects concerning the ability to feel (sentience) (Godfrey-
Smith, 2016), and connected with sensory, enteroceptive and affective experiences
(qualia) (Jackson, 1986; Nagel, 1974; Ramachandran and Hirstein, 1997). The sci-
entific explanation of how phenomenal consciousness and qualia are generated is the
“hard problem of consciousness” (Chalmers, 1995, 2010; Grossberg, 2017).
The Canadian psychologist Edving Tulving has proposed distinguishing three
states of consciousness: anoetic, noetic and autonoetic (Tulving, 1985, 2002,
2005). These three states have been linked to three different forms of memory: pro-
cedural/implicit (anoetic state), semantic (noetic) and episodic (autonoetic). Most of
the mental activity involved in linguistic and cognitive processing seems to be car-
ried out at a non-conscious (a-noetic) level (Dehaene, 2014). The ability to recognize
a person, or to distinguish concepts (trees with respect to cars), refers to cognitive
tasks concerning noetic consciousness and semantic memory. Instead, the ability
to remember a personal event in one’s life, reconstructing the here and now of a
multisensory scene from the past, is a typical cognitive activity involving autonoetic
consciousness. This form of consciousness involves the ability to imagine a mental
timeline, through which it is possible to remember and reconstruct, in the present
moment, the memories of the past. The ability to be simultaneously aware of the
present moment and memories of the past is a specific characteristic of autonoetic
consciousness, hence a form of higher-order consciousness (Rosenthal, 2005).

5 Neuroscientific theories of human consciousness


According to Gerald Edelman (1929–2014), the construction of mental scenes is
related to the activity of reentrant circuits, which connect the cerebral cortex with
the thalamus. According to Edelman, perceptual experience depends on memory,
since primary consciousness (noetic consciousness) is a sort of “remembered
present” (Edelman, 1990, 1992). He uses the metaphor of the “remembered present”
because the scene, which I now have in my mind’s eye, is constructed on the basis of
the elaboration of the stimuli that have occurred in the immediate past.
The scene is therefore a mental image, characterized by a background (the space)
in which an object or an event is placed in front of a subject who is not yet aware of
himself (Edelman, 2004; Edelman and Tononi, 2000; Llinás, 2001). In humans, there
is a higher order consciousness (autonoetic consciousness), which affords personal
identity and self-awareness and depends on one’s own language, culture, and capac-
ity to generate a model of the self that mentally extends through time, from the past to
ARTICLE IN PRESS

5 Neuroscientific theories of human consciousness 7

the future. Edelman believed that human self-awareness, with its phenomenal dimen-
sion, is an emerging process that depends on the enormous amount of re-entrant brain
circuits’ interactions between numerous neuronal maps (Edelman, 2004, 2006).
For Giulio Tononi phenomenal consciousness depends on the wealth of inte-
grated information. The wealth of information refers to the fact that each conscious
experience is distinguished by an incalculable number of other possible experiences.
Integration makes it possible to explain a peculiar aspect of consciousness: its
uniqueness and indivisibility. Tononi has developed a mathematical model to mea-
sure the integrated information of a system, indicated by the Greek letter Φ, where
the vertical line stands for “information” and the circle for “integration”
(Tononi, 2012).
Tononi and Massimini have developed an experimental technique for measuring
the level of integrated information (Φ) in the brain in different states of conscious-
ness. The procedure involves the delivery of magnetic pulses (via Transcranial Mag-
netic Stimulation, TMS) and the simultaneous recording of evoked brain electrical
activity (via Electroencephalography, EEG) during waking, sleep and dream states.
The idea is simple: if the system is integrated, the magnetic pulse can spread to many
cortical areas; if instead the system is segregated there will be no diffusion. The
results confirmed the idea that the integration of electrical activity at the level of
different cortical areas is an essential element of conscious experience. In fact, mag-
netic pulses spread to many cortical areas during waking and dream states, two states
of phenomenal consciousness, while they remain segregated in the areas of stimula-
tion in slow-wave sleep and general anesthesia, two conditions in which there is no
phenomenal consciousness (Massimini and Tononi, 2018; Tononi et al., 2016).
In addition to self-consciousness (autonoetic consciousness) and primary con-
sciousness (noetic consciousness), human beings are probably endowed with a min-
imal form of consciousness organized in subcortical structures and in particular in the
upper portions of the brain stem. Based on an investigation of epilepsy, the Canadian
neurosurgeon Wilder Penfield (1891–1976) was one of the first to indicate the
critical role subcortical structures (midbrain and thalamus nuclei) played in the gen-
esis of consciousness (Penfield, 1975; Penfield and Roberts, 1959). Subsequently,
the North American psychobiologist Jaak Panksepp (1943–2017) correlated the
functions of a large series of subcortical structures, responsible for the release of
the most important neurotransmitters dopamine, acetylcholine, noradrenaline, sero-
tonin and endogenous opioids, with the processing of emotional-affective conscious-
ness (Denton, 2006; Panksepp, 1998; Panksepp and Biven, 2012). More recently,
from a neurological and a neurophysiological perspective, Antonio Damasio
(Damasio, 2010; Parvizi and Damasio, 2001) and Bjorn Merker (Merker, 2007,
2013), have supported the idea that minimal states of consciousness are organized
in some structures of the midbrain and brain stem, such as the superior colliculus
and the periaqueductal gray, and of the thalamus, such as the dorsal pulvinar.
The study of the origin and evolution of human consciousness has used data
and knowledge coming from: (i) studies on the development of consciousness in
children; (ii) neurophysiological research on different states of consciousness
ARTICLE IN PRESS

8 Human consciousness

(sleep, dream, hypnosis, sleepwalking); (iii) neurological and neuropsychological


analyses of patients with impaired consciousness; (iv) investigations of the effects
of anesthetic and psychotropic drugs; (v) studies on consciousness in animals; and
(vi) paleoanthropology, neuroscience, psychology and linguistics studies concerning
the evolution of hominids and in particular of Homo sapiens.

6 The development of consciousness in children


Research on the development of consciousness in children suggests the existence of
different levels of consciousness in relation to the age of children (Rochat, 2001,
2010; Zelazo et al., 2007). From birth to the first year of age, children present a min-
imal level of consciousness (minC) characterized by the implicit ability to distinguish
oneself from others and by the development of an intermodal body schema that
allows children to explore the environment and build an implicit sense of self.
The minimum level of consciousness seems to emerge in the fetus between the
24th and 30th week of gestation.
Between 9 and 13 months of age, when the children begin to indicate the objects
and produce the first words, a new level of consciousness emerges, referred to as
recursive consciousness (recC). Through this level of consciousness, children are
able to connect the contents of two distinct moments of minimal consciousness.
For example, when a child sees a cat and utters the word “cat,” the child is able
to link the perceptual experience (the recognition of the cat) with the word that labels
the experience that is retrieved from semantic memory.
At the age of two, children reach the first forms of self-consciousness (SelfC).
During this period, they begin to recognize themselves in the mirror, use personal
pronouns and manifest conscious emotions, such as embarrassment and shame.
They are also able to describe past and future events. For example, a 2-year-old child
may be able to remember that yesterday he went to visit the zoo, while being aware
of what is happening now in the present. As mentioned before, in order to remember
past events and imagine future events, the child must have the capacity to imagine a
timeline while maintaining some stable sense of self; in other words, the child has to
have the capacity to mentally travel through time, called mental time travel (MTT).
Toward the third year of age, children develop the first stage of reflective
consciousness (refC1). Through this form of consciousness, children are able to com-
pare two types of arbitrary rules, through their executive and working memory func-
tions, in order to choose one of them instead of persevering in using only one
rule. In addition, many 3-year-old children are able to recognize that right now in
a small box there are pens while previously there was some candy (Gopnik and
Astington, 1988).
From 4 to 5 years of age, children develop the second stage of reflective con-
sciousness (refC2). During this period, children’s executive functions and theory
of mind develop further. For this reason, children are able to distinguish and coor-
dinate two series of temporal lines: one that relates to their own life and the other that
ARTICLE IN PRESS

7 Contributions of neurology to the study of consciousness 9

relates to the world itself. For this reason, 5-year-olds observed in the original Theory
of Mind test are able to realize there were pencils in a Smarties tube (the past of the
world) and that continue to be there (present of the world), while recognizing that at a
certain moment in their past (personal history) they had believed Smarties were in the
tube despite the fact there are now pencils (personal present). Thanks to reflective
consciousness, children are able to appreciate the existence of multiple temporal
perspectives that refer to the same reality.
Because consciousness is a dynamic process, throughout life adults can manifest
one of the different levels described in children. In fact, there is a continuous oscil-
lation within the different levels of consciousness present in adults, from the mini-
mum level to the levels of maximum reflective consciousness (Rochat, 2001). For
this reason, specific training programs have been developed in many cultural and
religious traditions that allow individuals to increase their own states of conscious-
ness and self-awareness, such as mindful awareness (Fabbro, 2019; Tomasino and
Fabbro, 2016; Tomasino et al., 2014).

7 Contributions of neurology to the study of consciousness


In neurology there are two main aspects of consciousness: contents and levels (Bayne
et al., 2016; Posner et al., 2007). The contents of consciousness concern a series
of systems operating to elaborate sensory, motor, cognitive and affective informa-
tion. Some neurological lesions can cause deficits that affect the contents of con-
sciousness, such as aphasias (language), amnesia (memory), agnosia (recognition
of objects), neglect (awareness of space), and dementia (deficit of memory and
awareness of the self ). On the other hand, the levels of consciousness depend on
the activity of a set of brain systems, located mainly in the structures of the brainstem
and diencephalon, operating to maintain alertness, attention and awareness of oneself
and the world. The level of consciousness can vary physiologically (in waking and in
sleep), be modified by drugs (general anesthesia), or change as a result of neurolog-
ical diseases, such as in coma, vegetative state, minimal state of consciousness and in
some forms of epilepsy.
A neurologist can objectively observe a patient’s state of consciousness (third-
person perspective) by evaluating his/her EEG activity, the level of vigilance (wake-
fulness), as well as the somatic expression of emotions in the patient and his/her
ability to organize behavioral plans to achieve complex objectives. Nonetheless,
the level of personal experience (first-person perspective), which concerns the ability
to develop mental images related to real or imagined objects or events of the world,
together with the ability to create a sense of self able to act and experience, is a
dimension that can be explored only through verbal communication (Damasio
and Meyer, 2009).
Within the physiological variation of consciousness levels, many studies have
examined sleep, and REM sleep in particular. REM sleep is a condition generally
associated with dreams containing visual images, emotions and a preserved
ARTICLE IN PRESS

10 Human consciousness

representation of the self. REM dreams are often associated with spatial and temporal
disorientation, bizarreness and unawareness of living a dream experience (Hobson,
1988, 2009). Much attention has been focused on the lucid dream, a condition in
which the subject is aware of being immersed in a dream (Baird et al., 2018).
General anesthesia is a pharmacologically induced condition that resembles
slow-wave sleep and coma. The most common used anesthetics (propofol, barbitu-
rates and benzodiazepines) work through their binding to GABA type A receptors.
Their action determines a functional deactivation of the brainstem and some struc-
tures of the central thalamus, with consequent loss of consciousness, oculomotor and
corneal reflexes, apnea and atony. During general surgery, an individual under gen-
eral anesthesia reaches a level of consciousness similar to that present in stage 2 of
non-REM sleep. In other therapeutic conditions the administration of anesthetics
(propofol or barbiturates) allows reaching a level of consciousness in which the
EEG becomes isoelectric or flat (Brown et al., 2010). Through brain imaging tech-
niques, it was possible to show that in individuals regaining consciousness after a
general anesthesia, the first forms of minimal consciousness to emerge are related
to the activity of some structures of the brainstem (locus coeruleus), hypothalamus,
thalamus and anterior cingulate cortex (Mashour and Alkire, 2013).
Preservation or loss of consciousness is also of fundamental importance in
epilepsy. Indeed, forms of epilepsy that affect only focal regions of the brain, partial
epilepsies, can be distinguished from the forms that affect extensive and bilateral
regions of the brain, generalized epilepsies (Blumenfeld and Meador, 2014). Sudden
loss of consciousness may be present in both generalized epilepsies (absence epi-
lepsy, tonic-clonic epilepsy) and in some focal epilepsies (temporal lobe epilepsy).
Loss of consciousness in these forms of epilepsy is correlated with an abnormal
increase in activity in some structures of the midbrain and medial thalamus, and a
decrease in activity in the cingulate gyrus, medial frontal cortex, and medial parietal
lobe, or precuneus (Blumenfeld, 2009).
The most serious neurological disorders of consciousness include coma, vegeta-
tive state and minimally conscious state. These disorders are due to brain injuries of
traumatic origin, or to hemorrhagic stroke. Coma is characterized by a complete loss
of consciousness; the sleep-wake cycle is lost and the patient’s eyes are kept closed.
It is a temporary condition that can last from a few hours to weeks. Thereafter,
patients die or emerge from the coma and pass into the vegetative or minimally con-
scious state. In the vegetative state the sleep-wake cycle is present, the eyes can be
opened but patients do not seem to be aware since they only show non-purposeful
movements. Instead, in the minimally conscious state, patients sometime show signs
of awareness, for example by executing a command or reacting appropriately to an
environmental stimulus (Laureys and Tononi, 2009).
Brain imaging techniques have led to the discovery that approximately 20% of
people in the vegetative state are in fact conscious. These individuals are able, on
verbal request, to imagine they are playing a game of tennis (activation of the pre-
motor cortex), or to mentally explore their home (activation of the parietal lobe and
the parahippocampal gyrus). Through fMRI or EEG it has been possible to establish
ARTICLE IN PRESS

7 Contributions of neurology to the study of consciousness 11

a communication code with these patients: in order to say “yes,” they have to imagine
playing tennis, to say “no” they have to imagine walking in their homes. In this way
patients in the vegetative state were able to correctly answer a series of questions
such as “Do you have any siblings?” or “Do you have any sisters?” and experimen-
tally show that they were conscious (Monti et al., 2010; Owen, 2014).
Particular attention has also been given to assessing the level of consciousness in
children with anencephaly who, due to a severe cerebral malformation, do not
develop cerebral hemispheres. In the past it was believed that these children, who
can live up to even a few decades, were in a persistent vegetative state. Because they
cannot verbally express themselves it was difficult to understand their state of con-
sciousness (Hypothesis P). However, several investigations on small groups and
more recently, a study on a group of >100 anencephalic children have revealed that
they produce a sleep-wake cycle and may express emotions and moods congruent
with ongoing social situations (Aleman and Merker, 2014; Shewmon et al., 1999).
Moreover, after brief lapses of consciousness, which may be present due to episodes
of absence epilepsy, contact with parents is resumed. In these children, the minimal
state of consciousness is maintained through activity by some midbrain structures
(superior colliculus) connected with the hypothalamus and the periaqueductal gray
(Merker, 2007).
In a recent literature review, Christof Koch et al. analyzed neural correlates of
consciousness (Koch et al., 2016). Different from proposals put forward by Wilder
Penfield, Bjorn Merker and Jaak Panksepp, these authors argue that midbrain and
diencephalon structures are not sufficient to sustain consciousness. Moreover, based
on reports of some exemplar clinical cases (e.g., agenesis of the cerebellum, bilateral
frontal lobectomy), they argued that consciousness and its contents are not dramat-
ically affected by lesions of the cerebellum and frontal lobes. They instead recognize
a temporal-parietal-occipital area of the posterior cerebral cortex as the best candi-
date for the neural correlates of consciousness. In our view, however, it is possible
that the authors’ general conclusions may be affected by the lack of adequate
neuropsychological tools necessary for reliable measures of patients’ consciousness
(different from the neuropsychological tests currently available for many other
cognitive and affective domains such as language, memory, attention, etc.).
For example, a few years ago one of us (Fabbro) had the opportunity to study one
of the few reported cases of a patient with an acquired lesion of the periaqueductal
gray. She was believed to be in coma by clinicians because she could not open her
eyes (eyelid paralysis) and nor speak. After some time, the clinicians realized that the
patient was suffering from a very serious condition known as acinetic mutism. The
patient appeared to be frozen, but if sufficiently stimulated she was able to under-
stand complex sentences (Esposito et al., 1999). How this could be associated with
the patient’s level of consciousness is hard to say, since only the usual, rather coarse,
clinical measures for disorders of consciousness had been used. The same reflections
can be made for one of the first reported cases of complete congenital agenesis of
the cerebellum, which was also studied by one of us (Fabbro) (Tavano et al.,
2007a,b). The patient had mild intellectual impairment but was autonomous, with
ARTICLE IN PRESS

12 Human consciousness

no significant motor, cognitive, or linguistic problems. His consciousness was


defined as normal, but due to the limitations of tools available it could not be
measured accurately. The same way of proceeding, once defined as anecdotal, is gen-
erally used to define the state of consciousness of patients with brain tumors affect-
ing, for example, the thalamus nuclei, basal ganglia, or cerebral areas such as the
frontal lobes (Fabbro and Paradis, 1995; Fabbro et al., 1997; Peru and Fabbro,
1997; Urgesi et al., 2010).

8 Contributions of neuropsychology to the study of


consciousness
The neuropsychological investigation of patients with specific visual impairments
has made a significant contribution to the study of consciousness (Naccache,
2009). In particular, the analysis of a series of patients presenting the phenomenon
of “blindsight” highlighted a dissociation between the unconscious recognition of
stimuli and the visual phenomenal consciousness. In the first half of the 1970s,
the English neuropsychologist Lawrence Weiskrantz (1926–2018) studied the visual
skills of a patient (D.B.) who had undergone the surgical removal of a malformation
in the right occipital lobe (Weiskrantz, 1986). Analyzing the lesion-related visual
deficits (hemianopia of the right upper quadrant), short light stimuli were sent into
D.B.’s blind quadrant: the patient reported he saw nothing, although he was able to
guess well above chance level (i.e., above 50%), the effective presence of stimuli in
this blind quadrant (phenomenal consciousness). Studies in monkeys (macaques)
with lesions to the primary visual areas showed the presence of the same dissociation
(Stoerig and Cowey, 1997).
David Milner and Melvyn Goodale described a second type of dissociation in a
patient (D.F.) with a bilateral lesion to specific areas of the occipito-temporal cortex
(Goodale and Milner, 1992). Following the lesion, the patient was no longer able to
recognize common objects or discriminate the orientation of simple lines and geo-
metric shapes. Brain imaging revealed a lesion to occipito-temporal areas (ventral
visual pathways) but not to occipito-parietal areas (dorsal visual pathways). Though
unable to describe the orientation of the slot in a postbox that could be rotated, D.F.
was able to post the letter, orienting her hand appropriately, without making mis-
takes. The study of this patient led to the hypothesis of the existence of the two visual
pathways: the ventral visual pathway would be involved in the phenomenal visual
consciousness or the “what” pathway, while the dorsal visual pathway would mainly
subserve unconscious visuo-motor transformation, representing the “how” pathway
(Milner and Goodale, 2006). Recently, a similar organization has also been hypoth-
esized for language: ventral pathways of language processing could be related to
semantic awareness while dorsal (unconscious) pathways could be more involved
in the phonological and syntactic aspects of language processing (Friederici,
2015; Skeide and Friederici, 2016).
ARTICLE IN PRESS

8 Contributions of neuropsychology to the study of consciousness 13

Unilateral spatial neglect is another important area of consciousness studies. It is


characterized by the inability to explore, perceive and respond to stimuli presented in
the contralateral space of a lesion, independent of significant sensory or motor
deficits (Vallar and Calzolari, 2018). The neglect syndrome generally depends on
lesions located in the right parietal lobe. Many patients with neglect lose the phenom-
enal awareness of objects placed in the left part of a space. Spatial neglect affects not
only the ability to explore and recognize objects of the external world, but also the
contents of one’s imagination or spatial memory (Bisiach and Luzzatti, 1978). The
neglect syndrome has been associated with a dysfunction of spatial attention sys-
tems; this means that in order to have phenomenal consciousness, both the ventral
visual pathways and neural structures supporting spatial attention must be preserved
(Naccache, 2009).
A very important neuropsychological condition for the study of consciousness is
the split-brain syndrome, also called callosal disconnection syndrome. This condi-
tion is characterized by a number of neurological abnormalities arising from the
partial or complete lesioning of the corpus callosum; for example, a surgical proce-
dure performed for the purposes of treating intractable forms of epilepsy. After the
complete section of the corpus callosum the patients appear normal, without evident
cognitive disturbances; however, they are no longer able to verbally recognize
objects placed in their left hand, nor write with their left hand. By using the tachis-
toscopic technique, Roger Sperry (1913–1994) and Michael Gazzaniga showed that
split-brain patients could consciously comply with verbal requests sent to their
left hemisphere, but unconsciously respond to stimuli presented to the right hemi-
sphere (single words). According to Gazzaniga, human beings have multiple mental
systems, each one capable of perceiving, memorizing and coordinating effective
actions; nevertheless, only one of these systems is endowed with awareness: the ver-
bal interpreter, which is located in the left cerebral hemisphere. When faced with
behaviors organized by non-verbal mental systems (located in the right cerebral
hemisphere), the verbal interpreter continually constructs explanation for actions,
possibly trying to make sense of what it sees happening (Gazzaniga, 1987, 2011).
The neural correlates of consciousness have also been studied from a neurophys-
iological perspective, analyzing the phenomenon of ocular rivalry: a condition
consisting in the simultaneous presentation of two different images to both eyes.
Instead of experiencing a superimposed view of the two figures, the subject is aware
of seeing only one of the two images alternately and with random duration. The
Greek neurophysiologist Nikos Logothetis has used this paradigm to study the neural
correlates of visual consciousness in primates (Logothetis, 1998). He trained ma-
caques to pull a lever when they saw a human face, a second lever when they
saw a flag and to release both levers when they saw a quilt. In this way he managed
to associate the motor response with the conscious perception of a visual stimulus.
While animals performed the task, electrical activity was recorded at various points
in the visual pathways. It was shown that the activity of primary visual areas was not
correlated with the awareness of visual stimuli. Neurons in these areas discharged
ARTICLE IN PRESS

14 Human consciousness

both when the image was perceived and when it was not. The situation was different
in higher order visual areas, such as in the inferior temporal cortex, where neurons
responded only to the image that the monkey was aware of seeing. Furthermore, the
prefrontal cortex also appeared to mediate conscious visual perception. Similar
results have been obtained studying ocular rivalry in humans using brain imaging
techniques (Blake and Logothetis, 2002).

9 Consciousness in vertebrates
Most of the animal taxonomic groups (phyla) first appeared during a short period of
a few million years, called the “Cambrian explosion” (approximately 541 million
years ago). The animals of previous periods were small, soft-bodied and slow. After
the Cambrian explosion, animals with complex active bodies appeared on Earth
(Trestman, 2013). In particular the animals belonging to three phyla (arthropods, chor-
dates and mollusks) developed complex active bodies equipped with: (i) appendages
(claws, hands, tentacles, mouths); (ii) bodies capable of producing movements with
many degrees of freedom; (iii) sensory organs suitable for receiving distal information
(eyes); and (iv) information processing systems capable of developing autonomous
mobility and active manipulation of objects.
The factors that caused the Cambrian explosion have not been completely clar-
ified. One of the most significant factors seems to have been the increase of oxygen
concentration in the atmosphere and water. Subsequently, organisms with sensory
organs (vision) developed and started to engage in active predatory behaviors.
The predatory behaviors, initially manifested in particular by species belonging to
the arthropoda phylum, promoted the differentiation of taxonomic groups; in fact,
some groups developed defensive armor, while others evolved defensive behaviors
based on an increase of mobility (chordates).
The British zoologist Andrew Parker claimed that a crucial factor in the Cam-
brian explosion was the development of vision in some phyla (Parker, 2003). In
his opinion, the appearance of eyes led to an escalation in predatory skills in some
species, which in turn led to the development of appropriate defensive strategies in
others. By contrast, Michael Trestman, a philosopher of mind, pointed out that one of
the critical aspects in the Cambrian explosion was not primarily due to the appear-
ance of eyes, but to the development of neural and cognitive systems connected to
vision, defined as basic cognitive embodiment (BCE). In his opinion, these cognitive
skills have developed to integrate sensory information and link them to active move-
ment. This allowed the creation of a representation of the “space,” which comprised a
“scene” composed of a center (the “self”) placed in front of the “object” (Jerison,
1973, 1991). Trestman argues that all animals with BCE capacities, that is at least
those belonging to the taxonomic groups of arthropods, chordates and mollusks, have
acquired an agentive or action-oriented bodily self-awareness, since they are able to
move autonomously in space, interacting with the objects contained in it (Colin and
Trestman, 2017; Trestman, 2013).
ARTICLE IN PRESS

9 Consciousness in vertebrates 15

However, as mentioned before, the problem of animal consciousness remains an


area of active debate among neuroscientists, psychologists, veterinarians, breeders,
philosophers and politicians. This is not just a philosophical or cognitive argument as
it has important practical implications on how to breed and care for animals. In
general, studies on consciousness in non-human animals are based on research inte-
grating neuroanatomical, neurophysiological and behavioral data (Edelman and
Seth, 2009). Based on these studies, a substantial part of neuroscientists and cogni-
tive psychologists believes that primary consciousness (noetic consciousness) is
present in mammals and birds, and this should be related to the presence of corti-
cothalamic reentrant and reverberating circuits (Edelman, 1992; Edelman and
Seth, 2009; Edelman and Tononi, 2000). Other neuroscientists believe that primary
consciousness is organized in some structures of the midbrain and the diencephalon
(optic tectum, periaqueductal gray, hypothalamus, central thalamic nuclei). These
structures are involved in sensorimotor integration (including eye movement), the
regulation of communicative and affective basic functions, and motor initiation
(Damasio, 2010; Fabbro et al., 2015; Feinberg and Mallatt, 2016; Merker, 2007;
Panksepp, 1998; Panksepp and Biven, 2012). According to this perspective, primary
consciousness would already be present in fish showing eye movement (Trestman,
2013; Trevarthen, 1968) (Table 2).
As already mentioned, Hypothesis P (the problem of other minds) deals with the
problem of ascertaining the existence of other minds besides our own through our
phenomenal consciousness. The assumption that other human beings are conscious
is essentially based on the ability to communicate our inner states through language.
In the case of non-human animals this capacity is not available (Farah, 2008; Sober,
2000). Nevertheless, neuroscience and cognitive psychology studies have shown the
presence of significant imitative, cognitive and social skills in numerous species of
vertebrates, including many species of fishes (Fabbro et al., 2015; Feinberg and
Mallatt, 2016; Watanabe et al., 2017). For example, recently a species of fishes
(Labroides dimidiatus) appeared to pass the “mirror test,” which is often used
as a benchmark for self-consciousness (Kohda et al., 2018). Given the complexity

Table 2 Levels of the self and consciousness in the various vertebrate classes.
Proto- Core- Self- Narrative- Possible level of
self self consciousness self consciousness

Fish (Teleostei) + + ? Noetic consciousness


Amphibians + ? ? ?
Reptiles + + ? Noetic consciousness
Birds + + + Noetic consciousness
Mammals + + + Noetic consciousness
Homo Sapiens + + + + Autonoetic
(current) consciousness

Notes: Based on Fabbro et al. (2015) and Feinberg and Mallatt (2016).
ARTICLE IN PRESS

16 Human consciousness

of the issue concerning consciousness in non-human animals, it seems appropriate


to cautiously hypothesize that some form of primary consciousness is likely
present in all vertebrates, i.e., that all vertebrates are sentient beings (Low et al.,
2012). This assumption should be taken into account in the breeding and care of
all vertebrates.

10 Origin and characteristics of consciousness in Homo


sapiens
The social and cultural dimensions exhibited by Homo sapiens distinguish the spe-
cies from other primates. As regards the social dimension, human beings are born,
grow up and live in social contexts nested inside each other. The nucleus of human
sociality is the mother-child dyad and the extended “family” in which little humans
develop (about 10–15 individuals). Some families meet periodically and constitute
so-called “bands” (about 30–40 individuals). Five or six bands form a village or
“clan” of about 150 individuals, while about 10 villages constitute a community
(about 1500 individuals). The British evolutionary psychologist Robin Dunbar has
shown that human group size (families, bands, clans and communities) is a universal
characteristic, which is present in every social structure of hunter-gatherers in any
part of the world (Dunbar, 1993, 2010). Furthermore, neuroanthropological research
by Dunbar indicates that the size of the fundamental human group, namely, that of
the village or clan (150 individuals), was one of the main factors connected with the
progressive growth of the cerebral cortex in the Homo species versus other species of
human primates (Dunbar, 1992, 1997, 2014).
The second main feature of Homo sapiens is its high propensity for cultural learn-
ing. By culture we mean the ability to develop specific types of learning concerning:
(i) social behavior (ambulation, sphincter control, singing and dancing), (ii) the con-
struction of tools, (iii) the learning of a language, and (iv) the appropriation of typical
habits and customs of a society (clothing, culinary traditions, religious traditions,
narratives and literature, etc.). In addition to showing a great propensity to learn,
humans have also developed the inclination to teach, which is absent in other pri-
mates. In fact, humans dedicate a large part of the interaction between mother
and child to teaching, a behavior that is very sporadic in chimpanzees (Mithen,
1998). For this reason, the Russian neuropsychologist Alexander R. Luria
(1902–1977) claimed that humans’ higher cognitive functions, in particular memory,
voluntary attention, language, mathematical skills, reasoning, reading and writing,
depend on both specific neurological substrates (especially the cerebral cortex)
and the historical-cultural environment in which such functions have developed
(Luria, 1962, 1973). Indeed, if a child does not grow up in a human culture, he will
not be able to learn to walk, speak, control sphincters, or develop fine motor skills
(Blakmore, 1977; Rymer, 1994). Moreover, all these different types of learning have
critical windows of sensitivity whose closure makes learning more difficult (Fabbro,
1999; Fabbro and Cargnelutti, 2018; Kuhl, 2010).
ARTICLE IN PRESS

10 Origin and characteristics of consciousness in Homo sapiens 17

If we consider the behavioral and cognitive abilities of Homo sapiens, we find a


series of distinctive features that we do not share with the species closest to us, such
as Pan troglodytes (common chimpanzee) and Pan paniscus (bonobo). These
characteristics concern the bipedal ambulation, fabrication of lithic tools, cooking
of food, shared attention, language, culture and Theory of Mind (Table 3). The first
of these, bipedal ambulation, is believed to have developed more than 4 million years
ago (Hay and Leakey, 1982; Tattersall, 2012). This brought about radical physiolog-
ical and cognitive changes, modifying breathing, freeing upper limbs and hands for
new functions, thus transforming the way one could have “access” or affordance to
the world (Gibson, 1979; Provine, 2000). Moreover, the cooking of foods occurred
between 1.8 and 1 million years ago and changed the digestive system, which in-
creased the percentage of nutrients absorbed from food, thus favoring an increase
in brain volume (Tattersall, 2012; Wrangham, 2009).
The fabrication of stone tools began about 3 million years ago and represented a
crucial feature differentiating the ancestors of the Homo species from all other an-
imals (Shumaker et al., 2011). The ancestors of the Homo species could make ever
more complex lithic instruments, which were conserved for a long time after their
use. In addition, they were made of materials coming from areas far from the place
the tools were actually manufactured (Dunbar, 2014; Mithen, 1998; Tattersall,
2012). From a cognitive point of view, this means ancestors of the Homo species,
probably since the australopithecines, already showed the ability to imagine the fu-
ture use of a stone, which was collected and conserved for this reason (Fabbro et al.,
2015). Thus, technological skills in humans are related to the temporal dimension of
existence (Heidegger, 1927). The ability to travel mentally through time (Mental
Time Travel), which is associated with episodic memory and autonoetic conscious-
ness, is a cognitive dimension that seems to be present only in Homo sapiens and in
some of its ancestors (Corballis, 2011, 2018; Suddendorf and Corballis, 2007;
Tulving, 2005).
Another cognitive aspect that appears to be typical of the human species and
some of its ancestors (Homo heidelbergensis) is the ability to cooperate, which is
associated with the emergence of Theory of Mind, i.e., the ability to attribute beliefs,
intentions, thoughts and moods to oneself and to others (Tomasello, 2014, 2018). In
fact, it is necessary to imagine the intentions of others (joint intentionality) in order to
effectively collaborate with them, a task that even chimpanzees seem unable to ac-
complish. The Theory of Mind ability does not only include the possibility to ima-
gine what others believe or are thinking about or second-order intentionality, but also
what others think that I am thinking or third-order intentionality (Baron-Cohen,
2003, 2011). The Theory of Mind is a cognitive device that plays a fundamental role
in human social relationships. For example, the narratives present in novels, or in the
most diverse religious traditions, may underlie complex cognitive abilities that imply
up to a fifth-order intentionality: I want [1] you to believe [2] that there is a super-
natural agent that understands [3] that I wish [4] that he intends to intervene [5] if you
do not conform to the established rules (Dunbar, 2010; Dunbar et al., 2005). These
are scenarios that deal with mental/virtual worlds that have been created through so-
cial interactions and underlie many human institutions.
Table 3 Cognitive and communicative skills in the different species of hominids.
Bipedal Manufacture of Habitual mental Cooking Theory Pantomime Vocal

ARTICLE IN PRESS
locomotion lithic tools time travel of food of mind gestures language

Pan troglodytes
(common chimpanzee)
Australopithecus + + +
Homo habilis + + + ?
Homo erectus + + + + +
(ergaster)
Homo heidelbergensis + + + + + +
Homo + + + + + +
neanderthalensis
Homo sapiens + + + + + +
(>100,000)
Homo sapiens + + + + + + +
(<100,000)

Notes: Based on Tattersall (2012) and Tomasello, (2014).


ARTICLE IN PRESS

10 Origin and characteristics of consciousness in Homo sapiens 19

Finally, language is what most radically distinguishes human cognition from


that of other animals. Language does not only represent a doubly articulated com-
munication system (Jakobson and Waugh, 1979; Sapir, 1921), but also a cognitive
faculty that allows humans to expand their creativity and knowledge in an almost
infinite way (Chomsky, 1975; Jerison, 1973). Convergent studies of genetics,
linguistics and paleo-archeology indicate that language was probably invented
shortly before the origin of symbolic culture (100,000–80,000 years ago) by a small
group (several thousand individuals) of Homo sapiens in Africa (cf. Tattersall, 2012,
2017). It is possible to conceive that after a rather short period of time (a few thou-
sand years), numerous languages then developed. This probably favored the increase
of cultural diversity, the development and diffusion of new hunting technologies (use
of arches and poisoned arrows), and the progressive migration of Homo sapiens in all
continents correlated with the extinction of all other Homo species (Homo nean-
derthalensis, Homo erectus, Homo floresiensis) (Fabbro, 1999, 2018).
According to this perspective, the invention of language is comparable to the
invention of writing that took place about 5400 years ago. In both cases some brain
structures, which had evolved for other functions, were subsequently recycled or
exploited for subserving language, reading and writing, known as exaptation
phenomena (Dehaene and Cohen, 2007; Lieberman, 2013). In fact, the acquisition
of the mother tongue (L1) is a complex sensory-motor and cognitive task that takes
many years to reach an adequate level (Locke and Bogin, 2006). Furthermore, some
children with no evident neurological or intellectual disorders present significant
difficulties in the acquisition of language and/or in reading and writing (Dehaene,
2009; Krishnan et al., 2016). Human language is subserved by a complex system
of brain structures linked with different types of memory (nondeclarative memories,
semantic and episodic memories) (Paradis, 2009; Ullman, 2001). According to the
notion of exaptation in human evolution, the development of phono-articulatory
structures must have preceded the invention of language by hundreds of thousands
of years. It is likely that human vocal organs evolved for singing, a behavior that
probably played a considerable role in sexual selection, as Charles Darwin empha-
sized (Darwin, 1871). Singing also played an important role in the social interaction
of human groups, allowing a significant reduction of social and individual stress
(Dunbar et al., 2012; Giustison and Bergman, 2017; Masataka, 2008; Mithen,
2006). In this sense, musical experience anticipated and favored the development
of language (Brown, 2017; Merker et al., 2015).
The possibility of using a language to exchange knowledge, reason, reflect, and
tell stories, including one’s own biography, has radically changed the mind and
human consciousness. An example of this transformation was described in the book
A Man without Words by Susan Schaller, which documented the story of a young
Mexican deaf-mute man. Through the learning of American Sign Language, the
man enters the world of language, a dimension that appeared shocking,
yet allowed him to get out of the isolation and “cognitive prison” in which he had
lived up to that moment (Schaller, 1991). It is thus likely that the structural charac-
teristics of different languages, the ways of life of diverse cultures, as well as the new
ARTICLE IN PRESS

20 Human consciousness

media of communication, can influence human consciousness in ways that are not
yet clear (Deutscher, 2010; Jaynes, 1990). As highlighted by many spiritual and
meditative traditions, the autonoetic state of consciousness is also probably charac-
terized by different levels. For example, the practice of mindfulness meditation
shows how easy it is in everyday life to slip from phenomenal states of consciousness
to noetic or anoetic levels of consciousness (Fabbro, 2019; Malinowski, 2013).

References
Aleman, B., Merker, B., 2014. Consciousness without cortex: a hydranencephaly family
survey. Acta Paediatr. 103, 1057–1065.
Allen, C., Trestman, M., 2017. In: Zalta, E.N. (Ed.), Animal Consciousness. The Stanford
encyclopedia of philosophy, Stanford.
Ananthaswamy, A., 2015. The Man Who Wasn’t There: Investigations Into the Strange New
Science of the Self. Penguin, London.
Anderson, P.W., 1972. More is different. Science 177, 393–396.
Baars, B., 1997. In the Theater of Consciousness: The Workspace of the Mind. Oxford
University Press, New York.
Baird, B., Castelnovo, A., Gosseries, O., Tononi, G., 2018. Frequent lucid dreaming associated
with increased functional connectivity between frontopolar cortex and temporoparietal
association areas. Sci. Rep. 8, 17798.
Baron-Cohen, S., 2003. The Essential Difference: Men, Women and the Extreme Male Brain.
Penguin, London.
Baron-Cohen, S., 2011. Zero Degrees of Empathy: A New Theory of Human Cruelty. Penguin,
London.
Bayne, T., Hohwy, J., Owen, A.M., 2016. Are there levels of consciousness? Trends Cogn. Sci.
20, 405–413.
Bisiach, E., Luzzatti, C., 1978. Unilateral neglect of representational space. Cortex 14, 129–133.
Blackmore, S., 2005. Consciousness: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford University Press,
Oxford.
Blake, R., Logothetis, N.K., 2002. Visual competition. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 31, 1–11.
Blakmore, C., 1977. Mechanics of the Mind. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Blumenfeld, H., 2009. Epilepsy and consciousness. In: Laureys, S., Tononi, G. (Eds.), The
Neurology of Consciousness. Elsevier, New York, pp. 247–260.
Blumenfeld, H., Meador, K.J., 2014. Consciousness as a useful concept in epilepsy
classification. Epilepsia 55, 1145–1150.
Bodei, R., 2015. The Life of Things, the Love of Things. Fordham University Press, New
York.
Botvinick, M., Cohen, J., 1998. Rubber hand “feels” touch that eyes see. Nature 391, 756.
Brentano, F., 1874. Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt. Meiner, Leipzig.
Brown, S., 2017. A joint prosodic origin of language and music. Front. Psychol. 8, 1894.
Brown, E.N., Lydic, R., Schiff, N.D., 2010. General anesthesia, sleep, and coma. N. Engl.
J. Med. 363, 2638–2650.
Chalmers, D., 1995. Facing up to the problem of consciousness. J. Conscious. Stud.
2, 200–219.
ARTICLE IN PRESS

References 21

Chalmers, D., 2010. The Character of Consciousness. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Charlton, T.L., Short, C., 1879. A Latin Dictionary. Clarendon Press, Oxford.
Chomsky, N., 1975. Reflections on Language. Pantheon Books, New York.
Colin, A., Trestman, M., 2017. Animal consciousness. In: Schneider, S., Velmans, M. (Eds.),
The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness. Wiley Blackwell, Oxford, pp. 63–76.
Conant, R.C., Ashby, R.W., 1970. Every good regulator of a system must be a model of the
total system. Int. J. Syst. Sci. 1, 89–97.
Corballis, M.C., 2011. The Recursive Mind. Princeton University Press, Princeton.
Corballis, M.C., 2018. Space, time and language. Cogn. Process. 19, 589–592.
Craik, K.J.W., 1943. The Nature of Explanation. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Damasio, A., 2010. Self Comes to Mind: Constructing the Conscious Brain. Pantheon, New
York.
Damasio, A., Meyer, K., 2009. Consciousness: an overview of the phenomenon and of its pos-
sible neural basis. In: Laureys, S., Tononi, G. (Eds.), The Neurology of Consciousness.
Elsevier, New York, pp. 3–14.
Darwin, C., 1871. The Descent of Man, and Selection in Relation to Sex. John Murray,
London.
Dehaene, S., 2009. Reading in the Brain. Penguin, New York.
Dehaene, S., 2014. Consciousness and the Brain: Deciphering How the Brain Codes Our
Thoughts. Viking, New York.
Dehaene, S., Cohen, L., 2007. Cultural recycling of cortical maps. Neuron 56, 384–398.
Dennett, D., 2017. From Bacteria to Bach and Back: The Evolution of Minds. Norton, New
York.
Denton, D., 2006. The Primordial Emotions. The Dawning of Consciousness. Oxford
University Press, Oxford.
Deutscher, G., 2010. Through the Language Glass: Why the World Looks Different in Other
Languages. Henry Holt and Company, New York.
Dunbar, R.I., 1992. Neocortex size as a constraint on group size in primates. J. Hum. Evol.
22, 469–493.
Dunbar, R.I., 1993. Coevolution of neocortical size, group size and language in humans.
Behav. Brain Sci. 16, 681–694.
Dunbar, R.I., 1997. Grooming, Gossip and the Evolution of Language. Harvard University
Press, Cambridge.
Dunbar, R.I., 2010. How Many Friends Does One Person Need? Dunbar’s Number and Other
Evolutionary Quirks. Faber and Faber, London.
Dunbar, R.I., 2014. Human Evolution. Pelican Books, London.
Dunbar, R.I., Barrett, L., Lycett, J., 2005. Evolutionary Psychology, a Beginner’s Guide. One
World Books, Oxford.
Dunbar, R.I., Kaskatis, K., MacDonald, I., Barra, V., 2012. Performance of music elevates pain
threshold and positive affect: implications for the evolutionary function of music.
Evol. Psychol. 10, 688–702. 147470491201000403.
Edelman, G., 1990. The Remembered Present: A Biological Theory of Consciousness. Basic
Books, New York.
Edelman, G., 1992. Bright Air, Brilliant Fire: On the Matter of the Mind. Basic Books, New
York.
Edelman, G., 2004. Wider Than the Sky: The Phenomenal Gift of Consciousness. Yale
University Press, New Haven.
ARTICLE IN PRESS

22 Human consciousness

Edelman, G., 2006. Second Nature: Brain Science and Human Knowledge. Yale University
Press, New Haven.
Edelman, D.B., Seth, A.K., 2009. Animal consciousness: a synthetic approach. Trends Neu-
rosci. 32, 476–484.
Edelman, G., Tononi, G., 2000. A Universe of Consciousness: How Matter Becomes Imagi-
nation. Basic Books, New York.
Esposito, A., Demeurisse, G., Alberti, B., Fabbro, F., 1999. Complete mutism after midbrain
periaqueductal gray lesion. Neuroreport 10, 681–685.
Fabbro, F., 1999. The Neurolinguistics of Bilingualism: An Introduction. Psychology Press,
Hove.
Fabbro, F., 2018. Identità culturale e violenza. Neuropsicologia delle lingue e delle religioni.
Cultural Identity and Violence. Neuropsychology of Languages and religions, Bollati
Boringhieri, Torino.
Fabbro, F., 2019. La meditazione mindfulness. Neuroscienze, filosofia e spiritualità. Mindful-
ness Meditation. Neuroscience, Philosophy and Spirituality, Il Mulino, Bologna.
Fabbro, F., Cargnelutti, E., 2018. Neuroscienze del bilinguismo. Il farsi e disfarsi delle lingue.
Neuroscience of Bilingualism. The Appropriation and Loss of Languages, Astrolabio,
Roma.
Fabbro, F., Paradis, M., 1995. Differential impairments in four multilingual patients with sub-
cortical lesions. In: Paradis, M. (Ed.), Aspects of Bilingual Aphasia. Pergamon Press,
London, pp. 139–176.
Fabbro, F., Peru, A., Skrap, M., 1997. Language disorders in bilingual patients after thalamic
lesions. J. Neurolinguistics 10, 347–367.
Fabbro, F., Aglioti, S.M., Bergamasco, M., Clarici, A., Panksepp, J., 2015. Evolutionary as-
pects of self- and world consciousness in vertebrates. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 9, 157.
Fabbro, F., Fabbro, A., Crescentini, C., 2018. Contributions of neuropsychology to the study of
ancient literature. Front. Psychol. 28, 9.
Farah, M.J., 2008. Neuroethics and the problem of other minds: implications of neuroscience
for the moral status of brain-damaged patients and nonhuman animals. Neuroethics
1, 9–18.
Feinberg, R., 2009. Bridging science and humanism: thoughts on the future of anthropology.
Anthropol. Newsl. 50, 4–8.
Feinberg, T.E., Mallatt, J.M., 2016. The Ancient Origins of Consciousness. How the Brain
Created Consciousness. The MIT Press, Cambridge.
Friederici, A.D., 2015. White-matter pathways for speech and language processing. Handb.
Clin. Neurol. 129, 177–186.
Frith, C.D., 2007. The social brain? Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B Biol. Sci. 362, 671–678.
Gallagher, S., Zahavi, D., 2008. The Phenomenological Mind. Routledge, London.
Gallup, G.G., 1970. Chimpanzees: self-recognition. Science 167, 86–87.
Gazzaniga, M.S., 1987. Social Brain: Discovering the Networks of the Mind. Basic Books,
New York.
Gazzaniga, M.S., 2011. Who’s in Charge? Free Will and the Science of the Brain. Ecco,
New York.
Gibson, J.J., 1979. The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Houghton Mifflin, Boston.
Giustison, M.L., Bergman, T.J., 2017. Divergent acoustic properties of gelada and baboon
vocalizations and their implications for the evolution of human speech. J. Lang. Evol.
2, 20–36.
ARTICLE IN PRESS

References 23

Godfrey-Smith, P., 2016. Other Minds: The Octopus, the Sea, and the Deep Origins of
Consciousness. Farrar, Straus and Giroux, New York.
Goodale, M., Milner, D., 1992. Separate visual pathways for perception and action. Trends
Neurosci. 15, 20–25.
Gopnik, A., Astington, J., 1988. Children’s understanding of representational change and its
relation to the understanding of false belief and the appearance-reality distinction. Child
Dev. 59, 26–37.
Gottschall, J., 2012. The Storytelling Animal: How Stories Make Us Human. Mariner Books,
Boston.
Graziano, M., 2015. Consciousness and the Social Brain. Oxford University Press, New York.
Grossberg, S., 2017. Towards solving the hard problem of consciousness: the varieties
of brain resonances and the conscious experiences that they support. Neural Netw. 87, 38–95.
Hay, R.L., Leakey, M.D., 1982. Fossil footprints of laetoli. Sci. Am. 246, 50–57.
Heidegger, M., 1927. Being and Time (J. Macquarrie, E. Robinson, 1962, Trans.). SCM Press,
London.
Hobson, A., 1988. The Dreaming Brain. Basic Books, New York.
Hobson, A., 2009. REM sleep and dreaming: towards a theory of protoconsciousness. Nat.
Rev. Neurosci. 10, 803–813.
Hobson, A., Hong, C.C., Friston, K.J., 2014. Virtual reality and consciousness inference in
dreaming. Front. Psychol. 5, 1133.
Humphrey, N., 1992. A History of the Mind. Simon & Schuster, New York.
Humphrey, N., 2006. Seeing Red: A Study in Consciousness. Harvard University Press,
Boston.
Humphrey, N., 2011. Soul Dust: The Magic of Consciousness. Princeton University Press,
Princeton.
Jackson, F., 1986. What Mary didn’t know. J. Philos. 83, 291–295.
Jakobson, R., Waugh, L., 1979. The Sound Shape of Language. Indiana University Press,
Bloomington.
James, W., 1904. Does consciousness exist? J. Philos. Psychol. Sci. Methods 1, 477–491.
Jaynes, J., 1990. The Origin of Consciousness in the Breakdown of the Bicameral Mind.
Mifflin, Boston.
Jerison, H.J., 1973. Evolution of the Brain and Intelligence. Academic Press, New York.
Jerison, H.J., 1991. Brain Size and Evolution of the Mind. American Museum of Natural
History, New York.
Koch, C., Massimini, M., Boly, M., Tononi, G., 2016. Neural correlates of consciousness: pro-
gress and problems. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 17, 307–321.
Kock, C., 2012. Consciousness: Confessions of a Romantic Reductionist. The MIT Press, Boston.
Kohda, M., Takashi, H., Takeyama, T., Awata, S., Tanaka, H., Asai, J., Jordan, A., 2018.
Cleaner wrasse pass the mark test. What are the implications for consciousness and
self-awareness testing in animals? BioRxiv, 1–39. https://doi.org/10.1101/397067.
Kriegel, U., 2007. Philosophical theories of consciousness: contemporary Western perspec-
tives. In: Zelazo, P.D., Moscovitch, M., Thompson, E. (Eds.), The Cambridge Handbook
of Consciousness. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 35–66.
Krishnan, S., Watkins, K.E., Bishop, D.V., 2016. Neurobiological basis of language learning
difficulties. Trends Cogn. Sci. 20, 701–714.
Kuhl, P.K., 2010. Brain mechanisms in early language acquisition. Neuron 67, 713–727.
Laureys, S., Tononi, G., 2009. The Neurology of Consciousness. Elsevier, New York.
ARTICLE IN PRESS

24 Human consciousness

Lenggenhanger, B., Tadi, T., Metzinger, T., Blanke, O., 2007. Video ergo sum: manipulating
bodily self-consciousness. Science 317, 1096–1099.
Lesher, J.H., 1973. The meaning of nous in the posterior analytics. Phronesis 18, 44–68.
Libet, B., 2006. Reflections on the interaction of the mind and brain. Prog. Neurobiol.
78, 322–326.
Lieberman, P., 2013. The Unpredictable Species. Princeton University Press, Princeton.
Llinás, R., 2001. I of the Vortex: From Neurons to Self. MIT Press, Cambridge.
Locke, J.L., Bogin, B., 2006. Language and life history: a new perspective on the development
and evolution of human language. Behav. Brain Sci. 29, 259–280.
Logothetis, N.K., 1998. Single units and conscious vision. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B
353, 1801–1818.
Low, P., Panksepp, J., Reiss, D., Edelman, D., Van, B., Koch, C., 2012. The Cambridge Dec-
laration on Animal Consciousness. http://fcmconference.org/img/CambridgeDeclaration
OnConsciousness.pdf.
Luria, A.R., 1962. Higher Cortical Functions in Man. Moscow University Press, Moscow.
Luria, A.R., 1973. The Working Brain. Basic Books, New York.
Malinowski, P., 2013. Neural mechanisms of attentional control in mindfulness meditation.
Front. Neurosci. 7, 1–11.
Masataka, N., 2008. The Origins of Language. Springer, Berlin.
Mashour, G.A., Alkire, M.T., 2013. Evolution of consciousness: phylogeny, ontogeny, and
emergence from general anesthesia. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U. S. A. 110, 10357–10364.
Massimini, M., Tononi, G., 2018. Sizing up Consciousness. Towards an Objective Measure of
the Capacity for Experience. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Merker, B., 2007. Consciousness without a cerebral cortex: a challenge for neuroscience and
medicine. Behav. Brain Sci. 30, 63–81.
Merker, B., 2013. The efference cascade, consciousness, and its self: naturalizing the first per-
son pivot of action control. Front. Psychol. 4, 501.
Merker, B., Morley, I., Zuidema, W., 2015. Five fundamental constraints on theories of the
origins of music. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. Ser. B Biol. Sci. 370, 20140095.
Metzinger, T., 2009. The Ego Tunnel: The Science of the Mind and the Myth of the Self. Basic
Books, New York.
Metzinger, T., 2018. Why is virtual reality interesting for philosophers? Front. Robot. AI 5, 101.
Milner, D., Goodale, M., 2006. The Visual Brain in Action. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Mithen, S., 1998. The Prehistory of Mind. Phoenix, London.
Mithen, S., 2006. The Singing Neanderthals: The Origins of Music, Language, Mind and
Body. Harvard University Press, Cambridge.
Monti, M.M., Laureys, S., Owen, A.M., 2010. The vegetative state. BMJ 341, 3765.
Naccache, L., 2009. Visual consciousness: an updated neurological tour. In: Laureys, S.,
Tononi, G. (Eds.), The Neurology of Consciousness. Elsevier, New York, pp. 271–281.
Nagel, T., 1974. What is it like to be a bat? Philos. Rev. 83, 435–450.
Nagel, T., 2012. Mind and Cosmos: Why the Materialist Neo-Darwinian Conception of Nature
Is Almost Certainly False. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Owen, A.M., 2014. Is anybody in there? Sci. Am. 310, 52–57.
Panksepp, J., 1998. Affective Neuroscience: The Foundations of Human and Animal
Emotions. Oxford University Press, New York.
Panksepp, J., Biven, L., 2012. The Archaeology of Mind: Neuroevolutionary Origins of
Human Emotion. W. W. Norton & Company, New York.
ARTICLE IN PRESS

References 25

Panksepp, J., Lane, R.D., Solms, M., Smith, R., 2017. Reconciling cognitive and affective neu-
roscience perspectives on the brain basis of emotional experience. Neurosci. Biobehav.
Rev. 76, 187–215.
Paradis, M., 2009. Declarative and Procedural Determinants of Second Languages. John
Benjamins, Amsterdam.
Parker, A., 2003. In the Blink of an Eye: The Cause of the Most Dramatic Event in the History
of Life. Free Press, London.
Parvizi, J., Damasio, A., 2001. Consciousness and the brainstem. Cognition 79, 135–160.
Penfield, W., 1975. The Mystery of the Mind: A Critical Study of Consciousness and the Hu-
man Brain. Princeton University Press, Princeton.
Penfield, W., Roberts, L., 1959. Speech and Brain Mechanisms. Princeton University Press,
Princeton.
Peru, A., Fabbro, F., 1997. Thalamic amnesia following venous infarction: evidence from a
single case study. Brain Cogn. 33, 278–294.
Polany, M., 1968. Life’s irreducible structure. Science 160, 1308–1312.
Posner, J.B., Saper, C.B., Schiff, N.D., Plum, F., 2007. Plum and Posner’s Diagnosis of Stupor
and Coma. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Provine, R., 2000. Laughter. A Scientific Investigation. Viking Press, New York.
Ramachandran, V.S., Hirstein, W., 1997. Three laws of qualia. What neurology tells us about
the biological functions of consciousness. J. Conscious. Stud. 4, 429–457.
Revonsuo, A., 2006. Inner Presence: Consciousness as a Biological Phenomenon. MIT Press,
Cambridge, MA.
Revonsuo, A., 2009. Consciousness. The Science of Subjectivity. Psychology Press, Hove.
Rochat, P., 2001. Five levels of self-awareness as they unfold early in life. Conscious. Cogn.
12, 717–731.
Rochat, P., 2010. The innate sense of the body develops to become a public affair by 2-3 years.
Neuropsychologia 48, 738–745.
Rochat, P., Zahavi, D., 2011. The uncanny mirror: a re-framing of mirror self-experience. Con-
scious. Cogn. 20, 204–213.
Rosenthal, D., 2005. Consciousness and Mind. Clarendon Press, Oxford.
Rovelli, C., 2018. The Order of Time. Penguin, London.
Russell, B., 1921. The Analysis of Mind. The Macmillan Company, London.
Rymer, R., 1994. Genie. A Scientific Tragedy. Penguin Books, London.
Sapir, E., 1921. Language: An Introduction to the Study of Speech. Harcourt, Brace and
Company, New York.
Savoldi, F., Ceroni, M., Vanzago, L., 2013. La coscienza. Contributi per specialisti e non spe-
cialisti tra Neuroscienza, Filosofia e Neurologia. Aras, Fano.
Schaller, S., 1991. A Man Without Words. University of California Press, Berkeley.
Schr€odinger, E., 1935. Alcune osservazioni sulle basi della conoscenza scientifica. In:
L’immagine del mondo, 2001. Bollati Boringhieri, Torino. (A. Verson, trad. it.). 2001.
Schr€odinger, E., 1967. Mind and matter. In: What Is Life. Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge.
Seager, W., 2007. A brief history of the philosophical problem of consciousness. In:
Zelazo, P.D., Moscovitch, M., Thompson, E. (Eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of
Consciousness. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 9–34.
Searle, J., 1997. The Mystery of Consciousness. The New York Review of Books, New York.
Searle, J., 2004. Mind: A Brief Introduction. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
ARTICLE IN PRESS

26 Human consciousness

Shewmon, D.A., Holmes, G.L., Byrne, P.A., 1999. Consciousness in congenitally decorticate
children: developmental vegetative state as self-fulfilling prophecy. Dev. Med. Child Neu-
rol. 41, 364–374.
Shumaker, R.W., Walkup, K.R., Beck, B.B., 2011. Animal Tool Behavior: The Use and Man-
ufacture of Tools by Animals. The Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore.
Skeide, M.A., Friederici, A.D., 2016. The ontogeny of the cortical language network. Nat.
Rev. Neurosci. 17, 323–332.
Smolin, L., 2013. Time Reborn: From the Crisis in Physics to the Future of the Universe.
Houghton Mifflin, Boston.
Sober, E., 2000. Evolution and the problem of other minds. J. Philos. 97, 365–386.
Stoerig, P., Cowey, A., 1997. Blindsight in man and monkey. Brain 120, 535–559.
Suddendorf, T., Corballis, M.C., 2007. The evolution of foresight: what is mental time travel,
and is it unique to humans? Behav. Brain Sci. 30, 299–313.
Tattersall, I., 2012. Masters of the Planet: The Search for Our Human Origins. Macmillan,
Palgrave.
Tattersall, I., 2017. The material record and the antiquity of language. Neurosci. Biobehav.
Rev. 81, 247–254.
Tavano, A., Fabbro, F., Borgatti, R., 2007a. Speaking without the cerebellum: language skills
in a young adult with near total cerebellar agenesis. In: Schalley, A.C., Khlentzos, D.
(Eds.), Mental States. Benjamins, Amsterdam, pp. 171–190.
Tavano, A., Grasso, R., Gagliardi, C., Triulzi, F., Bresolin, N., Fabbro, F., Borgatti, R., 2007b.
Disorders of cognitive and affective development in cerebellar malformations. Brain
130, 2646–2660.
Tinbergen, N., 1951. The Study of Instinct. Calderon Press, Oxford.
Tomasello, M., 2014. A Natural History of Human Thinking. Harvard University Press,
Cambridge.
Tomasello, M., 2018. How children come to understand false beliefs: a shared intentionality
account. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U. S. A. 115, 8491–8498.
Tomasino, B., Fabbro, F., 2016. Increases in the right dorsolateral prefrontal cortex and de-
creases the rostral prefrontal cortex activation after-8 weeks of focused attention based
mindfulness meditation. Brain Cogn. 102, 46–54.
Tomasino, B., Chiesa, A., Fabbro, F., 2014. Disentangling the neural mechanisms involved in
Hinduism- and Buddhism-related meditations. Brain Cogn. 90, 32–40.
Tononi, G., 2012. PHI: A Voyage From the Brain to the Soul. Pantheon Books, New York.
Tononi, G., Boly, M., Massimini, M., Koch, C., 2016. Integrated information theory: from
consciousness to its physical substrate. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 17, 450–461.
Trestman, M., 2013. The Cambrian explosion and the origins of embodied cognition. Biol.
Theory 8, 80–92.
Trevarthen, C., 1968. Vision in fish: the origins of the visual frame for action in vertebrates. In:
Ingle, D. (Ed.), The Central Nervous System and Fish Behavior. The University of
Chicago Press, Chicago, pp. 61–94.
Tulving, E., 1985. Memory and consciousness, can. Psychology 26, 1–12.
Tulving, E., 2002. Episodic memory: from mind to brain. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 53, 1–25.
Tulving, E., 2005. Episodic memory and autonoesis: uniquely human? In: Terrace, H.S.,
Metcalfe, J. (Eds.), The Missing Link in Cognition. Oxford University Press, New
York, pp. 4–56.
ARTICLE IN PRESS

Further reading 27

Ullman, M.T., 2001. A neurocognitive perspective on language: the declarative/procedural


model. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 2, 717–726.
Urgesi, C., Aglioti, S.M., Skrap, M., Fabbro, F., 2010. The spiritual brain: selective cortical
lesions modulate human self-transcendence. Neuron 65, 309–319.
Vallar, G., Calzolari, E., 2018. Unilateral spatial neglect after posterior parietal damage.
Handb. Clin. Neurol. 151, 287–312.
Velmans, M., 2009. Understanding Consciousness. Routledge, London.
Von Uexk€ull, J.V., Kriszat, G., 1967. Ambiente e comportamento (di P. Manfredi, trad.). Il
Saggiatore, Milano.
Watanabe, S., Hofman, M.A., Shimizu, T. (Eds.), 2017. Evolution of the Brain, Cognition, and
Emotion in Vertebrates. Springer, Tokyo, Japan.
Weiskrantz, L., 1986. Blindsight: A Case Study and Implications. Oxford University Press,
Oxford.
Wrangham, R., 2009. Catching Fire: How Cooking Made Us Human. Basic Books, New York.
Zelazo, P.D., Gao Hong, H., Todd, R., 2007. The development of consciousness. In:
Zelazo, P.D., Moscovitch, M., Thompson, E. (Eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of
Consciousness. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 405–432.
Zeman, A., 2002. Consciousness. A User’s Guide. Yale University Press, New Haven.

Further reading
LeDoux, J.E., 2015. Anxious: Using the Brain to Understand and Treat Fear and Anxiety.
Penguin Books, New York.

Você também pode gostar