Você está na página 1de 21

Dworkin and Critical Legal Studies

Laws Empire pp. 271-75


Perhaps evenpartial success is unavailable; perhaps every
interpretation he considers is inconsistent with the bulk of the material
supplied to him. In that case he must abandon the enterprise, for the
consequence of taking the interpretive attitude toward the text in
question is then a piece of internal skepticism: that nothing can count as
continuing the novel rather than beginning anew. 230-1

The chain novel analogy


Its easy to see how in some cases the
chain novel might prove impossible to
continue with integrity. Just imagine
that earlier writers introduced too much
weirdness for a coherent story to be
possible.
Could something similar happen in law?
What factors constrain sharp breaks in
the chain of law?

Do serious legal contradictions


get addressed in practical ways?
They are likely to lead to litigation or legislation
that will diminish the conflict.
Dworkin says as much: Contradiction between
two areas of law so closely related [as two
parts of contract law] would almost certainly
also be eroded by the practices of precedent
and academic criticism and restatement.
Reply to Waldron in Hershowitz, ed. Exploring
Laws Empire, 302

Stability in law and legal interpretation


Stability is promoted by:
Shared paradigms. Anyjudge who denied that the
traffic code was part of the law would be replaced, and
this fact discourages radical interpretations. 88
Precedentwhich no judges interpretation can wholly
ignore. 88
The social nature of legal practice. Judges think
about lawwithin society, not apart from it; the general
intellectual environment, as well as the common
languageexercises practical constraints on
idiosyncrasy. 88
Shared views about which texts are relevant. 91
Shared views about the legal furniture which is in
place.
What about stability in legislation?

The critical legal studies


movement

Although the intellectual origins of the Critical


Legal Studies (CLS) can be generally traced all the
way back to American Legal Realism, as a distinct
scholarly movement the CLS fully emerged only by
the late 1970s. Many first-wave CLS scholars
[were] profoundly influenced by the twin
experiences of the radical civil rights movement
and the anti-war movements of the late 1960s.
What started off as a critical stance towards
American domestic politics eventually translated
into a critical stance towards the dominant legal
ideology of the modern Western society. [T]he
"crits" sought to demystify the numerous myths at
the heart of the mainstream legal practice.
Wikipedia: Critical Legal Studies

Dworkin on What is Critical


Legal Studies?
Critical legal studies resembles the older
movement of American legal realism.
At its best and most promising, however, it
escapes the limits of legal realism by reaching
for the global and threatening form of internal
skepticism. It argues that our legal culture,
far from having any shape amenable to a
uniform and coherent justification of principle,
can only be grasped through the infertile
metric of contradiction. LE 272

Dworkin on how the Crits would


interpret McLoughlin
In McLoughlin CLS would tell a story of conflicting
principles respecting individual loss in accidents: of
two deeply antagonistic ideologies at war within the
law, one drawn, perhaps, from communitarian
impulses of altrusim and mutual concern and the other
from the contradictory ideas of egoism, selfsufficiency, and judgmental moralism. LE 272
CLS would say that Hercules must fail in imposing a
coherent structure on laws empire as a whole. LE
273 [Would CLS agree to use the Hercules idea?]

Dworkins view of the central


claim of CLS
According to the crits, Hercules must fail in
imposing a coherent structure on laws
empire as a whole. The reason is that our
law contains deeply antagonistic ideologies
at war. 272
CLS argues that liberalism, as a philosophical
system combining metaphysical and ethical
ideas, is profoundly self-contradictory and
that the contradictions of liberalism therefore
ensure the chaos and contradiction of any
available interpretation of our law. 274

Duncan Kennedy on contradiction


Kennedy writes that the opposing ethical
conceptions which inform legal doctrine reflect a
deeper level of contradiction. At this deeper level,
we are divided, among ourselves and also within
ourselves, between irreconcilable visions of
humanity and society, and between radically
different aspirations for our common future.
Andrew Altman, Legal Realism, Critical Legal
Studies, and Dworkin (1986) 217

Roberto Unger on internal conflict


it would be strange if the results of a coherent,
richly developed normative theory were to coincide
with a major portion of any extended branch of law.
The many conflicts of interest and vision that
lawmaking involves, fought out by countless minds
and wills working at cross purposes, would have to
be the vehicle of an immanent moral rationality
whose message could be articulated by a single
cohesive theory. This daring and implausible
sanctification of the actual is in fact undertaken by
the dominant legal theories. AA 222

Legal realism and indeterminacy


Judges have tremendous leeway in being able to
redefine the holding and the dictum in the
precedential cases. This leeway enabled judges, in
effect, to rewrite the rules of law on which earlier
cases had been decided. The upshot was that in
almost any case which reached the stage of
litigation, a judge could find opinions which read
relevant precedents as stating one legal rule and
other opinions which read the precedents as stating
a contrary rule. AA 209

Altman on Hercules
If the rule of law is to be a guiding ideal
for humans, and not just gods, then the
problem of legal indeterminacy must be
resolvable from a human point of view.
AA 220

Jeremy Waldron
Did Dworkin Ever Answer the Crits?
My aim in this paper is to explore the extent to which
Professor Dworkin is put to a hard choice between the
agile and discerning constructivism he needs to
respond to CLS, on the one had, and the integrity
thesiswhich he invokes to justify the claim that
making coherent sense of the existing legal materials,
foreground and background, is something we are
morally required to do. I think Dworkin really is
confronted with a dilemma here.
Waldron 156

Are Dworkin and the crits trying to


answer the same question?
CLS and Dworkin have a common interest in
what I would like to call the background
elements of a legal systemthe principles
and policies that lie in back of the rules and
texts that positivists emphasize. Waldron 155
Maybe not. Perhaps the crits are interested in
broad underlying ideologies and Dworkin in
specific principles of fairness, justice, and
procedural due process.

Waldron on possible responses:


competition versus contradiction
Dworkins second response is to argue that this sort
of CLS skepticism neglects an important
philosophical distinctions between competing
principles (such as autonomy and mutual concern)
, and contradictory principles (such as equality
and inequality) which cannot possibly be combined
in one coherent conception. W 167
Crits may, of course, be skeptical that humans can
deal adequately with the balancing of competing
principles that Dworkins view requires. See W 168

The contradiction/competition distinction


Hercules constructs two principles: that people should not be
held responsible for causing injury they could not reasonably
foresee and that people should not be put at disadvantage, in
the level of protection the law gives them, in virtue of physical
disabilities beyond their control. He has no difficulty
recognizing both at work in the law of tort and more generally,
and no difficulty in accepting both at the level of abstract
principle. These principles are sometimes competitive, but they
are not contradictory. He asks whether past decisions in cases
in which they do conflict have resolved them coherently.
Perhaps they have, though whatever account he accepts of that
resolution will probably require him to treat some past
decisionsas mistakes. 443-4

Waldron on possible responses: You


dont know if its worth trying until you try
For the search for unifying principles to be worth trying it must not
be out of the question that our argument or our principles fit a
significant portion of the legal materials.
This is where Dworkin should take his stand against the Crits.
He should say (and he does say): it is not clear up front that
attempts to argue in the mode of law-as-integrity are doomed to
failure. If it were clear, we should have no reason to resist the
siren charms of pragmatism: forget the existing law; ask instead
whats best for the future; and take ones chances on the
integrity issue. But sometimes legal argument looks promising,
and when it does were are obliged to make the attempt (and
the theory of integrity explains why). W 181

Dworkins criticisms of CLS


The skeptical interpretative claim that CLS makes is
powerful and germane, however, only if it begins where
Hercules begins: it must claim to have looked for a less
skeptical interpretation and failed.The internal skeptic
must show that the flawed and contradictory account is the
only one available. 273-4
Argumentsabout the incoherence of liberalismhave been
spectacular and even embarrassing failures. They begin
and end in a defective account of what liberalism is, an
account supported by no plausible reading of the
philosophers they count as liberals. 274
Further, CLS writers ignore the distinction we have just found
crucial to any internally skeptical argument, the distinction
between competition and contradiction in principles.

The contemporary focus helps


A contemporary Congress might disown the principles
that inspired Social Security in the New Deal.
No contradiction between what the law permits or
requires in different historical stages of a communitys
culture can pose any difficulty for a contemporary
judge seeking integrity within contemporary law. So
Waldron must suppose that the Crits have established
more than a historical claim: that they have shown
contradiction in the American communitys
contemporary legal practice. But Waldron offers no
examples at all of the conflicts he supposes endemic
in that practice. --Reply to Waldron in Hershowitz, ed.
Exploring Laws Empire, 303, 299.

Dworkins final reply to the crits


Their work is useful to Hercules, and he would neglect it at his
peril, because it reminds him that nothing in the way his law
was produced guarantees his success in finding a coherent
interpretation of it it.
But neither does history guarantee his failure, because his
ambitions are interpretive in the sense appropriate to the
philosophical foundations of law as integrity. He tries to impose
order over doctrine, not to discover order in the forces that
created it. He struggles toward a set of principles he can offer
to integrity, a scheme for transforming the varied links in the
chain of law into a vision of government now speaking with one
voice, even if this is very different from the voices of leaders
past. 273
An imaginative interpretation can be constructed on morally
complicated, even ambiguous terrain. 228
Perhaps Hercules can pull off such a constructive reinterpretation, but can ordinary judges?

Is legitimacy undermined if judges can


only pursue integrity in a limited way?
In answering this we should focus on real human
judges, not Hercules.
Perhaps it is enough to confer legitimacy if judges
and other participants are seriously trying to
achieve integrity. Through their efforts we attempt
to be a community of principle, and enough
success can be achieved to make those efforts
meaningful.
Perhaps the greatest integrity is achieved within the
various legal compartments.

Você também pode gostar